Skip to main content

Full text of "The history of biology : a survey"

See other formats


ERIK    NORDEN^KTfOLD 


^>^^ 
^ 


i^   u.    \^^^ 


t 


ID 


Marine  Biological  laboratory  Library 

Woods  Hole,  Mass. 


*^^«»'N* 


Presented  by 


From  the  estate  of 
Louis  W.  Hutchins 
M^,  1964 


01 


I 
I 
I 
I 

D 


I 
I 
I 


E3^^^^^^^^^^^^^E3E 


THE    HISTORY    OF    BIOLOGY 


CHAPTERS    IN 

MODERN    BIOLOGY 

AND 

BIOMETRICS 


By  Raymond  Pearl : 

THE     BIOLOGY     OF     POPULATION     GROWTH 

ALCOHOL     AND     LONGEVITY 

THE     RATE     OF     LIVING 

By  Julian  Huxley : 

ESSAYS     OF     A     BIOLOGIST 
ESSAYS     IN     POPULAR     SCIENCE 

By  William  lAorton  Wheeler : 

FOIBLES     OF     INSECTS     AND     MEN 


IKiillll'  l,ili(l'!i'!<il,  ';'lllll||'lilll!ljl!ir''(ll  i  l.'i'„|jlliri|l|  iHllliIiMi  llllliiliill'ril  i  'W  djlljl 


N 

I— I 

Pi 
< 

o 

< 

<: 

Pi 

0 


^ 


^ 

(A 

CA^ 

^ 

U) 

2 

< 

C/5 

h-^ 

w 

^ 

> 

^ 

C/3 
< 

^ 

ft< 

Q 

2: 

Q 

<: 

5 

^ 


By    ERIK    NORDENSKIOLD 

TRANSLATED  FROM  THE  SWEDISH  BY 
LEONARD  BUCKNALL  EYRE 


THE 

HISTORY 

OF 

BIOLOGY 


y  /5- 


A   SURVEY 


\"jLV  MASS. 


TUDOR  PUBLISHING  CO. 
MCMXXXVi  New  York 


COPYRIGHT     192.8     BY     ALFRED      A.      KNOPF,     INC. 

ALL   RIGHTS   RESERVED NO   PART   OF  THIS  BOOK  MAY   BE  REPRINTED 

IN  ANY  FORM  WITHOUT  PERMISSION  IN  WRITING  FROM  THE  PUBLISHER 


NEW    EDITION    AUGUST,    I935 
SECOND   PRINTING   JULY,    I936 


Originally  issued  as 

BIOLOGINS    HISTORIA 

in  three  volumes 
1920-24 

STOCKHOLM,     BJORCK    &    BORJESSON 


MANUFACTURED    IN    THE    UNITED     STATES     OF    AMERICA 


FOREWORD 

This  work,   ivhlch  is  here  presented  in  the  English  language,  is 
based  on  a  course  of  lectures  given  at  the  University  of  Helsingfors, 
Finland,  during  the  academic  year  igi6-iy.  It  is  the  author  s  in- 
tention to  present  a  picture  of  the  development  of  biological  science 
throughout  the  ages,  viewed  in  conjunction  ivith  the  general  cultural 
development  of  mankind.  Regarded  thus  as  a  link  in  the  general  history 
of  culture,  the  problems  of  biology  luill,  it  is  hoped,  prove  of  interest 
not  only  to  young  university  students,  for  whom  this  book  is  priinarily 
intended,  but  also  to  a  still  wider  public.  With  regard  to  modern  times, 
for  obvious  reasons  it  has  only  been  possible  in  such  a  brief  history  as 
this  to  give  a  very  summary  account  of  recent  developments.  A  more 
thorough  knowledge  of  the  results  of  specialised  biological  research  will 
be  gained  by  reference  to  the  literary  works  of  professional  biologists, 
which  often  contain  a  historical  survey  by  luay  of  introduction.   On 
the  other  hand,  the  theoretical  principles  on  which  research  work  has 
been  carried  out  have  been  discussed  here  in  greater  detail,  both  for  the 
reason  that  records  of  them  are  not  so  easily  accessible  and  on  account 
of  the  influence  they  have  exerted  upon  culture  in  general.  In  accordance 
with  this  principle  a  number  of  typical  representatives  of  each  trend  of 
thought  have  been  selected  for  inclusion  and  their  ivork  described,  while 
no  attempt  has  been  made  to  present  a  complete  record  of  all  personalities 
that  have  figured  in  the  biological  world.  In  this,  as  in  other  historical 


VI  FOREWORD 

works,  the  selection  has  of  course  been  made  by  a  process  of  elimination, 
which  to  a  certain  extent  was  bound  to  be  subjective;  especially  in  a 
work  dealing  mainly  with  a  general  historical  development  it  has  been 
necessary  to  exclude  the  names  of  a  great  many  brilliant  specialists^  in 
spite  of  the  fact  that  their  ivork  may  be  of  lasting  value,  while  other 
personalities,  perhaps  in  themselves  of  less  importance,  have  been  men- 
tioned on  account  of  the  part  they  have  played  in  the  getieral  cultural 
development  of  their  period.  For  the  same  reason  representatives  of 
scientific  progress  in  the  various  civilised  countries  of  the  world  have 
been  included,  as  far  as  space  has  alloived,  in  order  to  present  as  com- 
prehensive an  idea  as  possible  of  the  progress  of  science  and  the  contri- 
butions that  different  peoples  have  made  thereto. 

For  their  assistance  in  preparing  the  English  edition  I  take  this 
opportunity  of  recording  my  thanks  to  Mr.  Leonard  Bucknall  Eyre, 
B.A.  Cantab.,  of  Stockholm,  who  has  translated  the  book  from  the 
Swedish,  and  to  Mr.  Alfred  A.  Kfiopf,  ivho  has  promoted  its  pub- 
lication. 

StockhoUn,  Novetnber  igzj  The  Author 


CONTENTS 


PART      ONE 

BIOLOGY    IN    CLASSICAL    ANTIQUITY,    THE    MIDDLE 
AGES,    AND    THE    RENAISSANCE 

I.    The  development  of  biology  amongst  the  primitive  peoples 

and  the  civilized  nations  of  the  East  3 

II.    The  earliest  Greek  natural  philosophy  8 

III.  The  earlier  phase  of  Greek  medical  science  and  its  significance 

for  the  development  of  biology  15 

IV.  The   end   of  natural-philosophical  speculation.     The  prede- 

cessors of  Aristotle  30 

V.  Aristotle  34 

VI.  Natural-philosophical  systems  after  Aristotle  45 

VII.  Specialized  biological  research  after  Aristotle  50 

VIII.  The  decline  of  science  in  late  antiquity  58 

IX.  Biological  science  among  the  Arabians  68 

X.  Biology  during  the  Christian  Middle  Ages  74 

THE    HISTORY    OF    BIOLOGY    DURING    THE 
RENAISSANCE 

«; 

XI.  The  end  of  mediaeval  science  8z 

XII.    New  cosmic  ideas  and  new  scientific  method  84 
XIII.    Descriptive  biological  research  during  the  Renaissance: 

I.  Zoography  91 

X.  Anatomy  98 


8S070 


Vlll  CONTENTS 

XIV.    The  discovery  of  the  circulation  of  the  blood: 

I.  Harvey's  predecessors  108 

i.  Harvey  114 

* 

PART      TWO 

BIOLOGY    IN    THE    SEVENTEENTH    AND    EIGHTEENTH 

CENTURIES 

I.   The  origin  of  the  modern  idea  of  nature  in  the  seventeenth  and 

eighteenth  centuries  iii 

II.    The  mechanical  nature-systems  113 

III.  Mystical  speculation  upon  natural  science  131 

IV.  Biological  research  in  the  seventeenth  century: 

I.  Harvey's  successors  141 

X.  Attempts  at  a  mechanical  explanation  of  life-phenomena  151 

3.  Microscopies  and  microtechnology  158 
V.    Biological   speculations   and  controversial   questions   at   the 

beginning  of  the  eighteenth  century  174 

VI.    The  development  of  systematic  classification  before  Linnasus  190 

VII.    Linnasus  and  his  pupils  2.03 

VIII.    Buffon  XI 9 

IX.    Invertebrate  research  in  the  eighteenth  century  2.30 

X.    Experimental    and    speculative    biology    in    the    eighteenth 

century  X34 
XI.    Descriptive    and    comparative    anatomy    in    the   eighteenth 

century  X58 
XII.    The  first  beginnings  of  modern  chemistry  and   its  influence 

upon  the  development  of  biology  2.64 
XIII.    Critical    philosophy    and    Rc^mantic  conceptions   of  nature: 

I.  Kant  and  his  immediate  successors  2.68 

X.  Goethe  2.79 


CONTENTS  IX 

XIV.    Natural  philosophical  biology: 

I.  Germany  and  Scandinavia  2.86 

■3..  England  and  France  2.93 

PART     THREE 
MODERN    BIOLOGY 

BIOLOGY    DURING    THE    FIRST    HALF    OF    THE 
NINETEENTH    CENTURY 

I.    From  natural  philosophy  to  modern  biology: 

I.  The  predecessors  of  comparative  anatomy  301 

2..  Humboldt  314 

3.  Lamarck  316 

II.    Cuvier  331 

III.  Bichat  and  his  tissue  theory  344 

IV.  Cuvier's  younger  contemporaries  35i 
V.    The  progress  of  embryology  362. 

VI.    The  development  of  experimental  research  and  its  application 

to  comparative  biology  370 

VII.    Microscopy  and  cytology  389 
VIII.    The  continued  development  of  biology  until  the  advent  of 
Darwinism: 

I.  Experimental  research  work  406 

-L.  Morphology  and  classification  414 

3.  Microbiology  42.6 

4.  Botany  435 
IX.    Positivist  and  materialist  natural  philosophy  441 

* 

FROM  DARWIN  TO  OUR  OWN  DAY 

X.    The  preconditions  of  Darwinism: 

I .  Modern  geology  453 

1.  The  ideal  preconditions  of  Darwinism  458 


X  CONTENTS 

XL   Darwin  ^gi 

XII.   For  and  against  Darwin  477 

XIII.  The  doctrine  of  descent  based  on  morphological  grounds. 

Gegenbaur  and  his  school  ^og 

XIV.  Haeckel  and  monism  505 
XV.   Morphological   specialized  research   under   the   influence  of 

Darwinism : 

I.  Anatomy  and  embryology  518 

2-  Cytology  533 

3.  Microbiology  544 

4.  Vegetable  morphology  550 

5.  Geographical  biology  558 
XVI.    Neo-Darwinism  and  neo-Lamarckism  562. 

XVII.   Experimental  biology: 

I.  Experimental  morphology  574 

1.  Experimental  heredity-research  583 

3.  Biochemistry  594 

4.  Animal  psychology  599 
XVIII,    Modern  theoretical  speculations: 

I.  Mechanism  and  vitalism  603 
1.  The  idea  of  species  and  some  problems  in  connexion 

therewith  613 

Sources  and  Literature 

Sources  617 

Literature  6x9 

Index  of  Names  follows  page   6x9 


LIST    OF   ILLUSTRATIONS 


GIROLAMO    FABRIZIO-    |     Frontispiece 
ANDREAS    VESALIUS  • 

ULISSE    ALDROVANDI  •  74 

ANTONY    VON    LEEUWENHOEK  •  74 

GEORGE    LOUIS    LECLERC    DE    BUFFON  •   108 

WILLIAM    HARVEY  •  108 

ALBRECHT    VON    HALLER  •  131 

PARACELSUS  •   131 

MARCELLO    MALPIGHI  •   190 

GIOVANNI    ALFONSO    BORELLI  •  190 

NICOLAUS    STENO  •   134 

JOHN    RAY  •  134 

LINN^US  •  z68 

CHARLES    BONNET  •  2.68 

LORENZ    OKEN  •  2.86 

LAMARCK  •  i86 

CUVIER  •  304 

MARIE    FRANCOIS    XAVIER    BICHAT  •  304 

ALEXANDER    VON    HUMBOLDT  •  370 

JOHANN    WOLFGANG    GOETHE  •  370 

KARL    ERNST    VON    BAER  •  414 

JOHANNES    PETER    MULLER  •  414 


LIST     OF     ILLUSTRATIONS 


CHARLES    DARWIN  •  458 

CHARLES    LYELL  •  458 

CARL    GEGENBAUER  •  498 

RUDOLPH    ALBERT    VON    KOLLIKER  •  498 

MENDEL  •   561 

RICHARD    OWEN  •  561 

THOMAS    HENRY    HUXLEY  •  594 

OSCAR    HERTWIG  •  594 

ERNST    HEINRICH    HAECKEL  •  61I. 

WILHELM    LUDWIG    JOHANNSEN  •  6li 


PART     ONE 


.BIOLOGY    IN    CLASSICAL    ANTIQUITY, 
THE    MIDDLE    AGES, 
AND    THE    RENAISSANCE 


CHAPTER   I 

THE    DEVELOPMENT    OF    BIOLOGY    AMONGST    THE    PRIMITIVE 
PEOPLES     AND    THE    CIVILIZED     NATIONS    OF    THE     EAST 

Primitive  man  s  speculations  upon  life 

THE  EARLIEST  FOUNDATION  of  all  our  natural  scientific  knowledge  is  to 
be  sought  in  the  observations  of  nature  collected  in  the  course  of 
thousands  of  years  by  prehistoric  peoples  who  had  reached  a  primitive 
stage  of  civilization.  This  empirical  folk-knowledge,  which  the  student  of 
folk-lore  in  our  own  day  investigates  from  a  historical  and  national-psycho- 
logical point  of  view,  has  not  only  been  the  starting-point  for  all  scientific 
thought,  but  has  also,  right  up  to  the  most  recent  times,  to  a  certain  extent 
influenced  scientific  research  itself;  increased  its  store  of  facts  with  material 
for  observation  and  even  now  and  then  given  rise  to  problems  which  science 
has  debated.  Primitive  man's  speculations  upon  life  have  naturally  been 
influenced  by  his  mode  of  life  in  various  climates  and  under  varying  con- 
ditions. Common  to  them  all,  however,  would  appear  to  have  been  the  fact 
that  the  first  thing  that  has  induced  man  to  reflect  upon  life  has  been  its 
cessation:  death.  And  to  the  aborigines  what  we  call  a  natural  death  is 
actually  the  most  wonderful;  that  a  man  should  fall  in  a  fight  against  wild 
animals  or  his  enemies  is  all  part  of  the  order  of  the  day,  but  that  the  powers 
of  a  sound  and  healthy  man  should  suddenly  and  without  reason  begin  to 
fail  and  life  to  cease  with  or  without  the  accompaniment  of  pain  —  that  is  a 
thing  one  finds  it  hard  to  acquiesce  in.  And  the  thing  becomes  all  the  more 
remarkable  for  the  fact  that  again  and  again  at  night  the  departed  one  ap- 
pears in  dreams  to  those  who  have  survived  him.  These  dreams  have  given 
rise  to  a  belief  in  ghosts,  spectres,  and  spiritual  powers  of  various  kinds,  both 
friendly  and  evil,  and  this  belief  has  in  its  turn  called  forth  measures  with  a 
view  to  deriving  advantage  from  the  well-disposed  and  avoiding  the  snares 
of  the  wicked.  Thus  measures  of  many  and  various  kinds  were  adopted  in 
regard  to  the  bodies  of  the  dead,  which  were  either  cremated  or  otherwise 
destroyed  in  order  to  render  it  impossible  for  them  to  return  amongst  the  liv- 
ing, or  else,  on  the  other  hand,  they  were  elaborately  cared  for  by  the  preser- 
vation of  the  skeleton  or  by  embalming,  which  was  intended  to  make  the 
dead  well-disposed  towards  their  survivors.  From  these  manipulations  arose 
the  first  knowledge  of  the  anatomy  of  the  human  body,  while  observations 
of  the  actual  course  of  death  created  certain  physiological  ideas.  Men  learnt 

3 


4  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

to  observe  the  heart-beat  and  to  connect  life  with  its  continuance  or  cessa- 
tion, and  thus  the  heart  itself  was  regarded  as  the  organ  of  life.  Breathing 
was  also  observed  to  be  an  essential  condition  of  life,  and  in  particular  the 
deep  expiration  which  indeed  so  often  attends  the  actual  moment  of  death 
gave  rise  to  the  idea  of  life  as  having  something  of  the  nature  of  air,  being 
dependent  upon  the  respiratory  organs  and  leaving  the  body  through  them. 
In  medieval  church  paintings  this  belief  reappears  in  a  particularly  naive 
manner:  the  soul  of  the  dying  is  seen  to  leave  the  body  in  the  form  of  a  little 
child  creeping  out  through  the  mouth.  Likewise  the  words  of  the  biblical 
story  of  the  creation  to  the  effect  that  God  breathed  into  man's  nostrils  the 
breath  of  life  testifies  to  the  same  kind  of  idea.  And  so  there  arose,  as  a  fur- 
ther development  of  these  ideas,  the  belief  that  the  breath  or  spirit  lives 
when  the  body  dies.  The  contrast  between  body  and  spirit  which  is  an  out- 
come of  the  ideas  described  above  is  included  in  the  speculations  of  the  earliest 
natural  philosophers  as  a  fundamental  principle. 

Kelationship  to  animals 
However,  in  the  mind  of  primitive  man  these  lines  of  thought,  proceeding 
from  the  contrast  between  life  and  death,  are  crossed  by  others,  which  have 
their  origin  in  his  relationship  to  the  rest  of  the  world  of  living  creatures. 
The  great  w'ld  beasts  —  bears,  lions,  elephants  —  were  difficult  to  overcome; 
it  was  often  necessary  to  try,  as  far  as  was  possible,  to  make  friends  with 
them.  Other  beasts  were  regarded  with  terror  for  their  night-roving  habits 
and  horrible  cries,  such  as  hyenas  and  owls;  while  some  possessed  otherwise 
enviable  natural  gifts  —  the  fox  his  cunning,  the  deer  his  swiftness,  etc. 
It  is  out  of  all  this  that  we  must  explain  the  origin  of  the  mass  of  animal 
superstition  that  has  filled  the  life  of  both  wild  and  civilized  peoples.  As 
forms  in  which  this  superstition  has  developed  may  be  mentioned  totem- 
ism,  or  the  custom  existing  among  certain  wild  peoples  of  adopting  animals 
as  a  kind  of  guardian  spirit  and  family  symbol,  as  well  as  the  belief  in 
and  worship  of  holy  animals,  which,  even  amongst  highly  civilized  peo- 
ples, such  as  the  Egyptians  and  the  Romans,  have  played  such  an  important 
part  in  life.  This  animal  superstition  has  naturally  contributed  towards 
increasing  the  interest  in  and  knowledge  of  animals,  both  as  regards  the 
habits  of  life  of  those  which  were  worshipped  as  gods,  and  the  anatomy  of 
those  which  were  offered  in  sacrifice  and  were  most  minutely  examined 
with  a  view  to  divining  portents  for  the  future  from  their  internal  structure. 

Primitive  surgery  and  medicine 
Finally,  a  third  extremely  important  source  of  biological  knowledge  has 
been  medical  science.  Primitive  surgery,  which  originated  in  attempts  to 
cure  various  bodily  injuries,  must  of  course  eventually  lead  to  a  certain 
amount  of  knowledge  of  the  anatomy  of  the  human  body,  a  knowledge 
which  was  increased  by  the  process  of  comparison  with  the  experience 


CLASSICAL     ANTIQUITY,     MIDDLE     AGES  5 

gained  from  the  slaughter  of  wild  and  tame  animals.  As  to  the  natural  dis- 
eases, the  same  holds  good  for  these  as  what  has  just  been  mentioned  in 
regard  to  death;  for  lack  of  ability  to  explain  them  naturally,  people  took 
refuge  in  a  belief  in  supernatural  causes.  The  belief  in  enchantments  of  various 
kinds  which  arose  therefrom  and  which  has  been  maintained  even  amongst 
civilized  peoples  for  a  surprisingly  long  time,  fills  one  of  the  darkest  chapters 
in  the  history  of  civilization.  Disasters  of  supernatural  origin  of  course 
demanded  corresponding  remedies,  and  consequently  the  earliest  practice  of 
medical  science  among  all  races  of  mankind  has  been  that  of  magic:  they 
sought  to  remove  the  evil  by  setting  sorcery  against  sorcery.  However,  the 
regular  course  of  certain  processes  of  disease  could  not  fail  to  be  observed 
and  conclusions  drawn  therefrom  as  to  the  functions  of  the  body  in  sickness 
and  health.  By  a  comparison  of  these  observations  a  number  of  primitive  ideas 
were  acquired  on  physiology  and  pathology.  Hand  in  hand  with  this  was 
evolved  the  theory  of  pharmacology,  based  on  experiments  —  originally  for 
the  most  part  for  magical  purposes  —  with  plants  which  experience  proved 
to  be  poisonous  or  otherwise  capable  of  affecting  the  life-process.  Through 
observations  of  this  kind  the  knowledge  of  life  was  still  further  enhanced. 
It  was  not  given,  however,  to  just  anyone  to  acquire  all  this  knowledge,  the 
origins  and  development  of  which  have  been  described  above.  The  super- 
natural and  mysterious  elements  in  them  made  them  a  privilege  for  cer- 
tain qualified  persons:  magicians,  sorcerers,  sacrificial  priests.  Among  these 
classes  of  people  they  were  shared  and  handed  down  as  professional  secrets, 
until  in  course  of  time  a  division  of  them  took  place  —  the  magical  and  ritual 
customs  became  the  professional  sphere  of  the  priests,  while  the  amassed 
knowledge  of  nature,  released  from  the  obstructive  bonds  of  magic,  was  de- 
veloped by  independent  inquirers  into  a  free  sphere  of  learning.  The  people 
amongst  whom  this  independent  natural  science  first  arose  were  the  Greeks. 
But  long  before  Greek  culture  appears  in  history,  the  people  of  the  East 
had  already  bequeathed  historical  evidences  of  their  civilization,  and  these 
deserve  all  the  more  to  be  carefully  examined  for  such  contributions  to  bio- 
logical knowledge  as  they  may  have  to  show,  seeing  that  the  whole  of 
Greek  culture  was  so  highly  influenced  by  the  oriental. 

Babylonian  science 
The  earliest  home  of  human  civilization  is  now  generally  supposed  to  have 
been  Babylon,  and  a  high  standard  of  culture  was  maintained  there  under 
the  dominion  of  various  types  of  peoples  up  to  the  latter  part  of  the  Mid- 
dle Ages.  The  "oriental  wisdom"  which  has  played  such  an  important  part 
in  the  mystical  literature  of  all  times  also  originates  from  there  through 
a  more  or  less  varying  number  of  intermediate  stages.  Actually,  the  mys- 
tical and  the  magical  have  from  the  earliest  times  played  a  predominant 
role  in  that  country's  learning,  undoubtedly  owing  to  the  fact   that  all 


6  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

knowledge  was  nurtured  and  developed  by  a  powerful  priesthood.  The 
conception  of  nature  was  influenced  thereby:  the  early  knowledge  of  as- 
tronomy was  placed  at  the  service  of  mystical  powers,  as  were  also  mathe- 
matics and  medicine.  The  latter  science,  however,  in  certain  respects  made 
no  small  progress.  The  knowledge  of  anatomy  was  considerable;  preserved 
clay-models  of  certain  of  the  viscera  of  the  body  prove  this  and  give  evi- 
dence that  the  dissection  of  corpses  must  have  taken  place  in  spite  of  the 
horror  which  Orientals  have  always  felt  for  the  dead  and  their  spirits. 
It  is  clear  from  preserved  writings  on  medicine  that  the  heart  was  re- 
garded as  the  organ  of  intelligence,  and  the  liver  as  that  of  the  blood-cir- 
culation; the  blood  was  divided  into  "light"  and  "dark"  blood  —  arterial 
and  venous.  The  knowledge  of  higher  animal  forms  was,  as  extant  lists  of 
nomenclature  go  to  prove,  quite  considerable,  and  kings  and  princes  kept 
rare  live  animals  in  their  gardens.  Even  animal-doctors  are  mentioned  in 
preserved  inscriptions. 

Egyptian  medicine  and  natural  knowledge 
Again,  in  the  other  oldest  civilized  country  of  the  West,  Egypt,  there  was 
developed  at  an  early  period  an  art  of  healing  which  was  based  not  merely 
upon  superstition,  but  also  upon  actual  observations.  The  early  perfected 
religious  practice  of  preserving  dead  bodies  from  putrefaction  by  con- 
serving the  skeleton  and,  later,  by  embalming  offered  an  opportunity  of 
acquiring  anatomical  knowledge  which  proved  of  great  benefit  to  medical 
science.  The  sacred  animals  were  likewise  studied  with  minute  care,  and 
writings  have  been  discovered  giving  in  detail  the  history  of  the  develop- 
ment of  the  sacred  scarab,  and  even  the  metamorphosis  of  the  frog  and  the 
fly.  The  parasitic  worms  that  so  infected  Egypt  were  also  objects  of  investi- 
gation and  speculation. 

Israelitic  conception  of  nature 
With  regard,  finally,  to  the  Israelitic  people,  their  cultural  contribution 
has  been  in  a  sphere  entirely  different  from  the  natural-scientific;  namely, 
the  ethical-religious.  Their  material,  and  thereby  also  their  scientific,  cul- 
ture was  borrowed  from  the  earlier  developed  and  powerful  neighbouring 
peoples  and  may  therefore  be  passed  over  here.  Nevertheless  the  Israelitic 
conception  of  nature  as  preserved  in  the  Old  Testament,  has,  owing  to  reli- 
gious causes,  right  up  to  our  own  day  had  a  deeply  significant  influence.  The 
part  played  by  the  six  days'  creation  as  a  co-determining  factor  even  in  purely 
scientific  explanations  of  the  world  is  too  well  known  to  need  close  exami- 
nation. Likewise  the  ordinances  of  the  Mosaic  law  regarding  clean  and 
unclean  animals  have  had  their  great  importance  for  the  conceptions  of 
nature  held  by  the  Christian  peoples,  while  even  the  well-known  problem 
of  the  ruminant  hare  is  still  today  a  subject  of  lively  discussion  in  cer- 
tain circles.  And  undoubtedly,  even  in  the  far  distant  future,  the  religious- 


CLASSICAL     ANTIQUITY,     MIDDLE     AGES  7 

dogmatic  currents  of  thought  which  have  always  had,  and  indeed  always 
will  have,  a  powerful  influence  on  the  development  of  human  culture  will 
receive  guidance  from  this  quarter. 

Hindu  and  Chinese  science 
The  civilized  peoples  of  eastern  Asia,  the  Hindus  and  Chinese,  have  like- 
wise contributed  very  little  of  importance  to  the  development  of  the  science 
of  biology.  Hindu  science,  indeed,  especially  in  the  sphere  of  mathematics, 
reached  a  high  standard,  and  the  tendency  to  employ  figures  even  in  the 
other  branches  of  learning  which  this  people  cultivated  is  unmistakable. 
Thus  a  Hindu  work  on  medicine  states  that  the  human  body  has  seven  skins, 
300  bones,  107  joints,  900  tendons,  700  blood-vessels,  and  500  nerves.  But 
they  had  very  primitive  ideas  as  to  the  functions  of  these  organs,  and 
similarly  the  various  fluids  and  kinds  of  air  which  provide  for  the  body's 
renewal  are  of  interest  to  them  more  from  the  numerical  than  from  the  func- 
tional point  of  view.  Chinese  culture,  again,  has  essentially  occupied  itself 
with  ethical  and  social  problems.  Chinese  medicine  has  on  the  whole  ad- 
vanced little  beyond  that  of  primitive  peoples,  although  certain  isolated 
instances  of  progress  achieved —  for  example,  smallpox  inoculation — might 
perhaps  be  traced  back  to  the  experiences  of  this  people.  Even  pure  zoology 
has  on  the  whole  made  no  advance;  as  early  as  about  a  thousand  years  before 
Christ  mention  is  made  of  an  imperial  zoological  garden,  but  the  thorough 
study  of  the  causal  connexion  in  living  nature  did  not  come  within  the 
sphere  of  Chinese  interest. 


CHAPTER    II 

THE    EARLIEST    GREEK    NATURAL    PHILOSOPHY 

The  Greeks:  creators  of  natural  science 

IF  THE  Babylonians  and  Egyptians  thus  succeeded  in  collecting  quite  a  con- 
siderable  mass  of  individual  facts  of  science,  it  was  nevertheless  left  to  the 
Greek  nation  to  deduce  from  these  facts  a  consistently  realized  conception 
of  nature  —  not  free  from  mystical  and  magical  influences,  it  is  true,  but  still 
striving  more  and  more  after  a  natural  explanation  of  the  laws  of  existence. 
There  has  been  much  speculation  as  to  why  it  should  be  amongst  just  this 
people,  who  were  not  only  few  in  number,  but  were  also  politically  divided, 
that  such  a  splendid  development  of  human  thought  should  have  taken 
place.  The  deepest  cause  is  surely  to  be  sought  in  the  much  discussed,  yet 
fundamentally  so  inexplicable  national  character,  in  the  spiritual  and  cul- 
tural disposition  of  the  people.  It  may,  at  any  rate,  be  worth  while  briefly 
considering  its  manifestations  in  the  social  sphere,  in  order  to  gain  some 
idea  of  the  external  conditions  of  development  under  which  free  thought 
was  here  able  to  expand. 

The  people  of  Greece,  as  is  well  known,  never  achieved  political  unity; 
it  remained  divided  into  a  number  of  small  communities  independent  of 
one  another,  consisting  usually  of  a  city  with  its  surrounding  country  dis- 
trict. Trade  and  shipping  rather  than  agriculture  were  the  people's  main 
source  of  income.  Over-population  gave  rise  to  splendid  colonizing  activity 
along  the  coasts  of  the  Mediterranean;  the  colonies,  which  from  the  very 
beginning  were  made  independent  of  the  mother  city,  adopted  the  latter's 
institutions.  A  strong  national  feeling  prevailed  everywhere  and  was  main- 
tained by  law  and  custom.  Outside  the  boundaries  of  his  own  town  the  Greek 
was  a  foreigner  without  rights,  without  the  possibility  of  acquiring  civic 
privileges  elsewhere,  and  with  no  prospect  of  winning  the  consolations  of 
religion.  Religion  was  in  fact  as  localized  as  the  communities  themselves; 
every  town  had  its  own  gods,  which  could  be  worshipped  only  by  its  citi- 
zens and  within  its  boundaries.  Such  a  local  form  of  religion  was  naturally 
primitive  and  remained  so  even  at  the  time  when  Greek  culture  was  at  its 
zenith.  It  was  just  on  account  of  this  lack  of  a  more  highly  developed  re- 
ligion, however,  that  free  thought  was  able  to  develop  as  it  did.  Here  there 
was  no  priesthood,  as  there  was  in  Babylon,  Egypt,  and  India,  to  reserve  to 
itself  alone  the  right  to  the  higher  learning  and  to  ensure  that  its  results 

8 


CLASSICAL     ANTIQUITY,     MIDDLE     AGES  9 

did  not  conflict  with  the  ancient  religious  usages.  The  religious  persecutions 
that  occasionally  took  place  in  Greece  against  thinkers,  as,  for  instance, 
against  Socrates,  were  rather  the  work  of  the  mob  than  of  the  defenders  of 
religion  and  were  therefore  of  a  purely  incidental  and  transitory  nature.  On 
the  other  hand,  we  find  that  many  of  Greece's  oldest  philosophers  were 
priests  or  at  any  rate  the  sons  of  priests.  And  just  as  religion  in  ancient 
Greece  was  primitive,  so  also  were  the  moral  ideas:  provided  the  citizen 
obeyed  the  ancient  laws  of  the  State,  he  need  not  worry  much  about  what 
further  duties  were  owed  to  his  nearest  and  to  himself.  Thought  was  thus 
at  liberty  to  turn  to  external  nature  and  devote  itself  to  speculations  on 
how  things  arose  and  why  the  world  and  the  living  creatures  in  it  were 
formed  just  as  they  were.  The  oldest  Greek  thinkers  were  therefore  natural 
philosophers,  while  it  was  not  till  later  that  the  ethical  problems  —  which, 
for  instance,  among  the  thinkers  of  the  Jewish  people,  the  prophets,  had 
from  the  very  beginning  dominated  the  soul  —  through  Socrates  found  a 
place  in  Greek  thought  and  finally,  in  late  classical  times,  entirely  sup- 
planted the  interest  in  nature  and  its  phenomena. 

These,  mankind's  earliest  natural  philosophers,  went  about  their  work 
under  conditions  which  in  most  respects  were  utterly  primitive.  The  general 
education  amongst  their  neighbours  was  extremely  limited  and  far  from  wide- 
spread —  in  fact,  throughout  the  whole  of  the  classical  period  of  Greek  cul- 
ture it  was  confined  to  a  very  few.  The  public  instruction  provided  by  the  State 
for  the  benefit  of  its  citizens  was  of  the  simplest  kind;  in  Athens  in  the  time 
of  Pericles,  when  the  greatest  philosophers  and  poets  of  Greece  were  as- 
sembled there,  the  citizens  had  to  learn  in  the  State  schools  only  the  simplest 
rudiments  of  reading,  writing,  and  arithmetic,  besides  music  and  gymnastics, 
which  were  necessary  for  military  service,  while  it  is  said  that  at  the  same 
period  in  the  more  conservative  country  of  Sparta  the  majority  of  the  peo- 
ple were  illiterate.  Anything  that  the  private  individual  wished  to  study 
beyond  that,  he  had  to  find  out  for  himself  as  best  he  could.  Nor  were 
there  in  ancient  times  any  private  professional  teachers.  If  a  person  of  studi- 
ous mind  happened  to  belong  to  a  family  connected  with  the  priesthood, 
its  traditional  learning  was  naturally  at  his  disposal  as  a  foundation;  for 
the  rest  he  had  to  rely  upon  whatever  knowledge  he  could  acquire  in  his 
own  city  from  foreign  travellers  and  such  of  his  countrymen  as  had  travelled 
abroad,  unless  he  himself  was  rich  enough  to  travel  and  visit  learned  men 
in  their  own  homes.  Fortunately  hospitality  in  Greece  in  ancient  times  knew 
no  bounds;  in  actual  fact  it  took  the  place  of  learned  schools  and  universities 
and  even  of  books  and  writings.  For  if  the  knowledge  of  writing  was  rare, 
this  was  to  a  great  extent  due  to  the  difficulty  of  obtaining  writing-materials. 
The  Egyptians  had  discovered  a  cheap  material  in  their  papyrus,  the  Chaldees 
another  in  their  clay  tablets,  but  the  ancient  Greeks  had  nothing  but  metal 


lO  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

tablets  and  animal  hides,  both  of  which  were  expensive  to  get  and  incon- 
venient to  preserve.  The  learned  therefore  had  to  express  their  opinions  in 
short  and  weighty  compositions,  preferably  in  the  form  of  verse,  so  that  they 
could  be  easily  learnt  by  heart.  Thus  learning  became  the  asset  of  a  privi- 
leged few;  they  had  to  be  wealthy  in  order  to  be  able  to  undertake  the 
journeys  that  were  essential  for  the  acquiring  of  knowledge,  and  of  high 
standing  in  order  to  be  able,  both  at  home  and  abroad,  to  gain  access  to 
the  masters  who  were  primed  with  the  wisdom  of  the  period.  But  in  point 
of  fact  the  scholars  of  those  days  were  highly  respected:  the  various  states 
summoned  them  to  be  lawgivers  and  rulers,  paid  the  expenses  of  their 
costly  journeys,  and  gave  them  financial  assistance  when  they  ruined  them- 
selves over  their  research  work.  On  the  other  hand,  they  were  often  per- 
secuted by  hostile  political  factions  and  were  sometimes  condemned  to  end 
their  days  in  exile. 

The  earliest  scientists  of  Greece:  the  Ionian  philosophers 
The  earliest  of  these  Greek  natural  philosophers,  the  so-called  Ionic  philos- 
ophers, all  lived  in,  or  at  any  rate  originated  from,  the  colonies  which 
the  Ionic  tribes  of  Greece  founded  on  the  coast  of  Asia  Minor.  Through 
trading  with  the  Orient  these  cities  rapidly  grew  wealthy,  and  through 
contact  with  the  more  highly  cultivated  peoples  of  the  East  there  arose  a 
keen  desire  for  knowledge,  and  means  for  satisfying  it  were  obtainable. 
Chaldean  and  Egyptian  travellers  were  able  to  tell  of  the  great  learning  of 
their  priests  and  physicians;  journeys  to  the  East  gave  the  ambitious  lonians 
opportunities  of  acquiring  at  least  something  of  that  secret  knowledge. 
And  on  this  foundation  they  themselves  built  further.  —  Nature  presented  a 
great  number  of  phenomena  in  constant  variation,  and  herein  it  was  proved 
that  certain  phenomena  always  stood  in  a  certain  regular  relation  to  one 
another.  A  common  primary  cause  of  the  variations  of  existence  had  to  be  dis- 
covered —  a  common  element  out  of  which  everything  originated.  What  was 
this  primary  element  and  how  have  things  originated  from  it?  These  two 
questions  occupied  the  minds  of  the  Ionian  thinkers.  Nature,  the  Greek 
(pixTLs,  became  the  one  great  problem,  and  these  ancient  philosophers  who 
studied  the  problem  of  nature  were  therefore  called  physicists,  a  name  which 
later  on  was  reserved  for  those  who  carried  out  research  in  a  limited  sphere 
of  natural  science.  The  investigations  carried  out  by  these  ancient  physicists, 
however,  led  them  just  as  often  into  the  realms  of  metaphysics,  and  it  is 
just  that  lack  of  insight  into  the  insuperable  bounds  of  natural  science  that 
gave  to  their  speculations  that  vague  and  fantastic  character  which  is  so 
conspicuous  in  them. 

As  one  of  the  earliest  of  the  natural  philosophers  in  Greece  is  mentioned 
Thales  of  Miletus.  Even  in  ancient  times  very  little  was  known  of  his  life 
and  activities    The  very  epoch  in  which  he  and  his  immediate  successors 


CLASSICAL     ANTIQUITY,     MIDDLE     AGES        II 

lived  has  been  so  variously  stated  that  the  dates  differ  by  centuries.  It  is 
most  generally  assumed,  hov^ever,  that  he  lived  between  650  and  580  b.c. 
Historians  agree  in  declaring  that  he  .left  no  writings;  perhaps  he  was  not 
even  able  to  write.  He  was  probably  of  Phoenician  origin  —  some  assert  that 
he  immigrated  from  Phoenicia.  At  any  rate  it  is  clear  that  he  had  educated 
himself  by  travelling  and  studying  in  the  East.  He  was  very  rich  and  of  high 
standing  and  collected  around  him  a  number  of  disciples.  Of  his  philosophy 
it  is  mentioned  that  he  regarded  water  as  the  cause  of  all  things.  The  earth 
floated  like  a  disk  on  a  vast  sea  which  surrounded  it  on  all  sides.  The  details 
of  his  philosophy  are  unknown,  but  the  assumption  mentioned  above  is  to 
a  certain  extent  reminiscent  of  the  story  of  the  creation  in  Genesis,  with 
its  definite  assertion  of  "waters  which  were  under  the  firmament"  and 
"waters  which  were  above  the  firmament."  That  we  are  here  dealing  with 
a  theory  of  oriental  origin  seems  beyond  all  doubt.  That  Thales  was  the 
pioneer  of  the  Greek  natural  philosophy  is  undeniable;  he  is  unanimously 
acclaimed  as  such  by  the  thinkers  of  antiquity.  The  very  name  of  philosopher 
and  philosophy  probably  originates  from  him.  Once  asked  whether  he  was 
a  wise  man  (cto^os  in  Greek),  he  modestly  replied  that  he  could  not  call 
himself  one;  he  was  merely  a  lover  of  wisdom  (0tX6o-o<^os) . 

A  younger  fellow-countryman  of  Thales,  and  in  all  probability  a  disciple 
of  his,  was  Anaximander,  who  lived  approximately  between  the  years  611 
and  546  B.C.  Concerning  his  life  and  personality  about  as  little  is  known 
as  of  that  of  Thales.  On  the  other  hand,  it  is  known  that  he  described 
the  results  of  his  scientific  researches  in  a  poem  On  Nature  (jrepi  (i>v(Ttb:s), 
which  is  quoted  by  several  later  philosophers.  Even  Aristotle  declares  that 
he  had  read  it,  but  it  seems  to  have  been  lost  as  early  as  the  later  classical 
period;  the  people  of  antiquity  had  not  such  great  respect  for  "classical" 
authors  as  we  have  in  our  time.  Through  quotations  and  references  in  the 
writings  of  later  authors,  however,  it  is  possible  to  form  some  idea  of  this, 
the  first  work  on  natural  science  ever  written.  Just  as  for  Thales,  the  most 
important  question  for  him  is:  What  is  the  material  cause  of  the  universe? 
As  mentioned  above,  Thales  held  that  water  was  the  causal  principle; 
Anaximander  conceives  it  to  be  "apeiron"  (aireipov),  from  which  he 
supposed  the  things  on  earth  to  develop  themselves  and  into  which  he 
supposed  them  to  return.  What  he  actually  meant  by  this  "apeiron"  it  is 
difficult  to  say,  but  the  word  probably  means  "  the  quality-less,  the  indeter- 
minate." Out  of  this  primordial  cause  have  arisen  heat  and  cold,  from  these 
water,  and  from  that  again  earth,  air,  and  fire,  which  last  surrounds  the 
atmosphere  and  is  radiated  through  the  stars.  The  earth  came  into  being 
through  a  kind  of  condensation  of  water;  it  was  originally  composed  of 
pristine  mud  and  then  became  solid  and  floats  as  such  on  the  water,  in  form 
like  a  spherical  segment  —  that  is,  very  much  like  a  loaf.  He  is  said  to  have 


II  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

designed  a  map  of  the  world  and  even  to  have  made  a  celestial  globe  of  spheri- 
cal form,  with  the  earth  suspended  in  the  centre  of  the  circular  vault.  Living 
beings  he  conceives  as  having  evolv.ed  through  a  kind  of  primordial  pro- 
creation in  the  mud  which  formerly  covered  the  earth.  Thus,  first  there 
arose  animals  and  plants,  and  then  human  beings,  who,  originally  formed 
like  fishes,  lived  in  the  water,  but  afterwards  cast  off  their  fish-skin,  went 
up  on  dry  land  and  thenceforth  lived  there.  We  see,  then,  that  Anaximander 
produced  a  complete  theory  of  evolution,  childishly  clumsy,  it  is  true,  but 
interesting  for  the  audacity  with  which  he  deduced  his  conclusions  from 
his  premisses.  Nor  is  he  afraid  of  letting  the  world-process  continue  into  in- 
finity; the  present  universe  has  been  preceded  by  others,  which  were  evolved 
out  of  the  primordial  element  and  returned  once  more  to  it,  and  so  it  will 
always  continue.  We  should  not  go  too  far,  however,  in  making  a  comparison 
between  the  ancient  Ionian's  theory  of  creation  and  the  evolution  theory  of 
our  own  day.  An  attempt  has  been  made  to  prove  him  a  predecessor  to  Dar- 
win on  the  ground  of  his  above-mentioned  conceptions  of  the  origin  of 
man.  This  is  an  entirely  unhistorical  view  of  the  matter,  although  an  easily 
accountable  one;  highly  debatable  theories  have  always  sought  for  direct 
predecessors  as  far  back  in  time  as  possible.  Anaximander's  theory  of  the 
origin  of  man  is  in  reality  most  reminiscent  of  his  fellow-countrymen's 
legends  of  autochthonism  — ■  stories  of  how  men  were  born  of  the  earth  they 
lived  on,  which  was  one  of  the  very  popular  myths  of  these  periods  of  migra- 
tion of  peoples,  whereby  they  sought  to  justify  their  title  to  the  country 
they  possessed  on,  as  it  were,  semi-natural,  semi-divine  grounds.  But  if  we 
must  exercise  caution  in  gauging  the  speculations  of  Anaximander  by  modern 
standards,  they  at  any  rate  are  worthy  of  our  high  admiration.  Natural  re- 
search in  our  own  day  endeavours  to  discover  an  explanation,  based  on  a  nat- 
ural connexion  of  causes,  of  the  origin  of  things  and  of  the  variations  they 
present,  and  the  philosopher  who  was  the  first  to  realize  the  necessity  of 
such  a  natural  explanation  and  who  worked  it  out,  although  incompletely, 
must  be  regarded  in  all  ages  as  one  of  the  pioneers  of  human  thought.  The 
religious-poetical  myths  of  the  creation,  which  up  to  that  time  had  had  to 
serve  amongst  the  Greeks,  as  in  the  East,  for  an  explanation  of  the  cosmos, 
became  from  this  time  part  of  the  sphere  of  poetry  and  the  life  of  religious 
faith,  while  scientific  research  went  on  building  upon  the  foundations  laid 
down  by  Anaximander. 

Among  his  contemporaries  Anaximander  enjoyed  a  high  reputation,  and 
several  of  his  disciples  are  mentioned  in  history.  In  his  native  city  his  work 
was  carried  on  by  Anaximenes,  who  chose  air  for  his  principle  and  considered 
that  this  not  only  enveloped  the  world,  but  also  penetrated  living  beings 
and  represented  their  life-principle.  Shortly  after  his  death  the  city  of  Miletus 
was  ravaged  by  the  Persians  and  razed  to  the  ground  (494  b.c),  and  with 


CLASSICAL     ANTIQUITY,     MIDDLE     AGES       13 

that  the  city  of  Thales  and  Anaximander  disappears  for  ever  from  cultural 
history.  Their  theories,  however,  had  been  widely  dispersed,  and  when  the 
Asiatic  Greeks  lost  their  cultural  supremacy,  philosophers  and  philosophic 
schools  were  already  to  be  found  scattered  throughout  the  world  of  Greek 
culture. 

Thus  Diogenes  of  Apollonia,  in  Crete,  is  regarded  as  one  of  the  Ionian 
school  of  philosophy.  He  lived  in  the  first  half  of  the  fifth  century  and  is  not 
to  be  confused  with  the  more  famous  Cynic  Diogenes,  who  lived  in  the  time 
of  Alexander  the  Great.  His  explanation  of  the  universe  is  based  on  An- 
aximenes'  theory  of  air  as  the  primary  matter.  Out  of  the  air  are  formed  all 
other  elements  in  the  world  through  a  process  of  condensation.  He  conceives 
life  to  consist  of  warm  air  moving  like  currents  through  the  veins  and  thus 
preserving  the  strength  in  the  body.  Diogenes  has  described  the  ramifications 
of  the  venous  system  in  man,  or  rather  in  mammals,  and  this  description  is 
still  partially  extant  —  the  earliest  anatomical  work  known.  For  the  rest, 
we  know  of  Diogenes  that  he  conceived  living  beings  to  have  been  produced 
out  of  the  earth  through  the  influence  of  solar  heat  —  that  is  to  say,  a  fur- 
ther development  of  Anaximander's  theory.  Also,  he  believed  that  the 
embryo  in  the  uterus  was  developed  by  the  warmth  of  the  mother  out  of 
the  semen  of  the  father.  His  embryological  statements  must  therefore,  like 
his  anatomical  ideas,  have  been  based  on  dissection.  A  contemporary  of 
his  was  Hippo,  who  is  also  said  to  have  engaged  in  embryological  research. 
Unfortunately  we  know  very  little  about  him;  we  are  not  even  certain  of  his 
birthplace,  which  some  say  was  the  Isle  of  Samos  and  others  Rhegium,  in 
the  south  of  Italy.  His  reputation  as  a  philosopher  seems  to  have  been  in- 
ferior to  his  fame  as  a  naturalist,  which  is  largely  the  reason  for  his  having 
been  almost  forgotten.  He  is  said  to  have  maintained  Thales'  theory  of 
water  as  the  origin  of  matter. 

This  survey  of  the  old  Ionic  natural  philosophy  shows  that  there  was  a 
serious  attempt  made  to  discover  a  natural  connexion  in  the  events  of  earth, 
in  the  existence,  origin,  and  decay  of  matter.  However,  partly  through  the 
adoption  and  development  of  its  ideas  and  partly  through  fresh  influences 
from  the  East,  there  grew  up  side  by  side  with  it  other  lines  of  thought,  hav- 
ing in  some  ways  a  deeper  vision  of  the  phenomena  of  life,  but  at  the  same 
time  also  a  tendency  to  mysticism  and  fanciful  ideas  which  had  been  foreign 
to  the  Ionian  philosophers.  Although  it  was  not  particularly  interested  in 
biological  research,  it  is  necessary  here  to  mention  the  Pythagorean  philoso- 
phy, owing  to  the  important  part  it  plays  in  the  history  of  culture  in  general. 
Its  founder,  Pythagoras,  is  one  of  the  most  extraordinary  figures  in  cultural 
history.  Scientist,  religious  prophet,  and  statesman,  mathematician,  and  mys- 
tic all  in  one,  he  has  become  in  the  tradition  of  posterity  a  purely  legendary 
figure.  Born  in  Samos  off  the  coast  of  Asia  Minor,  he  travelled  widely  in  the 


14  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

East  —  how  far  is  not  known  with  any  certainty  —  and  afterwards  taught 
in  his  native  island,  but  on  account  of  political  disturbances  he  was  forced 
to  migrate  to  the  Greek  colony  of  Croton  in  the  south  of  Italy.  There  he 
carried  on  as  a  research-worker  and  religious  and  social  reformer  until  his 
death,  probably  about  the  year  500  b.c.  His  dates  are  in  any  case  highly 
uncertain  and  much  disputed.  There  is  no  doubt  that  much  of  the  wisdom 
he  taught  emanated  from  the  East;  his  famous  theory  of  the  wandering  of 
the  soul,  for  instance,  already  existed  in  India  long  before  his  time,  and  the 
geometrical  theorem  named  after  him  had  already  been  proved  by  Indian 
mathematicians  long  before  he  lived.  His  cosmological  theories,  however, 
are  extremely  interesting.  He  conceived  fire  to  be  the  origin  of  matter.  It 
should  be  borne  in  mind  that  to  the  people  of  antiquity  and  to  many  suc- 
ceeding generations  fire  was  not  a  chemical  process,  but  an  element,  like  air, 
water,  and  earth.  Pythagoras  believed  that  all  things  originated  in  a  primor- 
dial fire  forming  the  centre  of  the  cosmos.  Around  this  primordial  fire  re- 
volve all  the  celestial  bodies,  the  earth,  the  planets,  and  the  sun.  The  shape 
of  the  celestial  bodies  is  spherical  and  their  orbits  circular.  This  cosmology, 
as  compared  with  that  of  the  lonians,  represented  an  immense  advance. 
Through  him  the  fact  of  the  globular  shape  of  the  celestial  bodies  was  in- 
troduced into  science,  although  it  took  a  thousand  years  to  penetrate  the 
consciousness  of  the  world  in  general.  Still  more  remarkable  was  his  theory 
of  the  earth  as  a  moving,  revolving  body.  This  theory  the  people  of  antiquity 
found  it  impossible  to  accept;  ^  Copernicus  was  the  first  to  take  up  the  theory 
anew  and  was  actually  accused  by  his  opponents  of  Pythagoreanism.  In 
the  sphere  of  mathematics  Pythagoras  was  also  a  pioneer;  he  discovered  the 
regularity  of  number-series  and  was  led  by  his  speculations  in  mathematics 
to  propound  the  fanciful  and  mystical  theory  that  numbers  govern  matter, 
and  even  that  numbers  are  the  principle  of  matter.  Further,  he  even  included 
tonal  harmony  in  music  in  this  mystical  system  of  thought;  his  theories  on 
the  "harmony  of  the  spheres"  are  as  well  known  by  name  as  they  are  diffi- 
cult to  understand  in  substance. 

Pythagoras'  influence  on  scientific  development  was  very  great  and  was 
also  considerable  in  the  political  life  of  his  day.  His  disciples  founded  a 
strict  order,  or  kind  of  sect,  which  worshipped  in  Pythagoras  a  divinely 
inspired  prophet.  Persecuted  during  the  most  brilliant  period  of  Greek 
democracy  for  their  pronounced  aristocratism,  they  were  finally  dispersed, 
but  their  teachings  experienced  a  revival  in  late  classical  times. 

"The  Greeks  of  the  West 
With  Pythagoras  the  nationality  of  western  Greece  assumes  a  place  in 
scientific  history.  Southern  Italy  as  far  as  Naples,  as  well  as  Sicily,  had  been 

*  Aristarchus  of  Samos  taught,  it  is  true,  at  a  far  later  period  that  the  sun  is  the  centre 
around  which  the  earth  revolves,  but  this  theory  soon  fell  into  oblivion. 


CLASSICAL     ANTIQUITY,     MIDDLE     AGES       15 

colonized  by  the  Greeks  at  an  early  period,  and  by  the  extermination  or  the 
assimilation  of  the  aboriginals  a  homogeneous  Greek  nationality  had  grown 
up  here,  split  up  into  small  states,  as  in  the  mother  country,  and  living,  if 
possible,  under  still  worse  conditions  of  political  unrest.  But  their  intellec- 
tual culture  rivalled  that  of  the  Asiatic  cities.  A  peculiarity  of  the  western 
Greek  philosophers  was  that  a  number  of  them  were,  like  Pythagoras, 
imaginative  prophets  and  imperious  statesmen,  and  at  the  same  time  keen 
research-workers,  while  they  founded  schools  of  a  far  stricter  order  than 
their  Ionian  predecessors.  One  philosophic  school  of  this  kind  was  the 
Eleatic  school,  called  after  the  city  of  Elea,  in  southern  Italy.  There  came  to 
this  city  at  the  end  of  the  sixth  century  b.c.  a  man  whose  name  was  Xenoph- 
ANEs,  born  at  Colophon  in  Asia  Minor  and  a  disciple  of  Anaximander. 
Disturbances  in  his  native  city  had  driven  him  into  exile  and  he  had  wandered 
far  and  wide  in  the  greatest  poverty,  supporting  himself  by  reciting  his  own 
poems  in  the  towns  he  visited.  Finally  in  Elea  he  found  a  place  of  refuge 
and  died  there  about  490  at  a  very  advanced  age.  The  results  of  his  scientific 
researches  he  has  described  in  a  poem,  similar  to  his  master  Anaximander's 
treatise  On  Nature.  Some  fragments  of  this  poem  are  still  extant.  In  spite  of 
the  extraordinary  audacity  of  the  ideas  which  it  contained,  it  won  its  author 
a  great  reputation  and  a  large  number  of  disciples.  He  based  his  ideas  on 
Anaximander's  theory  of  the  origin  of  the  world  through  the  condensation  of 
water  and  primordial  mud,  and  he  developed  it  still  further.  Of  interest  in 
this  connexion  is  his  pointing  out  fossilized  marine  animals  high  up  in  the 
mountains,  which  he  declared  to  be  a  proof  that  the  mountains  were  at  one 
time  under  water.  These  ideas  were  neglected,  mainly  owing  to  the  fact  that 
Aristotle  and  his  disciples  regarded  fossilization  as  one  of  the  "lusus  natura." 
It  was  not  until  the  Renaissance  that  Xenophanes'  more  correct  views  once 
more  came  into  their  own.  But  speculations  as  to  the  origin  of  the  world 
drove  Xenophanes  further  and  further  over  to  purely  theological  problems. 
He  became  a  keen  and  eloquent  opponent  of  his  fellow-countrymen's  belief 
in  a  plurality  of  gods,  which  he  despised  on  account  of  their  purely  human 
limitations;  horses  and  oxen,  he  declared,  would,  if  they  thought  as  men, 
imagine  gods  in  the  form  of  horses  and  oxen.  On  the  other  hand,  he  for  his 
part  maintained  the  eternity  and  unfathomableness  of  divinity,  and  con- 
sistently therewith  the  eternity,  unity,  and  immutability  of  the  world  in 
which  we  live.  This  did  not  prevent  him,  however,  from  embracing  Anaxi- 
mander's theory  of  alternating  evolution  and  annihilation  of  the  earth  and 
all  that  lives  on  it.  But  it  was  the  theory  of  immutability  that  his  disciples 
further  developed.  The  most  famous  of  these,  Parmenides  of  Elea,  vigorously 
maintains  the  unity  of  being.  The  world  is  conceivable,  he  declared,  only  if 
we  disregard  the  variations  and  changes  and  seek  the  immutable.  In  this 
connexion  he  warns  us  against  relying  upon  the  senses,  whose  judgment  is 


l6  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

misleading  and  from  which  he  appeals  to  reason.  His  abstract  conception  is 
also  seen  in  the  antitheses  by  which  he  expresses  existence:  hot  as  opposed  to 
cold,  light  as  opposed  to  darkness,  the  "ent"  (being)  as  opposed  to  the  "«<?«- 
ent"  (not-being).  In  regard  to  man,  he  conceived  the  soul,  which  to  him  was 
the  same  thing  as  life,  as  hot  and  the  body  as  cold.  For  the  rest,  he  accepted 
Anaximander's  theory  of  the  origin  of  living  creatures  and  the  doctrine  of 
the  Pythagoreans  as  to  the  globular  form  of  the  celestial  bodies.  His  great- 
est service  to  mankind  lies  in  his  insistence  upon  logical  consistency  in 
thinking;  in  this  he  far  outstripped  the  Ionian  philosophers  and  strongly 
influenced  the  thinkers  of  the  ages  that  followed.  The  later  Eleatics  finally 
pursued  the  theory  of  immutability  to  sheer  absurdity  and  thereby  rendered  it 
untenable.  The  Eleatic  Zeno,  for  instance,  denied  all  change  and  even  motion. 
Of  far  greater  importance  for  the  development  of  biology  than  the 
Eleatics,  however,  was  another  western  Greek  philosopher,  Empedocles, 
of  Acragas,  in  Sicily.  His  period  of  activity  is  generally  placed  in  the  middle 
of  the  fifth  century.  Around  his  personality  and  way  of  life  there  has  grown 
up,  as  around  Pythagoras,  a  number  of  legendary  tales,  which  prove,  if 
nothing  else,  that  he  must  have  very  greatly  impressed  both  his  contempo- 
raries and  posterity.  And  this  seems  to  have  been  very  much  his  own  inten- 
tion. He  boasts  about  himself  in  the  writings,  fragments  of  which  have  been 
preserved  to  us,  concerning  his  own  supernatural  gifts;  he  claims  that  he  has 
power  to  heal  the  sick  and  cure  the  infirmity  of  old  age,  raise  the  dead, 
change  the  direction  of  the  wind,  and  bring  rain  and  sunshine  upon  the  earth. 
And  he  delights  in  being  acclaimed;  adorned  with  chaplets  and  flowers,  he 
goes  in  procession  into  the  city  that  besought  his  help  and  is  hailed  by  the 
inhabitants  almost  with  the  reverence  due  to  a  divinity.  In  our  days  this 
would,  of  course,  be  characterized  as  shameful  humbug,  but  in  early  times 
it  was  apparently  not  so.  Undoubtedly  Empedocles  himself  believed  in  his 
miraculous  powers,  and  the  taste  for  pageantry  he  shared  with  his  own 
countrymen.  History  also  relates  a  number  of  serviceable  acts  he  performed; 
for  instance,  he  improved  the  hot  and  unhealthy  climate  of  his  native  city  by 
making  a  breach  in  the  mountain  wall  which  shut  out  the  cool  north  wind; 
he  rid  a  neighbouring  town  of  malaria  by  arranging  for  the  draining  of  the 
district.  He  was,  besides,  a  leading  politician;  although  descended  from  a 
distinguished  family,  he  was  a  keen  democrat;  he  overthrew  the  oligarchies 
in  his  native  city  and  set  up  a  popular  government;  the  honour  of  kingship, 
which  was  offered  to  him,  he  declined.  However,  his  enemies  prevailed  over 
him  and  he  had  to  flee  in  exile  to  Greece,  where  he  died.  Shortly  after  his 
death  Acragas  fell  into  the  hands  of  the  Carthaginians  and  was  razed  to  the 
ground.  True,  the  city  again  flourished  in  the  time  of  the  Romans  under  the 
name  of  Agrigentum,  now  Girgenti,  but  the  part  it  played  in  the  history  of 
culture  was  at  an  end. 


CLASSICAL     ANTIQUITY,     MIDDLE     AGES        17 

The  four  elements 
As  a  philosopher  Empedocles  bases  his  theories  on  Parmenides.  The  world 
is  uniform,  immutable.  Nevertheless  changes  do  take  place,  but  these  must 
be  explained  by  movements  in  existing  matter  and  by  the  alternating  com- 
mixture and  dissolution  of  its  component  parts.  As  the  fundamental  ma- 
terial causes  Empedocles  postulates  fire,  air,  water,  and  earth  —  in  other 
words,  the  four  elements  or  roots.  The  theory  of  these  elements,  which  has 
been  maintained,  one  is  almost  tempted  to  say,  up  to  the  present  day,  origi- 
nates, as  was  universally  acknowledged  by  antiquity,  from  Empedocles.  And 
if  he  asked  what  it  was  that  produced  the  motions  in  the  four  elements  which 
caused  the  changes  in  their  constitution,  he  would  answer:  love  and  hate; 
love  acts  as  attraction,  hate  as  repulsion.  Through  their  alternating  predomi- 
nance are  produced  all  the  changes  in  nature.  Love,  when  it  ousts  hate,  gives 
rise  to  new  worlds;  when  hate  predominates,  they  are  again  dissolved.  The 
world  was  formed  by  parts  of  the  four  elements  becoming  united  in  a  work; 
through  the  same  kind  of  motion  the  water  elements  were  flung  out  of  the 
originally  humid  earth-mass,  so  that  the  latter  became  dry  and  habitable. 
If  fresh  beings  arise  or  such  beings  as  have  existed  perish,  it  is  not  to  be  con- 
cluded from  this  that  something  can  arise  out  of  nothing  or  become  nothing; 
for  whence  could  anything  new  come  to  that  aggregate  of  reality  that  exists, 
or  whither  could  anything  already  existing  disappear?  No,  the  cosmic  matter 
was  and  remains  the  same,  only  its  component  parts  are  mixed  in  different 
ways  through  love  and  hate  alternately  predominating.  Living  creatures  he 
conceives  as  having  arisen  out  of  the  earth;  first,  plants,  whose  life  he  com- 
pares in  detail  with  that  of  the  animals;  their  nourishment  is  procured 
through  pores  in  the  stem  and  leaves,  and  their  germination  is  comparable 
to  the  reproduction  of  animals.  Animate  organisms  have  likewise  originally 
sprung  from  the  earth;  first  arose  individual  limbs  and  later,  through  the 
powers  of  attraction  of  love,  these  were  conjoined;  from  them  then  arose 
animals  themselves.  But  this  development  did  not  proceed  undisturbed,  for  as 
the  conjoining  of  the  separate  parts  took  place  by  accident,  it  was  entirely  a 
matter  of  chance  whether  beings  capable  of  life  or  malformed  monsters  arose. 
Mankind  also  originated  in  a  similar  way;  through  the  co-operation  of  the 
subterranean  fire  there  were  cast  up  out  of  the  interior  of  the  earth  shapeless 
lumps  which  formed  themselves  into  limbs,  from  the  union  of  which  man 
developed.  Men,  who  are  of  a  warmer  temperament,  came  into  being  in  a 
southern  climate,  while  women,  the  more  cold-blooded  sex,  were  created  in 
a  more  northerly  climate.  In  reproduction  the  embryo  received  some  parts 
of  the  body  from  the  father's  and  the  others  from  the  mother's  seed.  Growth 
in  childhood  is  due  to  increase  of  warmth  in  the  body,  and  the  infirmity  of 
age  to  its  diminution.  Respiration  he  believed  to  be  effected  not  only  through 
the  windpipe,  but  also  through  the  pores  of  the  skin;  as  the  blood  is  conveyed 


l8  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

alternately  to  and  from  the  skin,  the  air  is  inhaled  in  conjunction  with  it. 
The  perceptions  of  the  senses  are  due  to  the  objects  that  are  perceived  or 
sensed  giving  off  fine  particles,  which  unite  themselves  to  the  corresponding 
components  in  the  organs  of  sense.  Thus  the  various  elements  are  apprehended 
by  corresponding  elements  in  the  organs  of  sense:  water  by  water,  air  by  air, 
etc.  Tones  are  created  by  the  air  brought  into  movement  forcing  its  way  into 
the  auditory  duct  of  the  ear  as  into  a  trumpet.  Empedocles  is  said  to  have 
been  the  first  to  describe  the  labyrinth  of  the  ear.  The  eye  he  compares  to  a 
lamp;  light  is  distinguished  by  the  eye's  fire-components,  darkness  by  its 
water-particles.  Even  in  the  operation  of  thinking  he  sees  a  purely  corporeal 
function;  the  blood,  in  which  all  the  elements  are  most  minutely  commingled, 
is  the  seat  of  intelligence,  but  in  this  other  parts  of  the  body  can  also  co- 
operate; elsewhere  in  the  operation  of  thinking  the  four  elements  in  the 
thinker  and  the  thought  seek  one  another.  The  more  finely  and  evenly  the 
elements  are  mixed  in  a  man,  the  better  does  he  think;  if  the  correct  mixture 
is  confined  to  particular  parts  of  the  body,  then  these  parts  are  more  highly 
developed  than  the  others.  —  In  curious  contrast  to  this  materialistic  theory 
of  sensation  are  several  utterances  of  Empedocles  in  which,  like  Parmenides, 
he  warns  us  that  the  evidence  of  the  senses  cannot  be  implicitly  trusted;  they 
can  deceive,  while  the  reasoned  thought  is  infallible. 

We  cannot  here  enter  into  a  discussion  of  Empedocles*  religious  theories. 
Like  Pythagoras,  he  believed  in  the  migration  of  the  soul  and  likewise  for- 
bade his  disciples  to  kill  and  eat  animals.  Even  certain  plants  were  in  this 
respect  sacred.  For  the  rest,  it  is  difficult  to  reconcile  his  mystical  religious 
pronouncements  and  his  miracle-working  activities  with  his  natural  philoso- 
phy, which  so  strictly  emphasized  the  doctrine  of  causality.  From  a  closer 
knowledge  of  the  conditions  under  which  he  lived  we  might  well  have 
been  able  to  explain  the  riddle;  now  he  stands  as  a  unique,  strange  phenome- 
non in  the  history  of  biological  research. 

Empedocles'  scientific  influence 
In  this  sphere  he  undoubtedly  deserves  a  high  place.  In  particular  his  specu- 
lations on  the  constitution  of  matter  and  its  changes  are  worthy  of  atten- 
tion. While  his  predecessors  and  even  his  successors  for  long  ages  afterwards 
had  no  other  natural  grounds  of  explanation  to  offer  in  regard  to  these 
phenomena  than  motion  in  space,  Empedocles  comes  forward  with  a  kind 
of  doctrine  of  affinity,  crude  and  clumsy,  it  is  true,  but  nevertheless  con- 
taining within  it  the  germ  of  a  number  of  ideas  which  it  was  only  possible 
for  far  later  ages  to  think  out.  And  the  fact  that  these  ideas  were  not  adopted 
by  his  successors,  that  antiquity  failed  to  produce  any  science  of  chemistry, 
does  not  detract  from  their  interest.  His  physiological  speculations,  naive 
though  they  are,  also  give  evidence  of  his  keen  powers  of  observation  and 
combination.  In  his  curious  theory  of  the  creation  of  living  organisms  from 


CLASSICAL     ANTIQUITY,     MIDDLE     AGES        19 

scattered  parts  brought  together  by  chance  an  attempt  has  been  made  to  see 
a  kind  of  primitive  theory  of  selection.  That  is,  of  course,  an  exaggeration; 
his  anthropogeny  gives  even  clearer  evidence  than  Anaximander's  of  being 
derived  from  the  old  legends  of  autochthones. 

With  Empedocles  the  western  Greek  school  made  their  final  and  most 
important  contribution  towards  the  history  of  biology.  A  couple  of  hundred 
years  later  this  people  saw  the  birth  of  their  greatest  philosophical  genius, 
the  physicist  Archimedes,  who  lived  to  see  the  destruction  of  the  liberty  of 
western  Greece.  He  was  indeed  a  specialist  in  his  own  sphere,  which  has  no 
place  in  this  work.  We  return  therefore  to  Asia  Minor,  whence  sprang  the 
whole  of  Greek  natural  philosophy  and  where  the  Ionian  succession  was  still 
being  carried  on  with  achievements  of  great  importance  for  its  further 
development. 

From  its  point  of  departure  in  the  Ionian  philosophy  Heracleitus  of 
Ephesus  (about  510-450)  developed  an  entirely  new  idea  of  nature.  He  was 
one  of  the  greatest  philosophers  of  antiquity,  called  "the  dark,"  on  account 
of  both  his  obscure  style  of  writing  and  his  gloomy  view  of  life.  He  came  from 
a  distinguished  priestly  family,  but  resigned  an  eminent  government  post  to 
devote  himself  entirely  to  philosophy.  His  life,  too,  however,  was  disturbed 
by  political  revolutions.  As  a  thinker  he  seems  to  have  been  essentially  auto- 
didactic,  and  though  his  system  is  to  a  certain  extent  based  on  the  Ionian 
philosophy,  mainly  on  that  of  Anaximander,  it  nevertheless  bears  an  en- 
tirely original  stamp.  In  contrast  to  the  Eleatics'  assertion  of  the  immuta- 
bility of  the  universe,  Heracleitus  sums  up  his  teaching  in  the  proposition 
that  everything  is  mutable,  that  mutability  is  the  essence  of  existence. 
"Struggle  is  life"  is  a  saying  that  comes  from  him;  "All  is  flux"  is  another. 
He  regards  fire  as  the  causal  principle  of  the  cosmos.  Everything  has  arisen 
from  a  primordial  fire,  to  which  everything  returns,  for  worlds  arise  and 
perish  alternately.  Heracleitus  saw  divinity  in  the  primordial  fire.  Fire  is  also 
the  soul  of  man;  fire  is  inhaled  in  breathing,  and  its  cessation  is  therefore 
identical  with  death.  Disease  arises  mostly  through  water,  the  enemy  of  fire, 
predominating  in  the  body;  intemperance  in  drinking  clouds  the  soul,  since 
the  wine  makes  the  soul  humid;  "The  driest  soul  is  the  wisest,"  he  expressly 
states  in  his  writings.  His  special  biological  investigations  have  not  been 
preserved.  He  is  said  to  have  dissected  animals,  but  it  is  not  known  whether 
he  drew  any  fresh  conclusions  therefrom.  The  service  he  rendered  to  science 
lies  in  his  general  view  of  existence;  in  his  constant  insistence  on  the  modifi- 
cation of  the  principle,  and  at  the  same  time  on  incontrovertible  natural  law 
governing  the  universe  —  these  two  factors  being  the  essence  of  existence. 
In  this  he  exerted  great  influence  upon  the  natural  philosophy  of  succeeding 
ages,  particularly  upon  Plato  and,  through  him,  upon  Aristotle. 

Contemporaneous  with  Heracleitus,   however,  there  appears  another 


lO  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

line  of  thought  which  is  far  more  concerned  with  a  close  study  of  nature  and 
makes  it  the  basis  of  the  entire  cosmic  system  —  the  atomic  theory.  The 
founder  of  this  philosophy  is  said  to  have  been  Leucippus,  a  thinker  of  whom 
we  know  nothing  except  that  he  was  the  teacher  of  Democritus,  one  of  the 
foremost  natural  research-workers  and  natural  philosophers  of  all  time. 
Democritus  was  born  at  Abdera,  a  Greek  colony  on  the  Thracian  coast.  In 
his  time  Abdera  was  a  rich  and  powerful  city,  but  in  the  course  of  subsequent 
centuries  it  declined  and  its  citizens  became  notorious  for  their  stupidity, 
which  gave  rise  to  the  epithet  "Abderitic"  as  a  universal  expression  for 
extreme  foolishness.  His  period  of  activity  is,  like  that  of  most  of  the  early 
Greek  philosophers,  not  known  for  certain,  but  it  is  generally  assumed  that 
he  was  born  between  the  years  470  and  460  b.c.  and  died  at  a  very  advanced 
age  —  in  fact,  not  far  short  of  a  hundred  years.  From  his  father,  one  of  the 
richest  and  most  eminent  citizens  of  his  native  town,  he  received  a  large 
inheritance,  which  he  is  said  to  have  spent  entirely  on  long  journeys  under- 
taken for  the  purpose  of  acquiring  knowledge  from  various  countries  and 
peoples.  On  his  return  home  he  was  supported  by  a  brother  until  his  fellow- 
countrymen,  proud  of  his  scientific  fame,  granted  him  a  pension  sufficient 
for  all  his  needs.  Known  for  his  mild  and  friendly  disposition  and  surrounded 
by  admiring  disciples,  he  grew  old  in  peace  and  died  without  suffering  from 
ill  health.  He  was  known  as  one  of  the  most  productive  scientific  authors  of 
antiquity,  and  his  writings  seem  to  have  embraced  many  and  varied  subjects. 
Except  for  a  few  fragments,  however,  they  are  entirely  lost  and  indeed  seem 
to  have  already  been  so  as  early  as  the  late  classical  period.  Through  other 
ancient  authors,  however,  particularly  Aristotle,  who  always  mentions  him 
with  respect  and  seems  to  a  large  extent  to  have  made  use  of  his  learning, 
we  are  able  to  form  a  fairly  good  idea  of  his  scientific  point  of  view. 

Maferialisfic  theory  of  the  universe 
His  teacher,  Leucippus,  seems  to  have  based  philosophy  on  Parmenides' 
theory  of  the  immutability  of  matter,  and  to  have  come  across  this  in  the 
paradoxical  form  that  it  assumed  among  the  later  Eleatics.  In  order  to  pre- 
serve the  elements  of  truth  in  this  theory  and  at  the  same  time  to  make  pos- 
sible the  changes  which  are  incontestably  observable  in  the  world,  Leucippus 
conceived  the  universe  as  composed  of  a  quantity  of  particles  moving  in 
empty  space.  Democritus  adopted  this  theory  and  developed  it  further.  He 
thus  became  the  founder  of  the  atomic  theory,  one  of  the  most  fruitful  ideas 
in  natural  science.  And  on  this  atomic  theory  he,  as  no  one  else  has  done 
either  before  or  since,  based  the  whole  of  his  theory  of  existence,  both 
spiritual  and  material.  No  thinker  of  antiquity  ever  produced  such  a  consist- 
ent and  materialistic  theory  of  the  nature  of  the  cosmos;  none  has  advanced 
further  in  the  endeavour  to  satisfy  the  demand  —  upon  which  Anaximan- 
der  had  already  insisted  —  for  a  natural  explanation  of  the  origin  of  matter. 


CLASSICAL     ANTIQUITY,     MIDDLE     AGES        II 

From  the  fragments  of  his  writings  a  number  of  general  principles  have  been 
gathered  which  are  characteristic  of  his  point  of  view;  some  of  them  sound 
surprisingly  like  modern  natural  science. 

Out  of  nothing  comes  nothing;  nothing  which  is  can  be  reduced  to 
nothing.  All  change  is  merely  an  aggregation  or  separation  of  parts. 

Nothing  happens  by  chance  or  intention,  everything  through  cause  and 
of  necessity. 

There  is  nothing  but  the  atoms  and  space;  all  else  is  an  impression  of  the 
senses. 

The  atoms  are  infinite  in  number  and  shape.  Their  movement  is  eternal; 
in  endless  space  they  impinge  upon  one  another,  thereby  producing  vortices 
out  of  which  worlds  arise,  only  again  to  perish.  All  the  qualities  of  matter 
are  due  to  the  shape,  size,  number,  and  motion  of  the  atoms  of  which  it  is 
composed.  The  atoms  possess  no  other  qualities  than  those  mentioned  above. 
The  soul  consists  of  the  finest  and  most  mobile  atoms;  they  fill  the  body  and 
give  it  life;  if  they  leave  the  body,  death  ensues.  Fire  likewise  consists  of 
small  mobile  atoms.  On  the  whole,  Democritus  seems  to  have  shared  Hera- 
cleitus'  idea  of  the  mutual  affinity  of  the  soul  and  fire.  The  stars  he  considered 
to  be  like  the  earth,  but  owing  to  their  rapid  motion  they  were  fiery  bodies. 
He  seems  also  to  have  observed  the  mountains  in  the  moon. 

Biological  knowledge  of  Democritus 
Democritus  has  achieved  important  work  in  the  science  of  biology  and  he  is 
here,  as  in  many  other  directions,  the  finest  of  Aristotle's  predecessors;  how 
much  of  his  learning  his  successor  borrowed  we  do  not  know,  but  there  are 
grounds  for  supposing  that  it  was  far  more  than  posterity  has  ever  guessed. 
Without  doubt  he  performed  dissections  of  both  the  higher  and  the  lower 
animals  and  was  the  first  to  differentiate  between  them  according  to  the 
quality  of  the  blood.  The  distinction  between  sanguiferous  animals  (verte- 
brates) and  bloodless  animals,  which  was  the  principle  of  classification 
adopted  by  Aristotle,  originates  from  Democritus.  In  contrast  to  Aristotle  he 
believed  that  even  the  minutest  animals  possess  perfected  organs,  although, 
owing  to  their  transparency,  they  are  invisible  to  the  human  eye.  In  the 
embryonic  development  the  external  organs  arise  first  and  the  internal  after- 
wards. Many  of  Democritus'  ideas  we  know  only  through  Aristotle's  po- 
lemics against  them,  and  in  this  respect  modern  research  not  seldom  proves 
Democritus  right.  For  instance,  he  considers  that  the  spider's  web  is  pro- 
duced from  inside  its  body  while  Aristotle  maintained  that  it  is  cast-off  skin. 
The  sterility  of  the  mule  he  seeks  to  explain  by  assuming  a  contraction  of  its 
uterus.  The  construction  and  functions  of  the  human  body,  however,  were 
naturally  the  main  object  of  his  studies.  He  conceives  man  to  be  a  world  in 
miniature,  a  microcosm  in ^ which  every  kind  of  atom  is  represented.  He  re- 
gards the  brain  as  the  organ  of  thought,  the  heart  as  that  of  courage,  and 


ZZ  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

the  liver  as  that  of  sensuality.  His  estimation  of  the  brain  places  Democritus 
once  more  in  front  of  Aristotle,  who  believed  the  brain  to  serve  only  the 
purpose  of  cooling  the  blood.  Democritus  considered  life  and  the  soul  to  be 
one  and  the  same  thing,  and  the  latter  he  believed,  as  already  mentioned,  to 
consist  of  fire  atoms  which,  owing  to  their  lightness  and  mobility,  are  con- 
stantly being  given  off  by  the  body.  Through  inhalation  the  body  receives  a 
fresh  supply  of  them;  if  respiration  ceases,  then  life  departs  from  the  body. 
Sleep  and  asphyxia  he  declared  to  be  also  due  to  a  loss  of  soul-atoms,  but  on 
a  smaller  scale.  Hydrophobia  in  dogs  and  human  beings  he  considered  to  be 
caused  by  inflammation  of  the  nerves.  Epidemics  he  believed  to  be  the  result 
of  atoms  falling  upon  the  earth  out  of  other  celestial  bodies.  Sensation  is  due 
to  the  movement  of  atoms  which  emanate  from  the  objects  perceived.  In 
connexion  with  Democritus'  materialistic  idea  of  the  soul  he  believed  in 
spiritual  beings  and  revelations,  a  belief  which  other  thinkers  who  regarded 
the  soul  as  matter  — ■  as,  for  instance,  Swedenborg  —  have  shared  with  him. 
On  the  other  hand,  he  denied  the  divine  beings  of  popular  belief,  without, 
however,  like  Xenophanes,  substituting  any  unified  and  eternal  divine  power 
in  their  stead.  Necessity,  which,  according  to  his  views,  governed  the  uni- 
verse, was  purely  impersonal. 

Democritus  on  the  whole  represents  the  climax  of  the  endeavour  of 
Greek  philosophy  to  arrive  at  an  explanation  of  existence  based  on  a  natural 
connexion  of  causes,  an  endeavour  which,  with  Anaximander  as  its  instigator, 
gave  rise  to  a  long  series  of  heterogeneous  explanations  of  the  cosmos,  of 
which  only  the  most  important  can  be  considered  here.  In  several  funda- 
mental respects  —  for  instance,  in  the  strict  theory  of  causation,  the  atomic 
theory,  and,  in  connexion  therewith,  the  principle  of  motion,  the  emphasiz- 
ing of  the  importance  of  the  brain  for  the  function  of  thinking,  the  insistence 
upon  the  complicated  organism  of  the  lower  animals  —  Democritus  achieves 
results  similar  to  those  that  have  been  attained  by  natural  research  in  our 
own  day,  although  his  speculations  were  in  detail  often  very  primitive,  even 
when  compared  with  the  achievements  of  philosophers  of  later  antiquity. 
The  promising  idea  was  not  pursued,  however,  by  succeeding  generations; 
for  certain  reasons  which  will  be  more  clearly  explained  when  accounting 
for  Aristotle's  theoretical  views,  shortly  after  the  age  of  Democritus  the 
Greek  natural  philosophy  started  to  work  out  a  method  of  explaining  the 
cosmic  process  entirely  different  from  that  indicated  by  the  atomic  theory. 
Democritus  thus  represents  the  close  of  the  first  and  the  purely  natural 
scientific  period  of  Greek  philosophy.  The  results  achieved  by  research  dur- 
ing that  period  have  been  mentioned  above;  what  it  failed  to  achieve  may 
also  be  briefly  described  here.  The  most  serious  defect  from  which  it  suffered 
was  undoubtedly  the  lack  of  material  for  investigation,  which  rendered  it 
difficult  to  follow  up  the  principle  of  causation  which  had  already  been 


CLASSICAL     ANTIQUITY,     MIDDLE     AGES        i} 

determined.  It  should  be  remembered  that  antiquity  knew  nothing  whatever 
of  chemistry,  so  that  the  ideas  of  chemical  association  and  affinity  were  en- 
tirely lacking  as  a  basis  for  the  changes  in  nature,  and  for  these  ideas  the 
vague  and  dogmatic  theory  of  vortical  motion  was  of  course  a  very  poor 
substitute.  Generally  speaking,  there  did  not  exist  in  antiquity  the  ideas  of 
force  and  energy  in  the  modern  sense,  but  philosophers  had  to  be  content 
with  motion  as  an  explanation  of  all  changes.  And,  finally,  they  drew  no 
definite  line  between  objective  facts  and  subjective  opinions;  they  had  no 
idea  whatever  of  hypothesis.  The  whole  of  Democritus'  cosmology  was 
purely  dogmatic  and  was  condemned  to  give  way  to  other  similarly  dog- 
matic explanations  of  the  universe,  which,  though  more  attractive  to  his 
contemporaries,  nevertheless  proved  fatal  to  the  future  development  of 
natural  science. 

Reaction  against  natural  philosophy 
The  first  sign  of  the  coming  reaction  is  given  by  the  philosophy  of  Anaxag- 
ORAs.  This  thinker  was  a  contemporary  of  Democritus,  probably  born 
somewhat  earlier  than  the  latter,  at  Clazomenas  in  Asia  Minor.  His  activi- 
ties, however,  were  pursued  in  Athens  in  the  time  of  Pericles  —  thus  in  the 
community  which  proved  to  be  the  first  great  power  of  Greek  nationality. 
This  is  the  first  time  in  Greek  scientific  history  that  the  town  is  mentioned 
which  was  afterwards  to  become  for  nearly  a  thousand  years  the  centre  of 
thought  of  classical  antiquity.  Athens  was  a  city  with  an  extremely  mixed 
population  and  an  equally  diverse  intellectual  life:  side  by  side  with  the  most 
daring  novelties  in  the  region  of  thought  dwelt  crass  superstition  and  fanati- 
cal intolerance  —  to  which  latter  Anaxagoras  fell  a  victim.  Accused  of 
"godlessness,"  hewas  first  cast  into  prison  and  then  had  to  flee  from  Athens. 
Nevertheless,  his  philosophy,  as  compared  with  that  of  Democritus,  must 
be  regarded  as  idealistic.  He  conceived  that  the  driving  force  in  the  universe 
is  what  he  calls  the  cosmic  reason  or  the  cosmic  soul;  a  kind  of  spiritual 
power  to  which  he  ascribes  unity,  omnipotence,  and  omniscience.  This  same 
power  is  part  of  all  living  creatures  and  in  them  represents  life  itself.  Matter 
he  believed  to  consist  of  an  endless  number  of  primary  elements  —  that  is,  in 
the  same  sense  as  that  in  which  the  old  lonians  conceived  this  idea.  He  does 
not  appear  to  have  gone  in  for  biological  research,  nor  do  his  natural-scientific 
views  in  general  show  any  advance  over  those  of  Democritus.  But  he  was 
not  without  influence  upon  the  succeeding  ages  and  is  therefore  worthy  of 
mention. 

The  Sophists 
Of  far  greater  influence  on  the  general  course  of  development,  however, 
was  a  school  of  philosophers  which  appeared  contemporaneously  with  him 
and  which  began  to  lead  Greek  thought  along  entirely  different  channels. 
These  were  the  famous  Sophists,  whose  founder  and  leading  personality  was 


Z4  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

Protagoras,  likewise  a  contemporary  of  Democritus.  Protagoras  introduced 
scepticism  and  subjectivism  into  Greek  thought:  "Man  is  the  measure  of  all 
things"  is  one  of  his  fundamental  principles;  "Contrary  assertions  are  equally 
true"  is  another.  To  such  a  thinker  any  consideration  of  nature  was  foreign; 
what  he  desired  to  teach  was  an  art  of  living,  such  as  would  free  mankind 
from  the  fetters  which  traditional  ideas  in  the  sphere  of  religion  and  morality 
had  imposed.  Highly  acclaimed  by  the  younger  generation,  bitterly  hated 
by  the  representatives  of  the  past,  not  least  because,  in  contrast  to  the  earlier 
philosophers,  he  taught  for  payment,  which  was  at  that  time  regarded  as 
equivalent  to  usury,  Protagoras  starts  an  entirely  new  era  in  the  Greek  view 
of  mankind,  in  relation  both  to  his  fellow-creatures  and  to  nature.  But  be- 
fore going  on  to  describe  this  new  tendency  we  must  make  a  brief  survey 
of  Greek  medical  science,  at  that  period  a  specialized  science  which  had 
achieved  results  of  lasting  value  to  general  biological  development. 


CHAPTER    III 

THE       EARLIER       PHASE       OF       GREEK       MEDICAL      SCIENCE       AND 
ITS       SIGNIFICANCE       FOR      THE      DEVELOPMENT      OF      BIOLOGY 

Magical  beginnings  of  Greek  medicine 

THE  EARLIEST  BEGINNINGS  of  the  scicncc  of  medicinc  among  the  Greeks 
were  as  always  in  primitive  medical  practice,  based  on  magical 
religion,  ^sculapius,  the  god  of  the  healing  art,  had  a  numerous 
priesthood,  in  which  secret  knowledge  of  the  forces  of  nature  and  their  use 
for  the  curing  of  disease  was  jealously  guarded  and  handed  down  from  gen- 
eration to  generation.  Pilgrimages  were  made  to  the  temples  of  ^sculapius 
by  crowds  of  sick  persons  ■ — •  both  those  in  real  and  those  in  imaginary  ill 
health  —  to  be  cured  of  their  maladies;  and  the  latter  class,  the  hypochondri- 
acs, were  not  slow  to  spread  abroad  and  confirm  stories  of  the  most  wonderful 
miracles  of  healing  performed  there.  Immense  hospitals  were  erected  in  the 
neighbourhood  of  these  temples  for  the  benefit  of  those  who  required  lengthy 
treatment,  and  the  very  necessity  of  having  to  watch  over  and  follow  the 
course  of  these  patients'  diseases  must  naturally  have  created  a  large 
supply  of  purely  empirical  observations  of  immense  value  to  the  sacer- 
dotal miracle-workers,  who  were  thus  enabled  to  estimate  the  result  of  their 
methods  of  treatment.  In  time  there  grew  up,  as  a  result  of  the  widespread 
adoption  of  these  empirical  observations  and  methods,  a  class  of  purely 
secular'healers,  no  longer  directly  associated  with  the  temples  of  i^sculapius, 
who  nevertheless,  in  order  to  denote  the  origin  of  their  art  and  to  take  ad- 
vantage of  the  confidence  inspired  by  religious  belief,  called  themselves 
Asclepiads  —  that  is,  descendants  of  i^sculapius.  As  other  professions  did  at 
that  time,  they  formed  a  private  guild,  the  members  of  which  taught  their 
art  preferably  only  to  sons  and  kinsmen.  Outsiders  too  were  able  by  paying 
large  sums  to  obtain  an  insight  into  the  secrets  of  the  profession,  while  the 
children  of  the  family  of  Asclepiads  always  had  the  right  to  receive  free 
instruction  from  any  of  their  father's  colleagues.  The  wording  of  the  oath 
which  the  young  physician  had  to  swear  before  being  allowed  to  begin  the 
practice  of  his  profession  is  still  extant.  By  this  oath  he  pledged  himself  to 
help  teachers  and  his  professional  colleagues,  give  free  instruction  to  their 
sons,  share  with  them  any  fresh  experiences  and  discoveries,  to  the  best  of 
his  ability  heal  the  sick,  and  refrain  from  mixing  poisons  and  producing 
abortions. 

2-5 


z6  THEHISTORYOFBIOLOGY 

Earliest  medical  xvritings 
The  oldest  known  medical  writings  date  from  a  period  when  medical  science 
was  still  materially,  if  not  also  in  its  ideals,  dependent  on  the  temples  of 
y^sculapius.  There  were  in  particular  three  famous  shrines  of  the  god  from 
which  profane  medical  science  was  thus  derived,  and  these  were  situated  on 
the  islands  of  Rhodes,  Cnidus,  and  Cos,  all  near  the  coast  of  Asia  Minor. 
The  situation  of  these  places  shows,  as  did  also  the  first  nurseries  of  philoso- 
phy, that  oriental  influence  had  been  at  work,  and  this  influence  did  in  fact 
prove  of  incalculable  importance  for  Greek  medical  science;  particularly  in 
Egypt  the  art  of  healing  had  from  the  very  earliest  times  been  highly  de- 
veloped, and  in  historical  times,  too,  was  highly  reputed  even  amongst 
foreign  peoples.  Of  the  Greek  temple  schools  mentioned,  that  on  the  Isle  of 
Rhodes  was  the  earliest,  that  at  Cos  the  most  famous.  The  Coan  school  is 
principally  indebted  for  its  fame  to  the  family  of  Asclepiads  originating  from 
there,  which  gave  the  world  one  of  the  greatest  pioneers  of  medical  science 
known  to  history  —  namely,  Hippocrates. 

History  has  preserved  the  memory  of  seven  Greek  physicians  called 
Hippocrates;  the  one  here  in  question  is  generally  spoken  of  as  Hippocrates 
the  Second  or  the  Great.  He  is  believed  to  have  lived  between  the  years  460 
and  377  B.C.  —  that  is  to  say,  at  the  time  of  Democritus.  He  was  born  in  the 
Isle  of  Cos  of  the  family  of  the  Asclepiads  which  for  several  generations  had 
been  attached  to  the  temple  of  ^^sculapius  on  the  island.  He  received  his 
medical  education  from  his  father,  Heracleides,  who,  however,  evidently 
died  when  his  son  was  still  a  youth.  The  young  Hippocrates  then  betook 
himself  to  Athens,  where  he  studied  philosophy  with  the  Sophist  Gorgias  of 
Leontini,  and  afterwards  made  several  journeys  in  the  Balkan  Peninsula  and 
Asia  Minor,  eventually  settling  down  in  Thessaly,  where  he  established  a 
large  practice  and  finally  died  in  the  city  of  Larissa.  His  sons  and  grandsons 
were  likewise  doctors  whose  reputation  was  high,  though  not  comparable 
to  his  own. 

Hippocrates'  fame  as  a  pioneer  of  medical  science  is  based  chiefly  on  his 
medical  authorship.  Even  in  ancient  times,  however,  there  prevailed  some 
uncertainty  as  to  whether  the  writings  that  go  under  his  name  are  genuinely 
his,  and  in  our  own  time  only  a  few  treatises  out  of  what  is  called  the  Hippo- 
cratic  Collection  can  be  accepted  as  coming  from  his  own  hand;  the  rest  are 
supposed  to  be  partly  the  work  of  his  school,  partly  Asclepiad  writings  dat- 
ing from  before  his  time,  partly,  and  m.ostly,  essays  by  considerably  younger 
authors.  Hippocrates'  own  main  treatise,  Airs,  Waters,  and  Places,  con- 
tains extraordinarily  brilliant  observations  on  climatical  and  geophysical 
conditions  and  their  influence  on  mankind  in  sickness  and  health,  in  their 
material  and  spiritual  aspects.  The  treatises  in  the  Hippocratic  Collection 
dealing  with  anatomy  and  physiology,  which  are  thus  of  interest  for  the 


CLASSICAL     ANTIQUITY,      MIDDLE     AGES        Xy 

history  of  biological  research,  are  all  believed  to  be  of  later  date  than  Hip- 
pocrates and  are  at  any  rate  influenced  by  his  views.  They  give  evidence  of 
a  close  study  of  anatomy  and  physiology  with  the  help  of  dissections  and 
vivisections.  From  the  enunciation  of  the  anatomy  of  the  human  body,  how- 
ever, it  is  clear  that  it  is  not  based  on  dissections  of  the  dead  body,  but  that 
the  results  of  experiments  carried  out  on  the  dead  bodies  of  animals  have  been 
applied  to  the  human  body  without  further  evidence.  To  dissect  the  human 
body,  to  violate  the  dead  bodies  of  human  beings,  was  from  the  very  earliest 
times  considered  a  dangerous  procedure  and  on  that  account  was  forbidden; 
the  reason  for  this  was  undoubtedly  the  universal  fear  of  ghosts,  which  has 
already  been  touched  upon.  It  is  certain,  at  all  events,  that,  except  in  a  few 
particularly  unprejudiced  cultural  epochs,  it  has  always  been  difficult,  even 
in  more  modern  times,  to  procure  dead  bodies  for  purposes  of  scientific  inves- 
tigation and  to  obtain  permission  to  utilize  them.  The  first  part  of  the  human 
body  to  be  studied  with  any  great  care  was  the  bone-construction,  which 
could  be  examined  in  the  skeletons  of  long-decomposed  and  consequently 
less  dangerous  individuals,  while  the  ancient  custom  of  preserving  corpses 
by  the  preservation  of  the  skeleton  —  a  practice  known  in  most  countries 
from  prehistoric  times  —  must  have  given  cause  for  observing  and  getting 
to  know  the  various  bones  of  the  body.  The  musculature  also,  at  any  rate 
its  external  layers,  which  it  was  possible  to  study  in  living  human  beings  in 
wrestling  and  athletics,  has  been  comparatively  well  understood,  while  the 
internal  organs  —  the  digestive,  respiratory,  and  circulatory  systems  —  re- 
mained longest  shrouded  in  obscurity,  as  regards  both  their  construction 
and  their  functions.  These  facts  have  also  had  an  inflluence  on  surgery;  while 
fracture's  and  sprains  were  carefully  studied  and  cleverly  treated  even  in  Hip- 
pocrates' time,  the  art  of  arresting  hemorrhage  was  extremely  primitive; 
from  antiquity  to  the  Middle  Ages  there  existed  no  better  method  than  cau- 
terizing with  red-hot  iron,  and  it  was  not  until  the  sixteenth  century  that 
people  learnt  how  to  apply  ligatures  when  operating. 

Hippocrafic  physiology:  the  four  temperaments 
The  Hippocratic  treatises  assume  with  Empedocles  and  his  successors  that 
the  human  body  is  composed  of  the  four  elements:  fire,  air,  water,  and  earth. 
To  these  elements  correspond  four  "juices"  in  the  body:  blood,  phlegm, 
yellow  bile,  and  black  bile.  Of  these  the  yellow  bile  is  produced  in  the  liver, 
and  the  black  bile  in  the  spleen.  Proof  of  the  existence  of  these  juices  was 
found  in  the  condition  of  the  blood  on  coagulation,  when,  as  is  known,  its 
component  parts  become  separated;  in  the  undermost,  black  part  of  the  clot 
was  recognized  the  black  bile,  in  its  uppermost,  red  part  the  blood;  the 
yellow  bile  was  seen  in  serum,  and  the  phlegm  in  the  fibrin.^  The  condition 

^  See  Fahraeus:  The  Suspension  Stability  oj  the  Blood  (Stockholm,  1911). 


x8  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

of  the  body  was  due  to  the  existence  and  commingling  of  these  four  primary- 
elements;  if  they  existed  in  the  proper  proportions,  health  was  the  result; 
if  the  harmony  between  them  was  disturbed,  sickness  followed.^  For  the 
rest,  Hippocrates  and  his  successors  seem  to  have  shared  the  conception 
which  originated  in  Heracleitus  that  the  soul,  the  life -principle,  consists 
of  fire  or  —  in  later  writings  —  of  substance  akin  to  fire,  called  pneuma 
(breath). 

In  regard  to  human  anatomy,  osteology  was,  as  has  been  mentioned, 
comparatively  carefully  studied.  The  skull  in  particular  was  radically  in- 
vestigated and  a  large  number  of  the  names  of  its  bones  and  sutures  are 
derived  from  these  works.  The  bones  of  the  face  were  also  minutely  studied. 
The  knowledge  of  the  backbone  was  more  defective,  while,  on  the  other 
hand,  the  bones  of  the  extremities  were  well  described.  Of  the  muscles  sev- 
eral, particularly  the  muscles  of  the  extremities,  are  correctly  described, 
though  the  actual  muscle  substance  is  not  accurately  distinguished  from  a 
number  of  other  internal  organs.  The  separate  parts  of  the  digestive  canal 
are  named,  but  their  connexion  and  function  were  extremely  vaguely  known. 
The  various  sections  of  the  intestinal  tube  are  given  different  names  and  char- 
acteristics in  the  different  writings  on  the  subject.  The  liver  is  an  organ 
which  particularly  interested  the  people  of  antiquity,  as  also  the  spleen,  but 
there  were  very  confused  ideas  of  their  respective  functions.  A  good  deal 
was  known  about  the  glands,  especially  the  lymphatic  glands;  the  pancreas, 
on  the  other  hand,  was  unknown.  The  function  of  the  glands  was  believed 
to  be  to  segregate  water  from  the  body.  Of  the  respiratory  organs  the  larynx 
and  the  trachea  in  particular  were  completely  described,  while  the  lungs 
were  treated  only  summarily.  Respiration  is  believed  to  serve  the  purpose 
of  cooling  the  heart.  Again,  in  another  treatise  it  is  asserted  that  the  inhaled 
air  spreads  to  the  various  parts  of  the  body,  to  the  brain,  the  body  cavity, 
and  the  arteries.  The  enunciation  of  the  circulatory  system  is,  as  mentioned 
above,  vague.  The  different  cavities  of  the  heart  are  fairly  accurately  de- 
scribed, but  here  exists  already  the  delusion  which  it  has  since  been  so  dif- 
ficult to  eradicate  that  the  left  cavity  of  the  heart  does  not  contain 
blood,  but  some  kind  of  airy  substance,  which  is  proved  by  reference  to 
slaughtered  animals,  in  which  the  arterial  blood  is  drained  off  by  severing 
the  jugular  veins!  The  apprehension  of  the  venous  system  is  far  vaguer  than 
that  of  the  heart,  and,  moreover,  the  description  of  the  former  in  the  differ- 
ent Hippocratic  treatises  is  highly  contradictory.  The  right  side  of  the  heart 


2  The  doctrine  of  the  four  temperaments,  which  counts  for  something  even  in  our  own  day, 
is  based  originally  on  the  theory  of  these  four  juices  and  their  distribution  in  the  body;  in  san- 
guine people  the  predominating  factor  is  the  blood,  in  phlegmatic  people  the  phlegm,  in  choleric 
people  the  yellow  and  in  melancholy  people  the  black  bile.  Melancholy,  owing  to  its  origin  in 
the  black  bile,  is  called  spleen  or  atrabiliousness. 


CLASSICAL  ANTIQUITY,  MIDDLE  AGES  19 
is  the  Starting-point  of  the  circulation  of  the  blood;  the  blood  flows  to  it 
from  the  rest  of  the  body,  and  there  obtains  warm  temperature  from  the 
left  cavity  —  that  is  to  say,  the  blood  coming  from  the  body  is  "cold." 
The  left  heart-cavity  gets  warmth  from  the  air  through  the  pulmonary  veins. 
The  arteries  likewise  contain  this  warm  kind  of  air,  called  pneuma,  which 
maintains  vital  action,  and  they  disperse  it  throughout  the  body.  It  is  truly 
remarkable  that,  in  spite  of  observations  made  from  innumerable  dissections 
and  vivisections  performed  by  various  research-workers,  this  primitive 
butcher's  experience  of  the  emptiness  of  the  left  heart-chamber  and  of  the 
arteries  should  have  been  maintained  up  to  the  final  era  of  the  science  of 
antiquity.^  The  warmed-up  blood  is  forced  from  the  right  cavity  of  the  heart 
out  into  the  body.  In  contrast  to  these  primitive  conceptions,  however,  cer- 
tain of  the  Hippocratics  have  had  some  idea,  though  a  vague  one,  of  the 
movement  of  the  blood  as  an  actual  circulation. 

Of  the  nervous  system  the  Hippocratic  school  had,  if  possible,  a  still 
vaguer  idea  than  of  the  circulation  of  the  blood.  The  brain  was  believed  to  be 
a  gland  which  segregates  water  and  possesses  the  function  of  cooling  the 
blood  and  collecting  mucus  out  of  the  body.  This  mucus  is  then  segregated, 
together  with  the  water,  by  a  catarrhal  affection  through  the  nose.  Certain 
later  Hippocratics,  however,  probably  influenced  by  Democritus,  have  a  more 
accurate  view  of  the  functions  of  the  brain,  believing  it  to  be  the  centre  of 
thought,  feeling,  and  motion.  The  nerves  are  invariably  confused  with  the 
tendons,  sometimes  also  with  the  veins,  and  for  this  reason  all  ideas  of  the 
functions  of  the  nervous  system  are  already  ruled  out.  Certain  of  the  most 
important  cerebral  nerves  are,  however,  described  and  named.  The  construc- 
tion of  the  eye  was  fairly  thoroughly  studied;  its  membranes  and  fluids,  as 
well  as  the  pupil,  were  known,  but  the  lens  was  unknown.  Sight  was  pro- 
duced as  a  reflection  of  the  object  seen  on  the  pupil.  Of  the  ear  the  bony  laby- 
rinth, the  auditory  canal,  and  the  tympanum  were  known.  The  urogenital 
apparatus  is  described  in  its  main  features;  regarding  fertilization  there 
existed  then,  as  indeed  throughout  antiquity,  extraordinarily  fantastic  ideas. 

With  zoology  proper  the  Hippocratics  naturally  had  little  cause  to  con- 
cern themselves.  Nevertheless,  there  exists  a  treatise  On  Diet,  in  which  there 
are  enumerated  fifty-two  different  edible  animals,  arranged  on  a  certain  defi- 
nite system;  first  quadrupeds,  tame  and  wild,  birds,  fish  of  several  kinds,  in- 
cluding coast-fish,  mud-fish,  river-fish,  mussels,  and  crayfish.  This  so-called 
Coan  animal  system  has  the  advantage  of  differentiating  between  various  cate- 
gories of  living  creatures  —  a  first  primitive  attempt  at  proper  systematization. 

3  This  idea  possessed,  it  is  true,  the  sanctity  of  religion;  in  sacrificial  animals  the  arteries 
were  naturally  empty,  and  the  interior  parts  of  these  animals  were  examined  with  a  view  to 
basing  on  them  prophecies  of  the  future.  To  deny  the  results  of  such  examinations  would  of 
course  have  involved  wounding  time-sanctioned  religious  susceptibilities. 


CHAPTER    IV 

THE    END     OF     N  A  T  U  R  A  L  -  P  H  I  LO  SO  P  H  I  C  A  L    SPECULATION.     THE 
PREDECESSORS     OF     ARISTOTLE 

The  results  of  natural  philosophy 
A  N  ENTIRE  ERA  in  the  history  of  biology  closes  with  the  philosophers 
/  \  that  have  here  just  been  characterized  —  Democritus,  Hippocrates, 
JL  JL  and  his  school  —  an  era  which  may  properly  be  called  the  era  of 
natural-philosophical  speculation.  The  results  achieved  by  their  researches 
cannot  be  regarded  as  anything  but  magnificent;  for  the  first  time  in  the  his- 
tory of  humanity  to  have  built  up  a  real  natural  science  is  an  achievement 
worthy  of  the  highest  admiration,  however  modest  the  results  may  have  been 
in  certain  details.  This  research  work  had  so  far  been  directed  by  three  illus- 
trious representatives,  Anaximander,  Empedocles,  and  Democritus.  All  of 
them  sought  an  explanation  of  existence  as  a  natural  course  of  events;  in 
this  direction  Democritus  proceeded  as  far  as  human  thought  has  at  any 
period  proved  capable  of  going.  Nevertheless,  even  in  his  own  lifetime  the 
revolution  was  being  prepared  which  was  shortly  to  lead  Greek  thought  in 
entirely  different  directions.  The  first  ideas  on  which  this  change  was  based 
originated,  as  hinted  above,  from  the  school  of  the  Sophists.  The  new  prin- 
ciple that  they  taught  was  subjectivity:  "Man  is  the  measure  of  all  things.  " 
To  this  really  true  assertion  the  ancient  "physicists"  could  make  no  objec- 
tion; indeed,  their  cosmic  explanations  were  as  numerous  as  themselves, 
and  each  one  of  them  could  only  declare  dogmatically  that  his  own  views 
were  the  true  ones  and  thereupon  produce  a  number  of  more  or  less  illogical 
arguments  in  support  of  them.  The  claim  of  the  Sophists  as  to  man's  being 
the  measure  of  all  things  thus  for  the  time  did  away  with  all  objective  ex- 
planations of  natural  phenomena,  for  what  was  the  use  of  disputing  about 
matters  which  all  viewed  from  different  standpoints  if  all  could  be  equally 
right?  Sophistry  itself,  however,  when  consistently  applied,  led  to  pure 
nihilism,  both  intellectual,  in  that  the  object  was,  by  means  of  ingenious 
turns  of  phrase  ("sophisms"),  to  prove  absolutely  anything,  and  moral, 
in  that  all  generally  accepted  sound  traditions  were  held  in  contempt  as 
laying  a  restraint  upon  the  individual's  freedom  of  action.  If  all  scientific 
thought  were  not  to  be  destroyed  altogether,  its  preservation  must  be  sought 
by  turning  the  whole  trend  of  thinking  into  quite  a  different  direction.  And 
this  was  found  by  maintaining  that  human  thought,  however  much  it  may 

3° 


CLASSICAL  ANTIQUITY,  MIDDLE  AGES  31 
be  the  measure  of  all  things,  such  as  they  appear  here  on  earth,  is  nevertheless 
itself  subject  to  eternal  laws,  more  infallible  than  those  which  the  old  phys- 
icists saw  in  existence.  The  men  who  thus  saved  the  Greek  philosophy  from 
degenerating  into  empty  rhetoric  and  worthless  quibbles  were  two  Atheni- 
ans, Socrates  and  his  disciple  Plato.  Socrates  worked  exclusively  in  the 
ethical  sphere;  in  this  he  sought  for  standards  binding  for  all  and  emanating, 
not  from  ancient  tradition,  but  from  the  conscience  of  the  private  individual. 
"Anyone  can  become  virtuous  if  only  he  accepts  a  knowledge  of  virtue"; 
that  is  his  principal  doctrine,  and  this  knowledge  he  for  his  own  part  derived 
from  a  divine  voice  in  himself,  which  he  desired  also  to  awaken  in  his  fellow 
human  beings.  Nature  did  not  interest  him  in  the  least;  the  streets  of  Athens 
were  his  haunt,  he  said,  and  neither  trees  nor  stones  had  anything  to  teach 
him. 

Plato,  a  disciple  of  Socrates,  generalized  the  doctrine  of  standards  in 
the  ethical  sphere  which  he  learnt  from  his  master,  so  that  it  was  applied  to 
embrace  the  whole  of  the  intellectual  life  of  man.  Born  at  Athens  in  4x9  of 
a  distinguished  family,  he  attached  himself  to  Socrates  at  the  age  of  about 
twenty.  Upon  his  master's  death  he  left  Athens  and  made  extensive  journeys, 
afterwards  returning  to  Athens,  and  there  he  established  a  school  or  college 
known  as  the  "Academy,"  which  survived  long  after  his  death.  He  died 
in  347.  Like  Pythagoras,  he  was  a  clever  mathematician  and,  also  like  him, 
combined  ah  inclination  for  the  conclusive  deductions  of  mathematics  with 
a  strong  attraction  for  the  mystic.  In  the  dialogue  Thnaus,  in  which  he  pro- 
pounds his  theory  of  the  origin  of  the  universe,  the  functions  of  the  human 
body,  and  the  relation  of  man  to  nature,  he  has  evolved  a  history  of  creation, 
poetically  very  fine,  but  at  the  same  time  purely  mystical,  testifying,  it  is 
true,  to  his  high  ethical  aims,  but  of  no  greater  value  as  natural  science  than 
any  of  the  ancient  popular  cosmogonical  myths.  The  world  was  created  by 
an  eternal  and  perfect  god,  and  therefore  there  can  be  no  question  of  an  endless 
number  of  worlds,  as  Anaximander  and  Democritus  made  out,  but  only  one, 
and  this  single  world  must  have  received  the  most  perfect  of  all  shapes,  the 
sphere.  He  accepted  Democritus'  atomic  theory  to  the  extent  that  he  believed 
matter  to  be  composed  of  particles,  though  these  again  are  not  of  endless 
variety,  but  are  five  in  number,  corresponding  to  the  five  regular  polygons 
of  the  geometry  of  space  (Plato  was  one  of  the  founders  of  this  science  and 
one  of  the  foremost  geometricians  of  all  time)  —  so  that  each  element  has 
its  atomic  form:  fire  the  pyramid,  the  earth  the  cube,  the  air  the  octahedron, 
and  water  the  icosahedron;  the  dodecahedron  represents  the  heavens.  Now, 
this  geometrical  atomic  form  is  in  itself  no  more  dogmatic  than  the  entire 
atomic  theory  of  Democritus,  but  it  forms  the  starting-point  for  a  process 
of  natural  speculation  which  is  diametrically  opposed  to  it.  For  while 
Democritus  takes  as  his  starting-point  the  atoms  and  the  matter  formed  by 


31  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

them  as  being  the  only  really  existing  element,  Plato  finds  true  reality  in 
the  world  of  abstract  thought  and  maintains  that  what  is  perceptible  by 
the  senses  is  an  imperfect  image  of  the  eternal  ideal,  the  divine  intelli- 
gence, conceivable  only  by  abstract  thinking.  The  nearer  things  are  to 
the  divinity,  the  more  perfect  and  animate  do  they  become.  Thus  the 
stars  of  heaven  possess  a  higher  animate  life  than  man  and  are  created  in 
greater  likeness  to  the  supreme  intelligence.  Of  man  the  first  thing  to  be 
created  was  the  head,  which  Plato,  like  Democritus,  regarded  as  the  organ 
of  the  animate  soul;  the  head  has  very  nearly  the  spherical  form  corre- 
sponding to  the  ideal,  and  trunk  and  limbs  are  created  to  save  the  head  the 
trouble  of  rolling  along  the  ground.  In  the  trunk  dwells  a  lower,  mortal 
soul,  whose  best  part,  the  heart,  the  organ  of  courage,  is  separated  by  the 
diaphragm  from  the  organ  of  animal  desires,  the  digestive  apparatus,  the 
most  vital  part  of  which,  the  liver,  however,  has  the  merit  of  producing 
dreams  during  sleep,  from  which  the  future  can  be  predicted.  The  plants  on 
our  earth  are  created  to  provide  man  with  food;  animals,  again,  are  sprung 
from  men  whose  souls  have  degenerated  and  have  consequently  been  given 
an  inferior  dwelling;  first,  women  have  come  into  being  out  of  cowardly 
men's  souls,  then  birds  and  quadrupeds  out  of  such  human  beings  as  have 
neglected  their  intelligence,  and,  finally,  the  most  worthless  souls  have  been 
placed  in  aquatic  animals,  "which  may  not  even  breathe  pure  air."  This 
theory  of  the  migration  of  the  soul  is  clearly  reminiscent  of  that  of  Pythag- 
oras; from  him,  too,  no  doubt  originates  Plato's  mystical  theory  of  number, 
the  details  of  which  do  not  belong  to  our  present  subject. 

Systematt%ation  of  thought 
It  may  seem  unnecessary  to  dwell  so  long  on  these  fantasies.  They  are,  how- 
ever, well  worth  noting,  for  their  originator  has  exercised  a  rare  and  radi- 
cal influence  on  human  culture  in  its  entirety  and  even,  as  we  shall  find  later 
on,  no  small  influence  upon  the  development  of  biological  science.  His  philo- 
sophical speculations  related  above  have  in  this  respect  had  but  little  signif- 
icance. Plato's  greatest  contribution  has  been  made  in  the  sphere  of  the 
purely  ideal  intellectual  life.  The  spirit  of  man  is,  he  said,  bound  by  laws  far 
more  abiding  than  those  that  may  be  deduced  from  natural  phenomena.  To 
these  inflexible  standards  for  intellectual  activity  he  is  led  by  speculations 
in  the  ethical  sphere,  in  which,  following  Socrates,  he  found  a  definite  paral- 
lel between  human  actions  and  their  consequences.  Having  advanced  thus 
far,  he  devoted  himself  to  developing  this  theory  of  the  conditions,  bound 
by  immutable  law,  of  the  world  of  ideas,  in  which,  as  mentioned  above,  he 
saw  the  true  existence,  of  which  the  phenomena  visible  in  natural  life  are 
mere  images.  Everything  on  this  earth,  then,  has  its  eternal  idea  as  its  proto- 
type; every  individual  horse  is  an  imperfect  image  of  the  idea  horse,  which 
is  eternal  and  perfect.  Through  this  reasoning  Plato  came  to  be  the  founder 


CLASSICAL     ANTIQUITY,     MIDDLE     AGES        33 

of  the  system  of  ideas,  which  has  played  an  important  part  in  biology;  out 
of  the  idea  horse  in  contradistinction  to  the  individual  has  arisen  the  no- 
tion of  species,  and  gradually  likewise  all  higher  systematical  categories.  It 
is  easy  to  realize  the  immense  influence  this  has  had  on  biological  research.  A 
mass  of  detailed  ideas  in  systematization  —  for  instance,  the  dichotomic  classi- 
fication tables  of  genera  and  species  —  come  from  the  Platonic  school.  And, 
mathematician  as  he  was,  Plato  further  endeavoured  to  make  his  inferences  as 
conclusive  as  possible;  the  listener  and  the  reader  should  realize  that  the 
result  of  the  investigation  must  be  so  and  could  not  be  otherwise.  Thus  for  the 
first  time  in  the  history  of  science  he  not  only  made  assertions,  but  also  sub- 
mitted proofs  of  them,  based,  it  is  true,  upon  abstract  reasoning,  as  was  the 
entire  world  of  thought  which  he  built  up,  but  at  least  formally  convincing. 

Theory  of  ideas 
But  if  Plato,  in  laying  the  foundation  of  biological  systematization,  made 
a  powerful  contribution  to  the  progress  of  biology,  nevertheless  his  activities 
proved  in  other  respects  unfortunate  for  it.  The  enunciation  of  the  world  of 
ideas  as  the  true  essence  of  being  led  to  the  underestimation  of  nature  and  of 
the  senses  by  which  man  observes  nature.  Plato  realized  the  relativity  and 
limitation  of  observation  through  the  senses,^  but  not  the  arbitrariness  to 
which  abstract  thinking  may  lead  if  it  is  not  controlled  by  observations.  In 
the  Timaus  he  expressly  states  that  no  true  knowledge  is  to  be  acquired 
through  the  observations  of  the  senses,  but  only  a  pleasure  to  the  eye  suitable 
for  a  diversion  —  a  statement  which  has  been  repeated  after  him  by  innumer- 
able idealistic  philosophers,  both  major  and  minor.  Plato,  the  creator  and 
perhaps  also,  so  far,  the  greatest  upholder  of  idealistic  philosophy,  is  like- 
wise responsible  for  the  contempt  with  which  this  trend  of  thought,  which 
otherwise  deserves  such  high  praise  for  contributing  towards  the  develop- 
ment of  human  thought,  regarded  natural  philosophy.  History  indeed  shows 
that  the  more  the  idealistic  philosophy  governed  man's  desire  for  knowledge, 
the  greater  became  his  indifference  to  the  study  of  nature.  In  a  far  greater 
degree  than  the  traditional  religions,  idealistic  philosophy  has  been  the  an- 
tipodes of  natural  science. 

On  the  whole,  Plato's  disciples  followed  in  their  master's  footsteps. 
Of  the  exact  sciences  mathematics  interested  them  most  and  they  worked  at  it 
with  great  energy;  otherwise,  like  many  other  schools  of  thought  emanating 
from  the  Socratic  circle,  they  mostly  occupied  themselves  with  ethical  ques- 
tions. Even  in  Plato's  lifetime,  however,  one  of  his  disciples  in  the  Academy 
had  begun  to  discard  his  ideas  in  a  number  of  essentials  and  started  to  guide 
philosophy  in  a  new  direction.  This  man  was  Aristotle,  the  greatest  biologist 
of  antiquity  and  one  of  the  most  many-sided  natural  philosophers  of  all  time. 

^  As  a  matter  of  fact,  Democritus  had  already  realized  this,  but  was  unable  to  develop  the 
thought  further. 


CHAPTER    V 


ARISTOTLE 


A  RisTOTLE  was  bom  in  384  b.c.  at  Stagira,  a  small  Greek  colony  on  the 
/  \  Macedonian  coast.  His  father,  Nicomachus,  belonged  to  an  old  fam- 
^  3L  ily  of  the  Asclepiads  and  was,  like  several  of  his  ancestors,  body- 
physician  to  the  Macedonian  royal  family.  His  predecessors  among  the  Greek 
philosophers  had  lived  amongst  the  mobile  and  restless  communities  of  the 
city  republics,  while  Aristotle  spent  his  childhood  at  a  royal  court,  and  a 
semi-barbarous  one  at  that.  This  fact  undoubtedly  put  its  stamp  on  his  per- 
sonality and  way  of  thought;  he  became  in  every  respect  an  upholder  of 
authority  and  conservatism.  At  an  early  age  he  lost  his  father,  and  his 
mother,  Phasstias,  retired  to  her  native  city  and  brought  up  her  children  there. 
Aristotle  received  his  earliest  education,  in  accordance  with  the  ancient  As- 
clepiad  tradition,  from  his  father's  colleagues,  who  initiated  him  into  the 
biological  and  medical  learning  of  their  profession.  It  was  necessary,  how- 
ever, for  a  properly  educated  physician  to  receive  also  philosophical  instruc- 
tion, and  for  this  purpose  Aristotle  was  sent  at  the  age  of  eighteen  to  Plato's 
Academy  at  Athens.  There  he  remained  for  twenty  years,  was  initiated  into 
the  teachings  of  his  master,  wrote  his  first  treatise,  and  already  at  that 
period  began  to  oppose  his  master's  authority,  which  the  latter  is  said  to 
have  observed  with  no  little  displeasure.  After  Plato's  death  he  was  passed 
over  at  the  election  of  a  successor  as  head  of  the  Academy,  in  spite  of  his 
already  established  reputation,  and  retired  to  Asia  Minor,  where  he  settled 
down  at  the  court  of  the  Persian  vassal-prince  Hermeias  of  Atarneus,  who 
gave  him  his  niece  in  marriage.  Some  years  later,  however,  Hermeias  was 
deposed  under  a  revolution,  and  Aristotle  had  to  flee  to  the  country  of  his 
birth,  Macedonia.  There  he  was  charged  with  the  task  of  educating  the  heir 
to  the  throne,  Alexander,  the  future  conqueror  of  the  world,  and  he  held  this 
post  for  three  years  (338-335).  What  influence  the  master  exercised  on  the 
pupil  it  is  of  course  difficult  to  decide;  the  relations  between  them,  however, 
were  on  the  whole  good,  though  Alexander's  increasingly  despotic  character 
and  barbaric  outbursts  of  passion  must  have  off'ended  the  cultured,  self- 
controlled  Aristotle.  His  profession  as  teacher  at  any  rate  brought  Aristotle 
illustrious  honours  and  made  him  a  wealthy  man,  able  to  choose  his  place 
of  abode  and  his  sphere  of  activity.  He  then  moved  back  to  Athens  and  lived 
there  under  the  protection  of  Alexander,  highly  esteemed  by  a  constantly 

34 


CLASSICAL  ANTIQUITY,  MIDDLE  AGES  35 
increasing  throng  of  pupils  for  the  space  of  twelve  years.  During  this  period 
he  displayed  indefatigable  activity.  He  was  granted  the  right  to  use  for  edu- 
cational purposes  a  temple  dedicated  to  Apollo  Lycieus,  after  whom  the  place 
was  called  the  Lyceum,  the  archetype  of  learned  educational  institutions 
throughout  the  world.  Here  every  morning  Aristotle  gave  scientific  lectures 
to  his  chosen  pupils,  often  old  and  highly  reputed  men  of  science,  who  col- 
laborated with  him;  and,  further,  every  evening  he  held  more  popular  courses 
for  younger  collegiates.  Moreover,  he  found  time  to  write  an  incredible 
amount  on  very  different  subjects:  logic,  metaphysics,  art,  politics,  psychol- 
ogy, and  biology.  This  extraordinary  activity  testifies  to  his  inexhaustible  en- 
ergy and  splendid  powers  of  organization.  It  is  obvious  that  his  disciples  had 
to  carry  out  the  rough  work.  Aristotle  kept  aloof  from  public  life;  indeed, 
he  was  a  foreigner  in  Athens.  He  was  a  conservative  and  a  monarchist,  how- 
ever, and  when  after  Alexander's  death  Athens  rebelled  against  the  Mace- 
donian supremacy,  his  position  became  dangerous.  For  lack  of  other  means 
of  calumniating  him  he  was  accused,  like  Socrates,  of  "godlessness."  In 
order,  as  he  himself  said,  to  save  the  Athenians  from  committing  a  fresh  crime 
against  philosophy  he  fled  to  the  island  of  Euboea;  there  he  died  shortly 
afterwards,  in  the  year  3x1.  In  external  appearance  he  is  said  to  have  been  of 
small  stature  and  corpulent;  his  carriage  was  proud,  his  manners  arrogant  and 
sarcastic,  his  dress  and  way  of  living  courtly,  refined,  and  elegant.  These 
latter  characteristics  brought  him  personal  enemies,  who  sought  to  blacken 
his  character.  It  is  not  possible,  however,  to  bring  any  serious  accusations 
against  him  as  a  private  person.  It  is  true  he  appropriated  with  considerable 
lack  of  bias  the  results  of  the  work  of  earlier  philosophers,  but  the  ideas  of 
literary  copyright  were  not  so  strict  as  they  are  now.  On  the  other  hand,  he 
treated  different  thinkers  with  true  humanity;  his  polemics,  when  he  went 
in  for  them,  were  always  courteous  and  his  arguments  founded  on  facts. 
Towards  his  family,  his  friends  and  pupils,  and  even  his  slaves  he  was  affec- 
tionate and  considerate. 

Aristotle's  sphere  of  activity  was,  as  mentioned  above,  extraordinarily 
extensive,  and  equally  universal  has  been  his  influence  during  these  thousands 
of  years  in  such  widely  separated  spheres  as  biology,  metaphysics,  statesman- 
ship, and  art.  In  the  present  work  it  is  of  course  possible  to  deal  at  any  length 
only  with  his  biological  work;  besides  this,  however,  we  must  touch  upon 
his  general  ideas  so  far  as  they  affect  his  views  on  life  in  nature.  And  as  varied 
as  his  own  interests  have  been  the  judgments  passed  on  him  by  others;  he 
has  been  by  turns  elevated  to  the  skies  and  dragged  in  the  mud.  On  the  whole 
the  biologists  have  been  the  most  loyal;  up  to  recent  times,  and  not  least  in 
our  own  day,  he  has  had  devoted  admirers,  and  his  works  have  been  remark- 
ably free  from  the  bitter  criticisms  which  biologists  of  more  recent  times 
(Linnaeus,  for  example)  have  passed  on  his  predecessors.  The  philosophers 


36  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

proper  have  judged  him  far  more  sternly;  they  have  realized  far  more  clearly 
the  deficiencies  in  his  system  of  thought,  and  the  weaknesses  inherent  in  its 
structure.  The  idealistic  philosophers  have  accused  him  of  vitiating  Plato's 
theory  of  ideas,  while  adherents  of  critical  philosophy  have  criticized  his 
dogmatic  ideas  of  the  universe.  His  extraordinary  influence  both  on  his  con- 
temporaries and  on  posterity,  however,  no  one  can  deny. 

Form  the  true  reality  of  matter 
As  a  thinker  Aristotle  bases  his  system  on  Plato.  According  to  Plato  the  ideas 
of  eternity  are  existing  realities,  of  which  the  things  of  our  earth  are  an  im- 
perfect image.  Aristotle  adopted  the  theory  of  ideas,  but  sought  to  overcome 
the  difficulty  arising  out  of  the  questions  how  ideas  are  really  related  to 
things  and  how  they  influence  them,  by  placing  ideas  not  outside  things  as 
something  independent  and  apart  from  their  existence,  but  in  things  them- 
selves. And  he  regarded  the  form  of  everything  as  its  idea,  as  its  true  reality. 
Form  is  the  thing's  reality,  matter  is  a  potentiality,  to  which  form  gives 
reality.  The  bronze  of  which  the  statue  is  made  is  a  potentiality;  the  form 
which  the  sculptor  gives  it  makes  of  the  statue  a  reality.  This  method  of 
observation,  derived  from  human  life,  Aristotle  applies  with  inflexible  con- 
sistency to  the  whole  of  nature,  both  animate  and  inanimate.  Thus  the  seed 
is  a  potentiality  out  of  which  the  germinating  plant  develops  reality.  The 
same  is  true  of  the  t^g  and  the  embryo  in  relation  to  the  creature  which 
develops  therefrom.  Consequently  every  lower  stage  of  development  is  a 
potentiality  in  relation  to  the  higher  stage  of  development  which  represents 
its  full  realization.  Thus  we  gtt  a  whole  series  of  stages  of  development,  be- 
ginning with  completely  formless  matter,  which  is  an  exclusive  potentiality 
without  any  reality  at  all,  through  inanimate  nature,  in  which  matter  is 
stronger  than  form,  to  the  animate,  in  which  form  governs  matter.  Form  in 
living  creatures  is  the  soul,  and  the  more  highly  developed  it  is,  the  more  does 
it  control  the  corporeal  matter.  Plants  have  a  lower  kind  of  soul,  which  only 
lives,  but  does  not  feel;  animals  possess  a  higher,  sensitive  soul,  and,  finally, 
man  has  conscious  reason.  The  means  whereby  form  gives  expression  to  its 
dominance  over  matter  is  motion;  all  that  occurs  in  the  universe  is  motion, 
and  the  more  form-perfect  the  motion  is,  the  higher  the  development  it 
represents.  Our  earth,  therefore,  with  its  manifold  irregularities,  is  a  lower 
form  of  existence  than  the  heavens,  whose  celestial  bodies  possess  the  most 
perfect  motion,  circular  motion.  The  heavenly  bodies  keep  their  position 
and  motion  owing  to  their  being  enclosed  in  transparent  spheres,  one  outside 
the  other.  Thus  they  represent  to  the  mind  of  Aristotle,  as  to  that  of  Plato, 
a  higher  form  of  existence  than  the  earth  with  its  creatures,  including  man, 
and  outside  the  outermost  celestial  sphere  is  the  world  of  form  free  from  all 
matter,  the  highest  intelligent  existence,  God,  the  fundamental  origin  of  all 
motion.  Since,  then,  existence  has  its  origin  in  a  supreme  intelligence,  it  is 


CLASSICAL     ANTIQUITY,     MIDDLE     AGES        37 

natural  that  everything  that  happens  has  an  intellectual  cause,  and  every- 
thing exists  to  serve  a  given  purpose.  This  purpose  is,  above  all,  the  develop- 
ment of  a  higher  form,  the  striving  towards  a  higher  intellectual  existence. 
Natural  necessity  and  its  cause,  chance,  have,  it  is  true,  their  part  to  play  on 
the  earth,  but  only  as  an  attendant  of  incomplete  matter;  in  the  heavenly 
spheres  nothing  happens  by  chance,  but  all  is  intellectual,  while  on  the 
earth  the  higher  intelligence  is  victorious  over  its  lower  opponents.  But  con- 
sequently terrestrial  life,  including  man,  is  also  governed  by  the  higher 
intelligence  of  the  heavenly  bodies,  which  get  their  impulses  direct  from 
God. 

The  first  evolutionist 
Thus  Aristotle  makes  his  biological  theories  a  link  in  the  general  cosmogony 
which  he  built  up  on  the  fundamental  principle  of  the  domination  of  form  — 
that  is,  of  the  spirit  over  matter,  and  of  motion  as  the  origin  of  all  things. 
The  whole  world  of  this  thought-structure  is  as  foreign  to  our  modern  ideas 
as  it  could  possibly  be;  Democritus'  atomic  theory  is  far  nearer  our  own 
notions.  Nevertheless,  Aristotle's  theory  implies  an  absolute  advance  in  the 
sphere  of  biology.  Here  we  find  enunciated  for  the  first  time  a  really  complete 
theory  of  evolution.  To  the  old  natural  philosophers,  Democritus  among 
them,  existence  was  a  casual  change  of  different  forms.  Again,  Aristotle  saw 
a  consistent  evolution  from  lower  to  higher  forms  of  being,  and  although  it 
is  based  on  purely  metaphysical  speculation,  this  idea  has  proved  for  all  time 
a  fertile  one  in  the  biological  sphere,  for  the  very  reason  that  it  is  here  in 
agreement  with  actual  fact.  Quite  in  accordance  with  this  his  fundamental 
principle,  Aristotle  also  made  special  investigation  into  the  development  of 
animals  from  the  tgg  and  embryo  to  the  perfect  state,  and  in  this  sphere  he 
has  made  his  most  important  contribution  to  biological  research.  But  other- 
wise his  philosophical  and  educational  activities  embraced  the  whole  of 
biology,  as  it  was  known  at  that  time,  as  well  as  all  natural  phenomena  in 
general.  Of  his  purely  biological  works  the  following  are  extant:  ten  books 
On  the  History  of  Animals,  of  which,  however,  three  are  considered  spurious; 
four  books  On  the  Parts  of  Animals;  five  books  On  the  Reproduction  of  Animals; 
and  three  books  On  the  Soul.  In  these  treatises  he  has  collected  all  contempo- 
rary knowledge  of  animal  life,  not  only  his  own  and  his  pupils'  personal 
observations,  but  also  all  the  knowledge  that  his  extensive  collections  of 
books  could  impart  regarding  the  observations  of  the  earlier  philosophers. 
All  this  material  he  worked  up  with  a  view  to  including  it  in  his  general 
cosmic  theory.  It  has  been  said  that  "never  before  or  since  has  a  scheme  been 
so  completely  carried  out  with  a  view  to  incorporating  biology  in  one  com- 
mon science,  while  at  the  same  time  by  personal  observations  and  literary 
notes  systematically  building  it  up  into  one  unit  out  of  the  phenomena" 
(Burckhardt).  This  is  true,  and  the  reason  for  it  is  to  be  found  in  that  unique 


38  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

genius  for  the  purely  formal  side  of  thinking  which  belongs  to  Aristotle 
alone;  he  is  in  fact  the  founder  of  formal  logic  and  in  that  sphere  his  laws 
hold  good  to  this  day.  He  is,  therefore,  also  the  originator  of  biological 
classification,  not  only  because  he  determined  those  categories  in  which 
human  thought  has  since  primitive  times  sought  to  arrange  natural  objects, 
and  because  he  subordinated  these  to  the  general  laws  of  thought  which  he 
created,  but  also  in  that  he  sought  to  interpret  and  combine  into  a  law- 
bound  whole  those  phenomena  which  accompany  life  in  all  its  forms.  By 
this  work  he  has  paved  the  way,  as  no  one  else  has  done,  for  the  further 
development  of  biology  as  a  science  based  on  fixed  principles.  And  his  influ- 
ence has  extended  to  our  own  day;  many  of  the  biologists  of  our  own  time 
have  revived  certain  expressions  out  of  his  terminology  and  have  been  influ- 
enced more  or  less  directly  by  his  ideas,  particularly  in  regard  to  evolution. 
But  his  great  gift  for  form  has  also  its  darker  side.  He  who  saw  in  form  the 
true  content  of  existence  could  not  imagine  a  world  to  be  other  than  finite  — 
spherical,  for  the  sphere  is  the  most  perfect  form  —  and  as  he  could  not  visual- 
ize an  infinite  world,  he  could  not  imagine  infinite  potentialities  of  knowl- 
edge; on  the  contrary,  he  expressly  declared  that  his  own  system,  complete 
as  it  was,  would  make  it  possible  to  solve  all  problems.  But  for  that  reason 
he  takes  up  all  questions  for  discussion,  even  such  as  in  our  time  would 
be  received  with  the  old  proverb  "A  fool  can  ask  more  than  seven  wise  men 
can  answer."  Often  when  reading  his  writings  one  can  fancy  that  one  hears 
an  inquisitive  pupil  offering  objections  which  the  master  takes  up  with  un- 
disturbed calm  and  answers  with  unerring  assurance  in  accordance  with  the 
principles  of  his  system;  as,  for  instance,  why  men,  and  not  women,  be- 
come bald;  why  the  sow  produces  many  pigs  while  the  cow  bears  only  one  calf, 
etc.  The  result  is  that,  while  the  reader  can  sometimes  trace  in  his  writings 
the  pen  of  a  biologist  with  almost  a  modern  view  of  life's  phenomena;  on  the 
next  page  he  may  receive  the  impression  of  a  master  of  scholastic  disputation 
from  a  mediaeval  university.  Many  of  the  irregularities  may  certainly  be  due 
to  his  treatises  not  having  been  carefully  planned  out;  a  number  of  them  are 
probably  notes  of  lectures  published  by  his  pupils,  and  as  such  are  perhaps 
in  places  based  on  misapprehensions  of  the  meaning  of  the  lectures. 

To  give  a  complete  description  of  Aristotle's  biological  works  would  be 
a  voluminous  task  and  would  result  in  a  wearisome  mass  of  detail.  In  order, 
however,  to  give  some  idea  of  the  peculiarities  of  his  work,  a  brief  account 
must  here  be  given  of  his  position  as  regards  the  various  main  sections  of 
biology. 

Aristotle's  classification  of  animals 
In  regard  to  the  classification  of  animals,  Aristotle,  as  was  hinted  above, 
has  made  an  essentially  important  contribution  to  the  subject  by  differentiat- 
ing between  and  analysing  and  characterizing,  from  different  points  of  view. 


CLASSICAL     ANTIQUITY,     MIDDLE     AGES        39 

a  number  of  systematic  categories.  "Animals  may  be  characterized  accord- 
ing to  their  way  of  living,  their  actions,  their  habits,  and  their  bodily  parts. ' ' 
According  to  the  three  first-named  principles  they  are  divided  into  land- 
animals  and  aquatic  animals;  certain  of  the  latter  live  entirely  i.'i  the  water  — 
the  fishes;  others  live  most  of  their  time  there,  but  breathe  and  breed  outside 
it  —  otters,  beavers,  crocodiles.  The  water-animals  can  partly  swim,  partly 
creep,  and  in  part  they  are  adherent.  The  land-animals  have  similar  charac- 
teristics as  regards  habitat  and  way  of  living,  feeding,  habits,  and  character. 
The  most  important  bases  of  classification,  however,  are  the  parts  of  ani- 
mals' bodies,  both  external  and  internal:  motive  organs,  respiration,  organs 
of  sense,  blood-circulation.  By  combining  various  qualities  the  groups  are 
defined  and  characterized.  These  groups  are  variously  extensive:  "Many 
animals  allow  of  association  into  large  divisions,  such  as  birds,  fishes,  and 
whales,"  and,  further,  ink-fish,  shell-fish  or  mussels,  and  crayfi:li.  Others 
are  more  difficult  to  classify,  such  as  the  quadrupeds,  which  may  certainly  be 
classified  as  oviparous  and  viviparous,  but  amongst  these  it  is  not  possible 
to  make  subdivisions,  the  animals  having  to  be  characterized  each  separately. 
The  categories  which  Aristotle  thus  established  he  never  summarized;  his 
tabulated  and  generally  recognized  "system"  has  been  extracted  from  his 
writings  by  others  and  need  not  be  repeated  here,  all  the  more  so  as  it  is 
reproduced  in  different  ways  by  different  authors.  Otherwise,  his  systematic 
categories  are  only  two  in  number,  the  genos  and  the  eidos,  the  latter  corre- 
sponding to  the  individual  animal  form  —  horse,  dog,  lion  —  the  former  to 
all  combinations  of  a  higher  degree.  That  is  really  the  reason  why  his  sys- 
tem cannot  be  compared  with  the  Linnxan,  with  its  manifold  categories, 
though  it  by  no  means  detracts  from  its  pioneer  importance  for  all  time. 

His  knoivledge  of  forms 
In  connexion  with  the  system  of  Aristotle  a  few  words  may  be  said  about 
his  knowledge  of  form  —  about  the  material  out  of  which  he  built  up  his 
system.  In  his  writings  have  been  recognized  about  5x0  of  the  species  which 
present-day  zoology  has  classified.  These  forms  all  belong  to  Greece  and  its 
seas,  and  it  seems  that  marine  fauna  interested  him  more  almost  than  land 
fauna;  fishes,  molluscs,  and  crustaceans  are  better  represented  in  his  works 
than  land-animals  —  in  sharp  contrast  to  what  was  afterwards  the  case  with 
Linnasus.  Exotic  animals  Aristotle  knows  only  from  the  descriptions  of 
others;  it  has  often  been  stated  that  Alexander  used  to  send  him  material  for 
investigation  from  the  countries  he  conquered,  but  this  can  hardly  be  true. 
The  crocodile,  for  instance,  he  describes  in  the  exact  words  of  Herodotus 
and  he  accepts  as  true  without  further  comment  the  latter's  statement  that 
the  upper  jaw  of  that  creature  is  jointed  on  the  lower  jaw  —  which  he  would 
never  have  said  had  he  seen  a  crocodile.  Still  more  remarkable  is  the  fact 
that  he  apparently  never  saw,  or  at  any  rate  never  carefully  examined,  a 


40  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

lion;  in  fact,  he  says  of  this  animal  that  it  has  no  cervical  vertebras,  but  in- 
stead has  a  single  conjoining  bone.  In  another  place  he  declares  of  a  lion's 
bones  that  they  are  so  hard  that  they  give  off  sparks  when  struck,  like  flint, 
and  that  they  are  "said"  to  have  no  medullary  cavity.  How  much  Aristotle 
in  general  borrowed  from  the  wisdom  of  his  predecessors  it  is  impossible  to 
determine,  as  their  writings  have  been  lost  and  he  never  quotes  others  except 
with  polemical  intent.  But  examples  such  as  those  cited  above  undoubtedly 
testify  to  a  quite  uncritical  exploitation  of  foreign  sources,  and  it  is  manifest 
that  the  value  of  Aristotle  lies  not  so  much  in  the  facts  he  established  as  in 
the  systematic  working-up  of  the  scientific  material  he  had  at  his  disposal. 
And  this  systematizing  work  of  his  was  of  course  as  comprehensive  as  was 
possible  with  the  means  available  at  the  time.  It  is  not  only  the  outward 
form  of  animals  and  their  existence  that  interests  him;  he  studies  the  migra- 
tions of  birds  and  the  wanderings  of  fishes  and  tries  to  discover  the  causes 
that  underlie  these  habits;  he  critically  examines  the  outward  manifesta- 
tions of  animal  intelligence,  and  everywhere  he  closely  compares  different 
forms  of  life. 

He  chiefly  occupies  himself,  however,  with  the  anatomical  and  mor- 
phological structure  of  animals,  as  well  as  with  their  reproduction  and 
evolution.  These  two  spheres  of  investigation  he  has  elaborated  with  the 
utmost  care,  and  here  we  find  he  stands  out  most  prominently  as  the  founder 
of  comparative  natural  philosophy.  His  t/eatises  on  human  anatomy  have 
been  lost,  but  his  great  descriptive  work  on  animals  is  extant  and  deals 
mainly  with  anatomical  questions.  Here  he  at  once,  in  the  very  beginning  of 
the  work,  lays  down  that  anatomical  research  should  be  comparative;  the 
less  known  should  be  studied  by  comparison  with  the  better  known,  and 
since  the  structure  of  the  human  body  is  best  known,  that  should  be  the 
point  of  departure.  Following  this  method,  he  goes  through  the  parts  of  the 
body,  the  external  as  well  as  the  internal.  He  bases  his  general  anatomical 
ideas  on  the  same  principles  as  Empedocles  and  the  Hippocratic  writings, 
and  certainly  also  as  Democritus.  With  the  first-mentioned  he  holds  that  all 
beings  are  composed  of  four  elements,  while  for  him,  too,  the  contraries  hot 
and  cold  are  of  fundamental  importance.  His  description  of  human  anatomy, 
which  forms  the  first  book  of  his  work  on  animal  life,  is  of  unequal  value 
and,  as  regards  its  details,  undoubtedly  very  much  dependent  upon  the  state- 
ments of  others;  but  his  manner  of  summarizing  his  description  is  excellent. 
As  to  his  description  of  the  internal  anatomy,  he  frankly  acknowledges  that 
it  is  founded  upon  conclusions  drawn  from  the  dissection  of  animals,  and, 
broadly  speaking,  it  is  not  very  different  from  the  Hippocratic  writings  re- 
ferred to  above.  Thus  the  heart  is  to  Aristotle  the  organ  of  the  soul  and  the 
intelligence,  the  brain  serves  the  purpose  of  producing  mucus  and  cooling 
the  blood;  in  this  respect  his  ideas  are  inferior  to  those  of  both  Democritus 


CLASSICAL     ANTIQUITY,     MIDDLE     AGES       41 

ind  Plato.  The  circulatory  system  is  described  in  the  same  way  as  in  Hippoc- 
rates. The  various  parts  of  the  digestive  canal  are  described  in  some  detail, 
but  as  regards  the  physiology  of  the  digestive  process  he  has  extremely 
primitive  and  vague  ideas,  which  is  not  to  be  wondered  at,  seeing  that 
the  science  of  chemistry  did  not  yet  exist.  "Cooking"  plays  the  essential 
part  in  his  physiology.  The  food  is  "cooked"  in  the  intestinal  tube;  the 
heart  pulsates  through  the  regular  "ebullition"  of  the  blood.  With  regard  to 
the  nervous  system  his  notions  are  equally  vague;  as  is  indicated  above,  the 
brain  is  cold,  the  spinal  marrow  is  hot;  nerves  and  tendons  are  confused.  The 
aural  cochlea  is  described,  as  are  also  the  membranes  of  the  eye;  the  moisture 
of  the  eye  is  believed  to  receive  the  visual  impressions.  It  is  curious  to  note 
the  amount  of  popular  superstition  that  is  accepted,  as,  for  instance,  predic- 
tions read  from  the  lines  of  the  hand,  or  the  idea  that  flat-footed  people  are 
of  a  treacherous  disposition.  In  the  comparative  anatomy  and  morphology 
of  animals  Aristotle  shows  his  many-sided  interest  in  all  kinds  of  life-forms 
and  his  immense  power  of  combining  observations  of  various  qualities  with 
striking  characteristics.  "Four-footed  beasts  which  produce  their  young 
alive  have  hair;  four-footed  beasts  that  lay  eggs  have  scales."  "A  single- 
hoofed  animal  with  two  horns  I  have  never  seen.  .  .  .  No  animal  has  at  the 
same  time  tusks  and  horns."  He  also  makes  many  sound  observations  re- 
garding birds  and  reptiles,  as,  for  example,  in  reference  to  the  outer  structure 
of  the  sensory  organs.  A  distinction  is  made  between  whales  and  fishes,  and 
the  gills  forming  the  breathing-apparatus  of  fish  are  described  with  emphasis 
on  the  difference  between  osseans  and  sharks.  Of  the  lower  animals  —  the 
bloodless,  as  Aristotle  calls  them,  after  the  example  of  Democritus  —  the 
ink-fish  in  particular  is  minutely  described,  many  carefully  observed  details 
being  given.  Crayfish,  too,  and  insects  are  cleverly  described  in  part,  though 
with  some  inaccurate  details. 

Reproduction  of  animals  asexual  and  sexual 
In  his  work  on  the  reproduction  of  animals  Aristotle  differentiates  between 
animals  which  reproduce  themselves  by  sexual  means,  by  asexual  means, 
and  by  spontaneous  generation.  The  latter  occurs  in  a  number  of  lower 
animals  which  are  produced  out  of  putrefying  substances;  among  these  are 
specially  mentioned  certain  insects,  such  as  fleas,  mosquitoes,  and  day-flies 
(other  insects,  such  as  grasshoppers,  wasps,  and  flies,  have  sexual  reproduc- 
tion). Among  the  shell-fishes  some  are  produced  by  asexual  means  through 
bud-formation,  others  through  self-generation.  The  possibility  of  this  latter 
method  is  explained  by  the  fact  that  the  whole  of  nature  is  full  of  life-spirit 
or  "soul";  this,  under  certain  circumstances,  gives  form  to  the  inanimate 
matter  and  so  gives  rise  to  new  beings.  Sexual  reproduction,  again,  is  due  to 
the  occurrence  of  male  and  female  individuals.  Of  these  two  the  male  —  or 
more  properly  the  man,  for  Aristotle  takes  as  his  starting-point  here,  as 


41  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

always,  man  —  represents  the  more  complete,  "warmer"  element,  and  the 
female,  the  woman,  the  more  incomplete,  the  "colder"  element.  The  mascu- 
line represents,  above  all,  form,  motion,  activity;  the  feminine  is  matter, 
the  passive,  and  consequently  potentiality,  which  achieves  reality  through 
form.  It  is  expressly  asserted  that  the  earth  represents  in  the  universe  the 
womanly  and  maternal,  the  sun  the  manly  — •  that  is  to  say,  the  ancient 
view  held  by  most  natural  religions.  The  male  sex-product,  the  seed,  is  a 
product  of  the  blood,  which  through  complete  "cooking"  receives  the 
purest  and  most  form-creating  qualities.  The  woman's  sex-product  is  the 
menstrual  blood,  which  is  an  undeveloped  sperm  —  "half  cooked,"  because 
the  woman  is  weaker,  "colder"  than  man,  and  has  not  the  power  to  cook  her 
product  completely.  In  impregnation  the  man  contributes  to  the  future  child 
form,  motion,  soul;  the  woman  matter,  body;  his  contribution  is  compared 
with  the  work  of  a  carpenter,  hers  with  the  timber  of  which  things  are  made. 
Holding  this  view  of  reproduction,  Aristotle,  when  making  his  thorough  in- 
vestigation into  the  question  of  heredity,  can  of  course  only  involve  himself 
still  deeper  in  abstract  speculations.  Against  the  opinion  of  earlier  philoso- 
phers that  the  seed  is  derived  from  all  parts  of  the  body  and  therefore  gives 
rise  to  similar  individuals  as  issue,  he  asserts  that  on  the  contrary  the  seed 
goes  to  the  different  parts  of  the  body,  through  which  process  a  remainder 
is  left  over  for  the  next  generation,  "as  with  a  portrait-painter,  a  certain 
amount  of  colour  is  left  over  similar  to  that  which  was  used  for  the  portrait. ' ' 
If  the  man's  form-building  power  is  sufficiently  strong,  the  child  will  be  a 
boy;  otherwise  a  girl;  for  that  reason  very  young  and  very  old  fathers  have 
mostly  girl-children.  The  cold  north  wind  also  favours  the  birth  of  girls,  for 
warmth  is  strength.  The  explanation  of  why  children  resemble  partly  their 
parents  and  partly  their  ancestors  is  very  complicated  and  ingenious,  for  all 
its  abstractness,  but  it  would  take  too  long  to  examine  it  here.  Of  far  greater 
value  than  these  metaphysical  speculations,  at  any  rate,  are  Aristotle's 
observations  on  the  reproduction  of  animals.  He  draws  up  a  scale  in  which 
the  animals  are  placed  according  to  their  development  and  points  out  that 
those  animals  are  highest  which  have  a  warm  and  moist,  and  not  an  earthy, 
nature.  For  all  animals  with  lungs  are  warmer  than  those  without  lungs, 
and  of  those  provided  with  lungs,  again,  the  warmest  are  those  which  have 
not  tough,  spongy,  and  anasmic,  but  soft  and  sanguineous  lungs.  The  most 
perfect  animals,  those  which  possess  most  warmth  and  moisture,  whose 
young  are  born  alive  and  immediately  start  growing,  are  the  mammals; 
those  which  possess  moisture,  but  less  warmth  lay  eggs  which  afterwards 
develop  inside  the  female  animal  and  are  born  alive:  sharks.  Warm  and  dry 
animals  lay  "complete"  eggs,  such  as  birds  and  reptiles;  cold  and  earthy  ani- 
mals lay  "incomplete"  eggs,  such  as  osseans,  frogs,  and  ink-fish;  and  finally 
the  lowest  animals  of  all  —  that  is,  of  those  that  propagate  in  a  sexual 


CLASSICAL     ANTIQUITY,     MIDDLE     AGES       43 

way  —  breed  worms  which  give  rise  to  eggs,  as,  for  instance,  insects,  whose 
pupas  Aristotle  regarded  as  eggs,  whereas  the  true  insect  eggs  were  unknown 
to  him.  His  descriptions  of  animal  development  contain  a  mass  of  extraor- 
dinarily sound  details;  as  always,  it  is  marine  animals  that  interest  him  most. 
His  account  of  the  breeding  of  sharks  is  especially  well  known,  while  the 
pairing  and  growth  of  ink-fish  are  also  described  with  a  thorough  knowledge 
of  his  subject.  Embryology,  too,  he  discusses  in  great  detail,  chiefly  the 
development  of  the  hen's  egg,  which  Hippocrates  had  also  studied;  in  particu- 
lar the  evolution  of  the  heart  and  the  first  blood-vessels  is  carefully  explained. 
Various  speculations  on  colour-variations,  change  of  teeth,  and  other  prob- 
lems of  development  complete  Aristotle's  work  on  the  reproduction  of 
animals,  which,  more  than  any  other  of  his  biological  works,  testifies  to 
both  his  greatness  and  his  limitations. 

H/s  evolution  theory  really  dogmatic 
Aristotle's  great  contribution  to  the  development  of  biological   science 
lies,  as  has  already  been  pointed  out,  not  so  much  in  the  sphere  of  discoveries 
as  in  the  thought-system,  embracing  all  the  phenomena  of  life,  which  he 
created  and  consistently  worked  out  in  all  its  details.  The  finest  merit  of  this 
system  of  thought  lies  in  the  fact  of  its  being  based  on  an  evolution  subject 
to  rigid  laws  and  proceeding  from  the  lower  to  the  higher.  But  as  this  theory 
of  evolution  is,  as  has  been  shown  above,  primarily  based  on  a  predominant 
guiding  intelligence,  it  acquires  a  dogmatic  arbitrariness;  the  subjection  to 
law  is  not  an  act  of  nature  itself,  but  rather  a  product  of  divine  wisdom,  or, 
in  other  words,  human  speculation.  This  could,  then,  it  is  true,  solve  with 
abstract  catchwords  all  the  problems  against  which  Democritus'   atomic 
theory  was  powerless,  but  any  such  method  of  solution  failed  to  stimulate 
thought  to  continued  search;  on  the  contrary,  it  induced  a  feeling  of  self- 
complacent  satisfaction  with  the  limited  cosmogony  produced  out  of  unreal 
systems  of  thought.  Thus  it  came  about  that  Aristotle,  the  founder  of  sys- 
tematic biology,  became  at  the  same  time  the  father  of  the  scholastic  philoso- 
phy of  the  Middle  Ages;  that  the  man  who  was  the  first  to  introduce  and 
logically  to  apply  to  the  conception  of  the  entire  universe  a  theory  of  evolu- 
tion from  the  lower  to  the  higher  appeared  fifteen  centuries  later  as  the 
founder  of  a  system  of  stagnation  and  obedience  to  authority.  What  the 
whole  of  this  long  period  lacked  was  a  conception  of  nature  which  would 
have  associated  Aristotle's  theory  of  subjection  to  law  with  Democritus' 
theory  of  the  dominance  of  necessity  in  nature.  Subjection  to  law  caused  by  a 
personal,  guiding  will,  and  necessity  with  pure  chance  as  its  driving  force: 
the  choice  lay  between  these  two  alternatives  until,  through  Galileo  and 
Newton,  the  impersonal,  law-bound  force,  operating  by  natural  necessity, 
was  made  the  basis  on  which  to  interpret  the  course  of  events  in  the  universe. 
For  the  fact  that  such  a  long  time  should  have  elapsed  before  this  conception 


44  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

of  nature  as  held  today  could  make  itself  realized,  Aristotle  and  the  system 
which  he  created,  unexcelled  in  its  perfection  of  form  as  it  is,  are  mainly- 
responsible.  Under  such  circumstances  it  is  not  to  be  wondered  at  that  the 
biology  of  antiquity,  in  spite  of  its  splendid  achievement,  never  succeeded 
in  advancing  beyond  Aristotle's  conception  of  the  phenomena  of  life. 

But  if  Aristotle  thus  represents,  in  most  fields  of  science,  the  highest 
that  the  culture  of  antiquity  could  attain,  beyond  which  no  further  develop- 
ment took  place,  this  is  not  merely  due  to  the  influence  of  his  own  personality 
and  system.  At  the  time  of  his  death  the  Greeks  had  already  seen  their  best 
days.  The  civic  spirit  which,  in  spite  of  sordid  party  strife  and  sanguinary 
border-feuds,  had  borne  forward  the  petty  Greek  states  both  before  and  in 
the  throes  of  the  Persian  wars,  disappeared  as  soon  as  the  states  lost  their 
independence,  first  through  the  hegemonies  which  the  Athenians  and  the 
Spartans  in  turn  exercised  over  them,  and  later  on  through  the  Macedonian 
and  the  Roman  conquests.  And  with  the  sense  of  patriotism  disappeared  also 
the  intellectual  power  and  will  to  act.  The  semi-oriental  monarchies  into 
which  the  empire  of  Alexander  became  split  up  were  certainly  often  governed 
by  enlightened  princes  who  generously  patronized  the  sciences,  but  their 
lavish  pensions  had  nevertheless  to  be  purchased  with  obsequious  flattery, 
and  the  proud  self-respect  which  induced  Empedocles  to  refuse  a  royal  crown, 
and  Heracleitus  to  decline  the  office  of  high-priest,  existed  no  longer.  The 
great  systems  of  thought  which  were  created  by  the  noblest  spirits  of  later 
antiquity  were  in  fact  essentially  founded  upon  ethical  aims;  they  were 
intended  to  reinforce  the  individual  in  the  struggle  against  the  ever-increas- 
ing difficulties  which  life  in  those  days  presented.  The  exact  sciences,  again, 
were  divided  up  more  and  more  into  special  spheres  and  the  research  work 
carried  out  during  the  succeeding  centuries  gave  substantial  results,  until 
here,  too,  the  spiritual  weariness  from  which  that  epoch  suffered  claimed 
its  due. 

In  these  circumstances  it  may  seem  suitable  in  the  following  chapter  to 
pay  special  regard  to  the  attempts  at  a  general  explanation  of  natural  phenom- 
ena which  were  made  after  Aristotle,  after  which  we  shall  view  the  results 
achieved  by  the  biology  of  antiquity  as  a  special  line  of  research. 


CHAPTER    VI 

NATURAL-PHILOSOPHICAL      SYSTEMS      AFTER      ARISTOTLE 

Aristotle' s  folloivers 

WHEN  Aristotle  fled  from  Athens  he  left  his  school  in  the  hands  of 
Theophrastus,  who  had  been  his  faithful  friend  and  follower  ever 
since  his  student  days  with  Plato.  Though  ten  years  younger  than 
his  master,  Theophrastus  was  an  old  man  when  he  assumed  the  leadership  of 
the  Lyceum,  but  he  lived  much  longer  and  for  more  than  thirty  years  presided 
with  honour  over  the  education  of  the  pupils.  Already  under  Aristotle  he  had 
paid  special  attention  to  the  study  of  botany  and  he  continued  to  work  in 
this  science  in  the  spirit  of  his  master.  His  two  treatises  on  plants  are  to 
botany  what  Aristotle's  works  were  to  zoology.  Furthermore,  there  is  extant 
a  "history  of  physics"  by  him,  which  has  always  been  the  main  source  of 
our  knowledge  of  the  ideas  of  the  ancient  natural  philosophers.  He  also 
wrote  a  zoological  work,  which  has  been  lost,  but  on  the  whole  it  seems  to 
have  contained  nothing  essentially  new  that  is  not  found  in  Aristotle. 

On  the  other  hand,  Theophrastus'  successor,  Strato,  developed  Aris- 
totle's theory  along  entirely  fresh  lines.  Unfortunately  the  present  age  is 
acquainted  with  his  point  of  view  only  through  the  references  of  other 
authors,  but  from  these  it  is  clear  that  he  was  a  truly  independent  thinker. 
Born  at  Lampsacus  in  Asia  Minor,  he  became  a  disciple  of  Theophrastus  at 
an  early  age,  and  after  the  latter's  death  held  his  professorship  for  eighteen 
years.  His  numerous  writings,  now  lost,  dealt  particularly  with  problems  of 
natural  science  and  procured  him  the  title  of  "the  physicist."  In  contrast  to 
Aristotle  he  denied  the  existence  of  a  dominant  intelligence  outside  the  uni- 
verse; he  imagined  that  the  forces  that  govern  the  course  of  events  dwell  in 
things  themselves  and  operate  by  natural  necessity.  Further,  the  soul  of 
man  he  believed  to  be  a  force  inhabiting  the  body,  expressing  itself  as  motion, 
and  having  the  brain  for  its  organ.  On  the  other  hand,  he  seems  to  have  at- 
tacked Democritus'  theory  of  the  atoms  and  infinite  space  and  considered 
the  whole  world  to  be  finite. 

Strato's  successors  appear  to  have  been  men  of  little  importance,  and 
although  Aristotle's  school  survived  down  to  the  sixth  century  after  Christ, 
it  nevertheless  ceased  to  act  as  a  guiding  light  in  science;  its  teachers  and 
pupils  became  for  the  most  part  involved  in  specialized  investigations  into 
grammar,  literature,  and  ethics,  and  the  keen  interest  in  the  natural  sciences 

45 


46  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

which  the  founder  of  the  school  had  evoked  disappeared  entirely  from  their 
circle.  Instead,  philosophical  speculations  on  nature  were  undertaken  by 
another  school  of  thinkers,  who  revived  the  atomic  theory  of  Democritus, 
which  was  thus  given  a  fresh  lease  of  life  and  survived  not  only  the  classical 
period,  but  through  the  Middle  Ages  until  the  Renaissance.  This  new  line  of 
thought  was  directed  by  Epicurus  the  Athenian,  one  of  the  most  discussed 
philosophical  personalities  of  antiquity.  He  lived  between  the  years  34x  and 
zji  B.C.,  and  in  his  native  town  founded  a  school  whose  members  lived 
quietly  and  carried  out  joint  researches  under  their  master's  guidance.  As 
already  mentioned,  his  theoretical  standpoint  was  Democritus'  atomic 
theory,  which  he  adopted  without  really  developing  it  further.  In  direct 
opposition  to  Aristotle  he  taught  that  universal  space  is  infinite,  that  bodies 
are  composed  of  particles  indivisible  in  themselves,  whose  motions  are  the 
cause  of  everything  that  happens  and  through  whose  alternate  association 
and  dissolution  worlds  arise  and  perish.  Even  the  soul  of  man  consists  of 
atoms  and  is  thus  a  purely  corporeal  organ.  There  is  no  universal  intelli- 
gence, but  all  things  happen  through  natural  causes.  What  these  causes  are 
Epicurus  did  not  bother  much  about.  In  fact,  he  considered  it  hardly  worth 
while  trying  to  find  out  the  secrets  of  nature;  thus  it  might  well  be,  he  ex- 
pressly assures  us,  that  the  moon  borrows  light  from  the  sun,  but  it  might 
equally  well  be  self-illuminating.  The  main  thing  was  that  one  assume  a 
natural  explanation  of  the  world  and  the  universe;  it  mattered  little  what 
this  explanation  turned  out  to  be  like  in  detail  if  only  man  rid  himself  of 
the  superstition  which  always  accompanies  a  belief  in  supernatural  powers. 
Epicurus'  system,  in  fact,  was  expressly  based  on  the  idea  of  creating  by  the 
aid  of  philosophy  a  pleasant  existence,  and  man  attained  this  best  by  being 
an  opportunist  in  all  the  main  problems  of  life.  That  on  account  of  this  he 
gained  numerous  followers  is  generally  acknowledged,  but  also  the  principle 
of  a  cosmic  conception  which  lays  most  stress  on  the  exclusion  of  all  super- 
natural elements,  and  in  doing  so  does  not  bother  much  about  the  difficulties 
arising  out  of  questions  of  detail,  has  always  had,  and  will  indeed  always 
have,  keen  adherents.  It  is  no  matter  for  surprise,  however,  that  the  follow- 
ers of  Epicurus,  with  such  a  view  of  the  functions  of  scientific  research,  could 
never  claim  any  really  great  natural  philosopher  of  antiquity  amongst  their 
number.  Epicureanism  survived  as  a  mode  of  living  which  invited  people 
during  depressing  and  hopeless  times  to  seek  life's  happiness  and  goal  in 
pleasure,  spiritual  as  well  as  material.  To  Epicurus  himself  and  to  his  friends 
pleasure  was  essentially  spiritual;  their  material  needs  were  extremely 
modest.  But  matters  became  worse  when  his  doctrine  was  brought  to  Rome. 
In  that  world-capital  it  degenerated  into  an  unbridled  worship  of  pleasure, 
particularly  under  the  Empire;  the  fact  that  Nero  and  his  friends  called 
themselves  Epicureans  was  not  calculated  to  heighten  the  school's  reputa- 


CLASSICAL  ANTIQUITY,  MIDDLE  AGES  47 
tion.  Even  in  Rome,  however,  it  gained  adherents  of  a  nobler  character.  One 
of  these,  Lucretius,  deserves  further  mention,  especially  as  his  enunciation  of 
the  atomic  theory  is  the  most  detailed  of  its  kind  that  has  been  handed  down 
to  us  from  antiquity,  and  as  such  it  is  also  of  interest  on  the  grounds  of  the 
biological  particulars  which  it  contains. 

Titus  Lucretius  Carus  was  probably  born  in  99  and  died  in  55  B.C.  He 
belonged  to  a  famous  patrician  family  and  seems  to  have  been  acquainted 
with  several  well-known  persons  among  his  contemporaries,  but  although 
the  epoch  in  which  he  lived  —  he  was  contemporary  with  Cassar  and  Cicero  — 
is  without  doubt  the  best  known  in  antiquity  from  a  historical  point  of 
view,  nothing  is  known  of  his  life  with  any  certainty.  He  seems  to  have  kept 
aloof  from  the  political  struggles  of  his  time  and  devoted  himself  entirely 
to  philosophical  and  literary  study.  An  early  father  of  the  Christian  Church 
declares  that  he  died  by  his  own  hand;  the  statement  may  indeed  be  true, 
for  in  the  deeply  unhappy  age  in  which  he  lived,  this  desperate  way  out  of 
life  was,  as  is  well  known,  resorted  to  by  many.  It  was  not  until  after  his 
death  that  his  great  work  On  the  Nature  of  Things  was  published,  in  which  he 
recorded  the  results  of  his  philosophical  speculations.  Following  the  example 
of  the  earlier  Greek  philosophers,  particularly  of  Empedocles,  whom  he 
greatly  admired,  he  has  clothed  his  thoughts  in  verse  form;  he  is  the  last  of 
the  ancient  philosophers  to  do  so.  The  wealth  of  imagination  and  the  high 
inspiration  which  fill  his  poem  have  given  him  a  place  amongst  the  greatest 
poets  of  antiquity,  but  he  is  of  great  interest  also  as  a  philosopher.  The  most 
striking  feature  of  his  poem  is  his  passionate  love  of  truth  and  his  absolute 
conviction  that  thought  ultimately  will  succeed  in  penetrating  the  true 
nature  of  things.  To  the  glorious  mission  of  philosophy  to  seek  after  truth 
he  opposes  the  grim  picture  of  darkness  and  superstition  called  forth  by 
traditional  theism,  a  miserable  state  from  which  he  hopes  free-thought  will 
save  humanity.  The  cosmic  explanation  which  he  accepts  as  the  only  pos- 
sible right  one  is  the  atomic  theory,  in  the  form  in  which  Epicurus  expounded 
it;  Democritus  is  mentioned  only  in  passing.  It  can  hardly  be  said  that  he 
contributed  anything  towards  the  development  of  the  general  principle  of 
that  theory,  but  at  any  rate  his  conception  differs  from  that  of  which  an 
account  has  been  given  above  in  connexion  with  his  predecessors.  The  worlds 
are  infinite  in  number,  formed  of  atoms  moving  in  empty  space.  Their  mo- 
tion is  due  to  gravity  and  consequently  represents  a  constant  descent;  the 
fact,  however,  that  they  strike  against  one  another,  as  presupposed  in  the 
atomic  theory,  is  due  to  their  fall's  being  for  internal  reasons  not  quite 
perpendicular,  but  deflecting  to  one  side. 

Lucretius'  soul  theory 
The  most  interesting  of  all,  however,  is  Lucretius'  attempt  to  apply  the 
atomic  theory  in  detail  to  the  phenomena  of  the  senses  and  the  processes  of 


48  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

the  soul.  Following  Aristotle,  with  whose  theory  of  the  finality  of  all 
things  he  nevertheless  sharply  disagrees,  he  assumes  three  kinds  of  soul, 
animus,  mens,  and  anima'^  —  that  is,  the  spirit,  the  understanding,  and  the 
soul  or  life-principle.  He  does  not,  however,  consistently  differentiate  be- 
tween these  three  categories,  but  discusses  them  mostly  as  one  single  idea. 
In  quality  the  soul  is  material,  an  organ,  like  the  rest,  formed  of  extremely 
small  atoms  distributed  throughout  the  body,  very  mobile,  and  therefore 
easily  dispersed.  These  atoms  are  of  three  determinable  kinds:  warmth,  air, 
and  "aura,"  a  more  rarified  kind  of  air  corresponding  to  the  "pneuma"  of 
Hippocrates.  But  besides  the  three  categories  of  atoms  just  named,  the  soul 
contains  still  a  fourth  component,  which  has  no  name,  but  which  forms  the 
real  percipient,  the  consciousness  in  the  soul,  and  whose  atoms  are  the  small- 
est and  most  mobile.  They  give  impulse  to  the  other  soul-atoms  and  thereby 
indirectly  to  the  movements  of  the  body.  These  component  parts  of  the  soul, 
being  variously  commingled,  produce  the  varying  soul-characteristics  in 
different  individuals  and  make  themselves  felt  in  different  degrees  in  the  same 
individual  in  different  states  of  mind;  heat  in  anger,  cold  air  in  terror,  etc. 
The  soul,  which  in  life  is  contained  by  the  body,  as  a  vessel  contains  whatever 
is  kept  therein,  dissolves  at  death  into  the  simplest  component  parts  and  is 
annihilated.  The  immortality  of  the  soul  as  maintained  by  Plato  and  his 
disciples  is  attacked  by  Lucretius  with  passionate  intensity.  Again  and  again 
he  seeks  to  prove  that  this,  combined  with  a  belief  in  gods,  is  the  cause  of  all 
human  miseries.  Sense-perceptions  are,  according  to  Lucretius,  due  to  things' 
giving  off  from  their  surface  a  kind  of  light  particles  which,  formed  like  the 
things  themselves,  float  about  in  space  and  influence  the  organs  of  sense.  As 
a  proof  that  such  images  are  given  off  he  cites,  inter  alia,  the  change  of  skin 
in  snakes  and  insects.  All  sensations  —  sight,  hearing,  smell,  and  taste  — 
are  thus  excited  by  different  atoms  which  affect  the  organs  of  the  body.  The 
ideas  arising  herefrom  are  caused  by  a  mass  of  still  more  subtle  images  of 
things,  floating  about  in  space  even  after  the  things  themselves  have  dis- 
appeared. Thus  one  sees  in  imagination  images  of  individuals  long  since 
dead,  and  owing  to  the  images'  sometimes  coalescing,  one  receives  impres- 
sions of  creatures  which  have  never  existed  in  reality;  for  instance,  through 
the  coalescing  of  a  horse  and  a  human  image  is  produced  the  mythical 
centaur.  Through  such  images  still  remaining  in  the  soul  dreams  arise.  Primi- 
tive as  these  sensory  physiological  speculations  are,  they  are  nevertheless 
accompanied  by  a  number  of  extremely  striking  observations  regarding  differ- 
ent kinds  of  sensations.  In  particular  Lucretius  discussed  in  detail  sensations 
in  the  sphere  of  sexual  life,  which  he  describes  with  a  curious  mixture  of 

^  These  names,  which  Lucretius  undoubtedly  himself  invented  on  the  Greek  model,  are 
again  found  in  the  psychological  terminology  of  the  Middle  Ages,  and  even  in  Swedenborg. 


CLASSICAL     ANTIQUITY,     MIDDLE     AGES        49 

minute  observations  from   a   natural-scientific   point   of  view   and   poetic 
inspiration. 

Lucretius'  influence  upon  posterity  has  been  both  lasting  and  important, 
It  is  undoubtedly  due  mostly  to  him  that  atomism  survived  throughout  the 
Middle  Ages,  although  in  obscurity,  owing  to  the  hostility  of  the  Church.'' 
During  the  Renaissance  he  was  held  in  high  estimation;  the  greatest  thinker 
of  that  epoch,  Giordano  Bruno,  was  strongly  influenced  by  him  and  in  imita- 
tion of  him  wrote  several  of  his  scientific  works  in  verse  form,  and  even  the 
free-thinkers  of  the  eighteenth  century  studied  him  closely.  Yet  it  can  hardly 
be  said  that  he  advanced  the  natural  sciences.  He  has  not  succeeded  in  improv- 
ing upon  the  atomic  theory  as  created  by  Democritus;  such  progress  as  Aris- 
totle made  in  the  sphere  of  biological  development  he  rejected  with  the 
theory  of  finality  upon  which  it  rested,  but  without  succeeding  in  substitut- 
ing any  better  subjection  to  law.  On  the  whole,  atomism  became  a  theory  that 
brought  no  benefit  to  natural  research  until  in  the  beginning  of  the  nineteenth 
century  it  was,  through  Dalton,  adopted  in  chemical  research  and,  thanks 
chiefly  to  Berzelius,  became  the  most  fruitful  working  hypothesis  of  that 
science.  Since  then  it  has  been  one  of  the  most  important  foundations  on 
which  our  idea  of  nature,  both  inorganic  and  organic,  is  based ;  but  the  univer- 
sal application  which  the  ancient  atomists  ascribe  to  it  it  has  not  received; 
no  true  natural  philosopher  of  today  hopes  to  be  able  to  explain  the  phe- 
nomena of  animate  life  with  its  aid,  although  in  quasi-scientific  popular 
literature  attempts  have  been  made  to  do  so. 

^  In  his  Divina  Commedia  Dante  relates  that  in  hell  there  were  several  thousand  "Epicu- 
reans," among  them  many  of  the  most  eminent  men  of  his  own  time. 


CHAPTER    VII 

SPECIALIZED      BIOLOGICAL      RESEARCH      AFTER      ARISTOTLE 

The  anatomists  of  Alexandria 

IF,  THEjsT,  the  ancient  conception  of  nature  failed  to  advance  beyond  the 
point  to  which  Aristotle  brought  it,  nevertheless  there  developed  after 
his  time  and  on  the  foundations  laid  by  him  a  specialized  form  of  biologi- 
cal research  which  during  the  following  centuries  produced  rare  and  abun- 
dant harvests.  The  centre  of  natural  research  during  this  period,  not  only  in 
the  biological,  but  in  other  branches,  was  Alexandria,  the  purely  Greek 
capital  of  Egypt.  Under  the  patronage  of  the  refined  and  generous  kings  of 
the  Ptolemaic  dynasty  there  was  here  established  an  institute  of  scientific 
research  the  like  of  which  the  ancient  world  never  saw  before  or  afterwards. 
Even  the  founder  of  the  dynasty,  Ptolemy  I  (died  in  283  b.c),  was  a  highly 
cultured  man  who  collected  books  and  was  himself  an  author.  His  son  Ptol- 
emy II  founded  the  Museum  of  Alexandria  (mouseion  —  a  temple  of  the  god- 
desses of  song  and  wisdom,  the  Muses),  an  institution  where  scholars  from 
every  country  received  lodging  and  maintenance  and  substantial  assistance 
for  the  furthering  of  their  research  work.  It  was  conducted  on  the  lines  of 
an  academy  with  the  chief  librarian  as  chairman;  the  highest  authority  was 
exercised  by  the  high-priest  of  the  Muses,  who  was  religious  head  of  the 
college.  All  the  branches  of  science  known  to  classical  antiquity  were  studied 
here;  the  science  of  biology  was  chiefly  pursued  in  connexion  with  medicine, 
like  anatomy  and  physiology. 

It  has  been  mentioned  above  that  medical  science  was  from  early  times 
highly  developed  in  Egypt,  inasmuch  as  the  custom  of  embalming  bodies  in 
that  country  contributed  towards  increasing  the  knowledge  of  human  anat- 
omy. Herein,  then,  lay  certain  preconditions  for  the  stimulus  given  to  the 
study  of  anatomy  in  Alexandria;  substantial  grants  of  money  and  literary 
and  material  aid  from  the  princes  rapidly  advanced  the  development  of  the 
school  of  medicine.  Two  teachers  of  more  than  usually  prominent  gifts, 
Herophilus  and  Erasistratus,  finally  brought  to  the  school  a  reputation  such 
as  no  other  attained  in  classical  times.  We  know  little  of  the  personal  history 
of  these  men,  and  not  much  about  the  general  ideas  of  nature  which  they 
embraced.  It  is  assumed,  however,  that  they  were  influenced  by  the  scepticism 
of  Pyrrho,  who  apparently  found  most  of  his  adherents  amongst  the  Alexan- 
drian physicians.  Pyrrho  of  Elis  (376-188  b.c.)  taught  that  no  knowledge 

50 


CLASSICAL  ANTIQUITY,  MIDDLE  AGES  5I 
of  things  is  really  possible;  man  can  know  nothing  and  prove  nothing,  not 
even  the  impossibility  of  knowledge  or  justification  for  doubt.  Such  a  funda- 
mental principle  naturally  precluded  any  theoretical  conception  of  nature, 
whether  Democritean  or  Aristotelean,  but  it  was  just  this  very  circumstance 
which  drove  a  philosopher  seeking  after  knowledge  to  become  all  the  more 
deeply  engrossed  in  specialized  science  and  its  practical  application.  It  was 
thus  exclusively  through  detailed  anatomical  research  that  the  Alexandrian 
medical  school  advanced  the  science  of  biology. 

Herophilus  was  a  native  of  Chalcedon  in  Asia  Minor,  studied  in  the 
Asclepiad  schools  in  Cos  and  Cnidus,  and  afterwards  worked  as  a  teacher  and 
researcher  in  Alexandria.  The  dates  of  his  birth  and  death  are  unknown,  but 
his  activities  fall  within  the  decades  about  the  year  300  b.c.  His  writings, 
too,  are  lost,  except  for  a  few  fragments;  their  contents  are  known  to  us  only 
through  the  references  of  other  authors.  That  Herophilus  was  one  of  the 
most  prominent  anatomists  of  antiquity  is,  however,  universally  acknowl- 
edged, both  by  classical  and  by  modern  authors.  His  fame  is  based  on  the 
numerous  discoveries  he  made,  particularly  in  human  anatomy.  Every  part 
of  the  human  body  was  investigated  by  him,  and  what  more  than  anything 
else  attracted  the  attention  of  his  contemporaries  was  the  fact  that  he  em- 
ployed human  bodies  for  the  purposes  of  investigation.  Sceptics  as  they  were, 
he  and  his  pupils  despised  the  traditional  fear  of  dissecting  human  bodies, 
and  the  enlightened  Ptolemaic  rulers  placed  material  at  their  disposal.  It  is 
even  declared  that  Herophilus  took  advantage  of  opportunities  offered  to 
him  to  carry  out  investigations  on  living  human  beings  —  criminals  con- 
demned to  death,  whose  internal  organs  he  studied  in  a  living  state. ^  Among 
the  organs  which  he  described  in  detail  may  specially  be  mentioned  the  brain; 
he  discovered  and  gave  an  account  of  its  membranes  and  its  venous  blood 
sinuses,  which  still  bear  his  name,  the  torcular  Herophili.  Moreover,  he 
studied  the  ventricles  of  the  brain,  being  particularly  interested  in  the 
fourth,  which  he  regarded  as  the  organ  of  the  soul.  He  gave  similar  close 
study  to  the  eye,  its  membranes,  film,  and  retina.  He  also  described  the  ali- 
mentary canal;  the  name  "doudenum"  for  its  upper  section  comes  from  him. 
The  liver  he  carefully  studied  with  regard  to  the  variations  in  its  shape  in 
different  individuals.  The  circulatory  system  he  also  made  the  subject  of  close 
investigation;  he  compared  the  walls  of  the  arteries  and  the  veins  and  studied 
the  pulse  at  different  ages  and  under  different  bodily  conditions.  That  the 
arteries  contained  the  pneuma  he  believed  in  common  with  all  other  re- 
searchers of  his  time.  For  the  first  time  he  cleared  up  the  question  of  the  dif- 
ference between  nerves  and  tendons.  Finally,  he  carefully  worked  out  the 

'  One  of  the  early  Fathers,  Tertullian,  quotes,  among  other  heinous  acts  committed  by 
the  heathen,  that  Herophilus  tortured  to  death  six  hundred  persons  —  a  story  on  a  par  with 
much  that  is  related  nowadays  in  anti-vivisectionist  literature. 


5X  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

anatomy  of  the  genital  organs.  His  physiological  ideas  were  governed  by  the 
usual  conceptions  of  antiquity  —  four  different  life-elements  localized  in 
corresponding  main  organs;  they  are  therefore  of  no  special  interest.  For  the 
rest,  Herophilus  was  a  great  admirer  of  Hippocrates,  whose  views  on  dis- 
eases and  remedies  he  accepted  without  reserve. 

Contemporary  and  in  competition  with  Herophilus  was  Erasistratus  of 
Cheos,  a  small  island  in  the  ^gean.  His  dates  and  personal  history  are  as 
unknown  to  us  as  those  of  Herophilus,  and  his  writings  were  lost  even  in 
late  antiquity.  According  to  a  late  and  unconfirmed  report  he  was  the  nephew 
of  Aristotle;  it  is  certain  that  his  teacher,  Metrodorus,  was  the  latter's  con- 
temporary and  friend.  Erasistratus  began  his  career  as  court  physician  to  the 
Seleucides  of  Syria,  but  he  was  called  thence  to  Alexandria,  where  he  founded 
a  school  of  medicine.  His  anatomical  works  dealt  chiefly  with  the  circulatory 
system.  The  heart  he  studied  with  care  and  gave  its  valves  the  names  they 
still  bear.  Further,  he  established  the  connexion  between  arteries  and  veins 
and  explained  the  bleeding  from  the  arteries  in  wounds  by  the  assumption 
that  their  pneuma  disappears,  and  in  its  stead  the  blood  from  the  venous 
system  penetrates  into  the  arteries  and  then  flows  from  the  wound.  Again, 
he  investigated  the  lymphatic  ducts  and  the  secretion  of  chyle  in  live  ani- 
mals. He  made  important  discoveries  which  increased  the  knowledge  of  the 
nervous  system;  he  distinguished  between  the  motor  and  sensory  nerves  and 
was  the  first  to  describe  in  detail  the  convolutions  of  the  brain.  As  a  physician 
Erasistratus  was  more  practical  than  Herophilus;  he  utterly  scorned  the  Hip- 
pocratic  traditions,  prescribed  simple  remedies,  avoided  venesection,  and 
strongly  advocated  a  hygienic  mode  of  life. 

Hostility  bettveen  the  medical  schools  of  Alexandria 
This  opposition  between  the  two  Alexandrian  anatomists  had  fateful  con- 
sequences for  science.  They  themselves  impugned  one  another  by  polemics 
and  intrigue,  while  there  existed  a  still  greater  hostility  between  the  respec- 
tive schools.  The  "Herophilites"  drove  their  master's  conservatism  and  re- 
spect for  Hippocrates  to  extreme  limits,  while  the  "Erasistratites"  held  up 
to  scorn  and  counteracted  the  virtues  of  the  medical  tradition.  This  was  natu- 
rally bound  to  prejudice  science,  and  it  was  all  the  more  disastrous  as  the 
cultural  conditions  in  Alexandria  became  in  time  seriously  impaired.  The 
early  enlightened  Ptolemaic  kings  were  succeeded  by  a  line  of  degenerate 
scoundrels  who  neglected  the  interests  of  learning  as  they  neglected  all  their 
other  duties.  The  Museum  declined,  its  grants  were  reduced,  and  the  learned 
often  fell  victims  to  the  tyrants'  whims.  Thus  finally  Alexandria  became  a 
provincial  town  within  the  great  Roman  Empire.  The  Museum  certainly 
survived,  but  without  the  encouragement  which  the  native  rulers  had  given 
to  it;  it  was  eventually  destroyed  in  a  riot  —  the  Alexandrine  mob  was  known 
as  the  most  unruly  in  the  whole  of  the  Roman  Empire  —  and  in  the  end  the 


CLASSICAL     ANTIQUITY,     MIDDLE     AGES        53 

extremely  fanatical  Christian  Church  in  Egypt  wiped  out  the  last  vestiges 
of  pagan  scholarship. 

Roman  natural  science 
In  Rome,  which  in  time  assumed  Alexandria's  position  as  the  supreme  capital 
of  the  world,  there  arose  no  equivalent  to  the  Museum.  It  was  not  until  a 
later  epoch  that  the  Roman  people,  with  their  decidedly  practical  mind, 
attained  to  the  higher  culture,  and  only  in  the  juridical  sphere  did  they  make 
any  independent  contribution  to  the  development  of  intellectual  work; 
otherwise  they  appropriated  Greek  culture,  special  branches  of  which  they 
converted  to  various  —  mostly  practical  —  purposes.  One  applied  science 
of  this  kind  which  the  Romans  created  was  the  science  of  agriculture.  In 
contrast  to  the  Greeks  they  were  agriculturists  body  and  soul  and  early  felt 
the  need  of  having  their  experiences  in  this  sphere  collated  and  recorded. 
The  old  censor  Cato  actually  wrote  a  treatise  on  agriculture,  and  after  him 
there  are  mentioned  a  large  number  of  writers  on  agricultural  subjects.  The 
foremost  of  these  was  undoubtedly  Columella,  whose  writings  contain  suf- 
ficient of  interest  to  biology  to  warrant  his  being  mentioned. 

Lucius  Junius  Moderatus  Columella  was  born  at  the  beginning  of  the 
Christian  era  in  Spain,  but  he  seems  to  have  lived  in  Rome  and  there  com- 
posed his  treatise  on  agriculture  in  twelve  books.  Of  biological  interest  is 
his  account  of  domestic  animals,  their  management  and  necessities  of  life, 
their  races  and  areas  of  distribution.  All  the  useful  animals  of  his  time,  even 
the  bee,  are  dealt  with  in  his  work,  most  sections  of  which  are,  as  a  matter 
of  fact,  of  purely  economic  interest. 

Pliny,  too,  shows  a  marked  interest  In  the  practical  application  of 
science.  He  was  the  most  eminent  of  Rome's  natural  philosophers  and,  next 
to  Aristotle,  the  most  influential  of  the  biologists  of  classical  antiquity. 
Throughout  later  antiquity  and  the  Middle  Ages  and  far  on  into  more  recent 
times  his  Natural  History  has  played  an  important  part  in  the  development  of 
science;  indeed,  it  may  be  said  that  even  in  our  own  day  his  influence  has  not 
entirely  waned.  In  contrast  to  Aristotle,  however,  he  has  been  harshly  criti- 
cized in  the  biological  literature  of  the  present  day  —  extravagantly  so,  be- 
cause more  has  been  demanded  of  him  than  he  ever  intended  and  more  than  he 
was  able  to  offer.  He  has  been  characterized  as  a  soulless  compiler,  because, 
more  honest  than  Aristotle,  he  always  quotes  his  sources;  his  superstition  has 
been  ridiculed  because  he  tells  of  marvellous  animals  the  existence  of  which 
none  of  his  contemporaries  doubted.  Above  all,  the  constantly  repeated  com- 
parisons between  him  and  Aristotle  are  entirely  unjustified;  the  aims  and 
methods  of  the  one  were  not  those  of  the  other.  A  study  of  Pliny's  life  and 
work  will  confirm  this. 

Gaius  Plinius  Secundus  was  bora  a.d.  i3  at  Comum,  now  the  Como 
of  northern  Italy.  He  belonged  to  a  family  of  public  officials,  and  his  own 


54  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

career  was  in  fact  an  official  career  after  the  typically  Roman  model.  He 
received  a  thorough  education  from  good  private  teachers  in  Rome  and  after- 
wards served  alternately  in  the  army  and  the  civil  administration.  He  spent 
a  long  time  in  Germany,  where  he  held  a  military  command,  and  eventually 
became  commander-in-chief  of  a  division  of  the  fleet.  On  the  first  occasion 
known  to  history  when  Vesuvius  was  in  eruption  (a.d.  79),  he  lay  with  his 
vessels  near  Naples.  In  order  to  study  the  unusual  phenomenon  closer  he 
ordered  a  boat  to  row  him  to  the  foot  of  the  volcano,  and  there  he  perished. 
Both  in  his  treatises  and  in  his  biographies  he  stands  out  as  a  man  of  the 
highest  probity  of  the  good  old  Roman  type,  brave,  honest,  and  loyal.  Con- 
stantly engaged  in  a  round  of  official  functions,  he  devoted  every  unoccupied 
moment,  both  at  Rome  and  in  the  distant  provinces,  to  study  and  author- 
ship. His  capacity  for  work  is  described  as  inexhaustible,  and  the  writings 
he  left  bear  witness  to  his  remarkable  erudition.  He  worked  at  the  most 
widely  different  subjects:  military  science  and  military  history,  rhetoric,  and 
linguistics.  The  only  treatise  of  his  which  has  come  down  to  posterity  is  his 
great  work  of  thirty-seven  books,  the  Nattiral  History^  on  which  his  fame 
really  rests.  It  represents  a  veritable  encyclopaedia  covering  the  entire  knowl- 
edge of  nature  at  that  time,  including  its  application  to  medicine,  technology, 
and  economy.  It  begins  with  an  account  of  the  universe  and  its  laws  and  goes 
on  to  give  an  increasingly  specialized  description  of  various  natural  objects. 
Books  VIII  to  XI  deal  with  animals,  and  a  number  of  scattered  notes  on 
zoological  subjects  are  also  to  be  found  in  other  sections  of  the  great 
work. 

In  his  general  conception  Pliny  was  a  Stoic.  The  Stoic  philosophy  was 
founded  in  Athens  at  the  same  time  as  the  Epicurean,  but  its  founders  and 
earliest  leaders  all  came  from  Semitic  countries,  and  several  historians  have 
made  an  attempt  to  trace  an  oriental  influence  in  its  ascetic  contempt  for 
material  life-values  and  its  strong  feeling  for  personal  responsibility.  How- 
ever, Stoicism  found  its  way  to  Rome,  whose  noblest  men  were  attracted  by 
its  austere  sense  of  duty  and,  as  was  the  Roman  habit,  converted  its  system 
to  practical  uses.  Stoicism  laid  greater  stress  than  Epicureanism  on  a  practi- 
cal way  of  living;  it  was  not  so  much  concerned  with  the  general  conception 
of  nature  and  its  laws.  Even  Pliny's  general  ideas  of  nature  constitute  a  not 
very  interesting  record  of  the  dicta  of  earlier  authors;  here,  for  instance,  we 
find  the  Aristotelean  theory  of  a  spherical  universe,  with  the  four  elements  as 
its  essential  components,  with  —  on  the  Pythagorean,  or  rather  Heracleitean, 
pattern  —  fire  as  the  primary  cause,  the  origin  of  the  soul;  a  divinity  governs 
the  world,  but  it  is  folly  to  seek  to  discover  its  entity,  though  a  greater  folly 
still  is  polytheism.  Oracular  utterances  and  prodigies,  on  the  other  hand, 
are  recounted  by  the  score  and  without  any  expression  of  doubt  of  their 
value. 


CLASSICAL     ANTIQUITY,     MIDDLE     AGES        55 

Pliny' s  description  of  animals 
The  zoological  section  of  his  natural  history  is  as  encyclopaedically  treated 
as  the  rest.  The  various  animals  are  enumerated  without  any  sequence,  but 
on  the  whole  the  largest  and  most  remarkable  are  mentioned  first;  they 
are  described  with  reference  to  their  habits,  their  utility,  and  the  mischief 
they  do,  the  date  of  their  first  being  exhibited  and  employed  in  Rome,  and 
in  general  their  relation  to  man.  On  the  other  hand,  no  attempt  whatever  is 
made  to  give  a  true  description  of  their  external  and  internal  structure.  The 
earlier  biologists  of  antiquity,  including  Aristotle,  were,  as  we  know,  not 
very  conspicuous  for  any  important  criticisms  on  points  of  detail,  especially 
where  exotic  animals  are  concerned,  and  Pliny  with  great  goodwill  collects 
all  the  marvels  he  can  find  in  earlier  writings  and  narrates  them  without  re- 
serve. Consequently  his  account  teems  with  the  most  fantastic  fables.  As  an 
example  of  the  assertions  he  makes  may  be  mentioned  his  description  of  the 
elephant,  which,  characteristically  enough,  is  named  first  of  all  animals. 
"Amongst  land-animals  the  elephant  is  the  largest  and  the  one  whose  intelli- 
gence comes  nearest  that  of  man,  for  he  understands  the  language  of  his 
country,  obeys  commands,  has  a  memory  for  training,  takes  delight  in  love 
and  honour,  and  also  possesses  a  rare  thing  even  amongst  men  —  honesty, 
self-control,  and  a  sense  of  justice;  he  also  worships  stars  and  venerates  the  sun 
and  moon.  In  the  mountains  of  Mauretania  it  is  said  that  herds  of  elephants 
move  at  new  moon  down  to  a  river  by  the  name  of  Amilo,  ceremoniously 
cleanse  themselves  there  by  spraying  one  another  with  water,  and  after  hav- 
ing thus  paid  their  respects  to  the  heavenly  light  return  to  the  forests  bearing 
their  weary  calves  with  them.  It  is  also  said  that  when  they  are  to  be  trans- 
ported overseas,  they  refuse  to  go  on  board  until  the  master  of  the  ship  has 
given  them  a  promise  under  oath  to  convey  them  home  again."  Further,  they 
are  so  modest  that  they  never  mate  except  in  very  secluded  spots,  while 
adultery  never  occurs  amongst  them.  Towards  weaker  animals  they  show 
compassion,  so  that  an  elephant  when  passing  through  a  flock  of  sheep  will 
with  his  trunk  lift  out  of  the  way  those  he  meets,  for  fear  of  trampling  on 
them.^  Besides  these  and  similar  childish  statements  accounts  are  given  of 
the  habits  of  elephants  and  the  way  to  tame  them,  which  are  quite  correct, 
as  well  as  a  number  of  facts  of  interest  from  the  point  of  view  of  cultural 
history  as  to  their  employment  amongst  different  peoples,  when  they  were 
first  exhibited  at  Rome,  etc.  Pliny  likewise  relates  many  wonderful  stories 
about  other  lesser-known  animals,  such  as  the  elk  and  the  aurochs  of  north- 
ern Europe.  On  the  other  hand,  the  information  he  gives  regarding  the  or- 
dinary domestic  animals  of  his  own  country  is  on  the  whole  reliable  and  the 

^  It  was  probably  this  description  that  directly  or  indirectly  induced  a  Danish  king  in 
the  Middle  Ages  to  found  an  Order  of  the  Elephant,  with  the  purpose  of  thereby  exhorting  its 
members  to  imitate  the  admirable  qualities  of  that  noble  animal. 


56  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

particulars  of  cattle-management  at  that  period  are  quite  sound.  Among 
land-animals  he  includes  even  the  cold-blooded  vertebrates;  after  that  he 
deals  with  birds,  fishes  (including  molluscs),  and  insects.  Details  of  all  kinds 
of  animals  belonging  to  these  groups  are  in  the  main  similar  to  those  men- 
tioned above.  Insects  in  particular  seem  to  have  attracted  his  attention;  he 
never  wearies  of  expressing  his  admiration  for  their  perfect  organisms,  in 
spite  of  their  small  bodily  size,  and  he  gives  an  account  of  what  was  known 
of  their  organic  systems.  The  bee  he  describes  in  great  detail  and  he  relates 
its  habits,  in  many  respects  correctly,  although  he  did  not  succeed,  any 
more  than  the  other  ancient  authors,  in  gaining  any  idea  of  its  method  of 
reproduction. 

Pliny' s  anatomical  ideas 
After  Pliny  has  thus  given  an  account  of  the  animals  known  to  him,  he  dis- 
cusses the  various  organs  of  the  human  and  animal  body  on  the  same  plan; 
each  organ  is  considered  in  reference  to  its  qualities  and  occurrence  in  the 
various  animals.  Here  we  clearly  find  Aristotle  to  be  the  pattern  and  main 
source  of  information;  but  while  the  latter' s  description  of  the  organs  is  given 
with  a  view  to  tracing  the  connexion  and  origin  of  the  forms,  Pliny's  ac- 
count still  has  the  character  of  a  work  of  reference,  in  which  all  the  memo- 
randa that  he  was  able  to  collect  out  of  his  vast  erudition  are  cited  with  no 
kind  of  theoretical  purpose  and  without  any  deeper  significance  than  the 
word  that  clothes  them;  for  instance,  the  horn  of  the  ox,  of  the  horned  snake, 
and  of  the  snail  are  treated  as  all  one.  A  wealth  of  valuable  notes  from  the 
rich  scientific  store  of  the  anatomical  knowledge  of  antiquity  has  thus  been 
preserved  for  posterity  by  Pliny,  whose  sources  of  information  have  been 
lost  to  us,  but  besides  this  he  conscientiously  notes  down  a  number  of  ancient 
prodigies,  which  of  course  inspired  fear  in  his  time  and  have  consequently 
been  handed  down  to  history  —  of  sacrificial  animals  which  had  no  liver, 
or  of  the  Messenian  champion  of  liberty,  Aristomenes,  whose  heart  the  Spar- 
tans found  to  be  covered  with  hair  —  without  in  any  way  hinting  at  the 
possibility  of  fraud  on  the  part  of  the  sacrificial  priests.  A  mass  of  information 
regarding  the  medicinal  use  of  animals  or  animal  parts  closes  the  zoological 
section  of  his  Natural  History. 

Pliny  himself  states  that  he  had  recourse  to  two  thousand  books  by 
various  authors  for  the  compiling  of  his  work,  which  maintains  also  from 
beginning  to  end  its  character  of  a  confused  motley  of  notes.  This  many-sided 
learning,  which  has  very  much  impressed  past  generations,  seems  in  our  day, 
when  only  first-hand  knowledge  is  really  respected,  rather  pitiful.  Never- 
theless, as  previously  pointed  out,  Pliny  has  certainly  been  underestimated. 
For  fifteen  hundred  years  his  work  was  the  main  source  of  man's  knowledge 
of  natural  history,  and  when  during  the  Renaissance  a  Gesner  or  an  Aldro- 
vandi  revived  the  pursuit  of  zoological  research,  they  at  once  began  where 


CLASSICAL  ANTIQUITY,  MIDDLE  AGES  57 
Pliny  had  left  off  and  carried  on  the  work  after  his  method.  In  this  way 
present-day  zoology,  as  regards  the  study  of  fauna  and  classification,  takes 
Pliny  as  its  starting-point,  just  as  in  the  matter  of  comparative  anatomy  and 
morphology  it  is  based  on  Aristotle,  and  therefore  the  services  of  the  one 
should  in  all  fairness  be  recognized  as  much  as  those  of  the  other,  even  if 
they  refer  to  entirely  different  fields  of  study. 


CHAPTER    VIII 

THE     DECLINE      OF      SCIENCE      IN      LATE      ANTIQUITY 

The  decline  of  ancient  civilisation:  its  causes 

IT  HAS  ALREADY  been  pointed  out  that  the  natural  science  of  antiquity 
reached  its  zenith  in  Aristotle,  and  a  number  of  reasons  have  been  given 
for  the  fact  that  only  in  points  of  detail,  but  never  in  regard  to  the  sum- 
marizing of  the  results  achieved,  did  it  advance  beyond  his  standpoint.  While 
Rome,  first  as  a  republic  and  then  as  an  empire,  was  conquering  and  adminis- 
tering the  whole  of  the  civilized  world,  there  began  an  era  which,  more  than 
any  other,  should  have  been  devoted  to  promoting  the  work  of  intellectual 
culture.  The  universal  peace  that  prevailed  during  the  first  two  centuries  of 
the  Christian  era  has  never  had  its  counterpart  either  before  or  since,  for  the 
border  feuds  and  insurrections  which  disturbed  it  were  entirely  local  and 
transient.  And  as  there  was  peace,  there  was  also  prosperity;  even  up  to  the 
present  day  the  ruins  of  buildings  bear  witness  to  the  common  and  private 
wealth  of  those  days  throughout  the  length  and  breadth  of  the  Roman 
Empire.  And  yet  it  was  this  very  epoch  which  witnessed  the  decline  of  an- 
cient science  —  indeed  the  whole  of  the  culture  of  antiquity.  It  was  not  long 
before  the  best  minds  in  the  intellectual  world  of  the  time  realized  this  fact. 
Pliny,  for  instance,  is  never  tired  of  repeating  that  humanity  is  corrupt  and 
that  his  age  was  worse  than  the  era  that  had  passed.  The  reason  he  gives  is 
the  increasing  corruption  of  morals  —  an  assertion  with  which  innumerable 
other  ancient  authors  are  in  agreement  and  which  has  therefore  been  re- 
peated in  more  recent  times.  The  cause  cannot  lie  there,  however;  moral  cor- 
ruption is  always  a  symptom  and  not  a  cause  of  cultural  decadence.  The  cause 
is  far  more  likely  to  be  found  in  the  change  in  the  common  conception  of  life 
which  was  a  consequence  of  subjection  under  the  Empire.  The  ancient  provin- 
cial patriotism  had  lost  its  power  to  survive  and  there  was  no  possibility  of 
any  fresh  form  of  social  community  developing;  instead  the  individual  per- 
sonality appears  as  struggling  for  freedom  from  external  oppression  and 
grievances.  This  self-assertion  against  an  oppressive  existence  both  Epicu- 
reans and  Stoics  sought  to  put  into  practice,  each  in  their  own  way;  but,  as 
we  have  seen,  their  teachings  formed  no  good  soil  in  which  to  cultivate 
empirical  research.  In  the  long  run,  however,  the  purely  negative  insensibility 
to  suffering  which  constituted  the  philosophy  of  life  of  these  schools  of 
thought  could  not  suffice;  in  their  place  appeared  lines  of  thought  start- 

58 


CLASSICAL     ANTIQUITY,     MIDDLE     AGES        59 

ing  out  from  the  idea  of  leading  the  personality  into  an  existence  differ- 
ent from  the  earthly,  of  creating  with  the  aid  of  some  kind  of  higher, 
secret  knowledge  a  happier  world  for  the  soul  to  live  in.  There  thus  arose  a 
half-mystical,  half-experimental  psychology,  which  was  nurtured  by  philo- 
sophical schools  possessing  sectarian  organizations,  like  that  of  the  Pythag 
oreans  in  the  old  days.  One  of  these  schools,  and  the  most  fantastic  of  all, 
actually  called  themselves  neo-Pythagoreans;  another,  more  scientifically 
serious,  was  the  neo-Platonic,  which  sought  to  bring  the  human  spirit,  along 
the  mystical  path  of  introspection,  into  contact  with  the  world  of  ideas, 
which  Plato  declared  to  be  the  only  true  world.  Through  this  development 
the  very  idea  of  philosophy  became  radically  altered;  the  philosopher  was  no 
longer  a  lover  of  wisdom,  as  the  name  implies,  but  a  lover  of  piety.  But  as 
such  he  retained  no  interest  in  natural  phenomena;  his  spirit  in  fact  lived  in 
supernatural  regions  of  space,  and  if  he  devoted  any  time  to  the  objects  of 
nature,  it  was  merely  in  order  to  discover  the  secret  divine  powers  which, 
hidden  from  the  eyes  of  the  ignorant,  dwelt  in  plants  and  animals. 

For  the  belief  in  God  awakened  to  new  life  during  later  antiquity;  not 
the  old  sacrificial  faith  ^  so  indissolubly  bound  up  with  the  inner  life  of  the 
petty  states,  but  faith  in  a  supreme  power  able  to  save  the  individual  from 
sorrow  and  suffering.  Numerous  religious  brotherhoods  were  founded  which 
sought  by  mystical  means  to  procure  for  their  members  peace  and  happiness 
in  this  life,  or  at  any  rate  in  the  life  to  come.  Among  these  faiths  appeared 
Christianity,  which  was  finally  triumphant,  thanks  to  the  message  of  univer- 
sal love  and  the  sure  promise  of  salvation  which  it  offered  to  mankind,  and 
not  least  as  a  result  of  the  strong  community-organization  which  its  first 
followers  set  up,  with  unlimited  charity  within  their  ranks  and  stubborn 
power  of  resistance  against  persecution  from  outside.  But  an  epoch  in  which 
the  best  of  humanity  sought  their  happiness  in  life  beyond  the  bounds  of 
actual  existence  must  inevitably  be  a  period  of  decay,  both  materially  and 
within  those  spheres  of  the  spiritual  life  which  have  to  do  with  reality :  exact 
science  as  well  as  creative  art. 

As  early  as  the  second  century  of  our  era,  when  material  prosperity  was 
still  at  its  highest,  there  appear  signs  of  this  spiritual  disintegration;  during 
this  century  lived  the  last  of  the  great  classical  authors  —  the  Latin  poet 
Juvenal,  and  the  Greek  Lucian,  by  the  side  of  a  mass  of  representatives  of  the 
new  era:  miracle-workers,  soothsayers,  and  necromancers,  whom  they 
strenuously  but  vainly  opposed.  At  that  time,  too,  lived  the  last  great  biolo- 
gist of  the  age  of  classical  culture,  the  physician  Galen,  who  in  his  writings 

^  The  cult  of  sacrifice  was  also  revived,  it  is  true,  in  late  antiquity,  but  it  was  not  so  much 
the  old  national  cult  as  one  accompanied  by  mystical,  impassioned  ceremonies,  originating  from 
the  East.  To  the  noblest  minds  of  the  time,  however,  it  had  very  little,  or  at  any  rate  a  purely 
conventional,  value. 


6o  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

has  strangely  combined  the  many-sided  biological  learning  of  antiquity  with 
the  mystical  trend  of  thought  of  the  new  era. 

The  last  great  biologist  of  antiquity 
Galen  was  born  in  131  at  Pergamum  in  Asia  Minor,  of  Greek  parents. 
After  moving  to  Rome  he  latinized  his  name  and  called  himself  Claudius 
Galenus,  but  continued  to  write  in  Greek,  this  being  a  characteristic  ex- 
ample of  the  mixed  culture  prevailing  at  this  time.  His  father,  Nicon,  was 
an  architect;  through  a  dream  he  learnt  that  his  son  was  destined  to  be  a 
physician,  and  Galen  thus  entered  upon  his  medical  career  under  what  was 
thought  to  be  divine  instigation.  Even  before  this  occurred,  he  had  been 
initiated  by  good  teachers  into  the  philosophy  of  his  time:  in  his  native  town 
he  studied  under  Platonists,  Epicureans,  and  Stoics,  but  he  was  particularly 
versed  in  the  writings  of  Aristotle  and  Theophrastus.  Medicine  he  studied  in 
his  native  country,  then  in  Corinth,  and  finally  in  Alexandria,  everywhere 
acquiring,  besides  medicine,  philosophical  knowledge  from  the  best  teachers 
of  his  time.  Having  thus  completed  his  education,  he  returned  home  in  the 
year  158  and  was  employed  in  his  native  city  as  physician  in  the  temple  of 
.^sculapius,  as  well  as,  characteristically  enough,  at  the  city's  gladiatorial 
school.  After  six  years,  however,  he  moved  to  Rome  and  there  began  to  give 
lectures  on  his  own  scientific  subjects,  as  a  result  of  which  he  won  the  friend- 
ship of  men  of  repute  and  the  envy  of  other  physicians.  In  a  still  greater 
degree  did  the  immense  practice  he  acquired  awaken  feelings  of  bitterness, 
and  as  he  himself  never  attempted  to  conciliate  his  envious  fellow  physicians, 
but  on  the  contrary  strongly  resented  the  decline  in  the  efficiency  of  medical 
practitioners,  such  a  storm  of  hostility  broke  over  his  head  that  for  a  time 
he  had  to  fly  the  field  and  return  to  his  own  country.  Wa  had,  however,  such 
an  established  reputation  that  after  the  lapse  of  onh'  a  few  years  he  was 
summoned  to  become  body-physician  to  the  Emperor  Marcus  Aurelius,  and 
thus,  under  the  protection  both  of  him  and  of  his  son  Commodus,  he  was 
able  to  carry  on  his  work  in  Rome  unmolested.  His  last  vears  passed  quietly; 
it  is  not  known  when  and  where  he  died,  but  probably  about  the  year  2.10 
at  Pergamum. 

Galen  s  zvri tings 
As  a  writer  Galen  was  very  productive;  he  himself  states  that  he  wrote  156 
treatises,  of  which  131  were  of  a  medical  character.  Of  the  Ktter,  83  are  still 
extant.  His  other  works  embraced  philosophy,  mathematic?,  grammar,  and 
law,  but  most  of  them  are  now  lost.  He  was  thus  a  many-sided  man  of  cul- 
ture, with  interests  far  above  the  specialized  fields  of  activifv  of  contempo- 
rary physicians  and  even  of  the  classical  Alexandrine  doctors,  and  well 
capable  of  critically  examining  the  various  medical  schools,  which  by  work- 
ing in  opposition  to  one  another  with  their  dogmatically  formulated  pro- 
grams brought  medical  science  into  disrepute.  He  also  laid  great  store  by 


CLASSICAL     ANTIQUITY,     MIDDLE     AGES        6l 

universality  of  knowledge,  and  in  one  of  his  writings  which  has  been  pre- 
served to  us  he  exhorts  his  professional  brethren  to  devote  themselves  to  the 
study  of  philosophy  as  an  essential  foundation  for  acquiring  a  proper  con- 
ception of  man's  nature  in  sickness  and  in  health.  For  this  purpose  he  refers 
above  all  to  Hippocrates,  whom  he  extols  with  extravagant  words  in  all  his 
works,  declaring  that  his  dicta  should  be  interpreted  as  if  they  were  the 
utterances  of  a  god.  But  both  Plato  and  Aristotle  also  represent  sources 
whence  he  gained  a  true  idea  of  nature  and  life,  and  on  their  ideal  conception 
of  existence  he  has  based  his  theory  of  biological  phenomena.  He  has  adopted 
their  fundamental  principle  of  a  divine  intelligence  as  the  origin  and  ruler 
of  all  things,  whose  existence  is  proved  by  the  finality  of  nature,  and  also 
the  theory  of  the  soul  as  a  purpose  justifying  the  existence  of  the  body.  But 
while  Aristotle  showed  the  finality  of  nature  by  comparing  different  forms 
of  life  and  pointing  out  the  consistency  displayed  in  their  existence  and 
evolution,  Galen  deals  only  with  the  organs  of  the  human  body  and  seeks  to 
prove  how  in  the  smallest  details  they  are  constructed  and  applied  exactly  as 
they  should  be.  And  in  this  perfect  organization  in  the  human  body  he  sees 
proofs  of  the  power  and  wisdom  of  the  Creator,  whom  he  never  wearies  of 
praising  in  words  testifying  to  a  deep  personal  sense  of  religion,  and  in  a 
tone  which  differs  widely  from  the  temperate  scientific  feeling  with  which 
Aristotle  shows  the  necessity  for  a  supreme  intelligence  in  existence.  And 
alternating  with  these  pious  expressions  there  are  in  his  writings  uncontrol- 
lably violent  outbursts  against  the  representatives  of  the  theory  of  the  domi- 
nance of  necessity  in  nature  and  of  the  atoms  as  the  primary  components  of 
matter,  particularly  against  Epicurus  and  his  disciple  the  physician  Ascle- 
piades.^  In  one  other  respect  also  Galen  proves  himself  to  belong  to  a  new 
era;  not  only  are  the  old  Greek  philosophers  quoted  by  him,  but  he  also  re- 
fers to  the  Mosaic  story  of  creation,  with  which,  it  is  true,  he  is  at  variance  — 
in  fact,  he  believes  matter  to  be  eternal  and  denies  the  possibility  of  creation 
out  of  nothing  —  but  which  nevertheless  certainly  influenced  his  conception 
of  nature.  That,  indeed,  constitutes,  one  might  say,  one  single  hymn  of 
praise  to  the  wisdom  of  the  Creator.  In  every  detail  of  the  human  system 
does  the  divine  Providence  show  its  foresight;  in  the  hand  not  only  the  num- 
ber and  length  of  the  fingers,  but  even  every  tendon  and  muscle  is  a  proof 
thereof;  likewise  with  the  minutest  details  of  the  rest  of  the  body.  He  scorn- 
fully rejects  the  assertion  of  the  Epicureans  that  the  organs  develop  with  use 
and  weaken  with  disuse,  saying  that  in  that  case  energetic  people  would  in 
time  acquire  four  legs  and  four  arms,  and  the  lazy  only  one  of  each.  Again,  if 
rightly  viewed,  even  organs  which  might  appear  to  be  useless  are  suited  to 

2  Asclepiades  was  a  famous  Greek  physician  who  lived  in  Rome  during  the  first  century 
before  the  Christian  era.  His  writings,  now  lost,  were  highly  esteemed  in  antiquity,  but  they  do 
not  seem  to  have  included  any  biological  investigations. 


6i  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

serve  a  certain  purpose;  if  it  is  asked,  for  instance,  why  man  has  not  long 
ears  like  the  donkey,  which  would  give  better  hearing,  the  answer  is  that 
man's  ears  are  such  as  they  are  in  order  to  enable  him  to  wear  a  hat.  And  the 
wise  Creator  has  not  only  taken  utility  into  consideration  when  making  man; 
He  has  even  taken  thought  for  human  beauty,  as  may  be  seen  in  the  distribu- 
tion of  hair  on  the  face;  the  beard  on  the  chin  is  a  suitable  adornment  for  a 
man,  while  the  growth  of  a  beard  on  the  nose  would  give  to  the  countenance 
a  wild  and  barbaric  appearance.  But  if  the  hair  of  the  head  is  thus  the  work 
of  the  Creator,  the  hairs  on  the  arms  and  legs  are  the  work  of  chance;  they 
are  likened  to  self-sown  weeds  —  the  Greeks  who  went  about  with  bare 
arms  and  legs  considered  these  hairs  disfiguring  and  therefore  removed 
them.  To  such  absurdities  did  Aristotle's  theory  of  the  finality  of  nature 
gradually  lead,  its  application  no  longer  being  guided  by  his  own  sober  and 
clear  logic.  However,  the  piety  of  Galen  expresses  itself  in  nobler  and  deeper 
thoughts  when  he  leaves  anatomical  details  and  proceeds  to  ethical  problems. 
There  is  a  truly  biblical  tone  about  words  such  as  these:  "In  my  opinion 
true  piety  consists  not  in  sacrificing  hundreds  of  beasts  or  offering  quantities 
of  spices  and  incense,  but  in  oneself  knowing  and  learning  about  the  wisdom, 
power,  and  love  of  the  Creator."  Equally  noble  are  the  words  with  which 
he  exhorts  his  colleagues  not  to  strive  for  profit,  but  to  offer  themselves  to 
the  service  of  suffering  humanity.  In  this  Galen  shows  the  same  noble  and 
humane  spirit  as  his  lord  and  master,  Marcus  Aurelius,  expressed  in  his  Medi- 
tations, and  there  is  every  indication  that,  like  the  latter,  he  lived  as  he 
taught. 

Galen's  anatomical  investigations 
But  if  Galen  in  his  general  conception  of  life  thus  stood  on  the  border-line 
between  antiquity  and  the  Middle  Ages,  he  was  as  regards  knowledge  of 
anatomical  detail  the  foremost  philosopher  of  the  classical  period,  and  as 
such  remained  the  undisputed  authority  in  his  own  branch  of  learning  up  to 
the  Renaissance,  and  strictly  speaking  even  up  to  the  time  when  Harvey 
discovered  the  circulation  of  the  blood  and  thereby  destroyed  one  of  the 
foundation-stones  of  his  theoretical  system.  Both  as  an  anatomist  and  as  a 
physician  Galen  had  indeed  the  inestimable  advantage  of  being  able  to  build 
upon  the  work  of  brilliant  predecessors,  but  he  also  realized  the  importance 
of  his  inheritance  and  considerably  enhanced  it  by  his  own  observations. 
These  he  carried  out  exclusively  on  animals,  both  dead  and  alive,  especially 
apes,  which  he  considered  particularly  suitable  as  material  for  investigation 
of  human  anatomy.  There  is  never  any  question  of  his  dissecting  human 
bodies;  the  times  had  changed  considerably  since  the  days  of  Herophilus; 
old  superstitions  had  again  been  revived  and  governed  men's  minds.  He 
characteristically  begins  his  enunciation  of  the  anatomy  of  the  human  body 
with  the  hand,  the  most  useful  of  all  organs  —  that  whereby  the  soul  effects 


CLASSICAL     ANTIQUITY,     MIDDLE     AGES        63 

its  will,  for  the  whole  body  exists  for  the  sake  of  the  soul.  The  human  hand 
is  described  in  detail  and  with  great  thoroughness,  but,  as  one  can  clearly 
see,  as  the  result  of  investigating  the  hands  of  apes.  Then  he  describes  the 
rest  of  the  extremities  and  afterwards  the  intestinal  canal,  the  respiratory 
organs,  the  brain,  the  spine,  the  blood-vessels,  and  the  genital  organs.  Galen 
stands  highest  as  a  brain  and  nerve  anatomist,  and  in  this  sphere  his  anatomi- 
cal and  experimental  investigations  gave  results  which  left  all  his  predeces- 
sors far  behind.  He  considerably  increased  the  knowledge  of  the  motor  and 
sensory  function  of  the  nerves,  which  the  Alexandrine  anatomists  had  already 
observed,  and  he  differentiated  between  the  sensory,  or,  in  his  terminology, 
the  "soft"  nerves,  and  the  motor,  or  "hard."  The  soft  nerves  go  from  the 
brain  to  the  sense  organs,  the  hard  from  the  spinal  marrow;  as  the  nerves  of 
the  spinal  marrow  also  show  definitely  sensible  qualities,  though  Galen  did 
not  succeed  in  discovering  the  difference  between  the  anterior  and  the  pos- 
terior medullary  nerves,  he  evades  the  difficulty  by  assuming  a  "mixed" 
consistency  and  function  in  certain  medullary  nerves.  By  experiments  in  sever- 
ing different  sections  of  spinal  marrow  in  living  animals  he  showed  the  con- 
nexion between  these  and  corresponding  parts  of  the  body.  The  brain  he 
likewise  described  in  detail;  of  its  nerves  he  traces  seven  couples,  the  rami- 
fications of  which  are  closely  worked  out.  On  the  other  hand,  his  idea  of 
the  function  of  the  brain  is  confused,  owing  to  speculations  upon  the  "soul 
pneuma,"  which,  produced  in  the  cerebral  ventricles,  circulates  through  the 
entire  nervous  system  and  forms  its  most  essential  component,  the  basis  of  its 
functions.  It  may  be  mentioned  in  this  connexion  that  he  shared  the  ancient 
idea  of  the  localization  of  the  various  qualities  of  the  soul  in  various  organs, 
which  naturally  gives  rise  to  long  expositions  on  the  wisdom  of  the  Creator 
and  the  finality  of  the  creation.  The  account  of  the  digestive  apparatus  and 
its  function  is  in  Galen,  as  in  the  anatomists  of  antiquity  in  general,  one  of 
the  weak  points.  The  human  digestive  canal  is  described  after  combining 
the  results  of  dissections  performed  on  various  animals,  both  vegetarian  and 
carnivorous,  which  fact  does  not  help  to  make  his  idea  of  it  clear.  Digestion, 
which  in  Aristotle  was  the  result  of  the  cooking  of  the  food,  is  ascribed  by 
Galen  to  a  special  "transformation  power"  in  the  stomach;  its  products  are 
transferred  through  the  blood-vessels  to  the  liver,  where  they  are  converted 
into  blood;  the  useless  parts  of  the  food  are  absorbed  by  the  spleen  and  con- 
verted by  it  into  "black  bile,"  which  is  excreted  through  the  bowel.  The 
kidneys  serve  to  remove  excessive  water  from  the  blood.  This  is  afterwards 
conveyed  through  the  veins  of  the  liver,  partly  to  the  right  chamber  of  the 
heart  and  partly  out  into  the  body. 

Heart  and  blood-vessels 
Galen  described  the  system  of  the  blood-vessels  in  detail,  and  his  opinion 
on  this  subject  —  with  its  errors  as  well  as  its  merits  —  had  a  more  lasting 


64  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

effect  than  that  on  any  other  subject.  As  one  of  his  services  to  science  it  may 
be  mentioned  that  he  finally  succeeded  in  overcoming  the  old  preconception 
that  the  arteries  and  the  left  heart-chamber  contain  air.  In  his  opinion  they 
contain  blood,  with  an  admixture  of  "pneuma"  —  that  half-airlike,  half- 
firelike  life-principle  which  gave  rise  to  so  much  discussion  in  ancient  times 
and  on  which  the  existence  of  living  creatures  depends.  In  one  place  Galen 
expresses  the  hope  that  the  time  may  come  when  someone  will  discover  the 
component  in  the  air  which  forms  pneuma,  the  substance  which  is  the  com- 
mon precondition  of  life  and  combustion  —  a  curious  idea,  which  in  fact 
the  discovery  of  oxygen  was  eventually  to  bring  to  realization.  He  gives  a 
detailed  description  of  the  heart,  both  its  structure  and  its  functions;  on  the 
other  hand,  like  his  predecessors,  he  lets  both  veins  and  arteries  convey  the 
blood  from  the  heart  to  the  rest  of  the  body,  in  which  it  is  consumed.  He 
is  not  aware  of  any  blood  flowing  from  the  body  to  the  heart,  while  his  idea 
of  the  movement  of  the  blood  is  still  further  confused  by  his  belief  that  the 
liver  is  to  a  certain  extent  the  centre  of  the  venous  system,  since  the  blood 
flows  from  it  not  only  to  the  heart,  but  also  to  the  rest  of  the  body.  The 
left  ventricle  receives  through  the  vena pulmonalis  "pneuma"  from  the  lungs; 
from  the  right  ventricle  the  excremental  products  proceed  to  the  lungs,  these 
products  being  "soot"  from  the  combustion  process  in  the  heart,  which  is 
got  rid  of  by  exhalation.  The  wall  between  the  right  and  the  left  ventricles 
of  the  heart  is  porous,  permitting  the  blood  to  pass  through.  The  walls  of 
the  blood-vessels  are  carefully  described,  and,  generally  speaking,  Galen's 
detailed  study  of  the  construction  of  the  individual  organs  is  one  of  his  strong 
points.  He  is  aware  of  the  connexions  between  the  arteries  and  the  veins, 
but,  as  is  seen  from  the  above,  he  has  not  realized  the  idea  of  circulation,  and 
this  fact,  combined  with  the  vagueness  with  which  he  explains  his  ideas  on 
these  organs,  proved  an  obstacle  to  the  development  of  biology  for  the  next 
fifteen  hundred  years. 

Galen  carefully  studied  the  respiratory  process  and  on  the  whole  de- 
scribed it  correctly.  With  regard  to  the  sense  organs,  in  spite  of  his  thorough 
investigations  into  the  subject  he  made  very  little  advance  on  his  predeces- 
sors, and  the  same  may  be  said  of  his  description  of  the  genital  system  and 
the  embryonic  process,  in  which  he  remains,  on  the  whole,  where  Aristotle 
stood. 

Splendid  as  Galen's  scientific  work  was,  it  does  not  appear  to  have  been 
highly  appreciated  by  his  contemporaries.  He  himself  complains  that  but  few 
understand  him,  but  consoles  himself  with  the  thought  that  the  Creator,  in 
spite  of  man's  ingratitude,  never  wearies  of  doing  good.  Here  posterity  has  to 
an  unusually  generous  extent  made  up  for  what  his  contemporaries  failed  to 
give  him.  The  fact  that  Galen  did  not  impress  his  contemporaries  may  have 
been  due  to  the  peculiar  transitional  attitude  he  adopted;  to  the  survivors  of 


CLASSICAL     ANTIQUITY,     MIDDLE     AGES        65 

the  purely  ancient  school  his  romantic  piety  must  have  been  repulsive,  while 
the  more  mystically  minded,  who  even  then  represented  the  majority,  were 
on  the  whole  not  at  all  interested  in  exact  natural  science.  The  miracle- 
workers'  laying  on  of  hands  and  invocations  were  undoubtedly  more  relied 
upon  than  Galen's  curative  method,  based  on  anatomical  studies.  On  the 
whole,  during  this  period  interest  in  the  study  of  nature  waned  more  and 
more,  at  least  in  the  sense  in  which  the  philosophers  of  old  times  understood 
it;  the  most  one  could  do  for  educational  purposes  was  to  collect  stories 
about  natural  objects.  One  such  collection  is  the  treatise  still  preserved  in 
our  day  On  the  Habits  of  Animals,  which  was  written  by  Claudius  v^lianus 
a  generation  after  Galen.  This  writer,  who  was  an  orator  by  profession  — 
that  is  to  say,  a  public  lecturer  —  lived  in  Rome  in  the  first  half  of  the  third 
century;  he  is  believed  to  have  died  in  the  year  x6o.  His  work  is  a  collection 
of  anecdotes  about  animals,  gathered  from  various  sources  —  thus  following 
the  method  of  Pliny.  But  while  in  Pliny  the  interest  in  nature  is  the  prin- 
cipal motive,  i^lianus  is  actuated  by  a  feeling  of  pure  edification.  Pliny,  it 
is  true,  can  also  edify  his  readers  with  the  examples  he  cites  of  the  virtues 
of  elephants,  but  they  are  related  in  order  to  testify  to  the  animals'  great 
qualities  of  soul.  In  .^lianus  even  the  lowest  creatures  are  uplifted  by  a 
purely  personal  reverence  for  the  Creator,  so  that  the  ecclesiastical  writers 
of  the  Middle  Ages  had  only  to  substitute  the  names  of  Christian  saints 
for  those  of  the  gods  quoted  and  they  thus  found  ready  to  hand  a  collection 
of  the  most  edifying  sermons.  Thus  i^lianus  tells  of  a  cock  that  had  one 
of  its  legs  broken;  the  bird  hopped  on  its  other  leg  before  a  statue  of  a  god, 
and  stretching  out  the  broken  foot,  crowed  so  pathetically  that  the  god 
showed  his  mercy  by  miraculously  healing  the  injury,  whereupon  the  cock, 
gratefully  flapping  its  wings,  went  on  its  way.  Here  we  find  the  purely 
mediaeval  conception,  and  this  more  than  a  century  before  the  final  victory 
of  Christianity;  an  example,  i^iter  alia,  of  the  incorrectness  of  the  frequent 
assertion  that  the  Christian  Church  after  its  victory  eradicated  the  culture 
of  antiquity. 

Neo-Platonists 
With  regard  to  the  natural  sciences  an  attempt  has  been  made  in  the  fore- 
going to  throw  light  on  the  process  of  internal  dissolution  which  gradually 
led  biology  from  Aristotle's  magnificent  system  of  thought  down  to  i^li- 
anus'  collection  of  legends.  The  interest  in  natural  phenomena  which  had 
for  so  long  been  a  living  factor  in  the  ancient  world  of  culture  had  now 
entirely  disappeared.  What  was  left  of  the  spirit  of  research  turned  to  ideal- 
istic philosophy,  Plato's  creation,  which  was  further  developed  by  thinkers 
who  adopted  his  name  and  made  his  theory  of  ideas  their  starting-point, 
proceeding  thence  in  a  curious  direction,  at  the  same  time  speculative  and 
full  of  religious  mysticism.  In  their  relations  with  the  outer  world  these 


66  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

neo-Platonists  were  as  opposed  to  the  men  of  antiquity  as  their  Christian 
contemporaries.  The  founder  of  the  school,  Plotinus,  was  ashamed  of  pos- 
sessing a  body,  while  its  last  great  thinker,  Proclus  (411-485),  lived  as  a 
hermit;  he  dwelt  in  a  cave,  avoided  wine,  meat,  and  women,  and  saw  visions 
of  supernatural  things.  For  to  be  uplifted  into  the  supersensible  by  means 
of  ecstatic  rapture  was  to  the  neo-Platonists  not  only  the  whole  object  of 
life,  but  also  the  very  foundation  of  science.  With  all  its  fantastic  specula- 
tion this  school  nevertheless  developed  human  thought  in  one  important 
sphere;  it  discussed  the  idea  of  infinity  as  none  of  its  predecessors  had  been 
able  to  do.  To  the  ancient  atomists  infinity  was  really  only  an  unlimited 
extension  in  time  and  space,  akin  to  the  custom  of  children  and  wild  men, 
who  when  they  are  weary  of  counting,  call  the  remainder  "much"  or 
"many."  To  the  neo-Platonists,  again,  the  infinite  was  equivalent  to  the 
inexpressible  and  the  unknowable,  that  which  exceeds  all  limitations  and 
measures.  And  though  their  endeavour  to  attain  to  this  infinity  by  way  of 
ecstasy  was  naturally  of  no  scientific  value,  there  was  nevertheless  an  in- 
disputable truth  to  be  gained  as  a  result  of  their  endeavours,  seeing  that 
the  impotence  of  the  power  of  knowledge  in  face  of  the  infinite  was  estab- 
lished once  and  for  all.  The  natural-research  work  of  our  time  is  based  on 
the  realization  of  the  limitation  of  knowledge  in  face  of  the  infinity  of 
existence  —  a  limitation  which  only  unscientific  dilettantism  thinks  it  pos- 
sible to  override. 

Destruction  of  the  old  culturt 
There  were,  then,  among  the  thinkers  of  this  period  ideas  which  pointed 
beyond  the  limitations  by  which  the  ancient  conceptions  of  existence  had 
been  surrounded.  It  is  impossible  to  estimate  how  these  aims  might  have 
developed  in  happier  external  circumstances.  For  as  a  result  of  the  fall  of 
the  Roman  Empire  the  external,  purely  material  preconditions  for  the  con- 
tinuance of  scientific  research  and  for  the  progress  of  culture  in  general  no 
longer  existed.  As  early  as  the  latter  half  of  the  imperial  epoch  the  pros- 
perity of  those  nations  which  formed  the  Roman  Empire  steadily  declined 
as  a  result  of  misgovernment,  civil  war,  and  the  inroads  of  neighbouring 
peoples.  In  the  fifth  century  the  world  empire  collapsed  entirely  owing  to 
the  invasion  of  the  Germans,  and  a  state  of  dire  distress,  economic,  politi- 
cal, and  moral,  ensued.  The  new  kingdoms  which  were  founded  by  barbar- 
ous nations  had  great  difficulty  in  firmly  establishing  themselves,  and  their 
rulers'  utter  lack  of  culture  rendered  impossible  any  kind  of  ordered  system 
of  government  and,  consequently,  any  high  standard  of  prosperity.  How- 
ever, the  inhabitants  of  western  Europe  gradually  co-operated  in  reviving 
culture  on  a  national  basis.  During  the  last  hundred  years  of  the  Roman 
Empire,  Gaul  had  been  the  most  civilized  country  in  the  Empire,  with 
numerous  institutions  founded  for  the  study  of  classical  learning.  During 


CLASSICAL     ANTIQUITY,     MIDDLE     AGES        67 

the  period  of  invasion  many  people  fled  from  western  Gaul  to  what  was 
certainly  a  barbarous,  but  all  the  same  a  peaceful  country,  Ireland,  and  thus 
was  founded  a  centre  of  culture  which  during  the  sixth  and  seventh  centu- 
ries was  the  foremost  upholder  of  the  classical  tradition  and  one  of  the 
starting-points  for  the  future  progress  of  civilization.  In  the  eastern  part  of 
old  Roman  Empire  the  Byzantine  power  was  still  dominant  with  a  despotic 
form  of  government  and  the  Greek  Orthodox  Church  as  a  binding  force. 
There,  too,  efforts  were  made  to  develop  national  culture,  which  was  ex- 
pressed in  literature,  in  the  national  tongue,  combined  with  interest  in 
Greek  science.  This  was  especially  so  in  Syria,  where  the  national  move- 
ment was  often  associated  with  religious  sectarianism;  but  in  Persia  too, 
under  the  Sassanid  dynasty,  Greek  science  was  studied,  particularly  Aris- 
totle. In  these  countries,  however,  there  shortly  arose  a  new  cultural 
power,  which  took  over  and  further  developed  the  learning  of  the  classical 
period  —  namely,  the  Arabian  people,  with  their  new  religion,  founded  by 
Mohammed. 


CHAPTER    IX 

BIOLOGICAL    SCIENCE    AMONG    THE     ARABIANS 

The  Arabian  conquest  of  the  East 

WHEN  MOHAMMED  DIED,  iH  63X,  the  religion  he  founded  had  already 
spread  throughout  Arabia,  and  his  successors,  the  first  caliphs, 
managed  in  the  course  of  a  few  decades  to  bring  under  their  do- 
minion the  old  civilized  countries  of  Babylon,  Persia,  Syria,  and  Egypt,  to 
which  were  later  added  North  Africa  and  Spain.  War  against  the  unfaithful 
was  indeed  the  prophet's  first  commandment,  and  according  to  his  injunction 
the  heathen  had  a  choice  between  death  and  conversion;  such  of  the  unfaith- 
ful, again,  as  possessed  religious  writings  —  Christians,  Jews,  and  Persians  — 
had  their  lives  spared,  but  were  subject  to  impositions  and  personal  humilia- 
tion. The  bedouins  of  the  desert,  who  thus  at  one  blow  became  the  rulers  of 
the  most  ancient  civilized  countries  in  the  world,  were  themselves  nothing 
but  barbarians,  it  is  true,  but  they  were  intelligent  and  susceptible  to  cultural 
influence,  all  the  more  so  as  in  the  course  of  the  wandering  life  they  led,  they 
had  already  come  into  contact  with  their  civilized  neighbours.  Their  new  re- 
ligion was  favourable  for  rapid  cultural  progress  in  that  it  was  a  legal  doc- 
trine with  few  and  easily  comprehensible  rules,  without,  to  be  sure,  the  lofty 
ethical  claims  of  Christianity,  but  also  without  the  theological  subtleties  of 
the  different  ecclesiastical  formulas.  And  as,  besides,  the  Arabs  troubled  them- 
selves but  little  about  social  and  political  questions  —  they  permitted  the 
institutions  of  conquered  nations  to  survive  and  contented  themselves  with 
appointing  governors  who  collected  taxes  from  them  —  they  had  ample  time 
to  devote  themselves  to  purely  intellectual  interests.  Indeed,  they  grasped  the 
elements  of  the  culture  of  the  period  with  a  rapidity  which  has  been  com- 
pared to  that  of  the  Japanese  in  our  own  day,  and  were  able  in  many  respects 
to  build  higher  upon  the  foundations  they  found  prepared  for  them.  These 
foundations  were  Greek  science,  as  the  subject  peoples  produced  it  in  Syrian 
and  Persian  translations;  it  was  not  until  later  that  the  Arabs  learnt  to  read 
Greek  writings  in  the  original.  They  developed  this  material  and  thus  created 
a  science  representing  at  the  same  time  a  direct  continuation  of  the  Greek 
and  a  reconstruction  of  it  to  suit  the  conditions  which  the  peculiar  Arabian 
view  of  the  world  required.  According  to  Mohammed's  theory,  the  Koran 
is  the  source  of  all  learning  and  contains  all  the  knowledge  that  man  requires; 
but  this  claim,  which  would  have  rendered  all  research  impossible,  was 

68 


CLASSICAL     ANTIQUITY,     MIDDLE     AGES        69 

evaded  during  more  liberal  eras,  while  obscurantist  rulers  continued  to 
threaten  the  learned  with  its  literal  application.  This  was,  however,  the 
cause  of  a  certain  restraint  invariably  characterizing  Arabian  research,  at  least 
in  form;  the  scientists  preferred  to  give  their  works  —  even  the  most  independ- 
ent —  the  appearance  of  commentaries  on  the  writings  of  some  famous  scien- 
tist of  antiquity.  In  philosophy  and  natural  science  it  was  naturally  Aristotle, 
in  medicine  Galen,  who  was  made  to  represent  the  authority  on  whom 
the  work  was  based,  and  at  the  same  time  the  screen  behind  which  the  Ara- 
bian scientists  saved  themselves  in  the  event  of  the  authorities'  finding  the 
results  of  their  research  work  inadmissible.  During  the  most  brilliant  period 
of  Arabian  research  it  was  certainly  possible  for  original  and  great  thoughts 
to  be  disguised  beneath  these  commentaries  on  ancient  writings,  but  the 
danger  of  slavish  imitation  lay  in  the  method  itself,  and  for  more  than  five 
hundred  years  the  science  of  the  East  was  drowned  in  an  utterly  soulless 
amplification  of  ancient  authorities. 

Experimental  method  introduced  iyito  science 
The  Arabian  contribution  to  the  development  of  the  exact  sciences  has  been 
most  important  in  the  spheres  of  mathematics  and  astronomy,  in  which  they 
received  impulses  not  only  from  Greek,  but  also  from  Hindu  quarters  —  the 
so-called  "Arabic  numerals,"  which  are  now  universally  used,  were  bor- 
rowed by  the  Arabs  from  India  —  and,  further,  geography,  a  study  which 
the  Arabs  applied  to  the  investigating  of  several  unknown  regions,  medicine, 
particularly  pharmacology  and,  in  connexion  therewith,  botany,  and,  finally, 
chemistry,  which  they  were  the  first  to  raise  to  the  rank  of  a  science.  Chem- 
istry, indeed,  is  experimental  science  above  all  others,  and  with  it  experi- 
menting as  a  scientific  method  was  introduced  and  developed  by  the  Arabs. 
This  contribution  alone  is  such  as  to  ensure  to  Arabic  science  a  place  of 
honour  in  the  history  of  research.  Experimenting,  in  which  the  research- 
worker  himself  interferes  with  the  course  of  events  in  nature  and  arranges 
that  course  with  a  view  to  having  a  specific  question  answered  —  this,  the 
most  certain  method  whereby  the  obedience  of  natural  phenomena  to  law 
can  be  proved,  was  unknown  to  ancient  research.  Even  Archimedes  himself 
was  no  experimental  physicist,  eminent  though  he  was  as  a  practical  en- 
gineer, while  Galen's  vivisections,  as  well  as  those  of  his  Alexandrian  prede- 
cessors, had  rather  the  character  of  observations  of  live  animals  than  of 
actual  experiments.  As  a  matter  of  fact,  however,  the  experimental  method 
is  very  ancient  and  has  its  origin  in  a  number  of  experiences  of  various  kinds 
which  survived  in  different  classes  of  people  before  science  adopted  their 
methodic  system  and  employed  it  for  obtaining  results  in  exact  research 
work.  Thus  every  type  of  peoples  has  practised  magical  experiments  based 
on  the  preparation  of  charms,  which  are  concocted  out  of  the  most  extraor- 
dinary ingredients  and  are  used  as  love-potions,  elixirs  of  life,  enchant- 


yo  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

ments,  and  pure  poison.  Such  magic  brews  were  prepared  among  the  nations 
of  antiquity  by  witches  and  wizards  and  are  still  concocted  amongst  inferior 
peoples  and  even  amongst  more  primitive  strata  of  higher  types  to  this  very 
day.  That  the  enlightened  scientists  of  antiquity  refused  to  associate  them- 
selves with  such  magical  preparations  was  but  natural;  it  required  that 
tendency  towards  the  vulgar  and  the  fantastic  which  the  decline  of  ancient 
culture  evoked  in  the  scientific  world,  before  the  methods  of  popular  sorcery 
could  begin  to  be  of  interest  to  thinking  and  inquiring  minds  as  well.  Nor 
indeed  does  the  earliest  experimental  science  deny  this  origin;  it  appears  in 
the  form  of  alchemy,  with  its  pronounced  mystical  aims,  and  above  all  in 
the  conversion  of  base  metals  into  precious  metals,  the  discovery  of  elixirs 
of  life  and  immortality,  the  reproduction  of  homuncules,  etc.  —  aims  to 
which  it  adhered  throughout  the  Middle  Ages,  even  after  its  means  and 
methods  had  become  characterized,  at  least  in  certain  features,  by  a  fair 
measure  of  exactness  and  an  extensive  knowledge  of  the  inorganic  objects  of 
nature  in  particular.  It  was  therefore  at  a  later  stage  than  any  other  branch 
of  exact  science  that  the  experimental  branch  succeeded  in  freeing  itself  from 
its  connexion  with  the  supernatural  world  of  thought,  from  which  all  science 
gradually  broke  away.  It  is  only  the  research  work  of  more  modern  times 
that  has  been  able  to  enjoy  to  the  full  the  advantages  which  experimental 
science  offers. 

Arabian  natural  philosophers 
With  biology  the  famous  Arabian  alchemists,  one  Geber  and  others,  had 
nothing  to  do;  they  occupied  themselves  only  with  inorganic  nature.  On 
the  other  hand,  the  East  possessed  a  number  of  purely  speculative  re- 
searchers who  dealt  with  the  phenomena  in  living  nature  from  a  theo- 
retical point  of  view  and  who  exercised  a  lasting  influence  on  the  conception 
of  them  in  succeeding  ages.  All  these  philosophers  took  Aristotle  as  the 
starting-point  for  their  researches  and,  as  already  mentioned,  they  likewise 
gave  to  their  own  often  quite  daring  speculations  the  form  of  commentaries 
on  his  works.  Indeed,  their  position  was  always  fraught  with  danger;  they 
were  looked  upon  with  suspicion  by  the  orthodox  Mohammedans,  who  be- 
lieved that  all  studies  that  did  not  concern  the  Holy  Koran  were  prohibited. 
Against  these  constant  persecutions  they  had  no  other  support  than  the  pat- 
ronage of  some  science-loving  prince,  which  had  to  be  won  and  sustained  by 
flattery  and  was  at  best  an  unreliable  guarantee  of  life  and  maintenance. 
These  philosophers  held  no  posts  as  teachers  —  in  the  Mohammedan  East 
there  were  colleges  only  for  students  of  the  Koran  —  but  their  scientific 
researches  were  always  a  private  occupation;  by  profession  they  were  fre- 
quently physicians,  sometimes  lawyers,  officials,  or  courtiers. 

Among  these  oriental  thinkers  there  are  primarily  two  who  exerted 
some  influence  on  the  progress  of  science  even  in  the  West,  their  writings 


CLASSICAL     ANTIQUITY,     MIDDLE     AGES        71 

being  at  an  early  date  translated  into  Latin  and  diligently  studied  in  Europe, 
becoming  at  the  same  time  the  basis  for  continued  philosophical  research. 
Abu  Sina,  or,  as  he  is  called  in  Europe,  with  a  latinized  distortion  of  his  name, 
AviCENNA,  was  born  at  Bokhara  in  980,  of  Persian  stock.  At  that  period 
Persia  was  divided  into  a  number  of  major  and  minor  states,  ruled  over  by 
princes,  who  in  mutual  rivalry  sought  to  win  honour  by  exploits  of  war  and 
peace.  There  prevailed  a  high  standard  of  intellectual  culture,  and  the  con- 
ditions of  the  country  have  often  been  compared  with  those  of  Italy  during 
the  Renaissance.  Avicenna  indeed  bears  a  great  resemblance  to  personalities 
living  at  the  time  of  the  Renaissance;  strictly  speaking,  he  was  a  physician, 
but  he  was  also  mathematician,  astronomer,  philosopher,  and  poet.  Cheq- 
uered too  were  his  fortunes;  at  one  time  he  was  an  all-powerful  minister  at 
the  court  of  some  vassal  prince,  at  another  he  was  an  exile  fleeing  from  his 
enemies  and  in  danger  of  his  life.  He  died  in  1037,  his  health  shattered  by 
his  manifold  exertions  and  his  reckless  love  of  pleasure.  The  most  important 
of  his  numerous  writings  is  his  great  Canon  of  Medicine,  which,  next  to 
Galen's,  remained  the  chief  authority  in  the  sphere  of  medical  science.  Its 
sections  dealing  generally  with  natural  philosophy,  anatomy,  and  physi- 
ology are  of  interest  from  the  point  of  view  of  biological  history.  There  is 
still  extant  a  major  work  of  his  on  general  philosophy.  As  a  thinker  Avi- 
cenna takes  Aristotle  as  his  starting-point,  but  he  is  also  tq.  a  certain  extent 
influenced  by  neo-Platonism.  His  conception  of  nature  is  governed  by  the 
"purpose"  theory  of  Aristotle  and  Galen.  Entirely  based  on  Galen,  too,  is 
his  idea  of  the  human  anatomy.  The  Arabs  were  in  fact  even  more  afraid  of 
dissecting  human  bodies  than  were  the  people  of  antiquity;  it  was  forbidden 
in  the  Koran,  and  with  however  little  prejudice  the  learned  interpreted  the 
sacred  book,  they  dared  not  in  this  respect  violate  both  it  and  public  opinion. 
Avicenna,  however,  was  more  independent  as  a  physiologist;  here  he  could 
take  advantage  of  the  progress  his  contemporaries  had  made  in  the  fields  of 
physics  and  chemistry.  But  actually  it  was  more  for  his  excellence  of  form  — 
brilliant  style  and  well-arranged  grouping  of  his  subject  —  than  for  any 
original  ideas  that  Avicenna  won  fame  in  the  East  and  eventually,  perhaps 
to  a  still  higher  degree,  in  the  West. 

Far  more  original  as  a  thinker  is  the  second  of  the  great  men  of  science  in 
the  East,  Averroes,  or  Ibn-Rushd,  as  he  was  properly  called  in  Arabic.  He 
was  born  at  Cordova  in  Spain  in  iiz6,  the  son  of  an  eminent  judge.  In  his 
native  city,  which  for  several  centuries  had  been  the  centre  of  Arabic  culture 
in  Spain,  he  studied  philosophy,  medicine,  and  jurisprudence,  was  for  some 
years  afterwards  cadi  of  Seville,  and  was  finally  governor  of  a  province.  The 
fanatical  religious  reaction,  however,  which  gradually  spread  among  the 
Mohammedans  in  Spain  towards  the  close  of  the  twelfth  century,  once  suc- 
ceeded in  bringing  about  his  downfall,  and,  accused  of  heretical  opinions 


72.  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

and  pursuits,  he  was  imprisoned,  stripped  of  his  honours,  and  banished  to 
a  village  near  Cordova  inhabited  by  Jews.  Fortunately  the  ruling  prince  who 
committed  this  act  of  injustice  died  a  year  or  two  afterwards  and  his  son 
and  successor  immediately  repaired  it;  Averroes  was  recalled  to  court  and 
resumed  his  honours,  but  died  shortly  after,  in  1198. 

As  a  natural  philosopher  Averroes  followed  Aristotle,  and  his  principal 
work  takes  the  form  of  commentaries  on  Aristotle's  writings.  Averroes's 
standpoint  is,  however,  far  more  than  that  of  his  predecessors  and  even  than 
that  of  any  other  mediaeval  philosopher,  independent  of  his  model.  He  bases 
his  philosophy  on  the  latter' s  ideas,  but  he  develops  them  further  on  his 
own  account.  In  particular  he  studied  the  relation  between  potentiality  and 
reality  in  nature.  Aristotle  considered  that  marble  is  a  potentiality,  which 
becomes  reality  when  a  statue  is  made  out  of  it,  and  he  consistently  applied 
this  method  to  life  in  nature  —  the  seed,  the  embryo,  is  a  potentiality;  the 
plant,  the  animal,  reality.  Averroes  argued  in  opposition  to  this  view  that 
nothing  in  nature  is  potential  that  does  not  exist  in  reality,  in  however  un- 
developed and  therefore  disguised  a  form  it  may  be;  the  plant  already  exists 
in  the  seed,  in  however  undeveloped  a  state,  just  like  the  animal  in  the  embryo. 
The  simile  of  the  marble  and  the  statue  Averroes  considers  inapplicable  where 
nature  is  concerned;  at  best  the  simile  would  be  admissible  if  the  statue  were 
to  be  found  already  shaped  in  the  veins  of  the  unsculptured  block.  By  this 
method  of  speculation  Averroes  has  carried  science  a  long  step  nearer  the 
present-day  conception  of  natural  evolution;  Aristotle's  purely  abstract 
idea  of  potentiality  is  here  replaced  by  something  which  approaches  far 
nearer  to  our  idea  of  energy.  Averroes  was  the  last  great  Arabic  philosopher 
and  the  greatest  natural  philosopher  of  the  Middle  Ages;  if  anyone  is  worthy 
to  be  called  the  Aristotle  of  the  Middle  Ages,  it  is  he.  He  resembles  his  pro- 
totype not  only  in  the  fact  of  his  having  lived  in  a  decadent  era  and  been 
subjected  to  religious  persecution,  but  also  in  the  fact  that  no  one  for  cen- 
turies succeeded  in  developing  his  ideas  further.  Shortly  after  his  death 
Arabic  science  succumbed  to  religious  intolerance,  while  even  the  Christian 
schoolmen,  who  closely  studied  and  highly  honoured  the  Arabic  philoso- 
pher,^ saw  in  him  only  the  interpreter  of  Aristotle  and  were  not  capable  of 
realizing  the  great  advance  he  made  towards  a  more  real  conception  of  na- 
ture. He  has  not,  however,  been  without  influence;  in  the  Middle  Ages  the 
opponents  of  ecclesiastical  philosophy  gathered  round  his  name,  and  the 
ideas  he  evoked  can  thus  be  traced  through  the  ages  until  they  find  confirma- 
tion in  the  natural  science  of  our  own  day. 

Arabic  literature  has  produced,  besides  the  natural  philosophers  men- 
tioned, several  authors  who  have  dealt  with  zoology  in  a  more  restricted 

^  During  his  imaginary  wanderings  in  the  underworld  Dance  sees  Averroes  in  the  court 
of  the  heathen  by  the  side  of  Aristotle  and  other  philosophers  of  antiquity. 


CLASSICAL     ANTIQUITY,     MIDDLE     AGES        73 

sense:  faunistics  and  zoogeography.  Such  authors  are  mentioned  as  early  as 
the  ninth  and  tenth  centuries,  but  their  writings  have  not  been  preserved. 
On  the  other  hand,  there  is  still  extant  an  account  of  the  animals  of  Egypt, 
written  by  Abdallatif  (1162.-1131),  which  is  manifestly  based  not  only  upon 
ancient  authors,  but  also  upon  personal  investigation.  Inter  alia,  he  gives 
a  detailed  description  of  the  hippopotamus  and  the  crocodile  and  also  an 
account  of  the  method  customary  in  Egypt  of  hatching  hen's  eggs  by  arti- 
ficial heat.  A  fairly  large  work  entitled  Animal  Life  by  Muhammed  el  Damiri, 
written  at  the  end  of  the  fourteenth  century,  has  come  down  to  us.  He  has 
described  a  great  number  of  animal  species  —  one  statement  declares  it  to 
be  nearly  nine  hundred  —  partly  based  on  his  own  observations,  but  partly 
also  on  pure  imagination.  Arabic  literature  possesses  one  author  comparable 
with  Pliny  in  the  person  of  Sakarja  ben  Muhammed,  called  el  Kasvini  after 
his  own  district  of  Kasvin  in  northern  Persia.  He  lived  in  the  thirteenth 
century  and  thus  had  at  his  disposal,  besides  Aristotle  and  Hippocrates, 
whom  he  freely  quotes,  a  number  of  Arabian  predecessors,  of  whose  works  he 
made  extensive  use.  His  important  collective  work.  The  Wonders  of  Nature,  is 
based  on  Aristotle's  natural  philosophy  of  evolution  from  the  lower  to  the 
higher;  the  capacity  to  feel  and  move  differentiates  the  plants  from  the  ani- 
mals. His  theory  of  fossilized  animals  is  curious;  he  believes  that  they  have 
been  petrified  by  steam  arising  out  of  the  ground  on  which  they  stood.  For 
the  rest,  he  describes  a  number  of  tropical  animals  which  were  unknown  to 
ancient  authors,  for  instance  the  orang-utan,  which  he  pictures  as  having 
the  human  characteristics  which  the  inhabitants  of  his  native  place  ascribe 
to  it,  and,  further,  the  flying  dog,  the  dugong,  and  others. 

On  the  whole,  it  is  through  their  having  promoted  the  knowledge  of 
and  the  cultural  influences  between  the  East,  even  its  most  distant  parts,  and 
the  West,  that  the  Arabs  have  become  best  known  among  the  peoples  of  the 
West;  rather  than  by  the  really  more  profound  cultural  service  they  performed 
in  having  preserved  and  developed  the  remains  of  ancient  culture  at  a  period 
when  the  West  was  incapacitated  from  preserving  the  inheritance  which 
nevertheless  most  directly  devolved  upon  its  peoples.  Through  the  interme- 
diary of  the  Arabian  philosophers  the  few  learned  scholars  of  the  West  in  the 
early  Middle  Ages  acquired  a  knowledge  of  the  products  of  classical  culture; 
Aristotle,  for  instance,  was  long  read  at  the  mediasval  universities  in  Latin 
versions  of  Arabic  translations  from  the  original  writings,  and  the  Arabic 
commentators,  Avicenna,  Averroes,  and  others,  were  the  first  to  act  as  guides 
to  an  understanding  of  the  treatises  on  nature  and  to  help  Europeans  to  pene- 
trate that  world  of  phenomena  whose  existence  they  had  entirely  forgotten. 
Thanks  to  Arabian  science,  the  so-called  dark  centuries  of  the  Middle  Ages 
were  at  any  rate  culturally  fruitful,  and  when  oriental  science,  after  flourish- 
ing for  a  brief  period,  died  out,  the  people  of  the  West  had  already  laid  the 
foundations  of  an  entirely  new  cultural  development. 


CHAPTER    X 

BIOLOGY    DURING    THE    CHRISTIAN    MIDDLE    AGES 

The  Eastern  Roman  Empire 

IN  A  PREVIOUS  CHAPTER  mention  has  been  made  of  how  the  culture  of  an- 
tiquity, itself  already  become  decadent,  received  its  death-blow  through 
the  transmigration  of  peoples  which  broke  up  the  Roman  Empire.  The 
first  political  evidence  of  this  dissolution  was  the  splitting  up  of  the  mighty 
Empire  in  the  year  395.  The  cultural  world  of  the  time  was  thereby  divided 
into  an  eastern  and  a  western  half,  which  suffered  essentially  different  for- 
tunes. In  the  eastern  section  the  old  imperial  constitution  was  still  to  survive 
for  over  a  thousand  years,  maintained  in  power  through  the  people's  being  so 
long  accustomed  to  a  despotic  form  of  government,  and  upheld  by  an  intimate 
connexion  with  the  strangely  established  Greek  Oriental  Church  —  in  actual 
fact  the  bond  that  held  together  the  mixed  populations  which  gave  alle- 
giance to  the  sceptre  of  the  Emperor  of  the  East.  Greek  was  the  prevailing 
language  here  and  the  medium  for  a  peculiar  form  of  culture,  the  Byzantine, 
which  displayed  extraordinary  qualities  of  resistance  to  the  pressure  of  hos- 
tile forces:  the  Mohammedans  in  the  East,  wild  hordes  of  migratory  peoples 
from  the  north  and  "Latins,"  as  the  western  Europeans  were  here  called, 
in  the  West.  This  constant  struggle  for  cultural  supremacy  produced,  as  it 
invariably  does,  a  tendency  to  strict  conservatism,  and  the  value  of  the  By- 
zantine culture  therefore  lies  not  so  much  in  independent  creative  work  as 
in  all  that  it  did  for  the  preservation  of  the  ancient  literature  which,  even 
for  philological  reasons,  it  already  had  some  interest  in  preserving.  The  capi- 
tal of  the  Empire  certainly  possessed  valuable  libraries,  and  educational  es- 
tablishments with  highly  complicated  methods  of  instruction,  but  the  studies 
pursued  there  consisted  mostly  in  theological  subtleties,  the  amplification 
of  ancient  authors,  and  the  compilation  of  histories.  The  scholars  of  Con- 
stantinople cared  little  for  natural  science.  On  the  other  hand,  the  Byzan- 
tine physicians  were  famed  for  their  great  ability;  they  honourably  upheld 
the  best  traditions  of  the  medical  science  of  antiquity.  Their  training  was 
entirely  practical,  however  —  they  received  no  academical  instruction  in  the 
science  of  medicine  —  and  they  were  in  fact  essentially  practitioners;  the 
theoretical  branches  of  medicine,  anatomy  and  physiology,  they  have  done 
very  little  to  promote.  The  principal  medical  work  of  the  Byzantine  era, 
written  by  Paulus  of^^gina  in  the  seventh  century,  deals  only  with  practical 

74 


Q 

< 
> 
o 

p 
< 
w 

1/5 

I— I 

h-l 


o 

w 
w 

<! 
> 

o 

H 


CLASSICAL     ANTIQUITY,     MIDDLE     AGES       75 

medicine;  its  surgical  section  is  celebrated  for  its  excellence  and  has  had 
great  influence  on  the  medical  science  of  both  Arabia  and  the  Occident.  — 
The  Byzantine  Empire  and  its  culture  eventually  succumbed  to  the  Turks, 
but  before  that  it  had  had  time  to  exercise  considerable  influence  upon  west- 
ern European  civilization,  especially  by  spreading  a  wider  knowledge  of 
classical  Greek  literature  and  thereby  paving  the  way  for  the  great  cultural 
regeneration  of  the  Renaissance. 

Western  culture 
The  western  Roman  Empire,  unlike  its  eastern  neighbour,  fell  a  prey  to 
hordes  of  migratory  peoples  and  was  dissolved  by  them  into  a  number  of 
minor  states  with  constantly  changing  frontiers  and  unsettled  internal  con- 
ditions. The  only  one  of  the  kingdoms  founded  under  these  circumstances 
which  attained  a  successful  development  was  that  of  the  Franks,  which  at 
one  time,  under  Charlemagne,  embraced  a  large  part  of  the  western  Roman 
territory  and  more  as  well.  After  his  death  his  empire  fell  to  pieces  and  out 
of  its  ruins  gradually  arose  the  national  states  of  western  Europe  which  still 
exist  today.  During  the  centuries  of  migration  both  material  prosperity  and 
intellectual  culture  in  the  western  Roman  countries  were  destroyed.  The  last 
remains  of  classical  culture  found  a  refuge  in  Ireland;  there  in  the  sixth  and 
seventh  centuries  were  read  and  copied  not  only  Latin,  but  Greek  authors, 
and  thence  culture  spread  to  England,  at  that  time  conquered  by  the  Anglo- 
Saxons.  In  Charlemagne's  time  these  two  countries  possessed  the  highest 
intellectual  development  and  it  was  from  there  that  the  Emperor  summoned 
learned  men,  with  whose  aid  he  raised  the  standard  of  culture  in  his  own 
country  and  created  what  was  called  a  "renaissance"  in  the  field  of  classical 
studies.  After  his  death,  however,  western  Europe  was  ravaged  by  a  fresh 
barbaric  invasion  by  the  Danes,  which  destroyed  culture  exactly  where  it 
had  hitherto  been  most  highly  developed  -^  in  Ireland,  England,  and  France. 
The  most  decadent  period  of  the  Middle  Ages  really  set  in  during  the  ninth 
and  tenth  centuries,  just  when  the  Arabic  culture  was  most  flourishing. 

The  one  power  that  kept  men  together  in  that  unhappy  period  was  the 
Catholic  Church;  it  gave  consolation  and  support  in  time  of  trial  and  was 
able  to  induce  minds  broken  down  by  misfortune  to  strive  after  ideals.  As  a 
unifying  cultural  force  it  came  to  take  the  place  of  what  the  Empire  had  once 
been,  and  so  Rome  became  once  more  the  capital  of  the  world.  But  while 
the  Church  thus  gave  to  culture  fresh  vitality,  it  at  the  same  time  set  rp  nar- 
row limitations  for  its  development;  it  demanded  absolute  subjection,  to 
the  extent  that  not  only  did  religious  sentiment  have  to  choose  the  paths 
the  Church  prescribed,  but  even  the  human  intelligence  had  to  adhere  to  its 
dogmas  and  doctrines  as  proved  truths.  These  had  been  drawn  up  by  the  ec- 
clesiastical Fathers  of  the  first  centuries  of  the  Christian  era,  whose  writings 
the  priests  and  monks  of  the  early  Middle  Ages  read  without  interpreting 


76  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

them  or  adding  anything  fresh  to  them.  Not  until  the  latter  half  of  the 
eleventh  century  did  the  first  independent  mediasval  theologian  appear,  in 
person  of  Anselm  of  Canterbury.  But  not  long  afterwards  a  more  liberal 
line  of  thought  began  to  find  expression,  which,  based  on  the  trifling  remains 
of  classical  literature  still  to  be  found  at  that  time  in  the  libraries  of  monas- 
teries and  churches,  sought  to  establish  rational  principles  of  thought.  Dur- 
ing the  twelfth  century  these  ideas,  expounded  by  the  Frenchman  Abelard 
and  his  pupils,  won  widespread  acceptance,  in  spite  of  strenuous  opposition 
on  the  part  of  the  Church,  and  received  further  stimulus  from  the  influence 
of  Arabian  science,  brought  over  partly  by  scholars  who  had  studied  in  Spain 
and  partly  through  the  crusaders'  contact  with  the  East  itself.  In  this  way 
the  countries  of  the  West  gained  their  knowledge  of  the  great  men  of  classical 
antiquity  — -  Plato  and  Aristotle,  Hippocrates  and  Galen,  as  well  as  of  their 
Arabian  commentators  and  successors. 

The  universities 
With  a  view  to  the  study  of  these  sources  of  knowledge  there  was  founded 
in  the  twelfth  century  a  form  of  educational  establishment  which  was  to 
become  of  fundamental  importance  for  the  scientific  development  of  the 
future  —  namely,  the  university.  Antiquity  had  nothing  equivalent  to  this 
kind  of  associations  of  teachers  and  pupils,  for  they  rested  on  an  ecclesias- 
tical foundation.  Charlemagne  had  already  founded  and  attached  to  the  met- 
ropolitan churches  cathedral  schools,  in  which  some  young  priest  gave 
instruction  in  theology,  music,  and  other  branches  of  learning  necessary  for 
men  of  the  Church.  As  the  number  of  pupils  at  these  schools  gradually  in- 
creased, it  became  necessary  to  employ  in  them  a  larger  and  larger  staff  of 
teachers,  magistri,  who,  in  order  to  protect  themselves  against  the  dangers 
and  insecurity  that  prevailed  everywhere  in  those  days,  formed  themselves 
into  corporations.  An  association  of  this  kind,  universitas  magistrormn,  under 
its  governor  (j-ector)  and  with  its  large  number  of  pupils  grouped  according 
to  nations,  represented  at  that  epoch  a  considerable  power,  which,  in  the 
course  of  violent  struggles  with  the  civic  and  ecclesiastical  authorities,  en- 
deavoured to  acquire  a  wide  measure  of  self-government  and  as  a  rule  actually 
succeeded  in  doing  so.  When  the  number  of  both  pupils  and  educational 
subjects  increased  still  further,  recourse  was  had  to  specialization  in  several 
faculties,  a  method  of  distribution  which  in  its  main  features  still  survives. 
Instruction  was  given  by  means  of  pulpit  lectures  —  a  method  based  on  the 
Church  sermon  and  similarly  adopted  with  a  view  to  instructing  large  num- 
bers of  pupils  at  one  and  the  same  time.  Further,  the  appearance  of  the 
university  system  involved  a  democratization  of  science,  of  which  classical 
antiquity  had  no  counterpart.  Whereas  the  finest  masters  of  antiquity  could 
probably  count  their  pupils  only  in  tens  or  hundreds,  the  great  universities 
of  the  Middle  Ages,  such  as  those  of  Paris,  Oxford,  Leipzig,  etc.,  had  thou- 


CLASSICAL     ANTIQUITY,     MIDDLE     AGES        77 

sands  and  even  tens  of  thousands  of  students  attending  at  one  time.  True, 
both  mass  education  and  self-government  had  their  dangers;  reactionary 
intellectual  movements,  equally  with  earnest  strivings  after  knowledge, 
might,  and  in  fact  did  at  times,  gain  the  mastery  at  the  medixval  universi- 
ties, just  as,  indeed,  later  liberal  and  reactionary  aims  alternately  dominated 
university  research  and  instruction. 

Scholastic  doctrine 
The  science  taught  in  mediaeval  schools  and  universities  —  scholastics,  as 
it  was  called  —  was  governed,  as  already  mentioned,  by  ecclesiastical  doc- 
trine. The  intellectual  movements  which  were  set  on  foot  independently 
thereof  and  which  were  consequently  persecuted  as  heretical  were  not 
founded,  as  they  generally  are  nowadays,  on  natural  science,  but  took 
their  stand  on  purely  speculative  ground.  The  question  which  had  been  de- 
bated ever  since  the  days  of  the  Church  Fathers  of  the  relation  of  reason  to 
faith,  or,  in  other  words,  the  right  of  the  individual  to  criticize  Church 
doctrine,  was  answered  in  the  first  place  by  the  universities  along  fairly 
liberal  lines,  in  spite  of  protests  from  the  Church,  but  in  the  thir- 
teenth century  a  religious  reaction  set  in,  evoked  by  the  struggle  against 
heresy  and  represented  by  the  orders  of  mendicant  friars  founded  for  the  ex- 
press purpose  of  combating  the  heretical  movement;  finally  these  orders 
succeeded  in  usurping  the  control  of  university  education,  at  least  of  theo- 
logical instruction,  which  was  thus  compelled  to  adapt  itself  to  ecclesiastico- 
political  aims.  This  occurred,  strangely  enough,  just  at  the  time  when  a 
closer  knowledge  of  Aristotle  began  to  be  disseminated  in  the  universities, 
based  on  the  Greek  original  and  not  merely  on  the  Arabic  translations  of 
his  writings.  But  the  High-Church  theologians  who  now  held  sway  in  the 
universities  soon  began  to  realize  what  a  splendid  ally  they  had  in  the  Aris- 
totelean  philosophy,  which  they  had  originally  mistrusted  as  mere  heathen 
delusion.  Aristotle's  conception  of  the  earth  as  the  centre  of  the  universe 
and  yet  as  the  home  of  all  imperfection  in  contrast  to  the  perfect  heaven 
might  very  well  be  adapted  to  the  Church's  doctrine  of  sin  and  salvation. 
His  strictly  formalistic  cosmic  system  and  mode  of  thought,  with  its  domi- 
nating intelligence  and  its  denial  of  any  material  causality,  was,  like  his 
conservative  and  authoritative  view  of  hum^n  life,  well  suited  to  form  a 
scientific  basis  for  the  hierarchical  aims  of  the  papal  power.  And  if  his  writ- 
ings did  not  agree  in  every  detail  with  the  revealed  Word,  the  inconsistencies 
made  apparent  thereby  could  be  explained  away  by  reference  to  the  author's 
paganism  and  ignorance  of  the  way  of  salvation.  Thus  was  created  in  the 
thirteenth  century,  mainly  on  the  initiative  of  the  greatest  thinker  of  the 
Catholic  Church,  the  canonized  Thomas  Aquinas,  the  curious  and,  in  its  way, 
fully  elaborated  system  of  thought  which  that  Church  has  ever  since  then, 
held  to  be  the  only  true  one.  According  to  this  system,  existence  is  divided 


78  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

into  three  "kingdoms,"  those  of  nature,  grace,  and  blessedness.  In  the  first 
dwell  all  men;  the  two  latter  are  attainable  only  by  members  of  the  Church. 
Knowledge  of  nature,  therefore,  even  the  heathen  may  acquire,  and  no 
heathen  has  possessed  deeper  insight  in  this  respect  than  Aristotle;  he  has 
explored  the  kingdom  of  nature  with  unexcelled  wisdom.  Consequently  the 
Christian  researcher  may  safely  rely  upon  his  explanation  of  nature  and  need 
not  engross  himself  in  the  subject  —  all  the  less  so  as  the  kingdoms  of  grace 
and  blessedness  are  open  to  him,  the  former  in  this  life,  the  latter  in  the 
eternal  hereafter.  In  these  circumstances  the  thinkers  of  the  Middle  Ages 
devoted  but  little  attention  to  natural-scientific  research;  they  contented 
themselves  with  the  writings  of  Aristotle,  which  were  closely  commented 
upon,  even  down  to  the  smallest  detail,  without  any  effort's  being  made  to 
develop  their  subject-matter  by  actual  investigation.  There  is  a  well-known 
story  of  how  the  learned  ecclesiastics  disputed  as  to  how  many  teeth  the 
horse  should  have  according  to  Aristotle,  instead  of  looking  into  the  mouth 
of  a  live  horse  to  see  for  themselves.  So  much  the  more  to  the  point  were  the 
Aristotelean  problems  regarding  the  relation  of  ideas  to  reality;  here  the 
dispute  waxed  hot  between  the  realists,  who  believed  that  ideas  existed 
before  things,  and  the  nominalists,  who  declared  that  ideas  exist  only  in 
things.  The  view  of  the  former  was  eventually  given  official  sanction,  but 
their  opponents  refused  to  give  in  and  so  played  their  part  in  undermining 
the  reputation  of  the  High-Church  philosophy  towards  the  end  of  the  Middle 
Ages. 

There  are  no  biological  writings  proper  dating  from  the  earlier  Middle 
Ages.  The  descriptive  work  on  animals,  the  Physiologus,  which  is  mentioned 
in  all  zoological  histories,  can  indeed  hardly  be  included  in  this  category;  it 
consists  of  a  collection  of  edifying  stories  relating  to  the  animal  world, 
intended  to  serve  as  examples  for  quotation  in  sermons  and  gathered  together 
from  all  quarters.  Probably  it  dates  from  later  antiquity,  which  produced 
many  such  collections,  as,  for  instance,  that  made  by  i^lianus  mentioned 
above.  The  Physiologus,  which  was  an  anonymous  treatise  revised  and  issued 
in  various  editions,  had  a  surprisingly  wide  circulation;  it  was  translated 
into  Ethiopian,  Icelandic,  and  most  languages  existing  between  these  bor- 
derlands of  Christian  culture.  It  abounds  in  fantastic  stories;  a  number  of 
them  have  survived  even  to  the  present  day. 

Even  in  the  Middle  Ages,  however,  there  existed  people  who  had  a 
broader  view  of  nature  and  a  deeper  interest  in  the  life  that  stirs  therein  than 
had  the  ecclesiastical  legend-writers.  Interesting  evidence  of  this  is  to  be 
found  in  a  treatise  dating  from  about  11 50  entitled  Physica,  written  by  the 
nun  HiLDEGARD,of  Bingen  on  the  Rhine.  The  book  contains  notes  on  animals, 
plants,  and  stones  and  on  the  benefit  that  man  can  derive  from  them.  It  is 
entirely  popular  in  style  and  without  any  pretension  to  learning,  and  for 


CLASSICAL     ANTIQUITY,     MIDDLE     AGES        79 

that  very  reason  it  is  of  interest  as  a  sample  of  the  ideas  about  natural  objects 
which  people  entertained  in  those  days. 

We  find  an  author  of  another  type  in  the  person  of  the  renowned  Emperor 
Frederick  II  of  Hohenstaufen.  As  is  well  known,  he  was  one  of  the  most 
remarkable  rulers  of  the  Middle  Ages,  Italian  in  his  upbringing,  half  oriental 
in  his  habits  and  mode  of  thinking.  In  his  south  Italian  kingdom  he  gathered 
round  him  learned  men  from  the  East  and  West.  He  had  Aristotle's  writings 
translated  from  the  Greek  into  Latin  and  founded  a  school  of  medicine  at 
Salerno,  where  for  the  first  time  since  Alexandrine  days  human  bodies  were 
dissected.  He  himself  wrote  a  book,  still  extant,  on  falconry,  a  sport  to  which 
princes  and  nobles  were  passionately  addicted.  Frederick's  treatise  is  far  more 
than  a  mere  dissertation  on  hunting;  in  a  lengthy  introduction  he  gives  an 
account  of  the  anatomy  of  birds,  in  which  he  not  only  displays  a  knowledge 
of  Aristotle's  anatomical  writings,  but  is  also  able  to  point  out  inaccuracies 
in  his  statements;  further,  he  describes  the  habits  of  various  birds,  the  move- 
ments of  migratory  birds,  etc.  Unfortunately  Frederick  lived  during  the 
period  of  ecclesiastical  reaction  in  the  thirteenth  century,  and  after  his  death 
his  Church  opponents  eradicated  most  of  the  cultural  progress  he  had 
achieved;  the  dissection  of  human  bodies  was  again  prohibited  and  physi- 
cians had  henceforth,  as  before,  to  rely  on  the  classical  authorities.  The 
translation  of  Aristotle  which  he  caused  the  learned  Michael  Scotus  to 
carry  out  was  perhaps  the  most  enduring  evidence  of  his  cultural  aims;  it 
was  on  this  work,  in  fact,  that  the  scientists  of  the  later  Middle  Ages  in 
general  based  their  learned  studies. 

Of  these  scientists  of  the  later  Middle  Ages  none  has  won  greater  fame 
or  survived  longer  in  the  popular  mind  than  Albert  von  Bollstadt,  known 
both  to  his  contemporaries  and  to  posterity  under  the  name  of  Albertus 
Magnus  (born  about  ixoo,  died  ii8o).  He  was  of  noble  family,  but  from  his 
earliest  youth  devoted  himself  to  learned  studies  and  afterwards  became  a 
member  of  the  Dominican  order,  one  of  the  then  newly-founded  orders  of 
mendicant  friars.  His  reputation  for  learning  spread  rapidly  throughout  the 
West;  he  was  at  one  time  a  professor  in  Paris,  being  afterwards  appointed  to 
a  school  in  Cologne  founded  by  the  Dominicans,  and  finally  becoming  Bishop 
of  Regensburg.  This  last  appointment,  however,  he  did  not  hold  for  long; 
he  returned  to  the  quiet  monastic  life  and  devoted  himself  entirely  to  science. 
He  believed  his  mission  in  life  was  to  edit  the  writings  of  Aristotle  —  known 
by  him  only  in  the  above-mentioned  Latin  translation  —  and  to  harmonize 
their  results  with  the  teaching  of  the  Church.  The  majority  of  his  many 
writings  deal  with  theology  and  philosophy,  though  natural  science  appears 
to  have  occupied  him  most  during  the  latter  part  of  his  life.  As  a  natural 
philosopher  he  is  principally  a  chemist.  He  was  the  first  to  produce  arsenic 
in  a  free  form  and  he  made  important  discoveries  in  regard  to  particular 


8o  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

combinations  of  metals;  he  also  introduced  into  chemical  terminology  the 
word  "affinity"  as  denoting  chemical  relationship.  As  a  biologist  he  follows 
Aristotle,  even  where  the  latter's  errors  have  been  corrected  by  other  ancient 
philosophers;  he  holds  that  the  arteries  contain  air,  that  the  brain  is  humid 
and  cold,  etc.  The  observations  which  he  himself  claims  to  have  made  are 
often  purely  fantastical,  but  they  also  sometimes  bear  witness  to  his  powers 
of  observation,  which  his  chemical  researches  prove  him  to  have  possessed 
in  a  high  degree.  His  greatest  service  undoubtedly  lies  in  his  having  directed 
the  world's  attention  to  Aristotle's  conception  of  nature  and  thereby  also 
indirectly  evoking  an  interest  in  nature  itself  —  an  interest  which  the  suc- 
ceeding centuries  were  able  to  cherish  and  widen. 

Contemporary  with  Albertus  and,  like  him,  a  Dominican  friar  was 
Thomas,  called  Cantimpratensis,  after  the  monastery  atCantimpre  in  France, 
where  he  worked.  His  home  was  at  Liege,  but  he  studied  at  Cologne  and 
finally  became  a  canon  in  the  afore-mentioned  monastery.  His  principal 
work,  De  naturis  rermn,  forms,  like  that  of  his  master,  a  compilation  of  the 
nature  theories  of  Aristotle  and  other  classical  authors,  with  a  wealth  of 
notes  on  animals,  both  real  and  imaginary.  More  than  Albertus,  Thomas  has 
a  penchant  for  weaving  into  his  accounts  of  animals  stories  with  a  moral 
point  to  them,  and  also,  on  the  whole,  he  enters  more  into  detail  and  is 
less  systematic  than  his  master. 

A  third  contemporary  of  these  two,  and  a  brother  monk,  was  Vincen- 
Tius  Bellovacensis,  who  was  likewise  named  after  his  monastery,  at  Beau- 
vais  in  France.  He  wrote  a  work  on  nature  entitled  Speculum  natura  — 
Nature's  Mirror.  This  work  is  compiled  from  various  sources:  Aristotle  in 
Latin  translation,  Pliny,  and  Avicenna,  as  well  as  the  Bible  and  the  Church 
Fathers.  Though  more  haphazard  and  less  lucidly  arranged  than  those  of 
his  colleagues  mentioned  above,  it  nevertheless  had  its  influence  on  the  age 
and  the  succeeding  centuries. 

It  is  not  worth  while  recounting  further  examples  of  this  kind  of  medi- 
aeval descriptions  of  nature  —  natural  research  it  can  scarcely  be  called.  Those 
already  cited  sufficiently  show  their  character,  that  of  a  compilation  of  the 
literary  material  of  past  ages  in  the  service  of  that  stock  conservative  theol- 
ogy which  dominated  science  during  these  centuries.  But  even  at  this  period 
there  arose  personalities  whose  ideas  presage  the  intellectual  liberation,  the 
foundations  of  which  were  laid  in  the  course  of  these  centuries  and  which 
was  destined  later  to  overcome  all  obstacles  during  the  Renaissance.  One 
such  man  was  Roger  Bacon  (born  1114,  died  12.94).  By  birth  an  Englishman, 
he  studied  at  Oxford  and  Paris  and  entered  the  Franciscan  order,  in  which 
he  soon  assumed  a  position  of  eminence.  His  liberal  views,  however,  gained 
for  him  bitter  enemies,  and  once  he  was  arrested  and  had  to  spend  years  in 
prison,  being  deprived  of  every  possibility  of  working  until  he  was  again 


CLASSICAL     ANTIQUITY,      MIDDLE     AGES        8l 

released.  No  small  cause  of  the  mistrust  he  inspired  was  his  interest  in  phys- 
ical and  chemical  experiments,  which  resulted  in  his  being  suspected  of 
witchcraft  and  necromancy.  Although  he  appears  to  have  been  a  clever 
experimentalist  with  a  wide  general  knowledge,  there  is  nevertheless  no 
record  of  any  epoch-making  scientific  discovery  that  can  be  attributed  to 
him.  His  greatness  lies  in  his  general  scientific  ideas.  He  set  himself  up  in 
determined  opposition  to  the  subtle  mode  of  thinking  of  the  schoolmen  and 
urged  that  science  should  rather  be  based  upon  experience  gained  through 
observing  natural  phenonema  —  that  is  to  say,  upon  a  method  harmonizing 
with  that  which  has  been  adopted  in  natural-scientific  research  in  more 
recent  times. 

Appearance  of  neiv  ideas 
This  intellectual  emancipation  from  the  hidebound  teachings  of  authority 
was  inspired,  however,  less  by  the  theoretical  contributions  of  Roger  Bacon 
and  any  of  his  successors  than  by  the  increasing  knowledge  of  nature  itself 
resulting  from  the  discovery  and  exploration  of  new  countries.  The  crusades 
had  already  made  some  contribution  towards  this  expansion,  but  still  greater 
was  the  influence  of  the  knowledge  of  far-distant  lands  acquired  through 
the  journeys  into  the  interior  of  Asia  undertaken  by  Marco  Polo  and  several 
of  his  contemporaries,  and  further  through  the  widely  extended  voyages  of 
the  Portuguese  in  the  fifteenth  century,  and  finally  through  the  discovery 
of  America.  As  a  result  of  all  these  geographical  discoveries  biology  also  ac- 
quired a  mass  of  fresh  material,  which  it  was  impossible  to  deal  with  merely 
by  studying  Aristotle;  it  forced  research  rather  to  seek  its  own  paths  and 
research-workers  to  rely  more  upon  themselves.  Biology  was  thus  compelled 
to  abandon  the  purely  literary  method  of  compilation  and  classification, 
which  had  been  the  most  characteristic  feature  of  medixval  science,  and 
instead  had  to  rely  for  its  progress  upon  working  out  its  own  observations 
and  developing  the  results  thereof.  But  before  it  could  do  this,  biology  had 
to  free  itself  from  the  restrictions  which  the  ecclesiastical  authority  of  the 
Middle  Ages  had  laid  upon  man's  intellectual  activities  in  general,  and  it 
thus  came  to  take  part  in  the  great  work  of  intellectual  liberation  whose 
various  phases  in  history  are  generally  summarized  under  the  name  of  the 
Renaissance.  The  progress  thus  achieved  in  the  knowledge  of  living  nature 
will  be  dealt  with  in  the  next  chapters. 


THE     HISTORY     OF 
BIOLOGY     DURING     THE     RENAISSANCE 

CHAPTER    XI 

THE     END     OF     MEDIEVAL     SCIENCE 

Revival  of  the  study  of  ancient  authors 

THE  UNIVERSAL  SCIENCE  of  the  Middle  Ages,  the  philosophy  of  the 
schoolmen,  was,  as  has  already  been  pointed  out,  a  system  of  thought 
complete  of  its  kind,  based  on  the  infallible  truth  of  the  Catholic 
Church  doctrine,  with  a  strictly  formalistic  conception  of  nature  founded  on 
Aristotle.  It  was  undoubtedly  of  service  in  its  own  time,  especially  in  that  it 
developed  the  formal  sides  of  thought,  but  it  lacked  the  possibilities  of  free 
expansion  and  it  was  thus  inevitable  that  it  should  finally  lose  itself  in  bar- 
ren subtleties.  The  intellectual  movement  which  history  calls  the  Renais- 
sance was  therefore  hailed  as  a  liberation  of  those  in  Europe  who  were  true 
seekers  after  knowledge.  This  movement  started  in  Italy,  where  the  connexion 
with  classical  antiquity  had  never  been  entirely  broken  and  where  the  system 
of  the  mediaeval  schoolmen  had  never  really  thrived;  in  the  Italian  colleges 
during  the  Middle  Ages  Latin,  rhetoric,  and  medicine  were  studied  rather 
than  philosophy.  The  mediaeval  Italian  felt  himself  to  be  the  rightful  heir  of 
the  old  Roman  people,  and  it  was  therefore  natural  that  the  cultural  revival 
in  that  country  should  take  the  form  of  a  close  study  of  ancient  literature; 
first  of  all  it  was  the  Roman  writers  of  antiquity  and  later  principally  the 
Greek  authors  unknown  to  the  Middle  Ages  who  here  attracted  the  interest 
which  in  other  countries  was  devoted  to  the  High-Church  scholasticism  and 
who  offered  in  exchange  an  entirely  new  and  freer  idea  of  existence  than 
mediaeval  philosophy  had  been  able  to  offer  —  an  opportunity  of  developing 
a  more  rich  and  many-sided  human  life  than  that  which  the  Church  of  the 
Middle  Ages  permitted.  It  was  also  in  this  sphere  —  that  of  the  general 
conception  of  life  —  that  the  great  cultural  revival  in  Italy  exercised  its 
greatest  influence,  an  influence  of  unique  depth  in  spheres  of  culture,  art  and 
literature,  politics  and  economy.  In  the  field  of  pure  science  this  revolution 
was,  at  least  in  the  beginning,  less  complete;  the  absolute  value  of  truth, 
which  the  schoolmen  ascribed  to  the  formulas  of  the  Church,  the  scientists 

8i 


RENAISSANCE  83 

of  the  Renaissance,  the  Humanists,  made  over  to  the  writers  of  antiquity. 
Aristotle  was  regarded  by  them  with,  if  possible,  still  greater  respect  than 
by  the  mediaeval  professors,  the  only  difference  being  that  now  one  had  ac- 
cess to  the  original  writings  of  the  master  and  could  interpret  them  without 
the  restriction  which  the  Church  had  formerly  laid  upon  them.  There  was 
no  possibility,  then,  of  any  new  conception  of  nature  and  its  phenomena 
developing  in  this  direction.  But  fortunately  there  were  other  points  of  de- 
parture for  this  development. 

The  fantastic  speculations  of  neo-Platonism  about  infinity,  and  the  al- 
chemistic  experimental  science  of  the  Arabs,  formed  the  bases  for  a  number 
of  attempts  at  an  explanation  of  nature  unfettered  by  Church  dogmas  and 
scholastic  systems,  while,  on  the  other  hand,  the  great  geographical  dis- 
coveries, as  well  as  the  newly-found  classical  authors,  offered  ideas  for  special 
investigations  in  the  sphere  of  biology  which  led  to  results  far  beyond  those 
of  either  Aristotle  or  Galen.  The  Renaissance  period,  therefore,  was  for  the 
science  of  biology  a  period  of  restless  seeking  and  collecting,  yielding  results 
which  the  succeeding  age  utilized  for  the  purpose  of  making  a  complete 
revaluation  of  the  whole  conception  of  nature  common  to  the  people  of  an- 
tiquity and  the  Middle  Ages.  It  would  seem  most  convenient,  then,  first  of 
all  to  give  a  brief  summary  of  the  new  philosophical  speculations  to  which 
the  Renaissance  gave  rise,  and  then  to  examine  in  detail  the  results  which 
were  achieved  during  that  period  by  the  science  of  biology. 


CHAPTER    XII 

NEW     COSMIC     IDEAS     AND     NEW     SCIENTIFIC     METHOD 

Opponents  of  scholasticism  during  the  Middle  Ages 

EVEN  DURING  THE  PERIOD  whcn  mediaeval  scholasticism  was  at  the  zen- 
ith of  its  power,  there  were  not  wanting  movements  hostile  to  it,  the 
representatives  of  which,  partly  by  way  of  logic,  like  the  so-called 
nominalists,  partly  by  exhortations  to  empirical  observations,  like  Roger 
Bacon,  previously  mentioned,  sought  to  undermine  its  thought-structure. 
These  movements,  besides,  very  often  had  points  of  contact  with  the  mysti- 
cism which  throughout  the  Middle  Ages  sought  in  the  sphere  of  a  holy  life 
to  induce  a  spirit  of  personal  sincerity  in  contrast  to  the  strictly  formal  piety 
taught  by  the  Church.  When,  later  on,  scholasticism  was  discredited,  owing 
to  the  reverence  of  humanism  for  antiquity,  the  field  was  left  open  for  a 
philosophy  in  which  all  the  above-mentioned  elements  —  theoretical  specu- 
lation, empirical  observations,  mysticism,  both  Christian  and  late  classical 
—  were  included  as  fundamental  components  in  a  fresh  conception  of  exist- 
ence, out  of  which  our  own  modern  ideas  of  nature  and  life  gradually 
developed. 

The  first  important  representative  of  this  fresh  view  of  nature  was  Nico- 
LAUS  CusANus.  He  took  his  name  from  the  village  of  Kues,  or  Cusa,  near 
Trier,  where  he  was  born  in  1401.  He  received  his  education  amongst  the 
"brothers  of  the  common  life,"  a  religious  community  having  a  pronounced 
mystical  tendency  —  an  education  which  had  a  decisive  influence  on  his 
entire  mode  of  thought.  He  had  a  brilliant  career  in  the  service  of  the  Church, 
into  which  he  shortly  afterwards  entered.  He  became  a  bishop,  and  later  on, 
as  a  cardinal,  he  was  one  of  the  most  trusted  men  of  the  papal  supremacy  at 
the  time.  As  such,  he  acted  constantly  in  the  interests  of  humanity  and  en- 
lightenment, ardently  opposing  the  sale  of  indulgences,  trials  of  witches, 
and  other  Church  superstitions.  He  died  in  Italy  in  1464. 

New  cosmic  ideas 
In  the  course  of  his  manifold  practical  activities,  however,  Cusanus  found 
time  for  research  work  which  places  him  in  the  first  rank  among  the  world's 
pioneer  spirits.  The  problems  he  deals  with  in  his  numerous  writings  are,  it 
is  true,  for  the  most  part  theological,  but  in  connexion  with  them  he  touches 
upon  the  problem  of  man's  place  in  existence,  and  it  is  here  that  he  makes  his 
most  important  contribution.  Curiously  interwoven  with  and  derived  from 

84 


RENAISSANCE  85 

his  mystical  speculations  appear  his  new  and  audacious  ideas  on  the  structure 
of  the  universe  and  man's  place  therein.  Basing  his  ideas  on  the  mystical  con- 
ception of  infinity  of  the  neo-Platonists,  he  asserts  that  it  is  impossible  for 
the  universe  to  have  a  spherical  form,  as  Aristotle  declares,  for  then  it  would 
always  be  possible  to  conceive  of  something  existing  outside  the  sphere,  in 
which  case  it  would  not  be  the  whole  universe.  Rather,  the  latter  is  infin- 
ite; it  exceeds  all  form  and  all  limitations.  Nor,  in  that  case,  can  the  globe 
be  the  centre  of  the  cosmos,  for  the  cosmos  has  no  centre,  but  man  on  the 
earth  imagines  he  is  in  the  centre  of  the  cosmos,  and  he  would  believe  the 
same  were  he  to  find  himself  on  the  sun  or  any  other  star.  Cusanus  thus 
maintained  the  relativity  of  mental  observation.  He  derives  this  knowledge 
of  his  from  what  he  calls  " docta  ignorantia  (wise  ignorance),"  by  which  he 
means  the  knowledge  that  all  contrasts  as  well  as  all  change  in  existence 
finally  become  absorbed  in  an  absolute  maximum,  infinite  and  unfathomable 
as  God  Himself.  It  was  this  '' docta  ignorantia"  that  Aristotle  lacked,  and 
therefore  he  believed  in  a  finite  world  and  absolute  mental  observations.  For 
the  rest,  Cusanus  employs  his  mode  of  thought  ^uite  as  much  in  theologi- 
cal sophistry,  as,  for  instance,  touching  the  true  nature  of  the  Trinity;  but 
while  these  subtleties  are  now  long  forgotten,  through  his  ideas  of  nature 
he  takes  his  place  as  one  of  the  pioneer  thinkers  of  the  beginning  of  the  new 
era,  half  medieval  mystic,  half  modern  natural  philosopher.  His  bold  ideas 
seem  otherwise  to  have  attracted  but  little  attention  outside  learned  circles; 
it  was  not  realized  how  revolutionary  they  were,  all  the  more  so  as  he  did 
not  concern  himself  with  the  details  of  our  solar  system;  consequently  he 
did  not  attack  the  theory  of  the  earth  as  the  centre  of  the  sun's  orbit.  His 
high  position  in  the  Church  undoubtedly  saved  him  from  such  persecution 
as  afterwards  befell  many  of  those  who  deduced  the  inevitable  consequences 
of  his  theories. 

If,  then,  Cusanus's  ideas  operated  in  silence,  the  views  which  about  a 
hundred  years  later  were  expressed  by  Copernicus  attracted  all  the  more  at- 
tention. Born  in  1473  at  Thorn  in  Poland,  Nicolaus  Copernicus  received  his 
education  at  the  Italian  university  of  Bologna  and  finally  became  dean  in 
his  own  native  city,  where  he  died  in  1543.  Even  in  his  youth  he  was  a 
keen  student  of  mathematics  and  astronomy  and  already  at  that  early  age 
began  his  life's  work,  to  think  out  a  new  cosmic  system  which,  more  easily 
than  the  Aristotelean-Ptolemaic,  could  be  reconciled  with  the  observations 
made  in  his  own  time  upon  the  movements  of  the  heavenly  bodies.  Their 
irregularities  could  in  fact  never  be  satisfactorily  explained  on  the  basis  of 
the  old  solar  system.  Copernicus  discovered  a  better  means  of  accounting  for 
the  irregularities  by  letting  the  sun,  in  contrast  to  the  direct  evidence  of  the 
senses,  represent  the  centre  of  the  cosmic  system,  and  the  earth  assume  the 
place  among  the  wandering  planets  which  the  sun  held  in  the  old  system. 


86  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

Otherwise  Copernicus  retained  that  system  practically  unaltered;  he  thus 
made  the  sun  the  immovable  centre  of  the  universe,  the  planets  moving  in 
circles  round  it  and  the  w^hole  surrounded  by  the  sphere  of  fixed  stars,  such 
as  the  ancients  imagined  it.  In  reality,  then,  his  theory  was  less  subver- 
sive than  Cusanus's  and,  as  a  matter  of  fact,  not  without  precedents  in  an- 
tiquity; but  still  it  attracted  far  more  attention,  because  it  was  entirely  at 
variance  with  what  everyone  was  accustomed  to  see  happening  daily  before 
his  very  eyes.  Copernicus  spent  decades  working  out  his  theory,  and  not 
until  the  year  before  his  death  did  he  dare  to  publish  a  book  on  it.  It  aroused 
fierce  opposition,  particularly  on  religious  grounds;  the  reformers  as  well  as 
the  Jesuits  condemned  its  teachings,  while  its  scientific  influence  was  at  first 
but  small,  all  the  more  so  as  the  proofs  he  offered  of  the  truth  of  his  new 
theory  were  really  rather  weak.  Shortly  after  his  death,  however,  a  thinker 
was  born  who  was  able  to  reconcile  Copernicus's  ideas  with  those  of  Cusanus 
and  thereby  founded  a  theory  of  the  universe  which  in  its  essentials  still  holds 
good  today. 

Giordano  Bruno  wa^born  at  Nola  in  south  Italy  in  1548.  As  a  young 
man  he  entered  a  monastery,  but  he  was  far  from  contented  with  the  life 
there,  was  soon  suspected  of  heresy,  and  saved  himself  by  flight.  After  this 
he  never  found  a  permanent  retreat;  excommunicated  and  persecuted  within 
the  Catholic  world,  he  nevertheless  found  no  consolation  in  the  Protestant 
countries  which  he  visited.  Upon  returning  to  Italy  he  became  a  victim  of 
the  Inquisition  and  after  many  years'  imprisonment  was  condemned  as  a 
heretic  and  burnt  at  the  stake  in  1600. 

In  numerous  lectures,  disputations,  and  published  works  he  preached 
in  the  countries  he  visited  the  new  doctrine  which  cost  him  his  life.  In  this 
he  takes  as  a  starting-point  Cusanus's  speculations  on  infinity,  Lucretius' 
atomic  theory,  and  Copernicus's  solar  system.  On  the  ideas  which  he  found 
in  these  various  conceptions  he  built  still  further  with  an  originality  which 
ranks  him  amongst  the  greatest  thinkers  of  all  time,  in  spite  of  the  fantasy 
and  mysticism  with  which  he,  like  the  other  philosophers  of  the  Renaissance, 
burdens  his  speculations.  In  agreement  with  Cusanus,  but  still  more  emphati- 
cally, Bruno  maintains  the  subjectivity  of  mental  observation;  when  a  man 
moves,  the  horizon  goes  with  him,  from  which  we  must  conclude  that  there 
exists  no  absolute  universal  centre.  On  the  contrary,  both  reason  and  faith 
demand  an  infinite  world,  infinite  as  God  Himself.  And,  like  mental  impres- 
sions, place,  movement,  and  time  are  relative  and  dependent  upon  the  po- 
sition in  space  from  which  they  are  observed.  —  Nor  can  the  assertion  main- 
tained by  Aristotle  as  to  absolutely  heavy  and  absolutely  light  bodies  be 
true;  this  being  so,  there  is  no  meaning  whatever  in  the  old  belief  that  planets 
and  fixed  stars  are  lodged  in  spheres  round  the  earth;  on  the  contrary,  they 
move  in  their  orbits  in  space  freely  and  by  internal  force.  And  like  his  cosmic 


RENAISSANCE  87 

system  Aristotle's  theory  of  matter  as  potentiality  in  contrast  to  form 
emanating  from  the  divine  intelligence  is,  in  Bruno's  opinion,  also  incorrect; 
matter  is  rather  the  essential  in  every  thing,  the  "divine  essence"  out  of  which 
all  is  evolved.  In  Bruno's  view,  Lucretius'  atomic  theory  and  the  neo- 
Platonic  ideas  of  the  unity  of  matter  are  combined  into  a  vision  of  the  world 
at  the  same  time  mysteriously  vague  and  grandly  fantastic,  as  a  single  whole, 
one  with  God  and  one  with  itself,  a  combination  of  all  the  contrasts  which 
human  thought  has  speculated  upon.  It  would  take  too  long  to  discuss  these 
ideas  in  detail,  all  the  more  so  as  Bruno,  strictly  speaking,  does  not  touch 
upon  any  purely  biological  problems.  His  importance  from  the  point  of  view 
of  world  history  lies  in  the  fact  that  he  for  the  first  time  worked  out,  or 
perhaps  rather  guessed,  the  cosmic  theory  which  has  since  come  to  be  held 
in  modern  natural  research.  His  influence  has  been  great  and  has  been  widely 
felt  through  all  the  ages. 

While,  then,  in  the  cosmological  sphere  Bruno  was  the  pioneer  of  the 
new  natural  science,  in  a  corresponding  manner  Francis  Bacon  (1561-1616) 
paved  the  way  in  the  sphere  of  pure  laws  of  thought.  His  life's  activities 
and  end  were  in  all  respects  different  from  Bruno's.  One  thing,  however, 
they  had  in  common:  restlessness,  that  diversified  seeking  after  knowledge 
which  was  so  characteristic  of  the  Renaissance.  Born  in  England  in  a  refined 
home.  Bacon  received  a  thorough  education,  but  lost  his  father  at  an  early 
age  and  was  not  very  successful  in  his  official  career,  in  spite  of  his  brilliant 
gifts  and  his  ruthless  ambition.  It  was  not  until  later  on  in  life  that  he  re- 
ceived higher  appointments  and  eventually  became  Lord  Chancellor  in  the 
reign  of  James  I,  whom  he  knew  how  to  flatter.  But  he  was  shortly  after- 
wards dismissed  and  condemned  to  pay  a  fine  for  bribery  and  corruption 
when  in  office,  and  his  last  five  years  he  spent  in  retirement. 

Bacon's  reform  of  science 
Even  in  his  early  years  Bacon  had  planned  to  reform  all  human  knowledge 
completely.  This  reform  was  to  have  been  carried  out  in  a  work  of  mighty 
proportions  entitled  Instauratio  magna.  Bacon  during  his  restless  life  found  no 
time  to  carry  out  even  approximately  the  great  task  he  had  set  himself;  the 
"great  reform"  remained  but  a  fragment,  of  which  the  first  two,  and  the 
best-constructed,  sections  are  called  The  Advancement  of  Learning  and  The  New 
Method.  The  latter  section  is  that  on  which  Bacon's  fame  principally  rests; 
its  title  is  chosen  as  a  direct  challenge  to  Aristotle,  for  whose  theory  of 
method,  Organum,  Bacon  wished  to  substitute  his  own  new  method.  Bacon's 
Novum  Organum  takes  the  form  of  a  collection  of  aphorisms,  intended  to 
illustrate  from  various  points  of  view  the  inaccuracy  of  the  traditional 
scholastic  mode  of  thought  and  the  correctness  of  the  new  theory  of  thought, 
which  it  was  necessary  to  set  in  its  place.  The  defects  of  the  Aristotelean 
philosophy  are  criticized  in  a  number  of  strongly  worded  and  merciless 


88  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

sentences;  under  its  guidance  human  thought  has  been  led  into  delusions, 
which  are  classified  under  four  different  categories  denoted  by  the  names 
"idols  of  the  tribe,"  "of  the  cave,"  "of  the  market-place,"  and  "of  the 
theatre."  By  idols  of  the  tribe  are  meant  those  fallacies  which  are  incident 
to  human  nature,  man's  tendency  to  interpret  the  phenomena  of  nature  ac- 
cording to  human  preconceptions.  The  idols  of  the  cave  are  man's  individual 
tendency  to  judge  according  to  his  own  person  or  ego;  it  is  as  if  a  man  sat  in 
a  cave  and  from  there  saw  things  in  a  one-sided  light.  The  idols  of  the  mar- 
ket-place are  fallacies  which  arise  out  of  human  community-life,  especially 
errors  arising  from  the  influence  exercised  over  the  mind  by  mere  words, 
the  confusing  influence  of  traditional  nomenclature  upon  the  idea  of  things. 
Finally,  the  idols  of  the  theatre  are  those  which  are  induced  by  the  power  of 
tradition  and  result  from  received  systems  of  philosophy  and  the  tendency 
of  their  theory  to  captivate  the  senses.  The  criticism  which  in  further  de- 
veloping these  principles  he  directs  against  the  philosophy  of  his  time  is  in 
many  cases  extraordinarily  sharp  and  holds  good  for  every  age.  Thus  he 
utters  insistent  warnings  against  the  common  tendency  to  regard  natural 
phenomena  as  simple  mechanical  constructions,  like  those  which  man  him- 
self puts  together  and  takes  to  pieces.  Nature  is,  on  the  contrary,  extremely 
complicated  and  one  must  be.  careful  how  one  ascribes  to  its  course  of  events 
the  same  order  and  regularity  which  man  loves  to  ordain  for  himself.  From 
this  error  arise  fallacies  such  as  the  idea  that  the  orbits  of  the  heavenly 
bodies  must  necessarily  be  circular,  just  because  the  circle  is  the  most  regular 
figure.  In  contrast  to  the  artificial  and  false  idea  of  nature  which  the  old 
philosophy  creates  by  means  of  such  modes  of  thought.  Bacon  sets  up  the 
true  knowledge  of  nature,  which  is  acquired  by  observation  and  experiment. 
Man  overcomes  nature  by  obeying  her  laws  and  learns  to  understand  her  by 
putting  proper  questions  to  her.  Thus  one  arrives  at  the  true  scientific 
method,  that  which  by  careful  observation  of  the  peculiarities  of  existence 
and  by  a  classification  of  them  acquires  knowledge  of  the  general  laws  of 
nature.  Bacon  attaches  the  very  highest  hopes  to  the  value  of  the  knowledge 
of  nature  which  he  thus  intended  to  create;  throughout  his  long  life  he  never 
ceased  to  contemplate  with  passionate  enthusiasm  the  thought  of  the  ex- 
traordinary life-values  which  awaited  the  human  spirit  in  an  enhanced 
knowledge  of  the  true  essence  of  nature.  Such  knowledge  could  be  attained 
by  means  of  a  schematic  procedure  laid  down  once  and  for  all,  applicable 
equally  to  high  and  low  in  the  realm  of  thought.  To  this  art  of  deduction, 
however,  based  on  a  consideration  of  the  temporal  sequence  of  phenomena, 
their  presence  and  absence,  and  their  numerical  relations.  Bacon  gave  a  value 
which  it  did  not  possess,  and  besides  applied  it  in  a  manner  which  led  to 
sheer  absurdities.  His  knowledge  of  nature,  moreover,  was  limited  and  by 
no  means  unprejudiced  —  he  was,  for  instance,  in  opposition  to  Copernicus  — 


RENAISSANCE  89 

and  the  experiments  he  arranged  were  primitive.  Further,  he  was  no  mathe- 
matician and  he  therefore  was  unable  to  employ  the  deductive  reasoning 
inherent  in  that  science.  Nevertheless  Bacon  has  done  an  everlasting  service 
to  the  development  of  natural  science,  primarily  through  his  activities  as  a 
critic.  It  has  already  been  mentioned  how  during  the  Renaissance  ancient 
culture  in  general  and  in  the  realm  of  science,  primarily  Aristotle,  was  treated 
with  unbounded  respect.  This  uncritical  and  slavish  attitude,  which  threat- 
ened to  ruin  all  chances  of  further  progress,  Bacon  combats  with  all  the 
severity  of  which  he  is  capable;  he  throws  overboard  all  respect  for  antiquity, 
whose  culture  he  considers  to  have  led  only  to  intellectual  decay  and  vain 
disputes.  He  maintains  that  the  peoples  of  antiquity  were  really  children  in 
comparison  with  his  own  age,  which  possessed  far  more  of  that  experience 
which  to  him  was  the  one  foundation  of  knowledge.  And  in  this  insistence 
upon  experience  as  the  sole  source  of  knowledge  lies  his  other  great  service 
to  the  development  of  science  and  in  particular  to  that  of  natural  research. 
He  realized  more  clearly  than  any  of  his  contemporaries  the  necessity  of 
extending  the  knowledge  of  nature  by  accumulating  the  results  of  obser- 
vations of  its  objects  and  of  experiments  carried  out  with  its  powerful  forces, 
and  though  he  himself  could  give  expression  to  his  ideas  only  in  clumsy 
efforts,  nevertheless  these  ideas,  through  their  intrinsic  theoretical  truth, 
exercised  great  influence  in  his  day  and  have  done  so  down  to  the  most  recent 
times.  Even  in  our  own  day  one  of  the  pioneers  of  research  into  the  problem 
of  heredity,  Johannsen,  has  openly  acknowledged  his  debt  to  Bacon's 
Organum  as  the  source  from  which  he  obtained  a  clearer  idea  as  to  the  objects 
and  means  of  natural  research.  And  it  is  certainly  no  mere  accident  that  the 
country  which  gave  Bacon  birth  should  have  led  the  way  in  the  great  pioneer 
work  that  has  been  done  in  promoting  the  development  of  biology. 

What  Bacon  thus  theoretically  conceived  and  insisted  upon  was  brought 
to  practical  realization  independently  of  him  by  Galileo,  the  creator  of  modern 
physics  and  astronomy,  and  hence  also  the  founder  of  the  whole  of  modern 
natural  research  and  its  conception  of  natural  phenomena,  so  fundamentally 
removed  from  Aristoteleanism. 

Galileo  Galilei  was  born  in  1564  at  Pisa,  where  his  father  held  a  good 
post.  At  an  early  age  he  displayed  mathematical  and  mechanical  gifts,  studied 
at  Pisa,  first  of  all  medicine  and  later  mathematics,  and  when  still  quite 
young  was  made  professor  of  that  science,  first  at  Pisa  and  then  at  Padua. 
In  the  latter  city  he  worked  as  a  teacher  for  eighteen  years  with  brilliant 
success;  finally  the  university  could  find  no  hall  large  enough  to  seat  all  his 
audience.  And  the  results  of  his  scientific  work  were  still  more  brilliant; 
especially  after  he  had  constructed  a  telescope  and  with  it  had  begun  to  study 
the  heavenly  bodies,  his  astronomical  discoveries  followed  one  another  in 
rapid  succession:  the  globular  form  of  the  moon,  the  satellites  of  the  planet 


90  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

Jupiter,  the  sun-spots, the  phases  of  Venus  and  Mercury.  But  it  was  impossi- 
ble to  reconcile  all  these  new  facts  with  the  ancient  Aristotelean-Ptolemaic 
cosmic  theory  and  so  Galileo  early  associated  himself  with  the  conception 
of  the  universe  as  enunciated  by  Copernicus  and  Bruno.  His  great  fame  pro- 
cured for  him  the  personally  brilliant  appointment  of  Astronomer  Royal  to 
the  Medicean  Grand  Duke  at  Florence,  with  a  high  salary  and  no  official 
duties.  But  in  leaving  the  service  of  the  powerful  Venetian  Republic  he  came 
under  the  influence  of  the  power  of  the  Roman  Church,  a  circumstance  all 
the  more  dangerous  to  him  as  his  new  discoveries  excited  the  bitter  hostility 
of  the  very  parties  which  had  condemned  Bruno;  moreover,  he  was  himself  a 
violent  controversialist,  who  never  spared  his  enemies.  His  end  is  a  matter 
of  common  knowledge  —  how  he  was  arraigned  before  the  Inquisition  on 
account  of  a  "dialogue"  on  the  solar  system  and  under  threat  of  death  was 
compelled  to  make  a  public  recantation  of  his  "Copernican  error,"  after 
which  he  lived  in  strict  seclusion  until  his  death,  in  1641. 

Galileo' s  theory 
Galileo's  fundamental  importance  as  a  natural  philosopher  is  not  based 
merely  upon  his  discoveries,  epoch-making  as  they  are;  he  has  contributed 
in  a  still  higher  degree  towards  scientific  progress  through  the  principles 
which  he  laid  down  and  which  have  become  the  basis  of  modern  natural 
philosophy.  As  we  know,  Aristotle  based  his  cosmic  theory  upon  the  con- 
trast between  form  and  matter,  where  form  is  assumed  to  be  a  realization  of 
matter's  powers  of  development;  the  higher  the  degree  of  its  realization,  the 
more  perfect  the  form.  Therefore  the  heavenly  bodies,  with  their  regular 
motions,  are  more  form-perfect  than  the  earth,  with  its  many  irregularities, 
while  beyond  the  heavenly  spheres  is  the  world  of  pure  form,  God,  the  origin 
of  all  forms,  the  cause  of  all  that  happens  in  the  universe.  Galileo  at  once 
came  into  conflict  with  this  system  through  his  astronomical  discoveries; 
according  to  Aristotle,  the  firmament,  as  existing  nearest  to  the  immutable 
divine  intelligence,  was  itself  immutably  regular  in  its  motions.  Galileo 
discovered  a  great  many  irregularities;  the  sun-spots,  Jupiter's  moons,  and  all 
else  that  the  newly-invented  telescope  brought  into  the  light  of  day  proved 
the  firmament  was  not  such  a  place  of  perfection  and  regularity  as  had  been 
supposed.  On  the  other  hand,  the  phenomena  of  motion  in  bodies  here  upon 
earth  showed  an  obedience  to  law  of  which  the  ancients  had  no  notion. 
Galileo  experimented  with  the  free  f^ll  of  bodies,  with  pendulous  motions, 
and  with  the  motions  of  bodies  along  an  inclined  plane,  and  discovered  in  all 
these  phenomena  ratios  between  weights,  lengths  of  time,  and  rapidity  of 
motion  so  mathematically  regular  that  he  could  express  them  in  the  form  of 
theorems  as  capable  of  demonstration  as  the  old  geometrical  propositions 
formulated  by  Euclid.  But  it  was  just  through  this  combination  of  natural- 
scientific  experiment  and  mathematical  calculation  that,  as  he  himself  says, 


RENAISSANCE-  91 

he  created  a  new  science.  Instead  of  Aristotle's  guiding  reason,  which  was 
in  reality  nothing  but  an  expression  for  the  speculating  philosopher's  own 
inferences,  deducted  for  the  most  part  from  purely  human-cultural  hypotheses 
Galileo  brings  the  phenomena  of  motion  on  the  earth  under  one  common 
law,  which  operates  out  of  mathematical  necessity  and  whose  manifestations 
can  under  given  conditions  be  calculated  in  advance,  just  as  at  an  earlier 
epoch  it  had  been  possible  to  calculate  the  regular  path  of  the  "divine" 
heavenly  bodies.  Galileo  was,  it  is  true,  unable  to  find  one  common  law 
governing  the  motions  of  terrestrial  objects  and  the  heavenly  bodies  —  that 
was  for  Newton  to  find  in  his  law  of  gravitation  —  but  Galileo  laid  down 
the  principle  governing  the  natural-scientific  treatment  of  terrestrial  phe- 
nomena, a  principle  which  he  expressed  in  the  words:  "To  measure  what  can 
be  measured  and  to  make  measurable  what  cannot  be  measured."  He  seeks  a 
mechanical  reason  for  everything  that  happens  —  a  force  that  sets  things 
in  motion.  To  refer  to  God  as  the  cause  of  natural  phenomena  serves  no  pur- 
pose, in  his  opinion,  for  one  can  attribute  anything  whatever  to  the  will  of 
God,  since  no  necessity  underlies  it.  According  to  Galileo,  natural  science 
should  compare  material  things  merely  with  one  another,  not  with  super- 
natural things,  and  at  the  same  time  it  has  to  be  remembered  that  nature  is 
itself  a  miracle,  although  its  phenomena  have  a  natural  explanation.  In 
actual  fact,  gravity  is  merely  a  word  for  something  which  we  do  not  know; 
we  cannot  tell  what  it  is  that  attracts  stones  to  the  earth.  Galileo  sees  clearly 
that  it  is  useless  to  try  to  find  out  what  the  forces  of  nature  are;  the  scientist 
can  only  discover  how  they  operate. 

Galileo' s  victory  over  Aristoteleanism 
Such  a  complete  revolution  of  the  aims  and  methods  of  natural  science  as 
that  carried  out  by  Galileo  could  not  of  course  penetrate  men's  minds  all 
at  once.  He  himself  fell  a  victim  not  only  to  the  Church's  intolerance,  but 
also  to  the  superstitious  respect  in  which  the  Renaissance  held  the  culture 
of  antiquity  and  its  chief  scientific  authority,  Aristotle.  Actually  another 
century  was  to  pass  before  Aristoteleanism  in  every  field  of  human  knowledge 
was  successfully  eradicated  from  the  ideas  underlying  the  science  of  the  pres- 
ent day.  In  order  to  rid  natural  science  of  Aristotelean  fallacies  it  was,  in 
fact,  necessary  to  destroy  Aristotle's  entire  thought-system,  and  this  was  first 
done  during  the  seventeenth  century  by  the  great  systematic  thinkers  of  that 
period,  Descartes,  Spinoza,  and  Leibniz,  who  will  be  discussed  later  on.  We 
shall  now  proceed  to  a  survey  of  what  the  Renaissance  period  achieved  in 
the  way  of  pure  biological  research,  not  only  in  the  purely  descriptive  sphere, 
but  in  the  more  speculative  field  as  well. 


CHAPTER    XIII 

DESCRIPTIVE     BIOLOGICAL     RESEARCH     DURING     THE     RENAISSANCE 

i'.    Zoography 

THE  EARLIEST  ACTIVITIES  of  Renaissancc  research  in  the  biological  field 
were,  in  accordance  with  the  general  tendency  of  that  period,  purely 
philological.  New  editions  of  Aristotle,  Hippocrates,  Galen,  and  other 
natural  philosophers  of  antiquity  were  published,  their  language  commented 
upon,  and  attempts  made  to  explain  their  contents.  However,  the  actual 
historical  course  of  events  compelled  the  learned  world  to  carry  out  inde- 
pendent work  in  regard  to  natural  objects  as  well.  Even  the  fauna  and  flora 
of  central  Europe  were  very  imperfectly  known  to  the  ancient  philosophers, 
and  the  information  regarding  many  of  them  needed  supplementing  with 
innumerable  facts,  which  entailed  much  independent  research  work.  And 
this  became  all  the  more  necessary  when  the  great  geographical  discoveries 
acquainted  mankind  with  the  perfectly  new  and  exceptionally  rich  nature 
of  the  tropics.  All  these  circumstances  combined  to  produce  an  abundant 
literature  of  a  purely  descriptive  kind,  both  zoological  and  botanical,  which, 
thanks  to  the  art  of  book-printing,  received  such  widespread  publication  as 
the  biological  works  of  antiquity  could  never  hope  for.  Further,  the  methods 
of  reproducing  pictures,  discovered  in  connexion  with  book-printing  — 
woodcuts  and  copperplate  engraving  —  now  for  the  first  time  made  it  pos- 
sible to  utilize  the  illustration  in  the  service  of  scientific  literature  —  a 
means  of  extending  human  knowledge  the  importance  of  which  can  be  ap- 
preciated only  if  we  consider  what  it  means  in  our  own  day  and  what  would 
be  the  consequence  if  modern  science  were  to  be  deprived  of  it.  A  review  of 
some  of  the  more  eminent  representatives  of  this  branch  of  biological  science 
during  the  Renaissance  will  give  us  some  idea  of  the  objects  they  aimed  at 
and  the  respects  in  which  they  advanced  this  science.  For  this  purpose  we 
shall  for  the  moment  discuss  only  the  results  of  zoological  research  during 
this  period;  the  botanical  results  may  perhaps  more  suitably  be  left  to  a 
subsequent  chapter  dealing  with  the  history  of  biological  classification. 

Edward  Wotton  (i49z-i555)  essentially  represents  the  point  of  view 
of  mediaeval  science.  The  son  of  a  college  porter  in  the  University  of  Oxford, 
he  studied  medicine  in  his  native  city  and  became  a  physician  with  a  wide 
and  distinguished  practice.  His  interest  in  nature  he  recorded  in  a  lengthy 

91 


RENAISSANCE  93 

work  entitled  De  differentiis  anhnalium,  on  which  he  worked  for  several 
decades.  In  this  book  he  shows  himself  a  faithful  follower  of  Aristotle, 
whom  he  imitates  both  in  his  method  of  classification  and  in  the  field  of 
anatomy.  His  division  of  the  animal  kingdom  is  entirely  Aristotelean:  san- 
guineous animals  and  non-sanguineous,  viviparous  and  oviparous  quadru- 
peds, and  so  on.  Nevertheless  he  criticizes  his  classical  predecessors  to  the 
extent  that  he  does  not  accept  without  reservation  the  masses  of  fabulous 
animals  which  they  invent,  but  on  the  other  hand  he  has  nothing  to  say 
about  the  many  new  animal  forms  which  the  explorers  in  his  own  century 
brought  home  with  them  and  which  otherwise  excited  general  interest 
among  his  contemporaries,  both  educated  and  uneducated.  Yet  he  contributes 
much  information  regarding  the  medicines  which  may  be  extracted  from  the 
various  animal  forms.  As  a  profound  exponent  of  Aristotle  and  representa- 
tive of  his  ideas,  Wotton  came  to  exercise  no  small  influence  on  his  age, 
particularly  upon  the  man  who  eventually  became  the  finest  zoological 
representative  of  the  Renaissance,  Gesner. 

KoNRAD  Gesner  was  born  at  Zurich  in  15 16.  His  father  was  a  Protestant 
artisan,  who  fell  in  1531  at  the  famous  battle  of  Kappel,  in  which  the  civic 
guard  of  Zurich,  under  the  reformer  Zwingli,  were  defeated  by  the  Catholics. 
Young  Konrad,  who  had  previously  been  sent  to  a  good  school,  was  now 
unprotected,  but  his  great  reputation  for  zeal  and  energy  brought  him  friends, 
who  sent  him  to  study  at  their  expense  in  Basel,  Paris,  and  Montpellier.  At 
these  places  he  studied  such  different  subjects  as  classical  and  oriental  lan- 
guages, natural  science,  and  medicine,  and  in  general  acquired  in  an  unparal- 
leled degree  that  many-sidedness  in  learning  which  during  the  Renaissance 
was  particularly  appreciated  and  admired.  After  having  been  for  some  time 
professor  of  Greek  in  Lausanne,  he  was  appointed  first  town-physician  at 
Zurich,  which  was  at  that  time  a  moderately  salaried  post.  There  he  died  of 
a  plague  that  ravaged  the  town  in  1665  —  that  is,  when  he  was  still  under 
fifty.  Of  a  quiet  and  unambitious  nature,  he  had  a  constant  struggle  against 
financial  difficulties,  which  compelled  him  to  wear  out  his  strength  in  ill- 
paid  hack-work.  His  energy  was  marvellous.  He  published  and  made  com- 
mentaries on  classical  authors;  he  compiled  dictionaries,  wrote  a  lexicon  of 
classical  literature,  which  must  have  been  a  very  fine  work  for  his  period, 
and  was  the  author  of  works  on  popular  medicine.  Besides  all  this  he  found 
time  for  extensive  journeys  both  for  scientific  purposes  and  for  pleasure  — 
he  was  one  of  the  very  first  to  be  interested  in  mountain-climbing,  and  he 
had  a  keen  feeling  for  Alpine  beauty  —  and  finally  he  had  the  time  and  lei- 
sure to  carry  out  one  of  the  greatest  biological  works  the  world  has  seen. 

Gesner's  Historia  animalium  comprises  four  immense  folio  volumes  of 
about  3,500  pages  in  all.  The  animals  are  arranged  according  to  the  principles 
of  Aristotle;  the  first  part  includes  viviparous  and  oviparous  quadrupeds,  the 


94  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

second  part  birds,  the  third  fishes,  the  fourth,  which  was  published  after  the 
author's  death,  reptiles  and  insects.  In  each  part  he  then  describes  one  animal 
after  the  other  on  the  lines  of  Pliny,  but  with  far  greater  expert  knowledge, 
based  oa  his  own  experience  and  criticism  of  his  source  of  information. 
Animals  are  arranged  alphabetically  "in  order  to  facilitate  the  use  of  the 
work,"  though  allied  forms  are  grouped  under  one  heading;  all  oxen  under 
Bos,  all  apes  under  Sitnia,  etc.  Each  animal  form  is  discussed  under  eight  sec- 
tions, marked  with  letters  of  the  alphabet  and  comprising  (a)  the  name  of 
the  animal  in  different  languages;  (b)  its  habitat  and  origin  and  a  description 
of  its  external  and  internal  parts;  (c)  "the  natural  function  of  the  body"; 
(d)the  qualities  of  the  soul ;(e)  the  animal's  use  to  man  in  general ;(f) its  util- 
ity as  an  article  of  food;  (g)  its  utility  for  medical  purposes;  and  (h)  poetical 
and  philosophical  speculations  about  the  animal,  anecdotes  and  resemblances 
to  be  found  in  different  authors.  Thus  the  reader  is  able  to  find  what  he  wants, 
whichever  part  of  the  work  he  turns  to.  This  clearly  shows  its  encyclopasdic 
character,  and  actually  it  is  far  more  reminiscent  of  Pliny  than  of  Aristotle. 
As  in  Pliny,  so  in  Gesner  one  seeks  in  vain  for  any  idea  as  to  the  connexion 
in  living  nature,  in  vain  for  any  comparison  worked  out  between  the  differ- 
ent forms  of  life,  regarding  their  organs  or  their  functions.  Gesner,  however, 
surpasses  Pliny  in  knowledge  —  in  this  respect,  of  course,  he  has  the  whole 
of  the  intermediate  literature  at  his  disposal,  and  indeed  he  has  it  at  his 
finger-ends.  True,  he,  too,  brings  in  a  great  many  stories  of  marvellous 
animals,  but  he  certainly  has  not  that  absolutely  unquestioning  belief  in 
the  miraculous  which  the  old  Roman  had.  And,  above  all,  he  was  able  to 
record  the  results  of  his  own  research  work,  for  he  studied  not  only  books, 
but  also  life.  He  was  a  keen  collector  of  observations  on  animals,  not  only 
his  own,  but  also  those  of  other  scientists  with  whom  he  corresponded. 

Illustrations  introduced  into  xpology 
His  most  original  contribution  to  science  was  his  introduction  of  the  illus- 
tration as  an  aid  to  the  study  of  biology.  He  desired  that,  as  far  as  possible, 
every  description  of  an  animal  should  be  followed  by  an  illustration  so  as  to 
give  the  reader  a  clearer  idea  of  the  animal,  and  he  spared  neither  trouble 
nor  expense  in  procuring  as  accurate  woodcuts  as  possible.  His  collaborators 
in  this  work  were  eminent  artists,  and  he  himself  declared  that  the  picture 
of  the  rhinoceros  was  done  by  no  less  a  person  than  Albrecht  Diirer.  With  all 
its  weak  points,  Gesner's  Historia  animalium  is  at  any  rate  the  foremost 
purely  zoological  work  of  the  Renaissance  period,  and  its  influence  on  the 
science  of  the  succeeding  age  was  considerable. 

Somewhat  younger  than  Gesner  and  partly  his  pupil  was  another  of  the 
foremost  zoologists  of  the  Renaissance,  Ulisse  Aldrovandi.  He  was  born 
at  Bologna  in  15x1  of  a  respectable  burgher  family  and  was  intended  to  be  a 
merchant.  Office  work,  however,  attracted  him  but  little,  and  so  he  went  in 


RENAISSANCE  95 

for  studying,  first  jurisprudence  in  his  native  town  and  then  philosophy  and 
medicine  at  Padua  and  Rome.  When  he  was  thirty  years  old,  he  took  the 
degree  of  doctor  of  medicine  and  shortly  afterwards,  in  1560,  he  was  made 
professor  at  Bologna,  where  he  worked  for  forty  years,  resigning  at  the  age 
of  nearly  eighty.  He  died  in  1605.  As  a  professor  he  lectured  chiefly  on 
pharmacology,  and  to  aid  him  in  his  teaching  he  planted  a  botanical  garden. 
This  caused  him  to  fall  foul  of  the  apothecaries  of  Bologna,  who  alleged 
that  in  cultivating  medicinal  plants  he  usurped  their  privileges.  The  contro- 
versy grew  so  fierce  that  it  finally  had  to  be  settled  by  the  Pope.  Aldrovandi 
was,  on  the  whole,  a  man  who  lived  for  his  science;  he  spent  his  fortune  on 
collecting  natural  objects  and  had  recourse  to  the  leading  artists  of  his  time 
to  draw  pictures  of  them.  The  Government  of  Bologna  doubled  his  salary 
in  recognition  of  his  great  services  to  science,  and  in  return  he  bequeathed 
to  the  city  his  collections  and  library. 

Aldrovandi' s  natural  history 
In  his  energy  and  capacity  for  work  Aldrovandi  resembled  Gesner,  and  as 
he  lived  longer  and  worked  under  more  favourable  conditions,  he  managed 
to  achieve  far  more.  His  collected  works  on  natural  history  consist  of  four- 
teen large  folio  volumes,  besides  which  there  are  preserved  in  the  University 
of  Bologna  quantities  of  unpublished  manuscripts  in  his  own  handwriting. 
He  himself  published  during  his  lifetime  only  four  volumes,  on  birds;  after 
his  death  his  friends  and  pupils  published  the  remainder:  those  on  other 
animal  groups,  on  plants,  and  on  stones.  These  latter  volumes,  however, 
seem  to  have  been  in  part  radically  revised  by  the  editors,  wherefore  Aldro- 
vandi should  be  judged  only  on  what  he  himself  published.  His  model  was 
chiefly  Gesner,  whose  work  he  diligently  studied  and  it  is  from  this  point  of 
view  that  his  own  work  must  be  judged.  His  relation  to  Gesner  is  by  no 
means  in  every  respect  that  of  an  improver;  he  is  far  less  critical,  and  similarly 
he  has  on  the  whole  less  stylistic  ability;  in  his  descriptions  he  piles  up 
masses  of  like  and  unlike,  so  that  one  of  his  most  eminent  successors,  BufFon, 
was  moved  to  express  the  opinion  that  only  one-tenth  of  the  whole  of  Aldro- 
vandi's  works  would  be  left  if  one  extracted  all  that  was  useless  and  untrue 
from  his  writings.  On  the  other  hand,  his  illustrations,  as  well  as  his  typo- 
graphical equipment,  are  better  than  Gesner' s,  while,  at  least  in  some  re- 
spects, he  is  in  advance  of  the  latter  in  regard  to  classification.  Birds  are 
classified  according  to  certain  groups:  first,  birds  of  prey;  then  wild  and  tame 
fowl  (gallinaceous  birds)  —  characterized  as  " pulveratrices" ;  i.e.,  those  that 
bathe  in  sand  —  further,  pigeons  and  sparrows,  which  bathe  in  both  water 
and  sand;  then  song-birds,  baccivorous  and  insectivorous;  and  lastly  water- 
fowl. Moreover,  he  has  paid  attention  to  anatomy,  particularly  osteology; 
and,  finally,  he  cites  a  far  greater  number  of  exotic  and  hitherto  unknown 
forms  than  Gesner.  He  too,  then,  has  in  his  own  degree  contributed  to  the 


96  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

advance  of  biology,  and  though  he  by  no  means  merits  the  vaunting  eulogy 
which  a  contemporary  artist  wrote  under  his  portrait  —  that,  though  not  in 
his  appearance,  yet  in  his  genius  he  resembled  Aristotle  —  nevertheless  his 
work  has  exercised  a  powerful  influence,  and  it  was  not  until  BufFon's  great 
zoological  work  in  the  eighteenth  century  that  Aldrovandi's  was  definitely 
out-distanced. 

Apart  from  these  representatives  of  the  knowledge  of  the  animal  world 
as  then  known,  certain  research-workers  are  worthy  of  mention  who  devoted 
themselves  to  the  study  of  particular  animal  groups  with  which  they  dealt 
monographically.  In  the  best  of  these  monographs  there  is  really  far  more 
evidence  of  independence  in  research  and  originality  of  ideas  than  in  the  great 
collective  works;  in  the  former  is  best  seen  that  power  of  independent  obser- 
vation and  investigation  of  natural  objects  which  was  a  feature  of  the  science 
of  the  Renaissance. 

GuiLLAUME  RoNDELET  was  bom  in  1507  at  Montpellier  in  the  south  of 
France,  where  he  also  worked  later  as  a  professor.  He  studied  first  in  his  own 
district  and  then  as  body-physician  to  a  distinguished  personage  on  his  travels 
in  Italy,  where  among  other  people  he  made  the  acquaintance  of  the  young 
Aldrovandi,  who  received  much  sound  teaching  from  him.  As  a  professor  he 
established  in  his  native  city  an  anatomical  theatre,  but  he  had  not  been 
working  there  long  as  a  teacher  when  he  died,  in  the  year  1556.  His  fame  as 
a  biologist  rests  on  his  work  De  fiscibus  marinis.  In  this  book  he  describes 
and  illustrates  the  aquatic  animals  he  knows,  for  he  regards  as  fishes  not 
only  seals  and  whales,  but  also  crustaceans,  molluscs,  echinoderms,  worms, 
and  other  marine  invertebrates.  He  makes  a  very  careful  study  of  whales, 
fishes  and  cephalopods.  According  to  his  own  statement,  he  dissected  a  large 
number  of  these  creatures  and  he  also  gives  a  number  of  correct  particulars 
which  are  sometimes  at  variance  with  the  great  authority  Aristotle.  He  fur- 
ther compares,  as  far  as  was  possible,  the  same  organs  in  different  fishes,  giv- 
ing exact  accounts  of  different  maxillary  and  dental  forms,  different  branchice, 
etc.  However,  his  comparative  work  practically  gets  stranded,  owing  to  the 
impossibility  of  finding  resemblances  between  the  vertebrate  and  invertebrate 
forms  discussed.  His  attempts  at  classification  are  likewise  very  primitive. 
He  differentiates  between  selachians  and  osseans,  which  again  are  divided 
into  "flat"  and  "high"  fish;  moreover,  whales  are  dealt  with  in  a  group  by 
themselves.  He  has  as  little  notion  of  species  in  the  modern  sense  as  had 
Gesner  and  Aldrovandi,  and  therefore,  like  them,  he  had  to  begin  the  de- 
scription of  every  form  by  recounting  as  many  names  for  it  as  possible.  On 
the  other  hand,  he  avoids  for  the  most  part  the  useless  petty  details  of  scholar- 
ship with  which  the  two  last-mentioned  authors  of  collective  works  over- 
burdened their  accounts,  and  this  at  once  gives  to  his  work  an  impression  of 
greater  accuracy.  And  though  he  certainly  does  illustrate  a  number  of  mar- 


RENAISSANCE  97 

vellous  creatures  reported  to  have  been  seen,  such  as,  for  instance,  a  fish  hav- 
ing "the  appearance  of  a  bishop,"  he  does  so  w^ith  a  reservation  as  to  the 
irrational  nature  of  stories  relating  to  such  phenomena. 

Besides  Rondelet,  a  younger  countryman  of  his  is  worthy  of  mention, 
Pierre  Belon,  in  several  respects  a  man  possessing  great  ideas  about  the 
future.  He  was  born  in  15 17  near  Le  Mans,  in  central  France,  of  poor  parents. 
His  genius  attracted  the  attention  of  the  bishop  there,  who  defrayed  the  cost 
of  his  medical  studies  in  Paris.  After  that  Belon  went  to  Germany  for  a  course 
of  study.  Upon  returning  to  France  he  received,  through  the  kindness  of 
certain  distinguished  patrons,  funds  to  enable  him  to  undertake  a  still 
longer  journey,  through  Greece,  Turkey,  Syria,  and  Egypt.  Everywhere  he 
collected  material  with  great  energy  and  made  notes,  not  only  on  natural- 
scientific,  but  also  on  archaeological  and  ethnographical  subjects.  On  his 
return  home  he  settled  in  Paris,  where  he  was  granted  a  pension  by  King 
Henry  II.  In  1564  he  was  murdered  by  highwaymen.  His  period  of  scientific 
authorship  was  thus  brief,  lasting  not  more  than  about  ten  years,  but  during 
that  time  he  brought  out  ideas  of  great  significance  for  the  future.  He  was 
held  in  high  esteem  even  by  his  contemporaries;  he  counted  amongst  his 
friends  the  famous  poet  Ronsard,  who  wrote  verses  in  his  honour. 

Like  Rondelet,  Belon  devoted  himself  to  the  study  of  marine  animals  and 
published  two  monographs:  UHistoire  naturelle  des  estranges  poissons  marins 
and  La  Nature  et  diversites  des  poissons.  The  term  "fishes"  he  makes  even  more 
comprehensive  than  Rondelet:  not  only  whales  and  seals,  crustaceans,  mol- 
luscs, and  actinic-e,  but  the  hippopotamus,  the  beaver,  and  the  otter  are  also 
described  amongst  the  fishes.  And  even  if  all  these  animals  could  be  classified 
by  a  faithful  Catholic  as  fishes,  just  because  the  Church  included  them  among 
the  animals  that  may  be  eaten  during  a  fast,  it  is  hard  to  understand  why  the 
chameleon  and  the  uromastix  lizard  are  catalogued  in  the  book  —  these 
beasts  of  the  desert  which  have  nothing  whatever  to  do  with  water.  Though 
the  external  grouping  of  the  subject,  then,  leaves  much  to  be  desired,  Belon 
has  certainly  endeavoured  to  introduce  into  the  class  of  true  fishes  some  kind 
of  systematic  division,  based  not  merely  on  external,  but  also  on  internal 
anatomical  characteristics.  Cartilaginous  and  bony  skeletons,  Ovipara  and 
Vivipara,  constitute  the  bases  of  classification,  which  still  hold  good  today, 
and  on  the  whole  his  system  of  classification  bears  a  somewhat  more  modern 
stamp  than  Rondelet's.  Even  attempts  at  an  investigation  of  various  forms 
on  the  lines  of  comparative  anatomy  occur  in  Belon's  work.  Whether  and, 
if  so,  to  what  extent  he  was  influenced  by  his  immediate  predecessor  it  is 
difficult  to  decide.  Their  works  were  published  practically  at  the  same  time. 
As  regards  wealth  of  material,  at  any  rate,  Belon's  work  is  superior.  More- 
over, thanks  to  his  travels,  he  was  able  to  include  many  oriental  animal 
forms  which  were  previously  unknown  to  the  Western  world. 


98  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

Far  superior  to  the  works  on  the  fishes  is  Belon's  second  main  treatise: 
Histoire  des  oyseaux.  In  this  work  he  describes  and  illustrates  all  the  birds  he 
knows,  arranged  in  groups  according  to  their  structure  and  habits  —  birds 
of  prey,  waterfowl,  shore-birds,  ground-pecking,  wood-pecking,  omnivo- 
rous, and  small  birds,  divided  into  Insectivora  and  Granivora.  The  individual 
forms  are  characterized  by  a  few  names  in  Latin,  Greek,  and  French;  unlike 
Gesner,  Belon  scorns  to  extend  his  knowledge  of  languages.  If  this  attempt 
at  classification  bears  witness  to  Belon's  keen  powers  of  observation,  there 
is  still  further  proof  of  them  in  the  attention  he  pays  to  the  morphology  and 
anatomy  of  the  individual  forms.  The  structure  of  beaks  and  claws  is  closely 
studied  and  compared  in  different  forms,  while  anatomical  relations  are 
treated  in  the  same  way.  Most  noteworthy,  however,  is  the  detailed  com- 
parison in  both  text  and  illustration,  in  the  first  book  of  the  work,  between 
the  skeleton  of  a  man  and  that  of  a  bird,  the  latter  drawn  in  an  attitude  cor- 
responding to  that  which  the  former  assumes  in  his  natural  standing  position. 
Although  this  comparison  by  no  means  agrees  in  every  detail  —  for  instance, 
the  human  clavicle  and  the  bird's  coracoid  bone  are  made  homologous  —  at 
any  rate  we  have  here  a  first  attempt  at  a  comparative  anatomical  investi- 
gation. The  idea  thus  started  by  Belon  was,  it  is  true,  for  a  long  time  neg- 
lected; it  was  not  until  two  centuries  later  that  it  was  taken  up  anew  by 
Buffon,  to  be  eventually  developed  by  Cuvier  into  one  of  the  most  important 
fields  of  biological  research.  The  fact  that  these  two  were  both  countrymen 
of  Belon  is  indeed  some  evidence  that  his  activities  in  this  sphere  did  not 
pass  entirely  unnoticed. 


z.  Anatomy 

That  the  age  of  comparative  anatomy  had  not  yet  arrived  was  of  course  due 
to  the  fact  that  research  was  still  fully  occupied  with  purely  descriptive 
anatomy.  In  this,  as  in  other  spheres,  the  Renaissance  inherited  from  the 
great  anatomists  of  antiquity,  of  whom  Galen  constituted  the  chief  author- 
ity, in  his  reputation  comparable  with  Aristotle,  and  like  him  regarded  with 
infinite  respect  by  the  physicians  of  the  Renaissance,  who  were  philologi- 
cally  rather  than  biologically  educated.  However,  it  was  not  the  phy- 
sicians alone  who  required  anatomical  knowledge;  even  art,  the  result  of 
the  admiration  of  the  Renaissance  for  antiquity,  now  began  to  demand  a 
closer  study  of  the  structure  of  the  human  body.  Amongst  the  pioneers  in 
this  field  the  first  name  that  should  be  mentioned  is  that  of  the  great  universal 
genius  Leonardo  da  Vinci  (i45x-i5I9). 

Leonardo  was  a  Florentine,  and  in  his  native  city,  which  was  the  very 
centre  of  Renaissance  culture,  he  was  brought  up  to  be  an  artist  and  at  the 


RENAISSANCE  99 

same  time  a  mechanician  —  the  professions  of  painting  and  mechanics  in 
those  days  were  often  combined.  He  afterwards  led  a  restless  life,  carried  out 
work  in  many  places  in  Italy,  and  ended  his  days  at  the  French  Court.  His 
world-wide  fame  he  of  course  won  as  a  pioneer  in  the  art  of  painting.  In 
this  his  greatest  contribution  was  his  introduction  of  a  close  study  of  human 
anatomy;  he  drew  for  the  benefit  of  his  pupils  a  vast  number  of  anatomical 
figures,  which  are  still  preserved,  and  published  a  work  on  the  proportions 
of  the  human  body.  He  did  not  study  only  man,  however;  all  sorts  of  natural 
objects  and  natural  phenomena  interested  him.  In  a  mass  of  roughly  drafted 
notes,  which  were  never  combined  into  a  connected  whole  and  were  not 
printed  until  our  own  day,  he  has  recorded  his  observations  and  reflections 
on  practically  every  sphere  of  human  knowledge.  He  not  only  studied  human 
anatomy;  he  also  compared  similar  organs  in  different  living  creatures;  he 
investigated  optical  sensations;  he  observed  the  structure  of  different  geo- 
logical strata,  and  maintained,  in  opposition  to  Aristotle,  but  in  agreement 
with  Xenophanes,  that  fossils  were  animal  remains.  In  every  field  he  shows 
himself  an  opponent,  not  only  of  scholastic  traditions,  but  also  of  the  slavish 
admiration  for  antiquity  that  characterized  the  Renaissance.  Not  the  classical 
authors,  but  experience  should  be  the  source  of  human  knowledge.  Unfor- 
tunately his  speculations  were  merely  fragmentary  and  for  that  reason  were 
unprinted.  It  was  not  until  later  that  they  were  more  closely  studied,  and 
Leonardo's  influence  upon  science  has  been  only  indirect,  as  a  result  of  the 
impression  made  by  his  personality  and  his  art.  The  study  of  the  human 
anatomy  which  he  initiated  was  continued  by  other  Renaissance  artists  and 
in  that  way  reacted  upon  culture  in  general;  these  painters  and  sculptors 
were  certainly  not  without  their  influence  upon  the  impetus  given  to  medical 
anatomy  in  the  sixteenth  century. 

In  the  field  of  medical  science  the  influence  of  the  Renaissance  was  felt 
in  the  same  way  as  in  other  branches  of  human  knowledge;  a  return  was  made 
from  the  mediasval  authorities  to  antiquity.  The  doctors  applied  themselves 
to  the  study  of  the  classical  languages;  they  severely  condemned  the  barba- 
rous Latin  of  the  mediaeval  professors  and  formed  their  style  on  the  best 
Roman  and  Greek  models.  And  in  conformity  with  this  enlightened  spirit 
the  poor  editions  of  the  medical  writers  of  antiquity  which  were  based  on 
Arabic  translations  were  banned  and  were  replaced  by  new  editions  of  Hip- 
pocrates, Celsus,  and  Galen,  which,  published  with  careful  textual  criticism 
and  sound  commentaries,  were,  thanks  to  the  progress  of  book-printing, 
widely  dispersed  throughout  the  universities.  One  of  the  most  brilliant  and 
at  the  same  time  most  typical  students  of  medicine  during  the  Renaissance 
was  Jacob  Sylvius,  of  Paris.  Born  in  1478,  he  devoted  himself  from  early 
youth  to  the  study  of  classical  languages,  not  only  Roman  and  Greek,  but 
also  Hebrew.  He  was  a  fine  stylist  and  was  the  author  of  several  works  on 


lOO  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

French  grammar.  He  was  nearly  fifty  years  old  when  he  took  up  medicine, 
applying  himself  to  the  study  and  exposition  of  classical  medical  literature. 
In  lectures,  which  were  brilliant  in  their  formal  delivery,  he  expounded  to 
the  students  of  Paris  the  theories  of  Galen,  which  to  his  mind  were  infalli- 
ble —  "divinely  inspired"  —  and  could  not  be  improved  upon.  These  lec- 
tures were  really  exercises  in  classical  oratory;  there  was  no  question  of  any 
empirical  research.  Practical  instruction  remained  in  all  respects  at  the  point 
to  which  the  Middle  Ages  had  advanced  it.  And  in  this  respect  the  Middle 
Ages  did  actually  advance  beyond  antiquity. 

Mediaval  dissection 
As  early  as  the  middle  of  the  thirteenth  century  dissections  had  to  be 
carried  out  on  human  bodies  at  the  Italian  universities;  the  Emperor  Fred- 
erick II,  who  had  no  prejudices,  made  it  compulsory  for  students  of  medicine 
and  surgery  to  attend  these  operations,  while  later  on,  the  prohibition  of 
the  popes  was  powerless  to  prevent  the  development  of  these  practices.  At 
the  universities  of  Salerno,  Bologna,  and  Padua  they  were  officially  ordained 
and  had,  if  possible,  to  be  carried  out  regularly.  As  a  result  of  this  it  should 
have  been  possible  to  leave  the  work  of  Galen  at  its  worth,  for,  as  we  know, 
he  had  never  dissected  human  bodies,  and  his  anatomical  dicta  were  very 
unreliable  and  highly  misleading.  This,  however,  was  not  to  be;  the  Middle 
Ages  were  far  too  bound  by  respect  for  authority,  and  in  particular  the  classi- 
cal authorities.  Moreover,  the  study  of  anatomy  was  rendered  difficult  on 
account  of  the  antagonism  prevailing  between  the  physicians  and  the  sur- 
geons. Members  of  the  faculty  of  medicine  pursued  their  studies  only  on  a 
literary  and  speculative  basis  and  looked  down  upon  the  surgeons  as  merely 
a  body  of  artisans.  In  dissections  it  was  always  a  surgeon  who  wielded  the 
knife,  while  the  professor,  staff  in  hand,  pointed  out  and  demonstrated  what 
was  brought  to  light.  The  results  of  this  collaboration  were  also  primitive. 
The  surgeon's  instruments  and  hold  were  the  simplest  imaginable;  with  a 
knife  —  the  use  of  a  saw  and  chisel,  probe  and  canula  was  unknown  then  — 
the  abdomen  and  chest  cavity  were  opened  and  the  internal  organs  laid  bare 
for  examination.  After  this  the  idea  was  that  muscles,  nerves,  and  blood- 
vessels should  be  exposed  for  study,  but  this  was  usually  too  difficult  a  task 
for  the  operators,  nor  did  it  amuse  the  students,  who  very  soon  marched  off 
unless  the  proceedings  ended  with  one  of  the  professorial  discussions  that 
were  so  popular  at  that  time.  The  professors  of  the  faculty  of  philosophy, 
who  were  usually  invited  to  attend  the  proceedings,  taking  Aristotle  as 
their  authority,  would  attack  Galen,  who  would  be  courageously  defended 
by  all  the  medical  professors  present.  The  differences  of  opinion  between 
these  great  authorities  of  the  ancient  world  could  be  dragged  out  into  end- 
less discussions  and  give  rise  to  the  most  absurd  sophistical  arguments.  This 
was  the  course  that  anatomical  studies  were  still  taking  in  the  sixteenth 


RENAISSANCE  lOI 

century,  so  that  nothing  was  to  be  expected  from  them  in  the  way  of  biologi- 
cal development.  Then  a  man  came  upon  the  scene  who  at  once  led  anatomi- 
cal research  into  a  completely  new  direction,  created  an  entirely  original 
method  of  procedure,  and  thus  started  a  new  era  in  the  history  of  science. 

Andreas  Vesalius  was  born  in  15 14  or  15 15  at  Brussels,  of  a  family 
which  had  taken  its  name  from  the  district  of  Wesel  in  the  Rhine  Province  and 
which  for  several  generations  had  been  devoted  to  the  medical  profession.  He 
himself  chose  the  same  profession  and  prepared  himself  for  it  by  a  thorough 
school-education.  Though  his  studies  were  exclusively  humanistic,  for  there 
was  no  other  kind  of  education  given  in  the  schools  of  those  times,  the  young 
Vesalius  was  able  in  his  own  way  to  satisfy  his  craving  for  biological  knowl- 
edge; he  studied  ancient  anatomical  works  which  he  found  in  the  family 
library  and  himself  dissected  animals  of  various  kinds  which  he  managed  to 
procure.  At  the  age  of  eighteen  he  went  to  Paris  in  order  to  study  medicine 
seriously.  There,  however,  Sylvius,  whom  we  have  mentioned  above,  was  the 
ruling  spirit,  with  his  classical-philological  method  of  education.  Vesalius 
had  again  to  rely  upon  his  own  resources.  And  his  force  of  will  enabled  him 
to  make  a  way  for  himself.  He  began  to  collect  bones  from  the  places  of 
execution  and  went  on  with  his  dissection  of  animals.  Soon  he  acquired  such 
a  reputation  that  he  was  called  upon  by  physicians  and  students  to  perform 
public  dissecting  operations  on  human  bodies  in  place  of  the  surgeon,  and  he 
fulfilled  his  task  so  well  that  not  only  the  internal  organs  of  the  corpse,  bui; 
also  the  muscles,  nerves,  blood-vessels,  and  bones  were  completely  demon- 
strated. After  three  years  he  left  Paris,  worked  at  his  home  for  a  brief  period  — 
in  the  course  of  which  he  succeeded,  inter  alia,  in  putting  together  a  complete 
skeleton  out  of  bones  from  the  gallows  —  and  then  went  to  Italy.  In  Venice, 
where  there  existed  at  that  time  a  very  keen  interest  in  medicine,  he  increased 
both  his  learning  and  his  reputation,  with  the  result  that,  immediately  after 
he  had  graduated,  he  was  appointed  professor  at  Padua,  at  the  age  of  twenty- 
two,  after  only  four  years  of  study.  He  could  hardly  have  wished  for  a  more 
satisfactory  field  of  activities.  An  enlightened  government,  an  interested 
audience,  and  a  thoroughly  educated  public  all  equally  favoured  the  attain- 
ment of  his  ambitions.  And,  indeed,  Vesalius  surpassed  all  expectations.  His 
interest  in  his  science  was  indefatigable  and  his  enthusiasm  for  imparting 
his  knowledge  inexhaustible.  His  demonstrations  on  dissection  used  to 
bring  together  as  many  as  five  hundred  listeners,  and  this  in  spite  of  what, 
according  to  the  ideas  of  his  time,  were  unheard-of  claims  that  he  put  upon 
his  audience,  which  he  kept  busy  from  morning  to  night  for  a  space  of  three 
weeks.  Dissection  lectures,  which  were  always  held  in  the  winter  so  that 
the  material  should  not  putrefy,  began  with  a  demonstration  of  the  skeleton, 
the  bones  of  which  were  carefully  gone  over;  then  the  muscles,  blood-vessels, 
and  nerves  of  one  corpse  were  prepared,  and  finally  the  internal  organs  of  the 


lOl.  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

abdomen  and  chest  of  another  body,  as  well  as  the  brain.  Vesalius  himself 
used  to  perform  the  essential  work  in  dissecting,  assisted  by  students;  the 
surgeons,  who  elsewhere  had  such  an  important  part  to  play,  had  nothing 
whatever  to  do  here.  A  mass  of  new  surgical  instruments  came  into  use;  the 
models  had  been  partly  invented  by  Vesalius  himself  and  partly  borrowed 
from  among  the  tools  owned  by  a  number  of  artisans  whom  he  visited  in 
order  to  initiate  himself  into  their  technical  ideas. 

Vesalius' s  great  anatomical  ivork 
In  his  demonstrations  Vesalius  was  at  first  a  faithful  follower  of  Galen,  for 
whom  since  his  youth  he  had  entertained  the  greatest  respect.  It  soon  became 
more  and  more  obvious,  however,  that  Galen's  observations  were  incomplete 
and  that  his  presentation  of  them  was  vague  and  self-contradictory.  The 
more  zealously  Vesalius  anatomized,  the  more  did  he  realize  how  necessary 
it  was  to  reproduce  in  print  all  his  anatomical  observations  and,  without 
reference  to  any  authorities,  to  describe  the  structure  of  the  human  body  as 
it  really  is.  The  result  was  his  two  literary  masterpieces:  De  humani  corf  oris 
jabrica,  a  large  folio  volume  of  over  seven  hundred  pages,  and  a  compendium 
of  the  same,  Epitome,  of  thirty-one  pages,  both  containing  numerous  illus- 
trations by  eminent  artists  after  Vesalius's  original  preparations.  These  books 
were  published  in  1543  at  Basel,  where  Vesalius  spent  a  whole  year's  leave 
of  absence  superintending  the  printing.  Through  these  two  works  Vesalius 
created  the  modern  science  of  anatomy.  They  made  an  enormous  impression 
on  his  contemporaries.  Galen's  followers  were  furious,  particularly  Vesalius's 
old  master  Sylvius.  Many  were  the  polemical  treatises  written  in  opposition 
to  the  man  of  dangerous  newfangled  ideas,  and  the  rage  of  his  opponents  can 
still  be  perceived  from  the  controversial  methods  they  adopted.  They  were 
not  content  with  merely  declaring  that  Vesalius's  work  was  absolutely 
inferior;  the  most  abominable  and  absurd  accusations  were  heaped  upon  his 
personal  character  —  he  was  godless,  he  was  sordid;  like  the  ancient  Alex- 
andrian anatomists  he  had  dissected  men  alive  (sentimentality  as  regards 
animals  was  not  so  deep  in  those  days  as  to  make  it  worth  while  quoting 
the  vivisection  he  actually  performed  on  animals).  Even  after  his  death  his 
memory  was  treated  with  contumely,  especially  in  France,  where  the  fol- 
lowers of  Galen  were  to  hold  unrestricted  sway  for  another  hundred  years. 
Vesalius  could  now  no  longer  hope  to  enjoy  the  tranquil  conditions  under 
which  he  had  worked  in  the  past.  In  the  year  after  the  publication  of  his 
writings  we  find  him  relinquishing  his  professorship  and  accepting  the  post 
of  court  physician  to  the  Emperor  Charles  V.  What  induced  him  to  take  this 
step  is  not  known;  it  is  assumed  that  after  the  completion  of  his  anatomical 
masterpiece  he  wished  to  devote  himself  to  practical  medicine,  but  that  he 
might  just  as  well  have  done  in  Padua.  It  is  more  likely  that  he  hoped  that 
in  his  appointment  at  the  court  of  the  most  powerful  monarch  in  the  world 


RENAISSANCE  103 

he  would  find  protection  from  the  persecution  of  his  enemies.  Besides,  several 
of  his  ancestors  had  been  court  physicians.  He  accompanied  his  delicate 
master  on  all  his  many  journeys  through  various  European  countries,  in  the 
course  of  which  he  had  but  little  time  for  continued  research.  In  1555,  how- 
ever, he  published  a  new  and  improved  edition  of  his  great  work,  in  which 
he  vigorously  refutes  his  calumniators.  Upon  Charles's  abdication  he  joined 
his  son  Philip  II,  whose  notorious  obscurantism  offered  but  the  smallest 
chance  for  his  personal  retainers  to  develop  liberal  ideas.  In  fact,  after  eight 
years  we  find  Vesalius  leaving  the  court;  in  1564  he  visited  Venice,  in  the 
hope  apparently  of  again  taking  up  his  old  professorship,  which  then  hap- 
pened to  be  vacant.  While  waiting  to  be  appointed  he  made  a  journey  to  the 
East,  visited  Jerusalem  as  a  pilgrim,  and  never  again  returned  to  the  West. 
The  reason  for  his  journey  is  not  known  for  certain,  nor  indeed  how  he  ended 
his  life.  Thus  disappeared  into  the  unknown  one  of  the  greatest  scientists  of 
modern  times. 

Vesalius 's  great  anatomical  work  is  arranged  in  the  same  order  as  that 
which  he  followed  in  his  anatomizing,  mentioned  above:  first  he  discusses 
bone-construction,  then  muscles,  blood-vessels,  and  nerves,  then  the  ab- 
dominal organs  and  those  of  the  thorax,  and  the  brain,  and  finally  he  devotes 
one  chapter  to  an  account  of  his  vivisectional  method.  In  his  general  concep- 
tions Vesalius  entirely  adopts  the  standpoint  of  antiquity.  His  division  of  the 
component  parts  of  the  body  into  simple  and  complex  is  borrowed  from  Aris- 
totle, as  also  are  most  of  his  physiological  terms;  the  food  is  "cooked"  in  the 
abdominal  cavity,  the  object  of  respiration  is  to  cool  the  blood,  the  embryo 
arises  out  of  the  father's  semen  and  the  mother's  menstrual  blood.  From  Galen, 
whom  he  still  highly  respected,  he  takes  his  general  conception  of  continuity 
in  existence  and  of  the  causes  that  govern  it.  The  Creator  has,  to  His  own 
honour  and  to  the  benefit  of  man,  made  the  human  body  as  perfect  as  pos- 
sible; every  part  of  it  has  been  created  just  as  it  is  in  order  to  fulfil  its  specific 
purpose.  In  many  important  details  also  he  adheres  to  Galen's  ideas,  particu- 
larly in  regard  to  the  circulatory  system;  he  gives,  it  is  true,  an  exhaustive 
description  of  the  structure  of  the  heart,  but  as  regards  its  and  the  liver's 
relation  to  the  vascular  system  he  still  retains  the  old  traditional  view.  The 
greatness  of  Vesalius  lies  in  his  method  and  technique.  In  this  he  created 
the  conditions  necessary  for  the  development  of  modern  anatomy.  Most  of 
the  technique  which  is  practised  in  every  anatomical  theatre  today  originates 
from  him;  the  instruments  used  at  the  present  time  are  practically  the  same 
as  those  which  he  designed,  and  the  majority  of  them  he  introduced  into 
dissectional  practice;  the  course  of  instruction  as  laid  down  in  his  works  is 
still  followed;  the  skeletons  used  for  demonstration  purposes  are  mounted 
after  his  method;  and  the  plates  used  to  facilitate  instruction  are  for  the  most 
part  merely  improved  editions  of  his  own.  But  his  great  service  to  science  is 


I04  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

not  confined  to  this.  In  almost  every  sphere  of  human  anatomy  he  made  im- 
portant discoveries  in  matters  of  detail  and,  still  more,  corrected  old  fallacies. 
To  enumerate  all  that  he  did  in  this  respect  would  be  impossible  here;  but  he 
who  cares  to  do  so  can  compare,  for  instance,  a  picture  of  a  skeleton  made  by 
any  one  of  his  predecessors  with  one  of  his.  If  we  add  to  this  his  masterly 
and  at  the  same  time  exact  and  highly  imaginative  descriptive  method,  with 
its  splendid  simplicity  of  arrangement  in  the  midst  of  a  wealth  of  detail, 
every  impartial  judge  must  admit  that  he  was,  in  spite  of  his  lack  of  original 
ideas,  one  of  the  greatest  biologists  that  have  ever  lived. 

Vesalius's  influence  on  the  development  of  anatomy  was  primarily  of 
benefit  to  Italy.  In  France  the  disciples  of  Galen  still  upheld  the  authority 
of  their  master;  in  Germany  the  interest  in  the  study  of  nature  was  being 
gradually  suppressed  by  interminable  religious  strife.  Italy,  on  the  other 
hand,  thanks  to  the  impetus  given  by  Vesalius's  practice  of  anatomy  in 
Padua,  became  throughout  the  succeeding  century  the  centre  of  anatomical 
study.  Vesalius's  pupils  followed  in  their  master's  footsteps  and  carried  on 
his  work  by  widening  the  field  of  detailed  research.  His  prosector  and  suc- 
cessor in  Padua,  Realdo  Columbus  (date  of  birth  unknown,  died  1559},  made 
a  special  study  of  the  organs  of  hearing  and  the  blood-vessels  in  the  lungs. 
He  published  the  results  of  his  experiments  in  a  work  entitled  De  re  anafomica, 
in  which  he  shows  himself  a  well-informed  anatomist,  but  a  not  very  sym- 
pathetic personality,  self-opinionated  and  overbearing,  not  least  towards 
his  old  master.  He  was  soon  called  away,  however,  to  carry  on  other  activi- 
ties elsewhere  and  was  succeeded  in  Padua  by  a  man  of  far  higher  qualities, 
Gabriele  Fallopio.  Born  in  152.3,  Fallopio  spent  his  youth  in  poverty,  was 
for  a  time  in  the  service  of  the  Church,  but  afterwards  had  an  opportunity 
of  studying  anatomy  in  Padua,  probably  during  the  very  last  years  of  Vesa- 
lius's professorship.  His  career  was  as  rapid  as  the  latter's;  at  the  age  of 
twenty-four  he  was  a  professor  in  Ferrara,  whence  he  was  summoned  to 
Padua,  where  the  Government  maintained  him  in  every  way.  He  carried  on 
the  Vesalian  traditions  with  honour,  attracting  to  his  lectures  a  large 
audience  and  at  the  same  time  working  at  an  extensive  medical  practice. 
Unfortunately  his  life  was  short;  he  died  in  his  fortieth  year.  During  his 
lifetime  he  published  only  one,  rather  small,  but  useful,  work  entitled 
Observationes  anatomka.  In  its  introduction  he  speaks  most  highly  of  his  mas- 
ter, Vesalius,  and  with  the  greatest  modesty  of  his  own  observations.  These 
are,  however,  in  certain  respects  of  fundamental  importance.  In  particular, 
he  increased  the  knowledge  of  the  sexual  organs  —  in  this  field  the  Fallopian 
tube  bears  his  name  —  while  his  contribution  to  the  knowledge  of  the 
structure  of  bone  and  of  the  organ  of  hearing  was  of  considerable  value. 
But  he  also  made  important  discoveries  in  most  other  fields  of  human 
anatomy.  Besides  this  his  activities  extended  to  other  spheres  of  medical 


RENAISSANCE  10$ 

science;  the  results  he  achieved  here  were  not  published  until  after  his 
death. 

To  Fallopio's  professorship,  which,  as  mentioned  above,  Vesalius  had 
hoped  to  resume,  was  appointed  after  the  latter's  death  another  scientist 
who  was  also  a  pioneer  in  his  branch  —  Girolamo  Fabrizio,  usually  called, 
after  the  place  of  his  birth,  Fabricius  ab  Aquapendente,  to  distinguish  him 
from  a  contemporary  German  anatomist  Fabricius.  Born  in  1537,  he  studied 
under  Fallopio,  was  his  prosector,  and  succeeded  him  as  professor  in  1565. 
In  contrast  to  his  famous  predecessors  he  lived  to  a  good  old  age:  he  died  in 
1 61 9,  having  been  for  ten  years  emeritus  professor.  Besides  anatomy  he  lec- 
tured on  surgery;  he  raised  that  despised  "handicraft"  to  the  rank  of  a 
science  and  was  himself  an  eminent  practitioner,  his  profession  bringing  him 
immense  wealth,  which  he  generously  utilized  for  the  benefit  of  science.  Ana- 
tomical research  was  in  his  time  liberally  patronized  by  the  Venetian  Govern- 
ment, which  built  a  fine  anatomical  theatre  and  paid  generous  salaries  to  its 
staff. 

Fabrizio  was  a  very  productive  scientist,  though  more  qualitatively 
than  quantitatively.  His  predecessors  had  devoted  themselves  exclusively 
to  human  anatomy,  and  such  contributions  to  comparative  anatomical  re- 
search as  had  been  made  in  other  quarters  —  Pierre  Belon's,  for  instance  — 
had  passed  practically  unnoticed.  Fabrizio  adopted  the  method  of  compara- 
tive research,  which  really  no  one  since  Aristotle  had  applied  with  anything 
like  original  results,  and  he  developed  it  further  in  one  of  the  most  important 
spheres  of  biology  —  namely,  embryology.  His  treatises  on  the  evolution 
of  the  egg  and  the  embryo  present  in  clear  and  concise  form,  with  good  illus- 
trations, the  process  of  embryonic  development  in  a  large  number  of  verte- 
brates: birds  and  reptiles,  mammals  and  sharks.  He  describes  the  anatomy 
of  the  embryo  and  the  shape  and  appearance  of  the  placenta  and  embryonic 
tissues,  pointing  out  the  similarities  and  differences  between  the  various 
animal  forms,  with  a  wealth  of  hitherto  unknown  facts,  which  it  would  take 
too  long  to  follow  in  detail.  Fabrizio  employs  the  same  comparative  method 
in  a  number  of  other  spheres  of  biology.  Thus,  he  describes  the  movements 
of  animals  from  a  comparative  point  of  view;  again  he  studies  the  noises  of 
animals.  This  leads  him  to  make  an  interesting  attempt  at  animal  psy- 
chology —  certainly  the  first  of  its  kind.  Amongst  his  purely  anatomical 
works  may  be  noted  his  investigations  into  the  structure  of  the  ear,  the  eye, 
and  the  larynx.  Of  more  definite  value  to  posterity,  however,  was  a  three- 
page  article  on  the  venous  valves,  which  he  discovered  experimentally  — 
through  binding  the  limbs  of  live  human  subjects  for  the  purpose  of  bleed- 
ing —  and  which  he  afterwards  closely  studied  with  reference  to  their 
structure  and  distribution.  In  spite  of  this  discovery,  which  was  so  obviously 
at  variance  with  the  Galenian  theory  of  circulation,  he  could  not  abandon 


lo6  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

the  latter;  he  explained  away  his  discovery,  and  it  was  left  to  one  of  his 
pupils,  the  Englishman  Harvey,  using  this  fact  as  a  starting-point,  to  formu- 
late a  true  conception  of  the  circulation  of  the  blood. 

Fabrizio  was  the  last  of  the  great  anatomists  of  Padua  —  a  line  of  great 
men  in  the  service  of  biological  research,  such  as  scarcely  any  other  university 
has  been  able  to  produce  in  an  unbroken  sequence.  But  besides  these  Italy 
possessed  in  the  sixteenth  century  a  great  number  of  eminent  specialists  in 
the  field  of  anatomy.  Space,  however,  does  not  permit  of  our  dealing  with 
more  than  one  or  two  of  them  as  examples  of  the  enthusiasm  with  which 
anatomical  research  was  carried  on  in  the  country  in  which  Vesalius  stimu- 
lated such  interest  in  that  branch. 

Bartolommeo  Eustacchi  was  a  student  of  research  possessing  wide  in- 
terests and  deep  knowledge,  which,  however,  owing  to  the  unhappy  fate 
that  befell  his  works,  came  to  have  but  little  influence  on  the  progress  of 
science.  The  date  of  his  birth  and  the  early  circumstances  of  his  life  are  un- 
known to  us;  in  the  middle  of  the  sixteenth  century  we  find  him  in  practice  as 
a  physician  in  Rome  and  then  as  professor  at  a  papal  medical  academy.  He 
died  in  1574.  He  had  recorded  his  widely  extensive  anatomical  investigations 
in  a  richly  illustrated  work,  which  at  his  death  was  ready  for  the  press.  It 
was  withdrawn,  however,  and  never  published  until  1714,  when  most  of  it 
was  naturally  out  of  date.  During  his  life,  Eustacchi  found  time  to  publish 
a  number  of  smaller  treatises,  Opuscula  anatomka,  among  which  were  several 
important  investigations,  as,  for  instance,  that  of  the  auditory  organ,  in 
which  the  Eustachian  tube  still  bears  his  name,  and  of  the  blood-circulation 
and  dental  development  in  the  embryo. 

Another  eminent  anatomist  was  Costanzo  Varolio,  of  Bologna  (1543- 
75),  who  in  the  course  of  a  short  life  managed  to  carry  out  important  in- 
vestigations into  the  nervous  system,  in  which  the  pns  Varolii  in  the  brain 
is  named  after  him. 

Far  more  remarkable  than  these  two,  however,  is  Cesalpino,  a  scientist 
who  made  weighty  contributions  in  several  different  fields  of  research;  in 
biology,  as  a  speculative  natural  philosopher,  and  as  a  botanist.  His  life's 
work,  however,  is  best  described  in  another  connexion,  among  the  pioneers 
in  the  discovery  of  the  circulation  of  the  blood. 

The  position  of  Marc'  Aurelio  Severino  among  the  Italian  anatomists 
is  a  curious  one.  Born  in  1 5  80  in  south  Italy,  he  came  at  an  early  age  to  Naples, 
where  he  studied  the  humanistic  sciences  and  philosophy  under  the  famous 
Campanella,  known  as  a  keen  opponent  of  Aristotle  and  as  a  victim  of 
political  and  scientific  persecution.  Soon,  however,  Severino  began  to  devote 
himself  to  the  study  of  medicine  and  was  appointed  professor  of  anatomy 
and  surgery  at  Naples.  He  had,  besides,  a  wide  medical  practice.  At  one  time 
he  was  subjected  to  persecution  by  the  Inquisition  and  had  to  flee  from  Naples, 


RENAISSANCE  107 

but  he  was  soon  recalled  and  throughout  his  life  enjoyed  a  great  reputation. 
He  died  in  1656  of  a  serious  plague,  which  he  had  endeavoured  to  stamp  out. 
He  wrote  a  handbook  of  human  anatomy,  a  monograph  on  the  viper,  and, 
finally,  the  work  which  made  his  name  famous:  Zootomia  Democritea. 

Zootomia  Democritea 
Severing  introduces  his  work  with  a  defence  of  the  comparative  study  of 
the  anatomy  of  different  animals,  the  advantages  of  which  he  demonstrates 
in  a  dichotomously  arranged  table,  and  then  further  dilates  upon  them  with 
a  mass  of  quotations  from  other  authors  and  arguments  of  his  own.  He  finds 
its  best  to  begin  the  study  of  anatomy  with  animals,  as  they  often  have  a 
simpler  and  more  easily  accessible  organization  than  man,  with  whom, 
moreover,  animal  dissections  offer  interesting  possibilities  of  comparison. 
He  submits  a  comprehensive  plan  of  organization  for  the  entire  animal 
kingdom,  and  even  extends  his  interest  to  the  invertebrates.  He  also  discusses 
the  anatomy  of  plants.  His  special  zootomical  investigations,  which  com- 
prise the  fourth  section  of  his  work,  actually  consist  of  a  miscellany  of  notes 
on  the  anatomy  of  a  number  of  different  animal  forms;  he  never  records  the 
results  of  a  radical  anatomical  study  of  any  particular  animal.  The  chapter 
entitled  "Tetrapodographia'  recounts  scattered  observations  on  the  anatomy 
of  domestic  animals  in  particular,  but  also  of  the  fox,  the  hare,  the  mole, 
the  tortoise,  and  the  hedgehog.  The  "Ornithograpbia"  contains  similar  in- 
formation on  birds  and  a  special  comparative  study  of  their  feet;  details 
(mostly  external)  are  given  of  insects  and  spiders,  and  thif  zootomical  hand- 
book closes  with  a  chapter  on  fishes,  of  which  the  ink-fish  are  dealt  with  in 
greater  detail.  The  last  section  of  the  work  consists  of  an  account  of  the 
technique  of  the  subject;  the  usual  dissecting  instruments  are  described,  and 
even  the  use  of  the  magnifying-glass  is  recommended. 

The  title  of  the  book,  Zootomia  Democritea,  testifies  to  the  tendency  of 
the  work  from  beginning  to  end  —  antipathy  to  Aristotle,  a  feeling  which 
had  been  inculcated  into  Severino  in  Campanella's  school.  In  the  first 
chapter  he  sets  up  the  observation  of  nature  in  opposition  to  the  theories  of 
Aristotle  —  the  same  system  of  natural  observation  on  which  Democritus 
laid  so  much  stress.  Severino  does  not  succeed,  however,  in  creating  any  fresh 
conception  of  natural  phenomena  in  the  place  of  the  Aristotelean,  and  so, 
like  Campanella,  he  has  to  a  great  extent  to  fall  back  upon  the  mediaeval 
schoolmen,  whose  deductive  method  of  argument  and  proof  he  employs  in 
his  zootomical  studies. 

The  death-blow  to  Aristotle's  biological  theories  was  destined  to  come 
from  quite  a  different  quarter;  curiously  enough,  from  a  man  who  had  the 
greatest  respect  for  his  teaching,  but  who  at  the  same  time  established  cer- 
tain facts  which  rendered  it  impossible  for  him  to  follow  it. 


CHAPTER    XIV 

THE  DISCOVERY  OF  THE  CIRCULATION  OF  THE  BLOOD 

I.      Harvey's  Predecessors 
Galen  s  system  of  blood-movement 

BIOLOGICAL  RESEARCH  Under  the  Renaissance,  as  the  above  narrative 
shows,  considerably  widened  the  knowledge  of  animate  nature.  The 
progress  achieved  was  particularly  great  in  the  anatomical  sphere- 
Vesalius  and  his  school  contributed  not  only  to  human,  but  also  to  animal 
anatomy  a  wealth  of  new  facts  which  put  the  knowledge  of  classical  antiquity 
completely  in  the  shade.  But  as  regards  their  general  conception  of  nature 
these  research-workers  remained  entirely  on  the  ground  that  had  been  broken 
by  Aristotle  and  Galen.  Now,  however,  these  newly-won  facts  could  not  be 
reconciled  to  the  old  system;  the  same  thing  had  happened  to  Copernicus 
and  Galileo  in  regard  to  astronomy.  A  definite  break  away  from  the  ancient 
ideas  of  life  was  inevitable.  In  one  field  in  particular  was  the  influence  of  the 
ancient  system  fated  -  regarding  the  idea  of  the  movement  of  the  blood  in 
the  body  and  its  importance  to  life.  Hippocrates,  Aristotle,  and  Galen  had 
all  held  the  same  views  on  the  heart  and  the  vessels  of  the  body  in  so  far  as 
they  took  the  most  important  qualities  of  the  blood  to  be  the  "vital  spirits" 
which  it  was  thought  to  contain;  and  in  face  of  the  speculations  on  these 
spirits     the  study  of  the  movements  of  the  blood  in  the  veins  was  sadly 
neglected.  Galen,  who  among  the  biologists  of  antiquity  had  the  richest 
experimental  material  at  his  disposal,  had  worked  up  into  a  systematic 
whole  all  the  knowledge  of  the  vascular  system  which  classical  antiquity 
had  accumulated.  He  had,  as  will  be  remembered,  succeeded  in  destroying  the 
old  illusion  that  the  arteries  and  the  left  ventricle  of  the  heart  contained  air; 
he  found  in  them  a  kind  of  blood  which  he  believed  to  have  acquired  its' 
light-red  colour  from  the  pneuma,  the  half-mysterious  life-spirit,  which  it 
contained.  The  pneuma  was  conveyed  to  the  blood  in  the  arteries  from  the 
air,  which  was  introduced  by  inhalation  into  the  lungs  and  thence  to  the 
left  ventricle  of  the  heart.  The  non-pneuma-conveying  blood  —  the  venous 
blood  —  had  its  centre  in  the  liver,  where  it  was  formed  out  of  food  from 
the  digestive  canal.  From  the  liver  the  blood  was  conveyed  through  the 
veins  partly  out  into  the  body,  in  which  it  was  converted,  by  a  process  that 
was  not  very  clearly  explained,  into  "flesh,;*  and  partly  to  the  right  heart- 

io8 


o 

eq 

Q 

u 

Pi 
w 
1-1 
u 

w 


o 
K-1 

0 
si 
O 
W 

o 


> 

M 


RENAISSANCE  109 

chamber,  from  which  "soot"  was  given  off  through  the  pulmonary  arteries; 
the  wall  between  the  right  and  the  left  ventricles  was  full  of  fine  pores, 
through  which  the  blood  oozed  from  the  right  to  the  left  side,  to  be  '  'cleansed" 
by  the  action  of  the  pneuma.  Galen  had  but  vague  ideas  as  to  the  movement 
of  the  blood  in  the  vessels;  in  the  veins,  at  any  rate,  the  blood  moved,  accord- 
ing to  his  notion,  alternately  in  both  directions.  Such  was  Galen's  theory 
of  the  blood-vessels  and  their  contents,  and  in  this  form  it  was  still  accepted 
by  the  great  anatomists  of  the  sixteenth  century.  All  its  vagueness  and  many 
contradictions  would  undoubtedly  have  been  realized  long  before  had  not  the 
blood-vessel  system  of  old  been  considered  the  very  centre  of  life  itself; 
the  mysterious  pneuma  was  only  one  side  of  this  blood's  specific  life-content; 
the  different  kinds  of  soul  that  man  was  believed  to  possess  —  the  "vegeta- 
tive," with  the  liver  as  its  organ,  and  the  "animal"  in  the  heart  —  were 
also  intimately  connected  with  the  blood  and  through  it  affected  the  entire 
body.^  Speculation  about  these  components  in  the  organism  certainly  did  not 
make  the  conception  of  the  vascular  system  any  clearer;  moreover,  it  en- 
tailed the  risk  that  any  critical  discussion  of  these  organs  might  be  inter- 
preted as  an  attempt  to  call  into  question  the  immortal  soul  of  man,  which 
would  inevitably  have  involved  the  scientific  student  in  trouble  with  the 
theologians  and  the  Inquisition.  Typical  in  this  respect  is  Vesalius's  attitude 
regarding  the  pores  in  the  dividing  wall  between  the  right  and  the  left 
heart-chambers;  he  could  not  find  any  trace  of  them,  but  cautiously  adds 
that  all  the  same  the  blood  might  perhaps  be  able  to  ooze  through  the  wall 
itself.  His  pupils  adopted  the  same  cautious  attitude  on  this  point,  particu- 
larly Fabrizio,  the  discoverer  of  the  venous  valves. 

To  attack  the  traditional  theory  of  the  blood-vessels  was  thus  a  task 
that  required  courage.  The  man  who  was  the  first  to  grapple  with  an  at- 
tempt to  reform  one  detail  of  the  old  theory  was  in  fact  well  qualified  in  that 
respect,  a  man  whose  whole  life  had  been  spent  in  a  struggle  against  time- 
honoured  ideas  and  who  was  at  last  to  die  for  his  principles.  This  was  the 
well-known  religious  enthusiast  and  martyr,  Michael  Servetus. 

Miguel  Servet  y  Reves,  which  was  his  real  name,  was  born  at  Vil- 
lanueva  in  north  Spain,  of  noble  parents.  The  date  of  his  birth  is  not  known 
for  certain  (1509  or  1511);  how  he  spent  his  youth  is  also  unknown.  It  was 
apparently  at  an  early  age,  however,  that  he  experienced  that  restlessness  of 
spirit  which  throughout  his  life  made  it  impossible  for  him  to  settle  to  any- 
thing permanent  or  find  any  definite  mission  in  life.  He  became  one  of  those 
passionate,  revolutionary,  and  at  the  same  time  deeply  mystical  enthusiasts 
who  were  particularly  in  evidence  during  the  Renaissance.  Having  visited 

'  The  theory  that  the  soul,  not  only  of  man,  but  also  of  animals,  is  in  the  blood  occurs 
in  the  Old  Testament:  "Only  be  sure  that  thou  eat  not  the  blood:  for  the  blood  is  the  life;  and 
'■hou  mayest  not  eat  the  life  with  the  flesh"  (Deuteronomy  xii.  2.3). 


no  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

several  places  in  Germany  and  Italy,  he  settled  down  in  Strassburg  and  there 
published  his  first  treatise,  De  trinltatis  erroribus,  in  which  he  recorded  the 
results  of  his  mystical  religious  speculations.  He  disapproved  of  infant 
baptism  and  expressed  a  view  of  the  Trinity  which  was  regarded  as  Arian. 
The  book  evoked  a  storm  of  bitter  criticism  from  both  Catholic  and  Protes- 
tant theologians;  Server  had  to  flee  from  Strassburg  and  subsequently  re- 
appeared under  a  different  name.  In  Lyons  he  found  refuge  with  a  physician, 
who  inspired  him  with  a  taste  for  medicine,  and  in  order  to  continue  his 
studies  he  moved  to  Paris  and  there  practised  anatomy  with  Vesalius.  At 
the  same  time,  characteristically  enough,  he  lectured  to  the  students  on 
astrology.  His  theories  of  the  influence  of  the  heavenly  bodies  upon  the  health 
again  brought  him  into  trouble  with  the  theologians  and  he  had  to  flee  from 
Paris.  In  the  city  of  Vienne,  on  the  Rhone,  he  found  employment  as  a  phy- 
sician and  spent  there  a  few  peaceful  and  happy  years.  During  that  period  he 
recorded  the  results  of  his  continued  theological  speculations  in  a  book  en- 
titled Christianismi  restitutio.  He  attempted  by  correspondence  to  win  over  to 
his  views  the  reformer  Calvin,  but  was  rebuffed.  When,  in  spite  of  this,  he 
dared  to  publish  his  book  anonymously  in  Vienne  and  concluded  it  with  a 
venomous  attack  on  Calvin,  the  latter  became  furious  and  had  the  author 
brought  before  the  Inquisition  in  Vienne.  Server  was  cast  into  prison,  but 
managed  to  escape,  and  this  time  sought  refuge  in  Geneva,  probably  in  order 
to  co-operate  with  the  anti-Calvinistic  party  which  was  just  then  planning 
an  attack  on  the  despotic  reformer.  Calvin,  however,  was  on  his  guard; 
Server  was  arrested  and  Calvin  seized  the  opportunity  offered  by  the  trial  of 
this  sectarian,  so  hated  by  the  whole  Christian  community,  to  strengthen  his 
position.  Having  obtained  the  consent  of  several  Protestant  Church  councils, 
the  court  at  Geneva  condemned  Server  to  be  burnt  at  the  stake,  and  the  ver- 
dict was  carried  out  on  the  xyth  October  1553,  to  the  eternal  shame  of  Prot- 
estantism. Shortly  before,  the  Catholic  Inquisition  in  Vienne  had  caused 
Server's  portrait  to  be  burnt  in  the  absence  of  Server  himself.  Through  his 
death,  however.  Server  won  such  renown  as  neither  his  personality  nor  his 
writings  in  themselves  warranted;  the  Catholics  in  particular  have  in  latter 
times  honoured  his  memory,  in  order  to  annoy  the  Calvinists.  Statues  have 
been  erected  to  him  in  both  Paris  and  Madrid. 

Servets  investigation  of  the  puhnonary  system 
Servet's  principal  work,^  On  the  Restoration  of  Christianity,  is,  as  its  title  im- 
plies, purely  theological  and  discusses  from  a  mystical  spiritualistic  point 

^  Of  the  original  edition  of  Servet's  Christianismi  restitutio  there  are,  as  far  as  we  know, 
only  three  copies  in  existence;  one  in  Vienna,  one  mutilated  copy  in  Paris,  and  one  defective 
copy  in  Edinburgh.  An  attempt  to  republish  the  work  in  England  in  the  seventeen-twenties 
fell  through  owing  to  the  opposition  of  the  ecclesiastical  authorities.  In  1790  a  new  edition  was 
at  last  published  in  Nuremberg;  even  this  edition  is  somewhat  rare. 


RENAISSANCE  III 

of  view  the  relation  of  God  to  the  world  and  man.  Every  conceivable  prob- 
lem of  life  is  drawn  into  discussion  in  this  connexion  —  jurisprudence  and 
statesmanship  as  well  as  astronomy,  physics,  and  medicine.  In  the  discussion 
on  the  Holy  Spirit  he  points  out  that  this  cannot  be  properly  comprehended 
without  knowledge  of  the  spirit  of  man,  and  the  spirit  of  man  in  turn,  if  it 
is  to  be  rightly  understood,  requires  a  knowledge  of  the  human  body.  In 
this  way  Server  arrives  at  a  discussion  of  the  structure  and  function  of  the 
human  body,  and  in  particular  the  part  played  by  the  blood,  which  is  so 
vital  in  its  spiritual  aspect.  And  here  he  pronounces  the  dictum  that  has 
given  him,  the  religious  idealist,  a  place  in  the  history  of  biology;  this  was 
his  exposition  of  the  course  of  the  pulmonary  circulation.  In  order  to  gain 
an  idea  of  the  relation  of  the  spiritual  to  the  physical  life  we  must,  says 
Server,  realize  the  three  vital  elements  in  the  body,  which  are:  the  blood, 
with  its  seat  in  the  liver  and  the  veins;  " spiritus  vitalis,"  in  the  heart  and 
the  arteries;  and  "  spiritus  animalisy'  which  is  a  ray  of  light  and  is  situated 
in  the  brain  and  the  nerves.  In  all  these  dwells  the  power  of  God's  spirit. 
The  vital  spirit  is  communicated  by  the  heart  to  the  liver,  for  in  the  heart 
dwells  first  of  all  the  spirit  communicated  by  God,  as  we  see  from  the  embry- 
onic life,  in  which  the  heart  is  the  first  point  that  lives.  On  the  other  hand, 
the  liver  provides  through  the  blood  material  to  the  spirit,  which  is  formed 
by  the  union  of  the  finest  components  of  the  blood  with  the  inhaled  air.  This 
union  takes  place  in  the  lungs,  to  which  the  blood  is  conveyed  from  the 
right  heart-chamber,  to  be  conveyed  thence,  purged  of  soot  through  exhala- 
tion and  mingled  with  inhaled  air,  back  to  the  left  heart-chamber.  That  the 
blood  does  not,  as  is  commonly  imagined,  pass  through  the  heart  wall  is 
proved  not  only  by  the  latter's  solid  consistency,  but  also  by  the  powerful 
structure  of  the  pulmonary  veins,  which  cannot  be  explained  simply  by  their 
function  of  feeding  the  lungs.  All  this  is  really  obvious,  concludes  Server, 
from  the  observations  recorded  by  Galen,  if  only  one  understands  how  to 
interpret  them  aright. 

The  strange,  strongly  spiritualistic  physiology  which  Server  expounds 
in  his  description  of  the  importance  of  the  blood,  above  referred  to,  is  in 
itself  nothing  peculiar  to  him;  on  the  contrary,  it  recurs  often  in  the  authors 
of  the  Renaissance  and  even  of  the  seventeenth  century;  in  Swedenborg,  too, 
we  find  a  similar  method  of  speculation.  Indeed,  Server  reminds  us  of  the 
latter  in  having  arrived  at  his  theories  by  way  of  speculation  rather  than 
through  his  own  observations.  True,  he  had  dissected,  as  mentioned  above, 
and  that  too  under  Vesalius  himself,  though  he  makes  no  reference  to  his 
experiences  in  that  line,  but  tries  to  give  a  correct  interpretation  of  Galen. 
What  in  these  circumstances  is  surprising  is  that  he  gives  such  a  clear  idea 
of  the  pulmonary  circulation  —  all  the  more  so  as  his  view  of  the  blood- 
vessel system  is  otherwise  purely  Galenian,  with  the  liver  as  the  principal 


111.  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

organ  for  the  blood  and  the  veins  emanating  therefrom.  Nor  indeed  was  it 
his  object  to  gain  any  knowledge  of  the  structure  of  the  human  body  for  any 
biological  or  medical  purpose;  just  as  his  method  was  speculative,  so  his 
purpose  was  exclusively  mystical-theological  and  he  thus  was  content  with 
the  old  tradition  as  it  stood,  except  in  that  one  point  in  which  it  was  not 
consistent  with  his  metaphysical  construction  of  thought.  However,  he  is 
undoubtedly  the  first  to  expound  a  theory  of  the  pulmonary  circulation 
agreeing  with  that  confirmed  by  the  research  of  later  times. 

It  is  hardly  to  be  supposed  that  a  treatise  which  was  prohibited  by  con- 
temporary and  later  governments,  and  to  the  best  of  their  powers  suppressed, 
would  succeed  in  exercising  any  great  influence  on  the  progress  of  science; 
it  was,  in  fact,  to  be  more  than  a  century  and  a  half  before  anyone  drew  atten- 
tion to  Servet's  contribution  to  the  discussion  of  the  circulatory  system. 
Nevertheless,  it  would  appear  that  Servet's  ideas  did  after  all  have  some 
influence  on  his  contemporaries,  since  during  the  latter  half  of  the  sixteenth 
century  one  comes  across  in  many  authors  statements,  or  at  any  rate  hints,  as 
to  the  blood-circulation  between  the  right  and  left  ventricles  through  the 
lungs.  One  or  two  of  these  writers,  who  had  some  influence  on  the  final  solu- 
tion of  the  problem  of  the  movement  of  the  blood,  should  be  mentioned  here. 

Realdo  Columbus,  Vesalius's  pupil  and  immediate  successor  in  the  chair 
of  anatomy  in  Padua,  to  whom  we  have  referred  above,  may  claim  to  be 
named  among  the  forerunners  in  this  field,  as  he  is  the  only  author  cited  by 
Harvey,  the  great  pioneer  of  research  work  on  the  blood.  Columbus  in  his 
work  on  anatomy  devotes  a  chapter  to  the  vascular  system.  Here  he  presents 
the  traditional  theory  of  the  liver  as  the  centre  of  the  venous  system  and  the 
true  blood-forming  organ,  from  which  the  blood  is  conveyed  to  the  diff^erent 
parts  of  the  body.  The  arterial  system  originates  in  the  heart.  Its  right  and 
left  ventricles  are  separated  by  an  intermediate  wall,  which,  contrary  to  the 
common  assumption,  is  impenetrable;  from  the  right  side  the  blood  is  con- 
veyed to  the  lungs,  where  it  is  mixed  with  air  and,  thus  diluted,  is  conducted 
back  to  the  right  side  of  the  heart.  This,  he  adds,  no  one  has  hitherto  ob- 
served or  described,  but  it  is  none  the  less  true  and  can  be  verified  on  experi- 
mental subjects,  whether  alive  or  dead.  Columbus's  work  was  published  in 
1559  —  that  is,  six  years  after  Servet's.  There  have  been  lively  discussions 
whether  both  arrived  at  the  same  conclusion  independently,  and,  if  not,  of 
which  borrowed  from  the  other.  The  question  can  of  course  never  be  defi- 
nitely decided,  but  it  is  probable  that  Servet,  who  indisputably  has  the  prior 
claim  on  the  point,  in  some  way  influenced  Columbus;  the  latter  presumably 
read  the  dangerous  heretical  treatise,  which  he  dared  not  quote  even  if  he 
had  desired  to  do  so.  There  is  no  doubt,  however,  that  Columbus,  in  a  far 
greater  degree  than  Servet,  confirmed  his  statement  by  observation  and 
experiment. 


RENAISSANCE  I13 

There  was  another  whose  opinions  on  the  question  of  the  circulation 
of  the  blood  attracted  far  greater  attention  than  the  above-mentioned  con- 
tribution to  the  subject.  This  was  the  Italian  botanist  and  physician  Ce- 
sALPiNO,  who  is  still  to  this  day  extolled  by  his  countrymen  as  the  true 
discoverer  of  the  circulation  of  the  blood.  Andrea  Cesalpino  was  born  at 
Arezzo  in  Tuscany  in  15 19.  He  studied  philosophy  and  medicine  at  Pisa, 
the  latter  under  Columbus,  who  was  called  to  that  city  from  Padua.  At  the 
age  of  thirty  he  became  a  doctor  of  medicine  and  shortly  afterwards  professor 
of  pharmacology  at  Pisa.  In  this  capacity  he  devoted  special  attention  to 
the  study  of  botany  and  is  reputed  one  of  the  pioneers  of  that  science.  His 
contributions  in  this  field  will  be  dealt  with  in  another  connexion.  In  his 
old  age  he  was  summoned  to  Rome,  where  he  was  appointed  body-physician 
to  the  Pope,  and  where  he  died  in  1605. 

Cesalpino  was  a  man  of  manifold  interest;  besides  botany  and  pharma- 
cology he  studied  anatomy,  mineralogy,  and  metallurgy,  but  he  was  above 
all  a  natural  philosopher  in  the  true  Aristotelean  spirit.  His  theoretical  spec- 
ulations he  published  in  a  work  with  the  characteristic  title  of  Peripatetic 
Problems.  In  this  book  he  endeavours  to  find  a  general  explanation  of  nature 
along  Aristotelean  lines;  in  the  purely  philosophical  aspect  of  his  conclu- 
sions he  goes  beyond  his  master  by  deriving  both  form  and  matter  from  a 
single  supreme  principle,  but  as  a  physicist  he  takes  his  stand  on  the  old 
ground,  with  celestial  spheres  and  circular  planetary  orbits,  heaviness  and 
lightness  as  a  quality  of  bodies  —  everything  in  fact  which  Galileo  was 
intent  on  demolishing.^  Even  his  biology,  the  subject  of  the  fifth  book,  en- 
tirely follows  the  lines  of  Aristotle.  It  opens  with  the  purely  mediasval  scho- 
lastic thesis  that  if  the  life  in  a  being  is  one  and  indivisible,  the  body  must 
also  be  one  and  its  centre  one,  whence  life  emanates  to  the  rest  of  animate 
things.  Plants  and  lower  animals,  which  are  able  to  live  even  when  cut  up 
into  bits,  require  no  such  centre  point,  but  in  sanguineous  animals  the  heart 
without  doubt  constitutes  this  centre  point  —  the  heart,  which  is  the  first 
to  begin  to  live  and  the  last  to  die,  and  which  is  situated  in  the  centre  of 
the  body.  Thereupon  Cesalpino  endeavours,  in  a  polemic  against  Galen  inter- 
larded with  quotations  from  Aristotle,  to  prove  that  the  veins  originate  in 
the  heart  and  not  in  the  liver,  and  that  the  nerves  likewise  originate  in  the 
heart  and  not  in  the  brain,  the  latter  point  being  proved,  i7Jter  alia,  by  the 
fact  that  happiness  and  grief  are  felt  first  in  the  heart,  while  the  function 
of  the  brain  is  to  cool  the  blood,  like  the  receptacle  in  a  distilling  appara- 
tus. By  thus  swearing  to  the  truth  of  his  master's  word,  both  good  and 
evil,  Cesalpino  at  any  rate  makes  this  point  in  regard  to  the  circulation  of 

^  Curiously  enough,  even  Cesalpino,  in  spite  of  his  loyal  Aristoteleanism,  fell  into  the 
hands  of  the  Inquisition,  but  he  saved  himself  by  his  dialectical  cleverness,  and  perhaps  also 
owing  to  his  being  in  the  papal  service. 


114  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

the  blood,  that  the  heart  is  actually  the  centre  of  the  vascular  system.  And 
in  regard  to  the  relation  of  the  lungs  to  the  heart,  he  maintains  with  his 
teacher  Columbus  that  the  blood  passes  through  the  lungs  from  the  right  to 
the  left  side  of  the  heart  —  a  process  which  he  for  the  first  time  calls  cir- 
culation. But  his  servility  to  the  authority  of  Aristotle  prevents  him  from 
taking  advantage  of  either  his  precursors'  or  his  own  progress  in  this  field 
of  research.  He  dares  not  abandon  the  theory  of  the  pores  in  the  heart  wall, 
but,  on  the  contrary,  admits  that  some  of  the  blood  goes  that  way;  he  ob- 
serves that  when  a  vein  is  tied,  it  fills  below  and  not  above  the  ligature, 
but  he  does  not  venture  to  draw  the  conclusion  that  the  blood-stream  in 
the  veins  always  leads  to  the  heart  —  this  he  believes  takes  place  during 
sleep,  but  not  in  a  waking  condition  —  and  so  the  existence  of  the  "vital 
spirit"  in  the  blood  naturally  takes  the  first  place  in  his  investigations.  His 
ponderous  and  involved  presentation  of  his  case  —  vague,  too,  in  compari- 
son with  Servet's  brief  and  explicit  style  —  has  enabled  his  admirers  to 
interpret  his  statements  as  it  suits  their  purposes,  but  just  as  none  of  his 
contemporaries  saw  in  him  one  who  had  revolutionized  knowledge  of  the 
vascular  system  —  a  fact  which  he  himself,  Catholic  and  papal  favourite  as 
he  was,  would  hardly  have  dared  to  admit  —  so  there  must  in  truth  be  a 
partisan  and  chauvinistic  spirit  in  those  of  posterity  who  would  ascribe  to 
him  the  honour  of  an  idea  which  he  himself  neither  clearly  expressed  nor 
ever  definitely  claimed. 


X.   Harvey 

Besides  those  of  whom  we  have  given  account  above,  there  were  during 
the  Renaissance,  as  has  been  said,  quite  a  large  number  of  anatomical  writers 
who  made  a  study  of  the  construction  and  function  of  the  vascular  system, 
in  vain  attempts  to  bring  order  out  of  the  chaos  to  which  the  inaccurate 
conception  of  the  ancient  biologists  had  reduced  the  problem.  The  necessity 
of  a  solution  was  generally  acknowledged;  several  had  been  on  the  right 
road,  but  had  stopped  prematurely.  Then  William  Harvey  took  the  decisive 
step  and  solved  the  hard  problem  in  one  stride. 

William  Harvey  was  born  at  Folkestone,  on  the  south  coast  of  England, 
in  the  year  1578,  of  respected  and  well-to-do  parents,  who  gave  their  children 
a  sound  education.  Having  taken  a  philosophical  degree  at  Cambridge, 
Harvey  made  a  number  of  journeys  and  eventually  came  to  Padua,  where 
at  that  time  Fabrizio  had  begun  to  attract  pupils  from  far  and  near.  Harvey 
joined  them,  and  after  four  years  of  study  took  the  degree  of  doctor  of 
medicine.  Returning  to  England,  he  settled  down  in  London  and  started  a 
medical  practice.  He  practised  in  hospitals,  was  elected  a  member  of  the 


RENAISSANCE  II5 

London  College  of  Physicians,  and  there  gained  such  a  reputation  that  he 
was  commissioned  to  give  lectures  to  his  colleagues.  Eventually  he  was  ap- 
pointed court  physician  to  King  James  I  and  later  to  King  Charles  I.  After- 
wards he  spent  many  years  in  peaceful  and  uninterrupted  research  work  and 
in  the  duties  of  his  medical  practice  in  London,  but  then  the  great  Civil 
War  broke  out  and  Harvey  accompanied  his  king  in  his  flight  from  London, 
while  his  house  was  plundered  and  his  collections  destroyed.  He  was  then 
made  a  professor  at  Oxford,  which  was  the  headquarters  of  the  King;  when 
this  city  was  also  captured  by  the  Parliamentary  army  after  Charles's  final  de- 
feat, Harvey,  then  sixty-eight  years  old,  had  to  retire  into  private  life.  Fortu- 
nately he  possessed  private  means  and  was  also  supported  by  his  brother, 
a  wealthy  London  merchant,  so  that  his  old  age  was  free  from  care,  and  at 
the  same  time  he  retained  the  deep  respect  of  his  countrymen  and  colleagues. 
A  stroke  brought  his  life  to  a  sudden  and  peaceful  close  in  the  year  1657. 
He  left  his  fortune  by  will  to  the  College,  whose  leading  personality  he  had 
been  during  his  lifetime,  and  ever  since  his  death  the  College  has  continued 
to  celebrate  his  memory,  an  annual  festival  being  held  in  London  in  his 
honour.  A  fine  monument  has  been  erected  over  his  grave. 

Harvey's  ivork  on  the  circulation 
The  work  in  which  Harvey  expounded  his  new  idea  of  the  circulation  of 
the  blood  was  published  in  i6i8  at  Frankfurt  am  Main  in  the  form  of  a 
quarto  volume  containing  seventy-two  pages.  Harvey,  however,  had  spent 
his  whole  time,  ever  since,  as  a  youth,  he  received  his  first  lesson  in  anatomy 
in  Fabrizio's  school,  in  working  out  the  ideas  which  were  recorded  in  this 
modest  volume.  There  are  still  extant  the  lecture  notes  dating  from  1616, 
in  which  are  expressed  some  of  the  thoughts  which  twelve  years  later  as- 
sumed their  final  form,  and  it  has  thus  been  possible  to  check  the  careful 
research,  the  mature  consideration,  on  which  the  work  is  based  and  which 
shows  itself  in  the  masterly  style,  at  the  same  time  concise  and  explicit,  in 
which  not  a  word  seems  superfluous.  After  giving  an  account  of  the  old  tradi- 
tional theories  on  the  subject,  in  which  he  sharply  brings  out  their  defects, 
Harvey  presents  his  own  observations  on  the  movement  of  the  heart.  Ac- 
cording to  the  old  theory  the  walls  of  the  heart  were  not  muscular  and  the 
dilatation  of  the  heart  was  its  most  important  function;  by  this  means  the 
blood  was  conveyed  from  the  veins  into  the  heart.  By  careful  experiments, 
of  which  he  gives  an  account,  Harvey  found  that  the  heart  is  muscular  and 
that,  on  the  contrary,  its  regular  contraction  is  its  most  important  move- 
ment, which  drives  the  blood  forward  —  that  is,  out  into  the  blood-vessels 
—  just  as  it  is  likewise  during  this  movement  that  the  heart  beats  against 
the  thorax.  In  this  movement  not  only  the  ventricles  of  the  heart  take  part, 
but  also  its  vestibule,  the  significance  of  which  Harvey  rightly  emphasizes 
for  the  first  time.  He  then  gives  an  account  of  the  course  of  the  blood  from 


Il6  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

the  right  to  the  left  side  of  the  heart  through  the  lungs,  ar.d  in  this  he  ac- 
knowledges the  services  of  Columbus  in  his  explanation  of  this  phenomenon. 
With  regard  to  the  part  played  by  the  lungs  and  the  air  in  this  circulation 
he  has  not  much  to  add  to  the  hypotheses  of  his  predecessors.  After  having 
thus  described  the  small  circulation  Harvey  proceeds  to  a  presentation  of 
the  blood's  movement  in  the  body  itself  and  it  is  here  that  he  brings  out 
his  most  daring  originality.  According  to  the  old  theory,  food  was  converted 
in  the  liver  into  blood,  which  was  driven  through  the  veins  partly  to  the 
heart,  in  order  to  receive  the  "  spiritus  vitalis,"  and  partly  into  the  body.  To 
this  theory  Harvey  opposes  a  mathematical  calculation;  if  the  human  heart 
contains  two  ounces  of  blood  and  gives  sixty-five  beats  to  the  minute,  then 
it  drives  in  less  than  one  minute  ten  pounds  of  blood  out  into  the  body. 
Such  a  quantity  of  blood  cannot  incessantly  arise  from  the  food  consumed, 
but  it  must  be  assumed  that  the  same  quantity  of  blood  incessantly  circu- 
lates in  the  body;  it  is  driven  out  through  the  arteries  and  returns  through 
the  veins.  Harvey  then  collects  a  quantity  of  evidence  in  proof  of  this  con- 
clusion from  the  relation  of  the  arteries  and  the  veins  in  the  body.  He  in- 
vestigates the  arterial  pulse  both  in  normal  individuals  and  in  those  having 
calcinated  veins;  he  opens  a  live  serpent  and  ties  up  first  the  vetia  cava  and 
then  the  aorta;  while  the  vein  is  emptied  between  the  heart  and  the  ligature 
and  swells  up  on  the  other  side,  the  contrary  is  true  of  the  aorta.  He  studies 
the  venous  valves  in  a  man's  arm,  which  were  discovered  by  Fabrizio,  and 
shows  how  they  swell  below  a  ligature;  he  severs  a  vein  and  an  artery  par- 
allel to  it  and  shows  that  the  blood  flows  from  the  different  ends  of  the 
wound.  On  these  and  several  other  grounds,  deduced  from  the  study  of  every 
possible  animal  form,  he  draws  the  conclusion  that  the  arteries  convey  the 
blood  from  the  heart  out  into  the  body;  there  it  is  transmitted  into  the  rami- 
fications of  the  veins  and  flows  from  these  into  the  principal  vein  and  thence 
back  to  the  heart.  The  arterial  blood,  he  considers,  provides  nourishment  for 
the  body,  while  that  of  the  veins  is  impure.  How  the  transition  between  the 
arterial  and  venous  system  takes  place  he  could  not  explain;  the  capillary 
system  he  was  unable  to  distinguish,  not  having  access  to  a  microscope,  and 
he  therefore  assumed  that  some  kind  of  ramified  hollows  formed  the  con- 
necting link  between  the  two.  Another  weak  point  in  his  theory  was  that 
he  could  never  find  a  satisfactory  explanation  of  how  the  components  of 
the  food  are  converted  into  blood,  but  he  had  to  be  content  with  the  old 
hypothesis  that  the  liver  was  the  medium  in  this  process.  He  lived  to  see 
the  discovery  by  others  of  the  lymphatic  and  thoracic  ducts,  but  then  he 
was  no  longer  capable  of  realizing  how  well  these  experiences  complemented 
his  own  discoveries;  he  desired  to  know  nothing  about  them  and  on  this 
point  adhered  to  the  old  theory. 

If  we  compare  Harvey's  account  of  the  circulation  of  the  blood  with 


RENAISSANCE  II7 

the  old  vascular  theory,  we  find  fundamental  differences  in  the  two  concep- 
tions, both  anatomically  and  physiologically.  According  to  the  old  theory 
the  heart  was  not  a  muscular  organ;  it  dilated  purely  passively  and  allowed 
the  blood  to  enter  in  order  to  be  provided  with  "  vital  spirit,"  this  being  the 
primary  life-function  of  the  heart,  if  it  were  not  also,  as  Aristotle  and 
his  followers  until  Cesalpino  held,  the  centre  of  intelligence.  Again,  the 
blood  moved  of  itself  owing  to  the  specifically  living  qualities  which  the 
" spirifus"  lent  it.  Harvey,  on  the  other  hand,  proves  that  the  movement  of 
the  blood  is  due  to  the  purely  mechanical  function  of  the  heart:  the  heart's 
muscular  contraction  propels  the  blood  out  into  the  blood-vessels,  through 
the  arteries  out  into  the  body,  thence  back  to  the  heart  through  the  veins, 
and  so  farther  through  the  lungs.  In  this  contrast  lies,  one  may  say,  the  great 
ditference  between  the  ancient  and  the  modern  biological  conception.  Even 
Harvey's  way  of  producing  his  proofs  is  purely  modern;  while  Servet  still 
refers  back  to  philosophical  speculations  and  the  interpretation  of  classical 
authors,  Harvey  propounds  a  purely  mathematical  calculus  on  the  volume 
of  the  heart  and  vascular  system  and  continues  to  prove  his  thesis  by  means 
of  observations  and  experiments  on  a  number  of  both  higher  and  lower  ani- 
mal forms.  He  thus  fulfils  in  the  sphere  of  biology  the  requirement  which 
his  contemporary  Bacon  laid  down  as  a  principle  of  science:  to  explain  na- 
ture by  experience  based  upon  observations  and  experiment.  And  even  Gali- 
leo's fundamental  principle  governing  natural  research  —  to  measure  what 
can  be  measured  and  to  make  measurable  what  cannot  be  measured  —  is 
applied  to  living  nature  by  Harvey  for  the  first  time.  Galileo  also  thought 
that  science  can  only  explain  how  the  forces  of  nature  operate;  what  their 
innate  essential  quality  is  will  never  be  known  under  any  circumstance.  In 
his  explanation  of  the  circulation  of  the  blood  Harvey  does  indeed  fulfil  the 
first  half  of  this  principle;  on  the  other  hand,  by  adhering  to  the  ancient 
belief  in  the  vital  spirits  in  the  blood  he  remains  in  his  theoretical  concep- 
tions entirely  on  ancient  ground. 

On  the  generation  of  animals 
This  conservatism  of  Harvey's  displays  itself  conspicuously  in  a  work  which 
he  published  in  his  old  age:  Exercitationes  de  generatione  animalium  (165 1). 
Like  his  work  on  the  circulation  of  the  blood,  this  book  is  the  fruit  of  many 
years'  labour,  but  in  contrast  to  the  former  it  is  somewhat  lengthy  and  far 
less  perfect  in  form.  In  this  Harvey  gives  a  comparative  account  of  the  em- 
bryonic development  in  higher  and  lower  animal  forms.  He  is  able  here  to 
quote  as  his  precursor  his  old  teacher  Fabrizio,  and  he  does  so  with  the 
utmost  piety.  But  above  all  he  proves  himself  to  be  a  follower  of  Aristotle, 
whose  conception  of  the  true  essence  of  life  he  has  made  entirely  his  own. 
Along  Aristotelean  lines  he  endeavours  to  find  a  formal  unity  in  the  mani- 
fold aspects  of  phenomena,  as  displayed  in  the  evolution  of  the  embryo,  and 


Il8  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

he  believes  that  he  has  discovered  such  unity  in  the  egg,  out  of  which  all 
living  creatures  are  evolved.  His  dictum:  "All  animals,  even  those  that  pro- 
duce their  young  alive,  including  man  himself,  are  evolved  out  of  the  egg" 
is  well  known.  He  was  naturally  not  able  to  observe  the  eggs  of  mammals  — 
such  a  study  requires  a  microscope,  which  he  did  not  possess  —  but  he  pre- 
supposes their  existence  on  theoretical  grounds,  a  conclusion  which  was 
confirmed  long  afterwards.  Nevertheless,  he  is  loath  to  abandon  the  idea 
of  primal  generation,  though  he  limits  this  principle  to  the  lowest  animals. 
Out  of  the  egg  the  higher  animals  are  evolved  by  epigenesis,  in  that  the 
organs  are  successively  formed  out  of  the  indifferent  matter  in  the  egg,  which 
thus  constitutes,  in  harmony  with  Aristotle's  theory,  the  potentiality  out  of 
which  the  individual  is  realized.  The  lower  animals,  on  the  other  hand,  are 
evolved  by  metamorphosis,  a  direct  reconstruction  of  complete  rudiments, 
as  is  proved  especially  by  the  evolution  of  the  pupa  of  insects;  Harvey,  in 
fact,  shares  Aristotle's  belief  that  the  pupa  is  the  insect's  egg.  On  the  sub- 
ject of  reproduction  his  ideas  are  entirely  mediaeval;  the  influence  of  the 
sperm  on  the  development  of  the  embryo  he  believes  to  be  due  to  the  vital 
force  it  contains,  and  this  he  compares  with  the  secret  force  exerted  by  the 
heavenly  bodies  upon  all  life  on  the  earth.  That  this  last  work  of  Harvey's 
should  also  contain  a  mass  of  remarkable  detailed  observations  is  not  sur- 
prising; he  describes  with  unprecedented  care  the  ovary  of  the  hen  and  its 
development,  the  nourishing  of  the  chicken  in  the  egg,  and  its  growth  from 
the  very  earliest  stages;  and  of  even  greater  interest  are  the  comparisons  he 
makes  between  the  embryonic  stages  in  different  animals  —  mammals,  birds, 
and  lower  types. 

Harvey  is  without  doubt  one  of  the  most  remarkable  figures  in  the  his- 
tory of  human  culture.  His  work  is  the  most  revolutionary  that  the  develop- 
ment of  biology  has  to  show,  for  it  undermines  the  foundations  of  the  ancient 
conception  of  life  and  its  manifestations,  and  nevertheless  he  himself  retains 
this  very  conception  as  long  as  he  lives.  He  thus  brings  to  a  close  the  great 
epoch  in  the  history  of  biology  which  is  governed  by  the  ancient  conception 
of  nature  and  he  initiates  the  modern  development  in  the  sphere  of  biology, 
just  as  Galileo  does  in  that  of  physics.  How  an  entirely  new  science  of  life 
has  developed  on  the  foundations  laid  by  Harvey  will  be  shown  in  the  next 
section  of  this  work. 


PART     TWO 


BIOLOGY    IN    THE    SEVENTEENTH 
AND    EIGHTEENTH    CENTURIES 


CHAPTER    I 

THE     ORIGIN     OF    THE     MODERN     IDEA     OF     NATURE     IN     THE 
SEVENTEENTH     AND     EIGHTEENTH     CENTURIES 

CLASSICAL  ANTIQUITY  gave  fise  to  two  explanations  of  natural  phenom- 
ena, each  splendid  in  its  own  way:  that  of  Democritus  and  that  of 
Aristotle.  As  will  be  remembered,  Democritus  attempted  to  explain 
all  phenomena  in  existence,  both  physical  and  psychical,  by  the  assumption 
that  things  were  composed  of  a  mass  of  particles,  varying  in  size,  shape,  and 
movement,  whose  mutual  interrelation  caused  all  that  is  and  all  that 
happens,  all,  in  fact,  that  is  observable  or  conceivable.  The  weakness  of  this 
theory  lay  in  the  fact  that  it  gave  no  explanation  of  the  obedience  to  law 
which  experience  has  proved  beyond  any  doubt  to  exist  in  all  that  happens 
in  nature.  It  was  therefore  supplanted  by  Aristotle's  cosmic  explanation, 
which  maintained  just  this  universal  obedience  to  law,  but  based  it  upon  the 
assumption  of  a  divine  intelligence  which  governs  and  gives  form  to  what  is 
in  itself  formless  matter,  controlling  the  latter  in  various  degrees  —  less  in 
inanimate  nature,  more  in  the  animate,  and  most  in  the  celestial  spheres 
which  hold  sway  over  the  imperfect  earth.  In  animate  nature  this  force  ap- 
pears as  soul,  vital  spirit,  which  creates  higher  forms  of  existence  the  more  it 
overcomes  matter.  This  cosmic  theory,  which,  owing  to  its  logically  consis- 
tent formulation,  is  unique  in  its  greatness,  has  been  characterized  as  dynamic 
and  vitalistic  in  contrast  to  materialistic  atomism.  It  has  with  greater  reason 
been  called  aesthetic,  since  Aristotle  really  looked  upon  natural  phenomena 
from  the  point  of  view  of  an  artist  who  gives  form  to  matter;  it  has  even  been 
called  teleological,  because  according  to  it  everything  in  existence  has  a  pur- 
pose which  is  determined  by  the  governing  intelligence.  In  this  latter  charac- 
teristic we  really  find  that  quality  in  the  Aristotelean  thought-system  which 
has  proved  most  fateful  both  for  that  system  and  for  man's  conception  of 
life  in  general.  The  divine  intelligence  which  Aristotle  invented  in  order  to 
make  possible  the  assumption  of  law-bound  existence  on  purely  speculative 
grounds  became  a  welcome  ally  to  the  pious  aims  of  late  antiquity  and  still 
more  so  to  the  mediaeval  Church.  One  found  indications  of  similarity  be- 
tween it  and  the  "divine  power"  of  the  old  myths  of  creation,  and  thus 
received  an  idea  of  the  course  of  the  world,  apparently  scientific,  but  actually 
based  upon  legends  from  the  childhood  of  man. 


I2.I 


I-LZ  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

Aristoteleanism  in  alliance  ivith  the  Church 
It  was  just  on  account  of  its  semi-scientific  nature  that  it  was  extremely 
difficult  to  controvert  this  idea  with  reasons  and  proofs,  seeing  that  it  was 
at  the  same  time  cherished  by  the  authority  of  the  Church  and  protected  by 
the  latter's  powerful  resources,  both  spiritual  and  temporal.  In  the  first  part 
of  this  work  it  has  been  shown  how  the  champions  of  natural  science  during 
the  Renaissance  took  up  the  cudgels  against  Aristoteleanism,  which  was 
upheld  not  only  by  the  authority  of  the  Church,  but  also  by  the  boundless 
respect  that  that  age  entertained  for  antiquity;  how  Cusanus  and  Bruno 
asserted  the  infinity  of  cosmic  space  in  contrast  to  Aristotle's  spherical  uni- 
verse; how  Francis  Bacon  ruthlessly  exposed  the  abstract  structural  system 
of  the  ancient  philosophy  and  urged  that  research  should  be  based  on  obser- 
vations of  nature  itself;  how  Galileo,  by  means  of  observational  material 
and  mathematically  conclusive  proof,  demolished  the  theory  of  the  immu- 
table regularity  of  the  celestial  regions  and  at  the  same  time  proved  the 
purely  mechanical  obedience  to  law  of  the  phenomena  of  motion  here  on 
earth;  how  Harvey  through  his  discovery  of  the  circulation  of  the  blood 
proved  a  purely  mechanical  action  in  the  life-process  which  the  old  theory 
considered  to  be  the  centre  of  animate  life.  But  however  many  defects  could 
be  proved  against  the  old  system  in  detail,  it  nevertheless  still  remained 
unaff"ected,  owing  to  its  consistently  carried-out  construction;  it  required  an 
entirely  new  system  of  thought  in  place  of  the  old  before  the  latter  could 
definitely  break  down.  Throughout  the  seventeenth  century  keen-minded 
thinkers  set  about  creating  such  a  system,  and  the  strength  that  underlay 
Aristotle's  cosmic  idea,  its  unassailable  consistency  and  perfect  lucidity,  had 
never  been  demonstrated  so  clearly  as  now,  when,  already  condemned  to 
fall,  it  made  a  stand  against  the  assaults  which  finally  shattered  it.  A  survey 
of  this  struggle  between  Aristoteleanism  and  the  new  systems  of  thought  is 
so  much  the  more  necessary  as  an  introduction  to  the  history  of  modern  biol- 
ogy as  it  was  actually  during  this  struggle  that  not  only  the  natural  science 
of  our  own  time,  but  the  whole  idea  of  life  as  conceived  by  present-day 
humanity  in  general  came  into  being.  Nevertheless  the  modern  conception 
of  nature  by  no  means  rests  solely  upon  the  purely  mechanical  foundations 
laid  by  Galileo.  It  is  self-evident  that  in  it  there  are  very  considerable  ele- 
ments of  vanquished  Aristoteleanism.  But  besides  him  there  appeared  also 
in  opposition  to  the  latter  theory  philosophers  who  from  neo-Platonism  and 
other  similar  systems  of  ideas  adopted  a  purely  mystical  view  of  nature. 
This  too  has  possessed  its  attractive  sides  for  the  human  mind,  especially  the 
advantage  of  making  possible  a  uniform  conception  of  both  the  material 
and  the  ideal  aspects  of  existence;  during  the  Renaissance  in  particular  it  won 
many  adherents  —  Bruno  is  the  most  brilliant  example  —  and  it  has  con- 
sequently left  a  strong  impression  upon  modern  natural  science.  In  the  fol- 
lowing chapter  an  attempt  will  be  made  to  illustrate  how  these  elements  in 
the  conception  of  nature  in  our  own  time  arose. 


CHAPTER    II 

THE     MECHANICAL    N  A  T  U  R  E  -  S  Y  ST  E  M  S 

The  period  of  the  great  systems 

THE  SEVENTEENTH  CENTURY  has  been  Called  the  period  of  great  systems 
of  thought,  during  which  all  the  knowledge  that  the  Renaissance 
brought  to  light  was  summarized  and  classified.  Order  and  system 
were,  in  fact,  what  this  epoch  strove  to  create  in  every  sphere  of  life;  in 
government  the  power  was  concentrated  in  the  hands  of  despotic  princes 
who  by  a  rigorous  exercise  of  power  overcame  all  opposition  on  the  part 
of  their  subjects  and  created  ordered  forms  of  administration  instead  of  the 
universal  unrest  of  the  Middle  Ages  and  the  Renaissance;  in  the  religious 
sphere  the  different  denominations  combined  into  stable  churches  which 
prohibited  any  divergence  from  the  strictly  formulated  dogmas  which  they 
set  up.  Such  a  period  was  bound  to  be  devoted  to  strictly  delimited  systems 
even  in  the  scientific  field,  and  indeed  many  such  systems  of  different  trends 
of  thought,  but  all  definitely  formulated,  more  dogmatic  than  critical,  based 
upon  speculation  rather  than  upon  observation,  saw  the  light  of  day  during 
this  epoch.  Some  of  these  which  highly  influenced  the  development  of 
biological  science  deserve  further  mention. 

The  pioneer  of  modern  philosophy 
Rene  Descartes  (in  his  Latin  writings  he  calls  himself  Cartesius)  is  com- 
monly regarded  as  the  pioneer  amongst  the  systematic  philosophers  of  the 
seventeenth  century.  Born  in  1596  of  wealthy  parents,  he  was  able  to  devote 
his  whole  life  to  research.  His  home  was  in  Brittany,  and  he  was  brought 
up  by  Jesuits;  he  spent  some  years  in  Paris  and  was  for  a  time  an  engineer 
officer  in  the  service  of  foreign  powers.  In  order  that  he  might  devote  himself 
to  his  science  undisturbed  by  the  Catholic  Church,  he  eventually  settled 
down  in  Holland,  where  his  most  important  work  was  done.  He  made  a 
journey  to  Sweden,  and  died  in  Stockholm  in  1650. 

Descartes,  like  Pythagoras  and  Plato,  was  a  mathematician,  and  like 
them,  too,  addicted  to  abstract  speculations.  His  ambition  was  to  place  sci- 
ence on  firm  ground,  valid  for  all  possible  phenomena,  and  excluding  all 
accidental  circumstances.  Among  these  latter  he  counted,  above  all,  mental 
impressions,  and  in  order  to  exclude  them  he  resolved  to  doubt  everything 
in  existence.  But  the  very  fact  of  doubt  proved  that  he  thought,  and  thinking 
gave  him  proof  that  he  existed;  "  Je  pense,  done  je  suis"  was  his  oft-quoted 

113 


114  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

Starting-point.  On  tiiis  foundation  he  then  builds  up  his  entire  conception 
of  existence  on  the  principle  that  the  composite  should  be  explained  from 
its  simple  components.  First  he  constructs  out  of  the  thought  of  man  an 
idea  of  God,  since  man's  finite  and  imperfect  personality  presupposes  an  in- 
finite and  perfect  origin;  once  we  believe  this,  we  must  also  be  right  in  rely- 
ing upon  our  mental  perceptions,  for  God  cannot  have  given  them  to  us 
without  cause.  Through  the  senses  we  are  convinced  that  matter  exists.  The 
simplest  and  therefore  the  most  essential  qualities  of  matter  are  extension, 
divisibility,  and  mobility.  On  the  other  hand,  form,  which  Aristotle,  it  will 
be  remembered,  made  his  main  principle,  is  of  momentary  and  therefore  of 
secondary  significance.  Descartes  also  rejects  the  atomic  theory,  for  it  is  in- 
consistent with  the  principle  of  divisibility;  nor  does  space  exist,  for  every- 
thing that  exists  must  have  extension.  On  these  principles  —  extension, 
divisibility,  and  mobility  —  Descartes  bases  the  whole  of  his  theory  of  mat- 
ter, both  inanimate  and  animate,  and  he  entirely  rejects  the  theory  of  final 
causes,  for  it  would  be  presumptuous  to  ascribe  any  limited  purposes  to 
unfathomable  and  infinite  divinity.  The  only  rational  explanation  of  the 
universe  is  to  regard  the  whole  as  a  machine.  Through  vortical  movements 
within  the  parts  of  matter  the  latter  have  accumulated  and  become  heavenly 
bodies;  and  movement  is  all  that  takes  place  in  nature. 

Life-phenomena  -purely  mechanical 
On  this  same  principle  he  seeks  to  explain  the  phenomena  of  life  —  that  is, 
the  corporeal.  These,  in  his  view,  occur  purely  mechanically,  without  the 
intervention  of  any  of  the  spiritual  forces  which  the  Aristoteleans  assumed, 
whether  animal  or  vegetative.  Confirmation  of  this  idea  of  the  living  body 
as  a  mechanism  Descartes  found  in  Harvey's  discovery  of  the  circulation  of 
the  blood,  which  he  enthusiastically  upheld  and  to  the  acceptance  of  which 
he  powerfully  contributed.  This  fact  in  itself  would  be  sufficient  to  ensure 
him  a  place  in  the  history  of  biology.  And  in  drawing  conclusions  from 
Harvey's  observations  which  the  latter,  faithful  Aristotelean  as  he  was, 
could  himself  never  have  perceived,  he  formed  a  theory  of  the  human  body 
as  a  mechanism  which  may  be  regarded  as  the  foundation  of  modern  physi- 
ology. In  particular,  he  sought  to  explain  mechanically  the  function  of  the 
nervous  system.  He  believed  that  from  the  brain  the  so-called  animal  spirits 
are  conveyed  through  the  nerves  to  the  muscles,  which  are  thereby  set  in 
motion  through  the  impulse  given  them  from  the  brain.  It  is  not  at  all  neces- 
sary that  these  impulses  should  be  conscious;  they  may  take  place  in  the  com- 
plete absence  of  thought  "  just  as  in  a  machine."  Thus  mental  impressions 
can  immediately  call  forth  movements  through  the  nerve  currents'  being 
"thrown  back"  —  that  is,  reflected.  He  has  thus  recognized,  described,  and 
from  his  own  point  of  view  explained  the  phenomenon  of  reflex  motion. 
In  regard  to  animals  he  believes  that  all  their  manifestations  of  life  are  the 


SEVENTEENTH     AND     EIGHTEENTH     CENTURIES       1x5 

result  of  such  reflexes;  it  is  not  possible,  he  thinks,  to  ascribe  to  them  the 
possession  of  a  soul.  That  man  has  a  soul,  on  the  other  hand,  Descartes  con- 
sidered to  be  proved  by  the  fact  that  man  has  consciousness,  and  this  soul 
he  regards  as  a  substance,  the  existence  of  which,  however,  is  entirely  inde- 
pendent of  the  body.  Only  at  one  point,  he  considers,  is  there  any  co-opera- 
tion between  soul  and  body  —  namely,  in  the  glandula  pinealis;  there  the 
currents  from  the  nervous  system  react  upon  the  soul  and  impart  to  it  a  share 
in  mental  impressions;  there,  on  the  other  hand,  the  soul  substance  makes 
impressions  upon  the  nervous  system,  which  give  rise  to  conscious  actions. 
Thus  Descartes  has  created  a  purely  mechanical  cosmic  theory  in  which 
everything  that  happens  takes  place  out  of  mathematical  necessity;  in  which 
neither  the  accidental  movement  of  the  atoms  nor  the  direct  intervention  of 
God  is  needed  to  keep  the  course  of  events  on  the  move.  It  is  manifest  that 
the  great  discoveries  made  during  the  Renaissance  have  conditioned  his 
theory.  But  he  himself  would  not  acknowledge  any  precursors  —  his  ac- 
knowledgment of  Harvey  constitutes  the  one  exception  —  he  was,  in  fact, 
a  very  cautious  man,  and  Galileo's  fate  had  made  a  deep  impression  on  him. 
He  anxiously  avoided  offending  the  Church,  for  which  he  always  showed  a 
deep  respect;  his  manner  of  escaping  from  controversy  was  more  adroit  than 
courageous,  as  when  he  gives  an  assurance  that  his  theory  of  the  creation  is 
merely  a  game  of  thought;  it  might  be  conceivable  that  the  universe  arose 
as  his  theory  declares,  but  one  knows  all  the  same  that  the  Church  main- 
tains the  true  theory  of  creation.  This,  together  with  his  constant  assertion 
of  the  immortality  of  the  soul  of  man,  was,  however,  the  reason  why  so 
many  eminent  ecclesiastical  personages  dared  to  embrace  his  theory,  and  thus 
the  mechanical  explanation  of  the  cosmos  wormed  its  way,  one  might  say, 
into  the  consciousness,  thrusting  out  Aristoteleanism.  And  naturally  the  new 
explanation  of  the  cosmos  —  Cartesianism,  as  it  was  called  —  had  great  ad- 
vantages over  the  old  —  above  all,  in  that  it  rendered  possible  the  appli- 
cation of  the  newly-achieved  results  of  research  in  the  fields  of  physics, 
astronomy,  and  biology.  But  even  the  new  theory  had  its  weak  points.  In 
particular,  the  relation  of  the  consciousness  to  material  phenomena,  or,  in 
other  words,  the  soul's  relation  to  the  body,  was  a  problem  which  worried 
Descartes  and  which,  as  we  have  seen  above,  he  finally  solved,  though  not 
very  successfully.  For  Aristotle  this  problem  did  not  exist;  he  had  in  fact 
made  the  soul  equivalent  to  form  and  thus  evaded  the  point.  For  the  rest, 
it  seems  that  the  individual  life  did  not  concern  him  very  much,  any  more 
than  it  did  the  other  philosophers  of  early  antiquity.  Late  antiquity,  and  in 
a  still  greater  degree  Christianity,  had,  on  the  other  hand,  devoted  earnest 
attention  to  this  problem,  and  now  that  material  phenomena  were  givr.n  a 
purely  mechanical  explanation,  it  became  extremely  acute  and  was  for  a  long 
time  to  be  the  main  point  of  discussion  in  the  philosophical  agenda.  This 


1X6  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

question  has  naturally  been  of  only  indirect  importance  to  biology,  which 
deals  mostly  with  the  material  phenomena  of  life,  but  all  the  same  it  has 
had  its  influence  on  many  purely  biological  problems  and  therefore  cannot 
be  entirely  neglected  here. 

It  was  just  in  this  sphere  of  science  that  Cartesianism  experienced  the 
strongest  opposition  on  the  part  of  such  scientists  as  did  not  accept  Aris- 
totle's views.  In  France  it  was  Pierre  Gassendi  (1591-1655)  who  stands  out 
most  conspicuously  as  the  opponent  of  Descartes.  He  was  born  of  poor  par- 
ents, but  rose  to  high  dignities  in  the  Catholic  Church.  As  a  philosopher  he 
sought  to  revive  the  ancient  atomic  theory  and  wrote  a  defence  of  Epicurus, 
who  in  the  Middle  Ages  was  the  object  of  universal  execration.  Against 
Descartes  he  argued  that  his  conclusion  that  thought  was  a  proof  of  exist- 
ence was  incapable  of  realization.  For  the  rest,  Gassendi  was  a  great  admirer 
of  Galileo  for  his  discoveries  in  the  realm  of  physics,  which  he  partly  im- 
proved upon;  being  a  priest,  however,  he  was  forced  to  deny  the  Coperni- 
can  cosmic  system.  He  conceived  warmth  to  be  the  soul  in  existence.  The 
relation  between  matter  and  human  consciousness  he  tried  to  explain  in  the 
same  way  as  Lucretius,  but  he  admitted  that  there  were  insoluble  difficulties 
in  the  way;  besides,  as  a  priest  he  had  of  course  to  maintain  the  existence 
of  an  immortal  soul. 

Another  thinker  who  held  a  markedly  mechanical  view  of  existence  was 
the  Englishman  Thomas  Hobbes.  He  had  studied  in  Oxford  and  travelled  a 
great  deal  in  Europe,  and  afterwards  spent  the  greater  part  of  his  long  life 
as  a  private  scholar.  He  died  in  1679  ^^  ^^^  ^E>^  ^^  ninety-one.  He  regarded 
all  that  happens  as  motion;  mental  impressions  were  in  his  view  motions  in 
the  nervous  system,  which  arose  as  a  reaction  to  motions  in  the  external 
world.  Hobbes  speculated  most,  however,  upon  problems  of  ethics  and  states- 
manship; he  had  no  interest  in  biology. 

The  same  may  be  said  of  another  philosopher,  who  nevertheless,  curi- 
ously enough,  came  to  play  a  not  unimportant  part  in  the  history  of  biology 
—  Baruch  Spinoza.  Born  of  Jewish  parents  at  Amsterdam  in  1631,  he  was 
brought  up  to  become  a  rabbi,  but  as  he  failed  to  follow  the  teachings  of 
the  synagogue,  he  was  excommunicated  and  afterwards  lived  in  the  closest 
retirement,  making  a  livelihood  by  polishing  eye-glasses,  until  the  time  of 
his  death,  in  1677.  Only  a  few  liberal-minded  people  dared  during  his  life- 
time to  acknowledge  acquaintance  with  the  outcast,  and  although  in  some 
respects  he  was  highly  admired,  it  was  not  until  later  that  his  writings  won 
any  general  acceptance.  He  himself,  thanks  undoubtedly  to  his  mild  and  un- 
assuming temperament  and  his  retired  life,  escaped  falling  a  victim  to  the 
religious  fanaticism  of  the  age,  for  even  in  Holland,  which  was  a  compara- 
tively liberal-minded  country,  tolerance  towards  heterodox  persons  was  a 
rare  thing  in  those  days. 


SEVENTEENTH  AND  EIGHTEENTH  CENTURIES  II7 
Spinoza's  system  of  thought  is  one  of  the  most  magnificent  and  consum- 
mate in  human  history,  one  of  the  most  ingenious  attempts  to  reconcile  the 
opposition  between  consciousness  and  matter  which  Cartesianism  brought 
out.  In  it  he  is  governed  by  a  feeling  inspired  by  the  Jewish  faith  of  his 
childhood  —  a  religious  awe  of  the  infinite,  eternal,  immutable,  "that 
which  is  in  itself  and  is  comprehended  out  of  itself."  This  he  names  sub- 
stance: that  into  which  all  things  that  exist  enter  as  parts.  This  immuta- 
ble substance  has  an  infinite  number  of  forms  in  which  it  appears,  of  which 
we  human  beings  can  distinguish  only  two:  the  material  extension,  and  the 
spiritual  consciousness.  These  cannot  in  any  way  be  explained  out  of  one 
another,  but,  on  the  other  hand,  both  revert  to  the  substance  out  of  which 
they  arose,  and  man  can  therefore  conclude  from  the  laws  that  govern  the 
one  that  they  also  govern  the  other;  the  laws  of  human  reason  have  abso- 
lute force  in  nature  as  well.  From  the  immutability  of  the  substance  it 
follows  that  the  development  that  seems  to  take  place  is  only  apparent; 
everything,  after  a  brief  individual  existence,  reverts  to  the  substance,  like 
a  wave  that  sinks  back  into  the  sea,  giving  place  to  new  individuals  of 
equally  ephemeral  existence.  To  acquire  knowledge  of  the  substance  is  the 
highest  aim  of  man;  it  cannot,  however,  be  attained  by  way  of  thought,  but 
only  by  direct  introspection.  Spinoza  thus  ends  in  mysticism  —  that,  too, 
probably  induced  by  his  Hebraic-oriental  origin.  It  is  strange  that,  in  spite 
of  this  and  of  his  utter  denial  of  any  kind  of  development,  his  system  has 
been  deeply  admired  by  the  very  students  of  nature  of  more  recent  times  who 
have  made  development  the  principal  aim  of  their  researches.  Goethe  was 
strongly  influenced  by  it,  and  in  more  recent  times  Haeckel  and  his  monist 
disciples  have  given  it  enthusiastic  support,  in  reality  perhaps  more  on  ac- 
count of  the  religious  persecution  suffered  by  Spinoza  than  on  account  of 
the  subject-matter  of  his  extremely  involved  writings. 

In  most  respects  his  somewhat  younger  contemporary  Gottfried  Wil- 
HELM  Leibniz  forms  a  sharp  contrast  to  Spinoza.  Leibniz  was  born  at  Leipzig 
in  1646,  the  son  of  a  professor.  He  was  a  veritable  infant  prodigy;  as  a  boy 
he  had  read  practically  the  whole  of  the  classics  and  at  the  age  of  seventeen 
he  delivered  his  doctor's  dissertation.  Mathematics  and  jurisprudence  were 
subjects  of  particular  interest  to  him;  he  became  one  of  the  pioneers  of  the 
former  science,  while  the  latter  provided  him  with  an  income  as  a  govern- 
ment official  and  diplomatic  representative  at  the  courts  of  several  German 
minor  princes.  He  died  at  Hanover  in  1716.  Throughout  his  life  his  energy 
was  remarkable  and  his  interests  incredibly  many-sided.  In  the  course  of  his 
travels  in  most  countries  with  any  standard  of  culture,  he  had  made  the  ac- 
quaintance of  the  most  eminent  men  of  his  time,  and  in  questions  of  culture 
his  advice  was  sought  from  all  sides.  Peter  the  Great  of  Russia,  as  well  as 
the  most  learned  men  in  western  Europe,  corresponded  with  him.  And  as  his 


1X8  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

temperament  was  as  pacific  as  his  interests  were  universal,  he  endeavoured 
everywhere  to  reconcile  and  to  unite.  At  one  time  he  speculated  upon  a 
universal  science  in  which  all  human  knowledge  was  to  be  represented  by 
short  symbols;  on  other  occasions  he  worked  for  the  union  of  the  different 
Christian  Churches.  The  same  efforts  to  reconcile  opposed  views  likewise 
govern  his  natural  philosophy.  Thus,  he  seeks  to  show  that  the  Church's 
doctrine  of  the  omnipotence  of  God,  and  natural  science's  mechanical  ex- 
planation of  the  universe  are  by  no  means  mutually  exclusive,  but  are  capable 
of  being  harmonized. 

Leibniz.' s  raonad  theory 
As  a  natural  philosopher  Leibniz  took  the  atomic  theory  as  his  starting-point. 
As  he  found  it  impossible,  however,  to  derive  consciousness  and  the  mani- 
festations of  the  soul  in  general  from  the  movements  of  atoms,  he  sought  a 
way  out  of  the  difficulty  by  assuming  a  universe  composed  of  units  of  an  ideal, 
not  of  a  material,  character.  The  idea  for  this  theory  he  found  through  using 
the  microscope,  which  had  then  just  been  invented;  by  this  means  it  is 
possible  to  see  that  every  drop  of  water  swarms  with  life  and  that  life  exists 
everywhere,  even  where  the  eye  cannot  see  it;  it  was  thus  but  a  short  step 
to  the  conclusion  that  the  smallest  particles  of  matter  are  life-principles  — 
not  dead  atoms,  but  living  "monads,"  as  Leibniz  called  them.  These  monads 
he  conceives  as  being  of  infinite  variety,  some  of  a  higher  type,  others  of  a 
lower.  The  human  soul  is  one  such  monad,  which  has  consciousness;  the  life 
of  animals  consists  of  lower  monads,  unconscious,  but  percipient;  the  monads 
of  plants  live,  but  are  not  percipient;  the  monads  of  inanimate  nature  are  in 
an  indifferent  state,  as  in  a  dreamless  sleep,  the  human  body  being  composed 
of  these  latter  monads.  The  activity  of  the  monads  is  not  motion,  as  the  atomic 
theory  supposed,  for  motion  is  something  relative,  but  their  ultimate  quality 
can  only  be  conceived  as  force  —  conatus,  as  Leibniz  calls  it.  By  this  means 
they  each,  in  a  higher  or  lower  degree,  obtain  some  notion  of  existence.  On 
the  other  hand,  they  do  not  react  upon  one  another,  their  interrelation  being 
governed  by  a  harmonious  cosmic  order,  originally  created  by  God,  who  is 
the  supreme  monad.  Thus,  the  human  body  functions  by  force  of  the  harmony 
of  existence  parallel  and  in  tune  with  the  soul,  like  two  clocks  which  go 
exactly  alike.  The  kingdoms  of  nature  and  of  grace  act  similarly  towards  one 
another.  —  All  this  extremely  abstract  speculation  might  at  first  sight  appear 
foreign  to  all  that  is  meant  by  natural  science.  Leibniz  has,  however,  actually 
exercised  great  influence  on  natural  research,  partly  by  awakening  interest 
in  life,  both  in  the  great  multiplicity  of  its  manifestations  and  in  its  most 
minute  forms,  and,  above  all,  by  insisting  upon  the  idea  of  force  as  the  basis 
of  natural  phenomena  instead  of  movement,  which  even  Descartes  believed. 
And  his  endeavour  to  reconcile  the  kingdoms  of  nature  and  of  grace,  which 
may  appear  foreign  to  the  ideas  of  natural  research  of  our  own  day,  would 


SEVENTEENTH     AND     EIGHTEENTH     CENTURIES        119 

have  seemed  by  no  means  unattractive  at  a  time  when  the  foremost  natural 
philosophers  were  at  the  same  time  pious  Christians  and  subservient  each 
to  his  own  Church.  This  even  Galileo  had  been,  as  also  those  two  of  his 
successors  who  have  contributed  more  than  any  others  towards  giving  natural 
research  its  modern  character  —  Boyle  and  Newton.  These  two  are  all  the 
more  worthy  of  mention  here  as  through  their  activities  they  have,  each  in 
his  own  way,  powerfully,  if  only  indirectly,  affected  the  development  of 
biology. 

Robert  Boyle  (1617-91)  is  generally  looked  upon  as  the  first  modern 
chemist,  in  so  far  as  he  definitely  broke  away  from  the  mystical  speculations 
of  alchemy  and  made  the  object  of  chemistry  the  breaking  up  of  complex 
substances  into  their  simplest  elements.  Thus  he  freed  experimental  effort 
from  the  fantastic  and  semi-magical  aims  and  means  of  the  Middle  Ages  and 
created  a  natural-scientific  method  based  on  rational  calculations.  On  the 
other  hand,  he  had  little  bent  for  purely  speculative  problems  and  accepted 
the  general  cosmic  viev/s  of  the  Church  without  reserve. 

Far  more  renowned  and  of  far  greater  influence  on  the  intellectual  prog- 
ress of  man  was  Isaac  Newton,  one  of  the  greatest  pioneers  of  natural  science 
that  the  world  has  seen.  Born  in  1641,  of  a  peasant  family,  he  studied  in 
Cambridge,  was  for  many  years  professor  there,  became  in  his  old  age  Direc- 
tor of  the  Royal  Mint  in  London,  and  died  at  the  age  of  eighty-four,  honoured 
and  respected  as  few  scientists  have  been.  He  was  known  everywhere  for  his 
liberal-minded  political  views,  deep  religious  sense,  and  modest,  lovable 
nature. 

The  gravitation  theory 
Newton's  important  discoveries  in  the  sphere  of  mathematics  and  optics  are 
universally  known.  Most  famous  and  most  vital  from  the  point  of  view  of 
cultural  development  is,  however,  his  theory  of  gravitation.  Galileo  had,  it 
will  be  remembered,  established  the  fact  that  the  movement  of  bodies  on  our 
earth  takes  place  on  fixed,  mathematically  calculable  principles.  Newton 
now  proves  that  the  same  laws  governing  the  movement  of  bodies  at  the 
earth's  surface  also  govern  the  movement  of  the  heavenly  bodies  in  their 
relation  to  one  another.  All  the  world  knows  the  story  of  how  in  his  youth, 
at  the  sight  of  a  falling  apple,  he  began  to  ponder  the  question  whether  it  was 
possible  to  calculate  the  movement  of  the  moon  round  the  earth  according  to 
the  same  law  of  attraction  as  that  governing  the  fall  of  the  apple.  He  spent 
twenty  years  working  out  his  idea  and  finally  laid  down  the  well-known 
principle  that  bodies  attract  one  another  with  a  force  directly  proportional 
to  the  mass  and  in  inverse  ratio  to  the  square  of  the  distance.  The  extraor- 
dinary importance  of  this  discovery  was  by  no  means  immediately  clear  to 
everyone;  it  was  at  variance  with  the  speculations  of  the  Cartesian  philoso- 
phers as  well  as  with  the  doctrines  of  the  theologians,  and  it  was  not  until 


130  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

after  the  lapse  of  several  decades  that  humanity  realized  that  here  was  a  new 
foundation  on  which  to  base  the  conception  of  the  universe.  This  was,  of 
course,  due  partly  to  the  fact  that  Newton  himself  remained  in  certain  re- 
spects at  a  somewhat  antiquated  point  of  view.  Like  Galileo,  he  was  quite 
aware,  as  he  himself  says,  that  it  has  not  been  possible  to  discover  "the  cause 
of  the  qualities  of  gravitation  from  phenomena,  and  I  form  no  hypotheses," 
and  he  maintained  that  it  was  justifiable  to  conclude  from  the  existence  of 
properties  in  those  bodies  which  had  been  investigated  the  existence  of  the 
same  properties  in  all  bodies.  At  the  same  time  he  was  firmly  convinced  that 
finality  in  nature  presupposes  a  personal  God  as  the  Creator  of  the  universe, 
and  even  as  the  Maintainer  of  the  whole,  since  the  irregularities  in  the  course 
of  the  heavenly  bodies  must  some  time  be  adjusted  through  the  personal 
intervention  of  the  Creator.  The  latter  assumption,  which  induced  Leibniz 
to  liken  Newton's  cosmic  system  to  a  clock  which  now  and  then  had  to  be 
regulated  in  order  to  go  properly,  testifies  more  clearly  than  any  other  factor 
to  that  mixture  of  childlike  innocence  and  intellectual  keenness  in  Newton 
which  gives  to  the  whole  of  his  personality  the  character  of  old  and  new  in 
conjunction,  such  as  is  so  often  to  be  found  in  philosophers  at  the  turning- 
point  in  the  scientific  history  we  are  here  discussing.  It  was  left  to  the  eight- 
eenth century  entirely  to  shake  off  the  traditional  ideas  of  the  structure  of 
the  universe  and  in  their  place  to  create  that  theory  of  existence  which  has 
been  maintained  ever  since.  The  man  who  more  than  any  other  exerted  a 
decisive  influence  in  this  respect  is  usually,  and  rightly  so,  not  counted  a 
scientist  at  all,  yet  he  has  in  a  greater  degree  than  most  aff'ected  the  progress 
of  science;  that  man  was  Voltaire. 

pRANgois  Marie  Arouet  de  Voltaire  is  one  of  the  best-known  and  most 
discussed  figures  in  cultural  history  —  uncritically  vaunted  to  the  skies  by 
his  admirers,  violently  calumniated  by  his  enemies.  In  the  course  of  his  long 
life  (1694-1778)  he  exercised,  more  than  perhaps  any  other  has  ever  done,  a 
purely  cultural  influence  in  every  sphere  of  life.  His  literary,  political,  and 
religious  activities  are  universally  known.  As  a  man  of  letters  of  middle-class 
origin  he  had  acquired  a  name  in  Paris  for  his  cleverness  and  love  of  opposi- 
tion, when  he  was  suddenly  ordered  by  the  Government  to  leave  the  country 
and  took  refuge  in  England.  After  a  three  years'  sojourn  in  that  country 
(172.6-9)  he  returned  full  of  ideas  which  he  had  assimilated  there,  and  de- 
voted the  rest  of  his  life  to  making  them  known  to  the  world.  Among  these 
new  conceptions  were  Newton's  discoveries  in  physics  and  astronomy.  By 
combining  these  with  a  number  of  ideas  gathered  from  Leibniz's  speculations 
he  produced  a  theory  of  the  universe  which  was  not  only  purely  mechani- 
cal —  that  the  Cartesian  theory  had  already  been  —  but  which  was  also 
based  upon  mathematically  calculable  facts  and  was  therefore  bound  to  work 
with  indisputable  authority.  He  worked  with  indefatigable  enthusiasm  to 


SEVENTEENTH     AND     EIGHTEENTH     CENTURIES       131 

get  this  theory  known,  using  his  brilliant  literary  powers  and  popular  gifts 
to  make  it  attractive;  indeed,  it  was  mostly  thanks  to  him  that  Newton's 
discovery  became  known  to  the  world  of  culture  in  Europe  within  a  space  of 
a  few  decades.  Thus  it  came  about  that  Voltaire  to  a  certain  degree  stands  in 
the  same  relation  to  Newton  as  Haeckel  does  to  Darwin.  Voltaire  also  re- 
minds us  of  Haeckel  in  that  he  made  his  natural-scientific  theory  the  basis  of 
a  comprehensive  view  of  the  world,  to  which  he  unceasingly  refers  in  his 
struggle  against  ecclesiastical  authority,  whose  doctrines  of  the  creation 
and  of  miracles  he  despised  and  ridiculed  from  that  standpoint.  From  his 
time  originates  the  custom  of  citing  "natural  laws"  as  proofs  controverting 
the  Church's  traditional  cosmic  theory.  Otherwise  Voltaire's  notions  of  the 
universe  constitute  in  themselves  no  really  radical  break  with  the  old  tradi- 
tion; he  believed  both  in  a  personal  God  and  in  the  causal  finality  of  nature, 
which  to  a  certain  extent  contributed  towards  making  the  transition  from 
the  ancient  to  the  modern  cosmic  theory  less  of  a  shock  to  the  great  majority. 
Furthermore,  his  doctrines  had  the  rare  consequence  of  bringing  about  a 
radical  revaluation  of  the  whole  of  man's  ideas  of  life. 

With  the  coming  of  this  so-called  "period  of  enlightenment"  introduced 
by  Voltaire  we  may  regard  the  conception  of  nature  created  by  antiquity 
and  handed  down  through  the  Middle  Ages  and  after  as  definitely  shattered. 
It  would,  however,  be  an  exaggeration  to  assume  that  Voltairianism  reigned 
supreme  in  his  period.  Besides  the  adherents  of  the  time-honoured  cult  of 
antiquity,  of  whom  there  were  always  a  great  number,  there  were  to  be 
found  during  the  enlightened  period,  in  ever-increasing  numbers,  supporters 
of  the  mystical-speculative  tendencies  which  have  been  mentioned  above. 
Throughout  the  whole  era  here  under  discussion  a  not  unimportant  part 
was  played  by  natural-scientific  mysticism,  influencing  even  otherwise  quite 
critical  people  in  the  scientific  world  and  everywhere  attracting  adherents, 
who  devoted  themselves  entirely  to  its  aims  and  purposes.  Its  roots,  as  has 
already  been  mentioned,  lay  far  back  in  time,  while  its  ramifications  can  be 
traced  even  in  the  field  of  modern  natural  research,  exact  though  it  apparently 
is.  Its  development  thus  deserves  a  chapter  to  itself,  the  beginning  of  which 
must  take  us  back  to  the  days  of  the  Renaissance. 


CHAPTER    III 

MYSTICAL    SPECULATION    UPON    NATURAL    SCIENCE 

Magic  during  the  Renaissance 

IN  THE  FIRST  SECTION  of  this  work  wc  havc  pointed  out  how  important  was 
the  role  played  by  mystical  speculation  in  science  during  the  Renais- 
sance, even  in  the  theories  of  its  principal  representatives,  such  as  a  Cusa- 
nus  or  a  Bruno.  As  a  matter  of  fact,  through  the  break-down  of  scholasticism 
in  science,  the  field  was  left  open  for  all  those  wild  fantasies  that  seem  to  be 
common  to  all  times  and  generations,  although  they  are  at  times  thrust  out 
of  sight  and  dare  not  show  themselves  for  fear  of  learned  authority  and  the 
derision  of  critics.  Seldom  indeed  is  it  that  mystical  speculation  and  magical 
experiments  have  gone  so  far  and  had  such  scientific  pretensions  as  during 
the  Renaissance. 

All  this  Renaissance  magic  was  based  on  a  great  many  preconceptions: 
primitive  superstition,  cabbalistic  interpretation  (originating  from  the  East) 
of  the  books  of  the  Bible  and  a  number  of  apocryphal  appendices,  Arabian 
experimental  science  and  its  Western  development.  Finally,  the  neo-Platonic 
philosophy,  striving  to  gain  by  means  of  direct  introspection  a  mystical,  uni- 
form conception  of  the  whole  of  existence  —  spirit  and  matter,  animate  and 
inanimate  things  —  provided  a  common  speculative  framework  in  which  to 
fit  all  these  various  elements.  Ideas  taking  this  as  their  point  of  departure  and 
objective,  foreign  though  they  really  are  to  both  the  aims  and  the  methods  of 
natural  science,  have  nevertheless  had  a  deep  influence  on  its  development; 
they  have  induced  a  striving  after  a  uniform  view  of  life  at  periods  when 
science  threatened  to  disintegrate  into  aimless  detailed  research,  and  they 
have  produced  a  love  of  nature  during  epochs  when  humanity  had  otherwise 
turned  to  abstract  philosophic  speculation. 

The  Renaissance  produced  a  number  of  personalities  of  this  mystical, 
half-experimenting,  half-brooding  type:  the  Italian  Pico  de  Mirandola, 
the  Germans  Heinrich  von  Nettesheim  —  called  Cornelius  Agrippa  —  and 
Trithemius,  and  many  others.  They  are,  however,  of  but  little  interest  to 
biological  history,  although  their  speculations  may  have  in  certain  cases 
indirectly  influenced  the  development  of  biology  during  the  succeeding  era. 
One  of  their  contemporaries,  however,  far  more  radically  than  they,  furthered 
the  progress  of  biology;  a  man,  moreover,  who,  owing  to  the  life  he  lived, 
is  of  more  than  common  human  interest;  namely,  Paracelsus. 

I3X 


0^ 

< 

o 

> 

H 

u 

w 
0:1 
« 

<3 


c/2 

h-I 
w 
u 

< 


SEVENTEENTH     AND     E  I  G  H  T  E  E  N  T  H     C  E  N  T  U  R  I  E  S       133 

Theophrastus  Hohenheim  was  born  in  1490,  or  somewhat  later,  at  the 
famous  monastery  for  pilgrims  at  Maria-Einsiedeln  in  the  Canton  of  Schwyz 
in  Switzerland.  The  name  Paracelsus,  by  which  he  is  best  known,  he  him- 
self adopted  later/  His  father,  who  is  said  to  have  been  the  illegitimate  son 
of  a  Knight  of  St.  John  of  the  noble  family  of  Bombast  von  Hohenheim,  was 
a  physician  at  the  above  monastery;  his  mother,  who  was  probably  a  peasant 
woman,  was  before  her  marriage  a  sick-nurse  there.  Young  Theophrastus, 
who  was  called  after  the  great  Athenian  botanist  and  disciple  of  Aristotle, 
grew  up  in  poverty  and  remained  throughout  his  life,  in  spite  of  his  ancestors' 
nobility,  in  all  respects  a  child  of  the  people.  Nevertheless  he  received  a 
sound  education,  partly  from  his  father  and  partly  from  two  priests,  friends 
of  the  latter;  and  as  a  youth  he  was  a  student  at  Basel.  However,  he  soon 
wearied  of  scholasticism,  studied  alchemy  for  a  time  under  Trithemius, 
referred  to  above  —  an  abbot  who  had  established  a  laboratory  in  his  monas- 
tery —  and  afterwards  became  an  apprentice  at  a  mine  in  the  Tyrol,  where  he 
studied  metallurgy  and  was  initiated  into  the  professional  secrets  of  the 
miners.  Even  this  work,  however,  did  not  appeal  to  him,  and  he  soon  joined 
the  hosts  of  learned  adventurers  who  ever  since  the  Middle  Ages  had  wan- 
dered about  Europe  under  the  name  of  scbolares  vagantes  or  mendicant  stu- 
dents. Young  Hohenheim  took  his  profession  more  seriously  than  most  of 
his  colleagues;  having  wandered  through  Germany,  Spain,  and  France,  he 
joined  the  army  with  which  Christian  II  conquered  Sweden  in  15x0,  as  a 
field  surgeon.  He  thus  came  to  Stockholm,  proceeded  thence  to  Moscow, 
from  there  again  —  by  which  route  is  not  known  —  to  Constantinople, 
and  finally  returned  home.  In  the  course  of  these  journeys  he  naturally  had 
an  opportunity  of  visiting  several  universities,  but  their  official  learning  was 
of  far  less  interest  to  him  than  the  experiences  he  was  able  to  gain  of  people 
who  were  at  that  time  believed  to  be  familiar  with  the  occult  sciences: 
barber-surgeons,  witches,  gipsies,  and  executioners.  He  made  such  good  use 
of  the  medical  knowledge  thus  gained  that  in  15x6  he  was  appointed  first 
town-physician  at  Basel,  with  the  right  to  revise  the  city's  pharmacopoeia 
and  to  hold  lectures  at  the  University.  As  a  practitioner  he  was  brilliantly 
successful  with  daring  cures  and  simple,  cheap  medicines,  while  at  the  same 
time  he  harassed  his  colleagues  by  his  extremely  overbearing  manner.  He 
gave  his  course  of  lectures  in  German  instead  of  in  Latin  and  started  by 
ceremoniously  burning  the  classical  treatises  on  medicine,  which  naturally 
increased  the  hatred  of  the  medical  profession.  When,  moreover,  the  apothe- 
caries, embittered  by  his  sharp  criticism,  intrigued  against  him,  he  had  to 

1  The  name  Paracelsus  he  used  as  a  nom  de  plume  in  some  of  his  writings;  it  probably 
means  "higher  than  Celsus"  (the  Roman  physician).  Another  name  which  he  adopted  is  Au- 
reolus  Bombastus,  the  former  meaning  "golden,"  and  the  latter  having  been  borne  by  his  grand- 
father. He  also  sometimes  calls  himself  "Eremita,"  after  the  place  of  his  birth. 


134  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

leave  Basel  after  some  years.  Thus  once  more  he  began  his  wanderer's  life, 
tramping  from  town  to  town  in  Germany  for  about  ten  years,  everywhere 
winning  popularity  for  his  wonderful  cures,  and  hatred  for  his  lack,  of  con- 
sideration and  imperiousness  towards  his  colleagues  and  patients.  There 
seemed  no  possibility  for  him  to  settle  down  in  peace;  rather  he  had  to  flee 
for  his  life  time  and  again,  until  finally  Archbishop  Ernst  invited  him  to 
settle  at  Salzburg,  which  he  did  about  the  year  1540.  Now  at  last  it  seemed 
that  better  days  were  in  store  for  him,  but  it  was  not  to  be  for  long;  in  1541 
he  suffered  a  violent  death  —  his  calumniators  declared  it  was  through  an 
accident  when  under  the  influence  of  drink,  but  his  friends  said  it  was  a 
result  of  a  hostile  attack.  Before  his  death  he  had  bequeathed  his  few  pos- 
sessions to  the  poor. 

Paracelsus^ s  -personality 
Both  in  life  and  after  death  Paracelsus  has  been  very  variously  judged:  by 
some  he  has  been  represented  as  a  bare-faced  scoundrel,  an  impudent  trader 
upon  the  good  faith  and  superstition  of  humanity;  by  others  —  of  early 
times  as  well  as  in  our  own  day  —  he  has  been  highly  extolled  as  one  of  the 
boldest  spirits  that  ever  lived  and  one  of  the  greatest  promoters  of  science. 
In  actual  fact,  one  can  find,  in  his  writings  and  in  his  life,  support  for  both  of 
these  judgments;  on  the  one  hand,  uncritical  superstition,  fantastic  paradoxes, 
boundless  self-conceit,  and  shamelessly  scurrilous  language  in  controversy; 
on  the  other  hand,  penetrating  criticism  of  his  predecessors'  theories,  and 
audacious  ideas  of  his  own,  aiming  far  into  the  future.  To  brand  him  as  a 
conscious  cheat  would  in  any  event  be  utterly  unjust;  rather  he  is  of  a  type 
that  has  been  very  common  during  the  Sturm  und  Drang  periods  of  human 
culture.  Throughout  his  writings  we  come  across  the  same  naive  self-satisfac- 
tion, the  same  pugnacious  temperament,  as  one  finds  in  several  romantic 
writers  of  the  beginning  of  the  nineteenth  century;  like  them  he  was  un- 
doubtedly induced  by  an  honest  intention  to  "explain  the  whole  of  nature 
and  to  reform  the  whole  world."  People  with  such  grandiose  aims  easily 
acquire  something  of  the  charlatan  and  humbug  in  their  natures,  which, 
however,  does  not  exclude  the  possibility  of  really  splendid  traits  in  their 
character.  And  such  Paracelsus  certainly  possessed;  his  kindness  towards  the 
poor,  his  earnest  desire  to  help  suffering  humanity,  his  often  very  poorly 
requited  loyalty  towards  his  friends,  are  sufficient  proof  of  that.  In  his  writ- 
ings, moreover,  he  often  praises  the  medical  profession  as  a  high  and  noble 
calling,  claiming  of  its  members  not  only  knowledge,  but  also  goodness  and 
morality.  Side  by  side  with  this  there  appears  in  him  a  feeling  of  self-respect, 
which  sometimes  finds  worthy  expression,  such  as  in  his  motto:  ''Nemo  sit 
alterius  qui  suus  esse  potest, ' '  ^  but  more  often  manifests  itself  as  high-sounding 

^  "Let  no  one  be  another's  who  can  be  his  own.'" 


SEVENTEENTH     AND     EIGHTEENTH     CENTURIES       135 

self-praise,  as  when  he  says:  "My  back  hair  knows  more  than  you  and  all 
your  hack  writers;  my  shoe-laces  are  more  learned  than  your  Galen  and  Avi- 
cenna."  And  his  confidence  in  success  is  unbounded.  "I  shall  be  king  and  the 

kingdom  shall  be  mine .  I  wish  I  could  protect  my  bald  head  from  flies 

as  easily  as  I  do  my  kingdom,  and  were  Milan  as  secure  against  its  enemies  as 
ray  kingdom  is  against  you,  no  Swiss  nor  Landsknecht  would  find  his  way 
there."  The  coarse  expressions  with  which  he  spices  his  controversial  writ- 
ings are  such  that  they  could  not  possibly  be  quoted.  Otherwise  his  language 
is  vigorous  and  original;  he  wrote  in  German,  like  his  great  contemporary 
Luther,  for  whom  in  his  writings  he  expresses  the  greatest  admiration. 

Alche7nistic  conceptiofi  of  the  human  body  and  its  junctions 
Paracelsus's  scientific  theories  are  far  more  difficult  to  characterize  than  his 
personality.  As  the  essential  part  of  his  activities  he  always  regarded  his 
medical  practice,  and  his  general  theories  of  life  invariably  have  direct 
reference  to  diseases  and  how  to  fight  against  them.  And,  being  originally  an 
alchemist,  at  bottom  he  despised  anatomy  as  he  did  all  detailed  research  in 
general.  He  sought  rather  to  get  the  human  body  and  its  functions  regarded 
as  a  part  of  the  world  in  its  entirety  and  therefore  also  as  dependent  upon  the 
cosmic  process,  as  it  goes  on  both  on  the  earth's  surface  and  in  the  firmament 
that  surrounds  it.  This  was,  indeed,  just  what  Aristotle  strove  after,  but 
while  the  latter  sought  to  solve  the  problem  by  means  of  a  theory  which  had 
primary  reference  to  the  forms  of  being,  to  Paracelsus,  who  from  his  early 
youth  had  lived  in  the  thought-world  of  mediaeval  alchemy,  existence 
represented  one  single  mighty  chemical  process.  The  alchemistic  thought- 
structure  was,  of  course,  based  upon  experiments  of  an  essentially  magical 
character  and  upon  speculations  of  neo-Platonic-oriental  origin,  especially 
upon  the  Hebrew  cabbala,  with  its  belief  in  the  secret  power  of  words  and 
graphical  signs  and  their  mystical  connexion  with  the  things  they  denoted. 
All  these  elements  of  learned  speculation  Paracelsus  interwove  with  all  that 
he  had  learnt  of  folk-magic  during  his  years  of  wandering,  into  a  natural- 
philosophical  system  of  unique  character.  Its  guiding  thought  probably 
emanates  directly  or  indirectly  from  the  cabbala  —  that  is  to  say,  the  in- 
trinsic connexion  that  Paracelsus  believes  is  to  be  found  between  everything 
that  exists:  the  celestial  bodies,  the  things  on  the  earth,  and  human  beings. 
This  occult  connexion,  which  Paracelsus  considers  it  to  be  the  function  of 
science  to  investigate,  leads  him,  the  more  involved  he  becomes,  into  a 
mysticism  which  a  modern  reader  will  find  extremely  difficult  to  grasp  even 
in  its  main  features.  And  the  systematic  divisions  of  the  subject,  with  which 
Paracelsus  is  excessively  generous,  certainly  do  not  make  the  matter  any 
clearer.  In  one  of  his  principal  works  on  science  in  general,  which  he  himself 
published  under  the  title  of  Paramirum,  he  divides  the  causes  of  sickness, 
which  he  always  takes  as  his  starting-point,  into  five  classes:  Ens  astrale. 


136  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

veneni,  naturale,  spirifuale,  deale.  What  these  different  ''ens''  really  are  one 
never  gets  to  know;  they  are  apparently  mystical  powers  which  produce 
diseases  and  which  have  different  origins.  Ens  astrale  proceeds  from  the  stars, 
which  have  life  and  can  poison  the  atmosphere,  precisely  as  a  person  in  an 
unventilated  room  pollutes  the  air  in  it  with  his  breath.  Ens  veneni  is  a  cause 
of  sickness  originating  in  the  digestion;  each  living  being  has,  in  fact,  his 
given  food,  which  is  made  by  that  being  partly  into  sustenance  for  the  body 
and  partly  into  a  poison,  which  is  expelled  through  the  excretive  organs; 
besides  the  true  excreta,  which  are  the  specific  poison  of  the  body,  quicksilver 
is  excreted  through  perspiration,  sulphur  through  the  nose,  and  arsenic 
through  the  ears  —  the  yellow  colour  of  the  cerumen  in  the  ear  probably 
reminded  Paracelsus  of  certain  arsenic  associations.  Thus  the  ox  consumes 
grass  in  its  own  way  and  man  the  flesh  of  the  ox  in  his.  Every  being  has  in  its 
body  an  "alchemist,"  who  directs  the  work;  if  he  gets  out  of  order,  the  body 
becomes  sick.  In  another  treatise  he  is  named  Archeus,  and  is  apparently  to 
be  regarded  as  a  spiritual  being,  though  no  exact  description  of  him  is  given. 
Paracelsus  describes  in  greater  detail  the  third  cause  of  sickness,  ens  naturale, 
and  here  he  expounds  his  real  theory  of  life  and  the  universe.  The  human 
body  is  a  microcosm,  possessing  elements  corresponding  to  all  the  phe- 
nomena of  the  exterior  world,  particularly  to  the  heavenly  bodies;  thus  the 
liver  corresponds  to  Jupiter,  the  gall-bladder  to  Mars;  the  heart  is  the  sun, 
the  brain  the  moon,  the  spleen  is  Saturn,  the  lungs  Mercury,  and  the  kidneys 
Venus.  All  these  organs  perform  planetary  movements  in  the  body,  and  if 
they  come  into  an  unfavourable  position,  disease  arises.  On  the  other  hand, 
they  are  all  independent  of  food  and  therefore  also  of  the  poisons  derived 
from  it.  Moreover,  there  are  included  in  the  body  the  four  elements,  as  well 
as  the  basic  substances  of  the  four  temperaments,  which  are  like  the  gustatory 
impressions,  sour,  sweet,  salt,  and  bitter.  All  these  likewise  circulate  and  give 
rise  to  disease.  In  regard  to  ens  spirifuale  Paracelsus  emphasizes  the  difference 
between  soul  and  spirit:  the  soul  is  a  work  of  God,  but  the  spirit  is  created 
by  the  human  will  and  by  means  of  it  man  can  influence  his  fellow  men.  Thus 
disease  can  be  occasioned  by  men's  hatred;  if  an  enemy  makes  an  image  of 
wax  and  maltreats  a  part  of  it,  his  action  induces  suffering  in  the  correspond- 
ing part  of  the  person  he  desires  to  persecute  —  a  method  to  which  witches 
are  particularly  partial.  Ens  deale,  finally,  is  the  divine  will  itself,  which  gives 
sickness  and  health  as  may  seem  good  to  it;  against  the  divine  will  medicines 
are  of  no  avail,  but  only  piety  and  prayers. 

Paracelsus' s  influence 
In  other  writings  Paracelsus  expounds  his  theory  of  the  connexion  in  nature 
in  different  directions;  one  describes  the  doctrine  of  the  "signatures"  in  plants 
and  their  connexion  with  diseases,  as,  for  instance,  that  Hypericum,  owing 
to  its  perforated  leaves,  cures  wounds  from  stabs;  the  peony,  owing  to  its 


SEVENTEENTH     AND     EIGHTEENTH     CENTURIES       137 

cerebral-shaped  pistil,  cures  paralysis  of  the  brain,  etc.  To  go  deeper  into 
these  fantastic  ideas  is  hardly  worth  while;  what  has  already  been  stated  may 
seetn  to  many  readers  more  than  enough  of  such  nonsense.  Nevertheless, 
Paracelsus 's  influence  has  been  both  wide  and  deep.  In  medicine  he  was  in 
many  respects  a  pioneer;  he  did  his  best  to  treat  wounds  hygienically  and 
otherwise  to  leave  them  in  peace;  owing  to  his  belief  in  specific  causes  of 
diseases,  he  sought  for  a  single  cure  for  each  disease,  and  several  of  his 
methods  proceeding  on  these  lines  still  hold  good,  especially  the  use  of 
mercury  in  the  treatment  of  syphilis;  moreover,  this  aim  of  his  formed  a  con- 
trast to  Galen's  and  his  followers'  disastrous  attempts  to  create  universal 
medicines  to  be  used  for  all  diseases  and  composed  of  everything  imaginable. 
Even  modern  biology  is  based,  at  least  in  one  respect,  on  a  principle  laid 
dovv^n  by  Paracelsus;  his  conception  of  life-phenomena  as  fundamentally 
chemical  processes  has  without  doubt  paved  the  way  for  modern  physiology, 
which  certainly  could  not  develop  before  chemical  science  had  been  freed 
from  the  primitive  mysticism  in  which  it  was  veiled  in  the  time  of  Paracelsus 
and  for  a  hundred  years  after  him,  but  which  in  any  case  represented  a  more 
stimulating  starting-point  for  the  modern  idea  of  substance  conversion  in  the 
body  than  the  Aristotelean  "cooking"  theory,  which  even  Vesalius  accepted. 
Further,  the  conception  of  life  as  a  mystical  force  uniting  the  whole  of  exist- 
ence, which  Paracelsus,  it  is  true,  did  not  actuafly  found,  but  developed  and 
stamped  with  his  own  original  personality,  has  never,  in  spite  of  its  many 
fallacies  and  absurdities,  succeeded  in  being  entirely  suppressed.  Time  and 
again  it  has  been  thrust  aside  by  some  more  exact  research  based  upon  actual 
facts  and  referred  to  the  vast  public  of  the  dilettanti  and  mountebanks,  but 
it  never  really  died  out,  so  that  at  certain  times  —  for  instance,  during  the 
romantic  period  at  the  beginning  of  the  last  century  —  it  revived  with 
renewed  vigour.  And  during  such  periods  Paracelsus's  reputation  has  been 
freshly  enhanced.  At  all  events,  history  cannot  but  acknowledge  the  fertile 
genius,  the  splendid  character  —  in  spite  of  its  many  exaggerations  —  and 
the  force  of  will  with  which  Paracelsus  throughout  a  life  of  adversity  and 
distress  fought  for  what  he  considered  to  be  the  supreme  aim  of  science. 

Paracelsus  was  not  very  fortunate  in  his  disciples.  Cultured  people  could 
not  endure  his  presence  for  long,  and  the  riff-raff  he  gathered  about  him  dur- 
ing his  wanderings  was  not  suitable  material  for  a  scientific  school.  His  chief 
influence  was  exerted  by  his  writings,  which  were  read  eagerly  and  produced 
a  mass  of  imitations,  wherein  the  defects  rather  than  the  merits  of  the  true 
Paracelsian  writings  were  conspicuous,  and  which,  published  under  the 
master's  name,  contributed  more  than  anything  else  to  lower  his  reputation. 
The  principal  successor  to  Paracelsus  appeared  about  a  generation  after  his 
death,  a  philosopher  who  extracted  from  his  writings  ana  still  further  dc' 
veloped  his  peculiar  conception  of  life  and  its  functions. 


138  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

Jean  Baptiste  van  Helmont  was  born  at  Brussels  in  the  year  1577,  of  a 
noble  and  wealthy  family.  Left  fatherless  at  an  early  age,  he  became  a  pre- 
cocious child,  and  by  his  seventeenth  year  he  had  already  completed  his 
university  studies  in  philosophy.  This,  however,  failed  to  satisfy  him;  he 
entered  a  Jesuit  college  and  there  studied  theology,  especially  that  of  a 
mystical  character,  and  this  puzzling  over  life's  problems  entirely  obsessed 
his  mind.  He  eagerly  studied  the  neo-Platonists  and  Paracelsus,  for  whom 
throughout  his  life  he  expressed  a  keen,  but  by  no  means  uncritical  admira- 
tion. At  the  age  of  twenty-two  he  took  the  degree  of  doctor  of  medicine, 
spent  the  next  few  years  in  travelling  through  different  countries,  and  then 
contracted  a  wealthy  marriage  and  settled  down  on  an  estate  in  his  home 
district,  dividing  his  time  between  scientific  research  and  splendid  acts  of 
benevolence.  He  carried  on  his  medical  practice  simply  for  charity  and  with- 
out any  fee;  every  offer  of  permanent  employment,  even  the  most  brilliant, 
he  firmly  declined.  He  died  in  1644. 

As  already  mentioned,  van  Helmont  regarded  Paracelsus  as  his  master 
and  undoubtedly  had  a  certain  afhnity  with  him.  True,  he  possessed  none  of 
his  precursor's  intrepid  geniality,  but  he  was  far  more  cultured,  both  scientifi- 
cally and  socially.  In  his  personal  character  he  was  mild  and  lovable,  but  he 
seems  to  have  been  of  a  nervous  disposition,  which  gave  his  mystical  specu- 
lations a  peculiar  quality  of  exaltation.  He  had  spiritual  visions,  which  he 
produced  by  auto-suggestion  through  gazing  at  some  strong  source  of  light; 
he  employed  in  his  researches  for  obtaining  scientific  results  a  direct  intro- 
spection which  he  achieved  by  exalted  concentration  of  thought,  both  during 
the  day's  work  and  in  the  night's  rest,  when  in  a  state  between  sleeping  and 
waking  he  received  inspiration,  by  which  he  set  great  store.  This  inspiration, 
however,  often  led  him  widely  astray,  as  when  he  believed  that  he  had  suc- 
ceeded in  producing  rats  in  a  vessel  in  which  some  rags  and  bran  had  been 
kept,  or  when  he  imagined  he  had  converted  quicksilver  into  gold,  a  dis- 
covery which  so  delighted  him  that  he  had  his  son,  who  was  born  just  at 
that  time,  christened  Mercurius.^  But  fortunately  he  had  also  better  inspira- 
tions. One  of  these  was  his  determined  opposition  to  the  classical  authorities 
Aristotle  and  Galen.  Their  theories  he  believed  it  was  his  mission  in  life  to 
challenge,  both  because  they  led  to  practically  worthless  results  and  because 
they  were  pagan.  This  latter  reason  is  characteristic.  While  the  man  of  the 
Renaissance  period,  Paracelsus,  scorned  the  classics  because  they  were  an- 
tiquated authorities  and  stood  in  the  way  of  his  personal  ideas,  the  emotional 
disciple  of  the  Jesuits,  van  Helmont,  felt  himself  moved  first  of  all  to  substi- 
tute a  Christian  for  the  heathen  science.  This  induced  him,  however,  to  make 

^  This  Franz  Mercurius  van  Helmont  devoted  himself  even  more  exclusively  than  his 
father  to  purely  mystical  speculations.  The  fact  of  his  having  published  the  latter's  complete 
works  constituted  his  greatest  service  to  science. 


SEVENTEENTH     AND     EIGHTEENTH     CENTURIES       139 

what  in  many  respects  was  a  sound  criticism,  particularly  of  Aristoteleanism, 
the  weak  points  of  which  he  brought  out  very  clearly.  In  his  writings  he 
closely  examines  Aristotle's  theory  of  the  relation  of  form  to  reality.  Simi- 
larly, he  rejects  the  theory  of  the  four  elements,  for,  said  he,  fire  is  not  an 
element  at  all.  Again,  when  Aristotle  believes  the  fertilizing  property  of  the 
sperm  to  be  due  to  its  heat,  van  Helmont  satirically  asks  how  it  is  that  the 
cold-blooded  fishes  are  more  fertile  than  any  warm-blooded  animal.  How- 
ever, it  proves  here,  as  often,  to  be  easier  to  destroy  than  to  build  up;  van 
Helmont's  own  theories  cannot  compete  with  Aristoteleanism  at  least  in 
clearness  and  consistency.  This,  indeed,  is  due  partly  to  the  peculiar  mystical 
principles  on  which  he  bases  his  views,  and  partly  to  his  lack  of  stylistic 
ability;  his  writings  are  extremely  obscure  and  difficult  to  read.  His  concep- 
tion of  nature,  like  that  of  Paracelsus,  is  chemical,  with  a  strong  dose  of 
mysticism,  which  belonged  to  chemistry  at  that  time. 

Van  Helmont' s  fermentation  theory 
The  "fermentation  process"  plays  an  important  part  in  his  theories  on  nat- 
ural phenomena;  he  had  thoroughly  studied  this  phenomenon  and  had  shown 
that  fermenting  must  produces  a  kind  of  air  which  is  identical  with  that  given 
off  by  burning  charcoal  and  that  which  sometimes  renders  the  air  of  caves 
irrespirable.  For  this  element  he  invented  the  name  of  gas,  a  word  which  has 
since  been  accepted  by  science.  He  distinguished  several  kinds  of  gas,  of 
which,  however,  only  the  above-mentioned  "gas  sylvestre,"  or  what  we 
call  carbon  dioxide,  has  been  fully  described.  According  to  him,  digestion 
and  every  kind  of  conversion  of  substance  in  general  are  due  to  ferments. 
The  many  different  processes  of  fermentation  which  he  thought  he  had  dis- 
covered in  the  human  body  were  for  the  most  part  mere  creations  of  his 
fancy,  but  he  had  certain  ideas  which  were  to  prove  to  be  correct,  as  when 
he  points  out  the  part  played  by  acid  in  the  cavity  of  the  stomach  in  the 
digestive  process,  and  shows  that  the  undue  acidity  of  the  digestive  juices  is 
neutralized  by  the  gall.  He  was  not  content  with  merely  establishing  facts  of 
this  kind,  however;  like  Paracelsus,  he  sought  to  get  on  the  tracks  of  life 
itself  and,  like  him  too,  saw  its  innermost  essence  personified  in  an  archeus, 
which  is  situated  in  the  region  of  the  stomach  and  controls  a  number  of 
subsidiary  archei  in  the  other  parts  of  the  body.  This  central  archeus,  however, 
regulates  only  the  material  conversion  in  the  body  and  exists  in  various 
forms  in  all  beings;  man  has,  besides  his  immortal  soul,  "intellectus,"  which 
makes  the  soul  participate  in  blessedness  and  would  wholly  control  the  body 
had  not  the  Fall  intervened.  After  the  Fall  man  received  a  lower  soul,  "ratio," 
which  makes  it  bound  to  earth  and  liable  to  its  impulses,  and  finally  to 
death.  Beings  in  the  universe  have  the  power  of  reacting  upon  one  another 
by  a  kind  of  force  operating  at  a  distance  which  he  calls  "bias" ;  in  particular 
the  bias  proceeding  from  the  heavenly  bodies  has  remarkable  properties,  but 


140  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

it  would  take  too  long  to  enter  into  fuller  details.  Van  Helmont  regards 
water  as  the  material  fundamental  element  underlying  the  whole  of  existence; 
out  of  water  arises  everything  on  earth,  both  inanimate  and  animate  sub- 
stance. As  a  proof  of  this  theory  he  cites  an  experiment:  he  filled  a  bowl 
with  loo  pounds  of  dry  soil  and  in  it  planted  a  willow,  weighing  5  pounds, 
and  watered  it  with  rain-water.  After  five  years  the  willow-tree  weighed 
164  pounds  while  the  soil,  when  again  dried,  weighed  about  loo  pounds 
less  3  ounces.  Thus,  he  argued,  the  entire  willow-tree  was  formed  of  rain- 
water. This  experiment,  which  indeed  was  perfectly  correct  in  both  plan  and 
execution,  although  the  conclusion  he  drew  from  it  was  wrong,  testifies 
better  than  anything  else  that  van  Helmont  was  nevertheless  a  true  pioneer 
in  the  field  of  natural  science;  to  have  thought  out  the  first  biological  ex- 
periment based  on  quantitative  calculations  is  a  service  to  science  which  well 
compensates  for  many  mistakes  in  the  theoretical  sphere.  Even  as  a  medical 
practitioner  van  Helmont  showed  the  same  curious  mixture  of  fancifulness 
and  foresight:  on  the  one  hand  he  worked  at  a  mysterious  universal  medicine 
which  he  called  "alkahest,"  while  on  the  other  he  strongly  protested  against 
the  abuses  common  at  that  time  in  connexion  with  violent  blood-letting  and 
strangely  concocted,  excessively  strong  medicines.  Moreover,  like  Paracelsus, 
he  undoubtedly  exercised  a  strong  influence,  for  both  good  and  evil;  his  fer- 
tile, far-seeing  ideas  proved  of  value  far  into  the  future,  and  traces  of  his 
mystical  fancies  can  even  be  found  in  scientists  of  subsequent  generations,  a 
number  of  whom  will  be  mentioned  in  the  next  chapters. 


CHAPTER    IV 


BIOLOGICAL     RESEARCH     IN    THE     SEVENTEENTH     CENTURY 


I.   Harvey's  Successors 


IN  THE  FOREGOING  have  bccn  described  the  two  entirely  contrasted  natural 
systems  which  appeared  independently  in  opposition  to  Aristoteleanism : 
the  mechanical  conception  of  nature,  and  the  mystical  view  of  life.  As  has 
been  shown  in  the  first  part  of  this  work,  the  foundations  of  the  mechanical 
view  of  natural  phenomena  were  laid  by  Harvey,  who  proved  that  the  circu- 
lation of  the  blood,  which  had  up  to  that  time  been  regarded  as  an  expression 
for  certain  vital  spirits,  goes  on  as  a  purely  mechanical  process.  Although 
himself  a  convinced  disciple  of  Aristotle,  Harvey  thereby  laid  the  foundations 
of  that  modern  scientific  theory  of  the  phenomena  of  life  which  follows  the 
same  methods  in  dealing  with  them  as  those  applied  to  the  investigation  of 
phenomena  in  inorganic  nature.  This  discovery  of  Harvey's  created  an  im- 
mense sensation;  during  the  immediately  succeeding  decades  after  its  publica- 
tion (in  1 6x8)  it  was  the  one  great  question  of  the  day  and  occasioned  a  vast 
quantity  of  literature  both  for  and  against  it.  Its  overwhelming  truth,  how- 
ever, soon  silenced  all  opposition;  the  conservative  adherents  to  the  old 
system  gradually  died  off  and  the  young  research-workers  were  easily  won 
over  to  the  new  view  and  devoted  themselves  to  gathering  fresh  proofs  of  its 
validity.  How  successful  it  was  is  best  evidenced  by  the  extraordinary  stimu- 
lus given  to  the  study  of  anatomy  during  the  middle  and  latter  half  of  the 
seventeenth  century.  This  period,  perhaps  more  than  any  other,  can  be  re- 
garded as  one  of  brilliant  anatomical  achievement,  to  which  the  preceding 
era,  beginning  with  Vesalius's  revolutionary  inventions  in  the  field  of  tech- 
nique and  methods  of  observation,  impresses  one  mostly  as  being  a  period 
of  introduction.  A  comparison  between  these  two  epochs  also  produces  a 
remarkable  contrast  of  a  national  character;  while  during  the  Renaissance 
Italy  was  the  sole  centre  of  anatomical  research,  its  range  had  now  spread 
northwards:  now  for  the  first  time  England,  Holland,  and  Scandinavia  begin 
to  make  definite  contributions  to  the  development  of  biology.  And  simul- 
taneously with  this  shifting  of  the  centre  of  biological  research  we  find 
another  change  appearing  in  its  conditions,   first  in  Italy  and  later  the 

141 


1 42.  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

farther  north  we  go.  During  the  sixteenth  century  the  natural  philosophers 
were  still  mostly  university  teachers;  such  had  been  both  Vesalius  and  Gali- 
leo. In  the  seventeenth  century,  on  the  other  hand,  and  still  more  so  in  the 
eighteenth  century,  the  universities  cease  to  be  the  centres  of  scientific  prog- 
ress and  become  instead  the  seats  of  unproductive  conservatism,  mechanically 
repeating  the  formulas  inherited  from  the  Middle  Ages;  the  real  pioneer 
scientists  are  now  private  scholars.  Descartes,  Spinoza,  Leibniz,  as  well  as 
Harvey  and  van  Helmont,  all  worked,  as  we  have  seen,  independently  of  the 
universities,  as  we  shall  also  find  did  several  of  the  leading  scientists  among 
their  successors,  in  both  the  seventeenth  and  the  eighteenth  centuries.  A  new 
type  of  bond  of  association  between  men  of  learning  came  to  be  established 
in  connexion  therewith  —  namely,  the  scientific  societies.  Such  "academies" 
were  founded  during  the  seventeenth  century  all  over  Europe,  earliest  in 
Italy,  afterwards  in  all  countries  north  of  the  Alps.  Princes  and  distinguished 
people  allowed  themselves  to  be  nominated  as  patrons  or  to  be  elected  honor- 
ary members,  thereby  acquiring  an  interest  in  the  study  of  nature.  To  pro- 
mote this  study  they  established  laboratories  and  made  collections  of  natural 
objects  —  so-called  "curiosity  cabinets"  — ■  mostly,  it  is  true,  as  the  name 
implies,  for  their  own  amusement,  but  still  in  many  cases  for  the  benefit  of 
science,  owing  to  the  possibilities  they  offered  for  research  and  the  grants 
of  money  made  by  scientists  in  connexion  therwith.  All  this  naturally  in- 
creased, as  it  were,  the  social  reputation  of  science  and  in  this  respect  offered 
a  decided  contrast  to  the  Renaissance;  whereas  then  the  students  of  nature 
had  to  live  in  inferior  positions,  during  the  seventeenth  and  eighteenth 
centuries  many  of  them  held  important  posts  in  the  community.  The  period 
now  to  be  described  was  thus  in  all  respects  a  brilliant  one  for  natural 
science  —  a  period  which  has  no  counterpart  until  we  come  to  the  latter 
half  of  the  nineteenth  century. 

Discovery  of  the  lymphatic  system 
As  Harvey's  immediate  successors  it  is  fair  to  regard  those  scientists  who, 
like  him,  studied  the  vascular  system  in  man  and  the  higher  animals  and  thus 
continued  along  the  path  he  initiated.  Mention  has  already  been  made 
(Part  I,  p.  113)  of  hov/,  even  during  Harvey's  lifetime,  a  hitherto  unknown 
type  of  vessel  was  discovered  —  namely,  the  lymphatic  duct  system  —  and 
how  Harvey  adopted  an  attitude  of  complete  ignorance  on  the  subject  and 
adhered  to  the  ancient  tradition.  As  a  matter  of  fact,  a  year  before  the  publi- 
cation of  Harvey's  treatise  on  the  circulation  of  the  blood  there  appeared  a 
work  on  "the  lacteal  veins  —  a  new  discovery."  — The  author,  who  had 
died  the  previous  year,  was  an  Italian  physician  named  Gasparo  Aselu 
(1581-162.6).  He  had  begun  his  profession  as  an  army  surgeon  and  afterwards 
became  for  a  time  professor  of  anatomy  at  Pavia,  but  finally  practised  in 
Milan.  There  he  once  carried  out,  together  with  some  of  his  colleagues,  a 


SEVENTEENTH     AND     EIGHTEENTH     CENTURIES       143 

vivisection  operation  on  a  dog  which  had  just  before  had  a  substantial  meal, 
and  thereupon  found  the  peritoneum  and  intestines  covered  with  a  mass  of 
white  threads;  he  casually  cut  one  of  them  off  and  saw  that  a  fluid  oozed  out; 
they  were  thus  not  nerves,  but  vessels  of  a  kind  hitherto  unknown.  Influ- 
enced, however,  by  the  traditional  Galenian  idea  of  the  liver  as  a  blood- 
former,  Aselli  assumed  that  these  vessels,  "chyle  vessels,"  as  they  are  now 
called,  extended  from  the  intestines  to  the  liver.  Nevertheless,  the  discovery 
aroused  general  interest.  Aselli 's  book  was  reprinted  several  times,  and  a 
number  of  contemporary  anatomists  interested  themselves  in  this  new  dis- 
covery. Among  them  there  is  one  who  deserves  special  mention  — Johann 
Vesling  (15 98-1 649),  who,  though  born  in  Germany,  became  a  professor  at 
Pavia  and  in  a  handbook  of  anatomy,  printed  in  1647,  gave  a  detailed  ac- 
count of  the  chyle  vessels  (lacteals).  Twenty  years  after  Aselli's  work  had 
been  published,  however,  a  young  student  by  the  name  of  Jean  Pecquet 
(i6iz-74)  iTiade  a  discovery  which  considerably  enhanced  the  knowledge  of 
the  newly-discovered  vascular  system.  While  performing  a  dissection  he 
found  the  canal  which  forms  the  common  trunk  of  the  lacteals  and  the 
lymphatics  —  the  so-called  ductus  thorackus.  This  contradicted  Aselli's  and 
his  immediate  successors'  belief  that  the  lacteals  lead  from  the  intestinal 
canal  to  the  liver.  Pecquet  was  born  in  Normandy,  studied  at  Montpellier, 
and  eventually  became  body-physician  to  the  minister  Fouquet,  who  was 
all-powerful  in  the  early  youth  of  Louis  XIV.  When  Fouquet  was  sentenced 
to  imprisonment  for  fraud,  his  physician  had  to  go  with  him,  and  after  that 
he  disappears  from  history.  He  is  said  to  have  had  a  blind  confidence  in  the 
power  of  brandy  to  cure  all  manner  of  diseases  —  an  illusion  which  rapidly 
brought  him  to  ruin.  It  was  instead  in  Scandinavia,  hitherto  unknown  in 
science,  that  the  problem  of  the  lymphatic  duct  system  was  finally  solved, 
and  it  was  a  strange  coincidence  that  two  scientists  from  different  countries 
should  have  quite  simultaneously  and  independently  of  each  other  attained 
the  same  result. 

Thomas  Bartholin  was  born  in  Copenhagen  in  161 6.  His  father,  Caspar 
Bartholin,  was  professor  of  anatomy  and  a  distinguished  scientist  of  the  old 
school.  Having  matriculated  in  his  early  youth  and  learnt  all  that  his  own 
country  could  teach  him,  young  Thomas  at  the  age  of  twenty  started  out  on 
his  travels,  which  lasted  for  nine  years.  First  he  studied  for  three  years  at 
Leyden  and  there  became  acquainted  with  Harvey's  discoveries,  after  which 
he  worked  for  two  years  in  the  anatomical  theatre  at  Pavia,  moved  on  to 
Naples,  where  he  was  a  pupil  of  the  old  Severino,  then  gave  a  dissertation 
for  his  doctor's  degree  at  Basel,  and  did  not  return  to  his  native  country 
before  a  professorship  was  assured  to  him.  As  professor  of  anatomy  he  did 
splendid  work,  which  within  a  short  time  made  the  unknown  Danish 
university  famous  throughout  Europe;  foreign  pupils  flocked  to  him,  among 


144  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

whom  may  be  specially  mentioned  the  German  Michael  Lyser,  who  as 
prosector  used  to  perform  Bartholin's  most  important  dissections,  and  after- 
wards became  professor  at  Leipzig.  A  number  of  valuable  works  were  pub- 
lished by  Bartholin  in  the  sixteen-fifties,  but  his  productive  powers  very 
soon  waned.  After  Lyser's  resignation  from  the  post  of  prosector  (1651) 
little  occurred  there  in  the  way  of  fresh  anatomical  results;  as  early  as  1660 
Bartholin  was  completely  relieved  of  all  instructional  and  examination  work, 
and  then  he  had  only  his  membership  of  the  board  of  the  university,  of  which 
he  seems  to  have  taken  advantage  mostly  for  the  pui-pose  of  providing  his 
relations  with  good  appointments.  With  this  end  in  view  he  is  believed  to 
have  passed  over  deserving  pupils,  including  Steno,  who  is  mentioned  later 
on.  Other  not  very  attractive  characteristics  of  his  are  also  mentioned,  such 
as  that,  physician  though  he  was,  he  once  fled  from  the  city  during  a  plague 
for  fear  of  infection  and  retired  into  the  country;  again,  the  way  in  which 
he  procured  extra  salary  from  the  Government  caused  him  to  be  censured  on 
several  occasions.  His  writings  abound  in  expressions  of  the  most  extravagant 
self-praise,  though  he  displays  in  them  a  really  genuine  respect  for  science  — 
undoubtedly  the  most  attractive  trait  in  his  character.  He  died  in  1680  and 
was  succeeded  by  his  son  Caspar,  who  carried  on  his  work,  reaping  a  number 
of  external  honours,  but  in  no  wise  possessing  his  father's  merits. 

Bartholin  discovers  the  lymphatic  system 
Thomas  Bartholin's  most  important  achievement  is  generally  considered  to 
have  been  his  clearing  up  of  the  mystery  of  the  lymphatic  duct  system.  He 
was  not  aware  of  Pecquet 's  discovery  when  he  began  to  study  the  chyle 
vessels  (lacteals),  and  therefore  believed,  with  Aselli,  that  they  led  to  the 
liver.  By  observation  and  experiment,  however,  he  soon  found  that  this  was 
not  so  and  at  the  same  time  discovered  that  these  vessels  were  connected 
with  a  vascular  system  distributed  throughout  the  entire  body,  and  con- 
taining a  fluid  clear  as  water.  These  discoveries  he  described  in  a  treatise 
which  came  out  in  1653,  in  which  he  declares  that  the  liver  cannot  perform 
the  blood-forming  function  which  classical  anatomy  had  ascribed  to  it;  nor, 
since  the  chyle  vessels  do  not  connect  with  the  liver,  but  on  the  contrary  a 
number  of  lymphatic  ducts  go  in  the  opposite  direction,  can  the  food  be 
converted  into  blood  in  the  liver,  as  the  anatomists  up  to  the  time  of  Harvey 
and  Aselli,  and  the  two  latter  as  well,  had  concluded.  He  closes  his  essay 
by  erecting  a  monument  to  the  liver,  the  body's  now  dethroned  ruler,  in  the 
form  of  a  parody  of  the  high-falutin  memorial  speeches  which  it  was  the 
custom  of  the  time  to  make  in  honour  of  the  distinguished  dead. 

Bartholin  set  great  store  by  his  discovery  of  the  lymphatic  system  and 
wrote  several  fresh  articles  on  the  subject,  without,  however,  making  any 
very  important  additions  to  his  first  account.  The  rest  of  his  scientific  literary 
work,  which  is  rather  extensive,  cannot  be  compared  from  the  point  of  view 


SEVENTEENTH     AND     EIGHTEENTH     CENTURIES       145 

of  interest  with  that  dealing  with  the  discovery  which  he  rightly  regarded  as 
his  greatest  contribution  to  the  development  of  anatomy.  Consequently  he 
must  have  been  extremely  chagrined  to  find  at  the  very  start  a  competitor  for 
the  honour  of  having  made  the  great  discovery  —  a  youth  into  the  bargain, 
without  any  previous  successes  to  his  credit,  either  scholarly  or  literary. 

Olof  Rudbeck  was  born  at  Vasteras  in  1630,  the  youngest  but  one  of 
eleven  children.  His  father  was  the  imperious  Bishop  Johannes  Rudbeckius, 
a  man  of  deep  learning,  great  powers  of  leadership,  and  corresponding  am- 
bition. In  his  diocese  he  had  founded  a  college,  which,  as  far  as  education 
was  concerned,  could  compete  with  the  University.  It  possessed  both  a 
library  and  a  botanical  garden.  There  young  Olof  received  a  thorough  edu- 
cation, and  there  too  he  undoubtedly  acquired  that  love  for  natural  science 
which  induced  him,  immediately  after  his  entry  into  the  University,  to  take 
up  the  study  of  medicine,  which  was  at  that  time  in  not  very  high  favour. 
Having  matriculated  at  the  age  of  seventeen,  he  felt  himself  at  once  moved  to 
begin  to  work  on  his  own  account,  which  the  poorly  equipped  faculty  of 
medicine  rendered  it  absolutely  necessary  to  do.  Like  Vesalius,  he  devoted 
himself  to  the  dissecting  of  animals  and  in  doing  so  was  initiated  almost  at 
once  into  the  then  newly-discovered  and  interesting  chyle  system.  The  obser- 
vations which  he  had  made  within  a  very  short  time  in  this  field  created  such 
a  sensation  that  Queen  Christina  herself  desired  to  become  acquainted  with 
them.  In  1651  young  Rudbeck  was  given  an  opportunity  of  demonstrating 
his  experiments  before  the  Queen  and  as  a  reward  was  given  a  grant  to  enable 
him  to  travel  abroad.  Before  starting  he  published  his  observations  in  the 
form  of  a  dissertation,  in  the  year  1553,  and  then  went  to  Leyden,  where  he 
studied  for  three  years.  When  he  returned  home,  he  was  appointed  professor 
of  anatomy  and  now  devoted  himself  with  great  energy  to  reforming  the 
system  of  medical  education,  which  had  till  then  consisted  mostly  of  lectures 
on  the  writings  of  the  ancient  authorities.  Rudbeck  built  after  his  own  de- 
sign a  splendid  anatomical  theatre,  which  still  exists,  and  there  carried  out, 
as  often  as  material  was  available,  dissections  of  human  bodies.  Exercises  of 
this  kind  had  never  been  seen  before  in  Upsala  and  they  consequently  aroused 
bitter  opposition,  but  Rudbeck  did  not  allow  himself  to  be  deterred;  on  the 
contrary,  he  openly  showed  his  contempt  for  his  opponents'  prejudices.  To 
ridicule  them  he  once  caused  the  remains  of  a  criminal  which  he  had  dissected 
to  be  buried  with  great  pomp  and  drew  up  for  the  ceremony  a  program  in 
which  he  delightfully  parodied  the  academical  rhetoric  of  the  period.  How- 
ever, this  educational  work  made  too  great  demands  on  even  his  extraordi- 
nary energy  to  allow  him  time  for  scientific  research;  a  book  on  general 
animal  anatomy  which  he  intended  to  publish  was  —  undoubtedly  to  the 
immense  loss  of  science  —  never  written.  His  childhood's  interest  in  botany 
bore  fruit,  for  he  devoted  much  of  his  time  to  the  production  of  a  large 


146  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

work  composed  of  botanical  engravings  and  entitled  Campi  elysii,  but  this 
was  never  completed  , either,  owing  to  the  fact  that  he  allowed  himself  to 
be  attracted  to  a  new  sphere  of  activity;  he  became  engrossed  in  that  ex- 
traordinary, colossal,  linguistic-archasological-patriotic  work  Atland,  in 
which  he  seeks  to  prove  that  Sweden  is  the  oldest  civilized  country  in  the 
world.  He  died  in  1701,  having  shortly  before  seen  a  great  part  of  his 
scientific  production  go  up  in  flames  in  the  conflagration  which  destroyed 
Upsala  in  the  same  year. 

Discovery  of  the  "vasa  serosa" 
The  anatomical  work  of  his  youth  is,  however,  all  that  justifies  Olof  Rud- 
beck's  being  regarded  as  the  earliest  in  the  long  line  of  eminent  naturalists 
that  Sweden  has  produced.  In  his  first  dissertation  in  i65z  he  gives  an  ac- 
count of  the  circulation  of  the  blood  in  the  true  spirit  of  Harvey  and  presents 
a  number  of  theses,  one  of  which  denies  the  existence  of  any  spirit  in  the  body 
other  than  the  animal,  while  another  denies  the  property  of  the  liver  as  a 
blood-forming  organ  —  proving  that  he  was  far  in  advance  of  Harvey's 
standpoint.  In  a  dissertation  printed  in  the  following  year  he  describes 
the  lymphatic  duct  system,  which  he  had  independently  discovered  when 
attempting  to  ascertain  the  structure  of  the  lacteals;  he  describes  the 
course  of  these  ''vasa  serosa,"  as  he  calls  them,  not  only  within  the  trunk, 
but  also  in  the  extremities;  he  gives  an  account  of  their  distensions,  the 
lymphatic  glands;  he  observes  the  nature  of  the  lymphatic  fluid  —  that  it  is 
salt  to  the  taste  and  coagulates  in  cooking;  he  tries  to  ascertain  the  movement 
of  the  fluid  in  the  vessels  by  observing  their  valves;  and,  finally,  he  endeav- 
ours to  work  out  a  theory  of  the  significance  which  the  entire  system  has  for 
the  body. 

Between  the  two  rivals  for  the  honour  of  having  discovered  the  lym- 
phatic duct  system  in  its  entirety,  Bartholin  and  Rudbeck,  there  ensued  a 
struggle  for  priority,  carried  on  with  the  aid  of  pamphlets,  and  breaking  out 
into  mutual  recriminations  of  a  not  very  attractive  character.  National 
chauvinism  took  a  part  in  the  game,  and  the  question  was  debated  long  aftet 
the  death  of  the  parties  to  the  dispute,  until  finally  an  impartial  examination 
of  the  documents  put  an  end  to  the  controversy.  After  having  investigated 
the  matter  R.  Tigerstedt  came  to  the  conclusion  that  Rudbeck  was  the  first 
to  make  the  discovery,  but  that  Bartholin  had  the  prior  claim  as  regards  the 
date  of  publication.  That  these  two  eminent  scientists  both  came  to  the  same 
result  independently  of  each  other  would  now  appear  to  be  beyond  all 
doubt. 

The  discovery  of  the  lymphatic  duct  system  constituted  a  great  and  im- 
portant work  supplementing  Harvey's  discovery  of  the  circulation  of  the 
blood.  It  was  possible  now  for  the  first  time  for  research  to  grapple  with  the 
problem  of  how  the  food  substances  in  the  digestive  canal  are  utilized  by 


SEVENTEENTH     AND     EIGHTEENTH     CENTURIES       147 

the  body,  a  subject  on  which  the  biologists  of  antiquity  had  as  confused  ideas 
as  they  had  on  the  movement  of  the  blood  in  the  veins.  Both  Rudbeck  and 
Bartholin,  indeed,  were  prepared  to  draw  the  obvious  conclusion  from  their 
discovery:  since  the  lacteals  did  not,  as  even  Aselli  believed,  lead  to  the  liver, 
but  just  the  opposite,  it  was  impossible  for  that  organ  to  play  the  all-con- 
trolling part  in  the  digestive  process  which  the  ancients  had  ascribed  to  it. 
Both  Rudbeck's  thesis  and  Bartholin's  funeral  eulogy  on  the  liver  were  con- 
firmations of  this.  It  must  be  admitted,  however,  that  in  this  both  scientists 
to  a  certain  extent  overshot  their  mark;  research  work  in  recent  times  has 
revealed  that  a  large  portion  of  the  substances  from  the  intestinal  tube  — 
carbo-hydrates,  albuminous  substances,  and  others  —  are  received  by  the 
ramifications  of  the  cystic  vein  in  the  digestive  canal  and  conveyed  to  the 
liver,  where  they  are  converted.  It  would  of  course  be  absurd,  however,  to 
ascribe  to  the  opponents  of  Rudbeck  and  Bartholin  greater  prescience  in  this 
respect;  conservatism  which  can  give  no  other  reason  for  adherence  to  the 
past  than  respect  for  tradition  has  no  historical  justification  in  face  of  the 
pioneer  who  bases  his  ideas  on  newly-discovered  facts,  even  though  he  often 
overestimates  their  fundamental  value. 

As  has  been  mentioned,  anatomical  research  during  the  middle  and  close 
of  the  seventeenth  century  was  practised  with  special  keenness  in  England; 
Harvey's  achievement  acted  as  a  stimulus  particularly  on  his  own  country-, 
men.  Space  does  not  allow  of  a  discussion  of  all  the  eminent  discoverers  in 
this  field  of  science  which  England  produced  during  the  era  in  question;  one 
or  two  of  the  most  representative  will  be  given  here  as  examples. 

Francis  Glisson  (15 97-1 677)  was  the  son  of  a  landowner;  he  studied  at 
Cambridge,  first  philosophy  and  afterwards  medicine.  He  took  his  doctor's 
degree  in  1634  and  as  early  as  two  years  later  became  a  professor.  The  Civil 
Wars,  however,  soon  compelled  him  to  abandon  his  educational  activities; 
he  moved  to  London,  where  he  became  a  practitioner  of  repute  and  one  of  the 
first  members  of  the  Royal  Society,  the  scientific  association  founded  in  1660, 
which  has  ever  since  been  the  most  distinguished  centre  where  the  scientists 
of  England  have  gathered.  Besides  some  purely  medical  works,  which  were 
excellent  for  the  period  in  which  they  were  written,  Glisson  published  two 
pioneer  works  on  anatomy,  the  one  dealing  with  the  anatomy  of  the  liver, 
the  other  with  the  stomach  and  intestines.  The  first  gives  a  monographical 
account  of  the  liver  which,  for  the  then  prevailing  conditions,  was  an  exemp- 
lary work  and  laid  the  foundation  on  which  the  modern  knowledge  of  the 
anatomy  of  this  organ  rests.  In  memory  of  this,  the  subperitoneal  tissue  of  the 
liver  is  to  this  day  called  Glisson's  capsule.  But  the  author  does  not  merely 
give  a  detailed  description  of  the  liver;  he  also  expounds  a  general  biologi- 
cal theory  in  connexion  therewith,  in  which  he  entirely  adopts  Aristotle's 
standpoint.  In  the  component  parts  of  the  body  he  distinguishes  matter  and 


148  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

form  and  describes  them  entirely  in  the  Aristotelean  spirit:  matter,  that  out 
of  which  something  is  produced;  form,  the  change  in  matter  which  serves  a 
given  purpose;  that  which  produces  form  is  either  nature  or  art.  He  emphati- 
cally protests  against  the  "physical"  conception  of  form  and  matter  which 
the  "philosophers"  advance.  His  conclusions  are  formed  on  the  scholastic 
model,  and  the  physiological  problems  that  he  sets  up  he  solves  by  a  purely 
abstract  method.  Nevertheless,  there  are  among  his  ideas  one  or  two  which 
remind  one  of  modern  lines  of  thought,  such  as  his  belief  that  the  evacu- 
ation of  the  gall-bladder  is  caused  by  nervous  irritability.  And  when  it 
comes  to  the  lacteals,  he  shows  a  knowledge  and  a  comprehension  of  Pec- 
quet's  and  Bartholin's  discoveries.  He  thus  exhibits  in  his  views,  as  often 
happens  in  transitional  periods,  a  mixture  of  old  and  new. 

Glisson's  younger  contemporary  and  friend  Thomas  Wharton  was  a 
specialist  pure  and  simple.  Born  in  161 4,  likewise  the  son  of  a  landowner,  he 
took  the  degree  of  doctor  of  medicine  at  Oxford  and  then  practised  in  Lon- 
don, finally  becoming  head  of  a  hospital  there  and  a  highly  reputed  member 
of  the  College  of  Physicians.  He  died  in  1673.  His  fame  as  an  anatomist  rests 
on  his  Adenographia,  a  work  in  which  is  given  for  the  first  time  a  comparative 
account  of  the  glands  of  the  body.  In  this  book  Wharton  seeks  in  the  first 
place  to  explain  the  actual  term  "gland"  and  assumes  secretion  to  be  the 
essential  criterion  of  it;  he  lays  special  stress  on  the  difference  between  the 
"viscera,"  or  intestines,  and  the  glands.  The  tongue  is  not  a  gland,  but  a 
muscle;  nor  is  the  brain  a  gland,  but  a  special,  "precious"  substance.  As 
belonging  to  the  true  glands  he  characterizes  the  digestive,  lymphatic,  and 
sexual  glands.  Wharton  discovered  the  exit  of  the  submaxillary  gland  —  it 
now  bears  his  name  —  and  he  also  for  the  first  time  gave  a  detailed  descrip- 
tion of  the  pancreas.  The  kidneys,  the  testes,  and  the  thyroids  are  also  care- 
fully described.  With  regard  to  the  glandula  fmealis,  Wharton  denies  its 
quality  of  a  soul-organ,  as  maintained  by  Descartes;  he  considers  it  to  be  an 
excretal  gland,  to  which  the  nerves  from  the  brain  drain  off  waste  products, 
which  are  then  removed  by  the  blood-vessels  —  a  curious  conclusion  in 
regard  to  internal  secretion,  formed  more  than  two  centuries  before  this 
process  was  established  in  our  own  time.  The  hypophysis,  according  to 
Wharton,  possesses  similar  functions,  though  with  a  different  kind  of  eject- 
ing apparatus.  Wharton  does  little  in  the  way  of  theoretical  speculation;  on 
the  other  hand,  investigation  and  discussion  of  disease  conditions  in  the 
glands  play  an  important  part  in  his  work. 

A  more  weighty  personality  we  find  in  Thomas  Willis.  The  son  of  a 
farmer,  he  was  born  in  i6xi,  studied  in  Oxford,  and  during  that  time  fought 
in  the  ranks  of  the  Royal  Army  against  the  Parliamentary  troops.  Having 
taken  his  medical  degree,  he  worked  as  a  medical  practitioner  until,  in  1660, 
upon  the  victory  of  the  King's  party,  he  obtained  a  professorship  as  a  reward 


SEVENTEENTH  AND  EIGHTEENTH  CENTURIES  1 49 
for  his  loyal  conduct.  This  appointment,  however,  he  did  not  retain  for  long, 
but  he  moved  to  London  and  again  set  up  in  practice;  there  he  made  a  great 
reputation,  became  a  member  of  the  Royal  Society,  and  published  several 
treatises.  He  has  been  described  as  an  honest  man  of  firm  character,  towards 
the  end  of  his  life  not  very  popular  at  court,  owing  to  his  outspoken  criticism 
of  its  corrupt  morals.  He  died  in  1675. 

Willis's  principal  work  is  his  investigation  of  the  anatomy  of  the  brain 
and  the  nervous  system.  His  exposition  of  the  structure  of  the  brain  and  of 
the  nerves  proceeding  directly  therefrom  is  the  first  that  may  be  said  to  ful- 
fil modern  requirements;  to  his  description  of  the  outward  configuration  of 
these  parts  posterity  has  had  very  little  to  add.  He  performed  a  still  further 
service  to  science  in  having  paid  special  attention  not  only  to  the  human 
brain,  but  also  to  that  of  other  vertebrates:  in  the  introduction  to  his  work 
he  expressly  points  out  that  comparative  anatomy  alone  can  provide  a  fully 
satisfactory  explanation  of  the  structure  and  functions  of  the  organs.  The 
account  of  his  investigations  into  the  brains  of  different  animal  forms  is 
illustrated  with  very  fine  engravings,  a  number  of  which  were  drawn  by  his 
friend,  the  famous  architect.  Sir  Christopher  Wren,  the  designer  of  St. 
Paul's  Cathedral  in  London.  With  regard  to  the  functions  of  the  nervous 
system,  Willis,  in  contrast  to  the  Aristoteleans  Harvey  and  Glisson,  asso- 
ciated himself  entirely  with  the  theory  advanced  by  Descartes.  The  manifesta- 
tions of  life  are  induced  by  currents  in  the  nervous  system,  which  penetrate 
the  brain  and  according  to  their  nature  are  distributed  into  the  different  parts 
thereof;  the  world  of  ideas  and  the  memory  he  places  in  the  cortex  of  the 
great  brain.  Willis  thus  forestalls  Swedenborg's  radical  investigations  into 
the  localizations  in  the  brain,  which  are  certainly  considerably  deeper  and 
more  detailed  than  his  precursor's.  Willis  also  carefully  studied  the  func- 
tional spheres  of  the  different  nerves;  thus,  by  binding  up  the  vagus  nerve  in 
a  live  dog,  he  established  their  influence  on  the  lungs  and  heart. 

In  a  work  published  at  a  later  date  Willis  deals  with  the  soul  of  animals. 
This  work  has  a  far  wider  range  than  its  title  implies,  for  it  contains  a  mass 
of  information  of  various  kinds.  Thus,  he  gives  an  account  of  a  number  of 
investigations  he  made  into  the  anatom^y  of  invertebrates,  which  would 
have  been  of  interest  to  his  age  had  not  at  the  same  time  Malpighi  and 
Swammerdam  given  far  better  accounts.  The  main  purpose  of  the  work,  how- 
ever, is  a  comprehensive  study  of  the  vegetative  and  sensitive  soul,  which  in 
his  view  —  and  in  that  of  Descartes  —  is  common  to  the  animals  and  man. 
Man  has,  indeed,  his  rational  soul  as  well,  which  is  immaterial  and  can  there- 
fore survive  after  death;  the  soul  under  discussion  here  is,  on  the  other  hand, 
that  material  vital  spirit  which  finds  expression  in  currents  in  the  nervous 
system  and  which  produces  all  the  manifestations  of  life  in  animals  and  those 
that  are  purely  animal  in  man.  How  it  happens  that  animals  can  in  some  cases 


150  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

perform  actions  which  indicate  a  conscious  intelligence  is  a  problem  which 
causes  the  author  considerable  difficulty;  true  reason  cannot  exist  in  animals, 
for  then  they  would  soon  come  to  resemble  man  and  would,  moreover,  be 
immortal;  it  must  therefore  be  the  material  vital  spirit  that,  either  instinc- 
tively or  mechanically,  directs  their  actions.  In  endeavouring  to  apply  this 
theory  Willis  becomes  involved  in  a  maze  of  speculations  that  it  would  be 
hopeless,  and  indeed  would  take  too  long,  to  follow  in  all  the  subtleties  to 
which  they  give  rise;  the  numerous  learned  authorities  whom  he  quotes 
merely  give  additional  confirmation  of  the  state  of  helpless  confusion  into 
which  psycho-physiological  speculation  had  drifted  ever  since  it  left  behind 
it  the  safe  harbour  of  Aristoteleanism.  When  a  scientist  of  Willis's  rank  can 
seriously  discuss  the  question  whether  the  vital  spirit  can  be  compared  with 
spiritus  vini  or  hartshorn  oil,  it  is  easy  to  realize  to  what  hopeless  lengths 
the  natural-scientific  speculation  of  that  age  could  go.  Nevertheless,  there 
were  even  at  that  time  students  of  nature  who  applied  with  far  more  sub- 
stantial results  the  newly-discovered  exact  method  of  research  in  the  sphere 
of  biology.  Examples  will  be  given  in  the  next  section  of  this  chapter;  first, 
however,  we  may  give  one  more  example  of  radical  anatomical  research  dur- 
ing this  epoch. 

Raymond  Vieussens  was  born  in  1641,  of  a  military  family;  he  devoted 
himself  to  medical  studies  at  Montpellier  and  after  having  graduated  became 
a  doctor  at  a  hospital  there.  He  paid  specially  keen  attention  to  the  study  of 
the  structure  of  the  nervous  system  and  after  many  years  of  preparatory  work 
published  his  great  Neurologis  universalis  in  1685.  This  brought  him  immediate 
fame.  He  was  summoned  to  the  court  in  Paris  and  was  for  a  time  physician 
there,  but  afterwards  returned  to  his  old  post,  which  he  retained  until  his 
death,  in  171 5.  His  description  of  the  nervous  system  is  remarkable  for  its 
unprecedented  accuracy  and  completeness  in  its  anatomical  details;  for  us  it 
is  of  special  interest  as  representing  the  foundation  upon  which  Swedenborg 
based  his  ingenious  speculations  upon  the  connexions  of  the  nervous  system, 
which  Vieussens  studied  and  illustrated  with  great  exactitude.  Unfortu- 
nately he,  too,  became  involved,  with  but  little  success,  in  physiological 
speculations  upon  the  "spiritu/'  of  the  nervous  system,  which  he  believes  to 
be  secreted  in  the  brain  from  the  blood  circulating  through  it  to  the  latter, 
as  well  as  upon  a  "spirifus  nitro-aerius,"  contained  in  the  blood  itself;  a  kind 
of  acid  component  thereof,  which  is  drawn  from  the  air  and  from  the  con- 
stituents of  food.  As  a  result  of  these  ideas  he  became  involved  in  a  tedious 
controversy.  He  also  brought  out  a  couple  of  anatomical  works  on  the  heart 
and  the  vascular  system,  but  they  are  of  less  value  than  his  neurology. 


SEVENTEENTH     AND     EIGHTEENTH    CENTURIES       151 

i.  Attempts  at  a  Mechanical  Explanation  of  Life -phenomena 

Giovanni  Alfonso  Borelli  was  born  at  Naples  in  1608.  His  father  had  been 
an  officer  in  the  service  of  Spain.  At  an  early  age  young  Alfonso  showed  a 
marked  genius  for  mathematics;  in  order  to  complete  his  education  in  this 
subject  he  went  to  the  University  of  Pisa.  There  Galileo  had  once  been  pro- 
fessor and  he  now  lived,  an  honoured  and  influential  man,  as  court  astrono- 
mer in  the  neighbouring  city  of  Florence.  It  was  not  surprising,  therefore, 
that  Borelli  was  won  over  to  his  physical  and  astronomical  theories,  and  he 
entered  with  ardour  into  the  new  field  of  research  which  they  opened  up  for 
him.  After  a  period  of  deep  study  he  was  elected  professor  at  the  University 
of  Messina  by  the  Government  of  his  country,  and  there  he  gave  instruction 
for  some  years.  Conditions  at  that  university,  however,  were  limited  and 
offered  him  no  scope,  wherefore  Borelli  returned  in  1656  to  Pisa,  whence  he 
was  summoned  to  Florence  in  the  following  year.  In  the  latter  city  the  disci- 
ples of  Galileo  had  founded  a  free  academy,  called  "Accademia  del  cimento"; 
here  Borelli  found  employment  and  worked  for  ten  years.  He  went  in  seri- 
ously for  medical  studies  with  a  view  to  applying  Galileo's  physical  princi- 
ples to  medicine.  Unfortunately  for  him,  however,  he  was  induced  by  the 
promise  of  a  higher  salary  to  return  to  Messina.  As  a  matter  of  fact,  shortly 
afterwards,  in  1674,  ^^^  inhabitants  of  that  city  formed  a  conspiracy  against 
Spanish  rule  in  Sicily.  The  rebellion  having  been  quelled,  Borelli,  who  had 
leagued  himself  with  his  countrymen,  had  to  save  himself  by  flight.  Ruined, 
the  already  ageing  philosopher  arrived  at  Rome  and  there  at  first  obtained 
employment  in  the  service  of  Queen  Christina  of  Sweden,  who  in  her  exile, 
as  once  she  had  done  in  her  native  land,  loved  to  surround  herself  with  distin- 
guished scientists.  For  some  years  he  remained  her  private  physician  and 
actually  dedicated  the  best  of  his  writings  to  her.  But  a  fresh  misfortune 
befell  him;  through  the  dishonesty  of  a  subordinate  he  was  again  ruined, 
and  the  Queen,  whose  own  aff'airs  were,  as  is  well  known,  in  a  bad  way,  was 
unable  to  assist  him.  He  had  to  take  refuge  in  a  monastery,  and  there  he  died, 
in  1679. 

The  movements  of  animals 
BoRELLi's  restless  life  may  possibly  have  been  due  to  his  temperament,  which 
is  said  to  have  been  reserved  and  morose.  However,  he  enjoyed  a  universal 
reputation  as  one  of  the  foremost  scientists  of  his  time,  and  his  literary 
production  was  of  an  exceptionally  many-sided  character.  He  carried  on  his . 
teacher  Galileo's  work  in  physics  and  astronomy.  But  his  books  on  these 
subjects,  however  valuable  they  may  have  been,  were  entirely  overshadowed 
by  his  great  biological  work,  De  motu  ani?nalium,  which  was  published  in  the 
same  year  in  which  he  died,  dedicated,  as  mentioned  above,  to  Queen  Chris- 
tina, who,  according  to  the  preface,  defrayed  the  cost  of  printing.  Through 


152.  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

this  work  he  ranks  by  the  side  of  Harvey  as  one  of  the  leading  pioneers  of 
modern  biology. 

"As  is  generally  done  in  other  physical-mathematical  sciences,  we  shall 
endeavour,  with  phenomena  as  our  foundation,  to  expound  this  science  of 
the  movements  of  animals;  and  seeing  that  muscles  are  the  principal  organs 
of  animal  motion,  we  must  first  examine  their  structure,  parts,  and  visible 
action."  In  these  words  Borelli  states  his  views  on  the  function  of  biology 
and  thereby  declares  his  starting-point  to  be  Galileo's  conception  of  nature, 
and  the  work  reveals  the  fact  that  here,  as  with  Galileo,  we  are  face  to  face 
with  "a  new  science."  Even  the  very  arrangement  is  original:  by  means  of 
short  sentences,  which,  on  the  model  of  Euclid,  are  called  propositions,  with 
accompanying  proofs  and  corollaries,  the  inquiry  is  led  from  the  simplest 
element  of  the  motory  system,  the  individual  muscle,  gradually  to  more  and 
more  complicated  organs  and  organic  systems,  until  finally  the  whole  of  the 
being's  power  of  movement  is  described  in  the  form  of  a  summary.  First  of 
all,  of  course,  he  discusses  the  movements  in  man,  to  whom  the  lion's  share 
of  the  work  is  devoted,  after  which  he  studies  the  movements  of  mammals, 
the  flight  of  birds,  the  swimming  of  fishes,  and  even  the  characteristic  move- 
ments of  insects  and  others  of  the  lower  animals.  The  first  propositions  are 
introduced  by  an  analysis  of  the  actual  muscular  substance,  Borelli  maintain- 
ing that  these  elements  of  bodily  movement  are  identical  with  the  flesh  — 
which  the  Aristoteleans  denied.  Then  he  describes  in  detail  the  different 
mechanical  functions  of  the  muscles,  this  being  clearly  explained  in  schematic 
form,  with  figures  appended.  On  this  basis  he  then  proceeds  to  a  study  of  the 
different  forms  of  movement:  first  the  individual  extremities,  then  the  move- 
ment of  the  whole  body  under  different  kinds  of  action,  lifting,  walking, 
running,  jumping;  and  even,  what  was  for  a  southerner  an  unusual  form  of 
motion,  that  of  skating  is  observed  and  analysed.  After  the  movements  of 
mammals,  as  above  mentioned,  have  been  examined,  he  describes  birds' 
power  of  flight  in  comparison  with  the  foregoing  movements,  and  finally  he 
analyses  the  action  of  swimming,  in  which  he  pays  attention  not  only  to  the 
motory  system  of  fishes,  but  also  to  the  possibilities  of  man  and  other  land- 
creatures  in  this  respect.  In  connexion  herewith  Borelli  puts  forward  sug- 
gestions for  a  diver's  dress  and  a  submarine  vessel;  whether  he  was  ever  in  a 
position  to  make  practical  tests  of  these  inventions  history  does  not  relate. 

M-Uscular  -physiology 
In  another  part  of  his  work  Borelli  seeks  to  explain  the  causes  of  muscular 
action.  For  this  purpose  he  first  of  all  tries  a  number  of  purely  mechani- 
cal alternatives,  which  he  rejects,  among  them  being  the  possibility  of  the 
muscle's  being  shortened  merely  by  contracting  its  mass,  produced  by  the 
concentration  of  its  smallest  particles.  Such  takes  place,  according  to  Borelli, 
when  a  piece  of  red-hot  wire  becomes  shorter  on  cooling,  but  this  cannot  be 


SEVENTEENTH  AND  EIGHTEENTH  CENTURIES  153 
assumed  to  take  place  in  muscular  contraction,  which,  indeed,  occurs  as  the 
result  of  impulse  from  the  nervous  system  —  that  is  to  say,  through  fluid 
flowing  to  it  from  without.  Here  obviously  comes  in  Descartes's  theory  of 
the  currents  in  the  nerves;  on  the  basis  of  this  theory  Borelli  concludes  that 
the  swelling  of  the  muscles  upon  contraction  is  caused  by  a  process  of  fer- 
mentation, which  arises  when  the  blood  in  the  muscles  is  mixed  with  the 
nervous  fluid  flowing  into  it.  For  the  fact  that  Borelli  was  unable,  with  the 
means  available  at  that  time,  to  explain  the  extremely  involved  co-operation 
of  physical  and  chemical  processes  which  constitute  muscular  contraction, 
he  cannot,  however,  be  blamed;  on  the  contrary,  his  assumption  that  a 
complicated  chemical  action  and  not  a  simple  mechanical  one  is  here  in- 
volved must  be  admitted  to  be  an  inspired  presentiment  of  what  our  modern 
science  has  at  last  definitely  established.  After  having  then  given  an  account 
of  a  thorough  investigation  of  the  muscular  mechanism  of  the  heart  and  the 
respiratory  system,  Borelli  concludes  his  work  with  some  speculations  on 
the  subjects  of  digestion  and  fertilization,  which  are  partly  based  upon  the 
opinions  of  his  precursors  and  are  otherwise  not  very  successful,  so  that  they 
may  be  passed  over  here.  The  same  is  true  of  his  purely  medical  speculations, 
such  as  his  theory  that  fevers  do  not  originate  in  the  blood,  but  in  the  nerv- 
ous fluid,  and  other  assumptions  in  connexion  therewith. 

Borelli  creates  experimental  biology 
Borelli  was  above  all  a  mechanician  and  his  greatness  lies  in  his  having 
created  experimental  biology  operating  with  purely  mechanical  forces.  In 
the  introduction  to  his  work,  it  is  true,  he  gives  the  assurance  that  all  the 
mechanical  phenomena  in  the  living  body,  which  he  proceeds  to  describe, 
are  produced  by  the  vital  spirit  —  had  he  not  admitted  this,  he  would  cer- 
tainly never  have  obtained  the  papal  authority  to  publish  his  work,  which 
now  adorns  the  first  page  of  his  book  —  but  having  once  made  this  theoreti- 
cal reservation,  he  carefully  avoids  in  the  discussion  that  follows  the  inclusion 
of  any  other  points  than  the  purely  mechanical.  And  it  is  just  for  this  reason 
that,  in  spite  of  occasional  weaknesses,  his  work  stands  out  as  the  first  to 
apply  all  through  the  fundamental  principle  on  which  modern  biology  is 
based. 

Borelli  was  highly  appreciated  by  his  own  and  the  succeeding  age;  thus, 
the  great  Dutch  physician  Boerhaave  advises  every  doctor  to  read  the  work 
De  motu  animalium.  Although  he  was  certainly  the  foremost,  he  was  not 
the  only  scientist  of  his  kind  to  tackle  biological  problems  from  a  purely  me- 
chanical point  of  view.  Of  those  of  his  contemporaries  who  distinguished 
themselves  in  this  respect  two  in  particular  are  worthy  of  a  detailed  account. 

Claude  Perrault  was  born  in  Paris  in  161 3,  the  son  of  a  lawyer.  He 
studied  at  the  university  there;  first  of  all,  mathematics  and  the  classical 
languages,  and  then  chemistry.  Having  taken  a  doctor's  degree  he  practised 


154  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

for  a  time,  but  became  more  and  more  attracted  to  architecture.  It  is  in  this 
sphere  that  he  became  best  known:  as  the  designer  of  the  Louvre  colonnade 
he  is  mentioned  in  every  guide-book  to  Paris.  How^ever,  the  interest  in 
anatomy  that  he  acquired  as  the  result  of  his  medical  studies  he  maintained 
throughout  his  life;  he  dissected  animals  of  every  available  kind  and  com- 
pared the  results  he  achieved.  Finally  he  fell  a  victim  to  his  own  zeal:  he 
died  (in  1688)  of  blood-poisoning  contracted  when  dissecting  a  camel  that 
had  died  in  the  Royal  Zoological  Garden. 

The  work  in  which  Perrault  recorded  his  biological  speculations  bears 
the  characteristic  title  of  Essais  de  la  physique.  The  third  of  the  four  volumes 
that  the  work  comprises  is  called  Mkbanique  des  animaux,  and  in  it  he  has 
developed  his  ideas  on  the  functions  of  animal  life.  The  work  was  published 
in  1680  —  that  is  to  say,  at  the  same  time  as  Borelli's,  and,  of  course,  quite 
independently  of  the  latter's.  As  already  mentioned,  Borelli  was  a  disciple 
of  Galileo;  Perrault,  on  the  other  hand,  shows  himself  in  his  writings  to  be 
manifestly  influenced  by  Gassendi,  although  accessible  biographies  make  no 
mention  of  either  any  personal  or  any  literary  contact  between  them.  Gas- 
sendi based  his  conception  of  nature  on  the  ancient  atomic  theory,  such  as  it 
has  been  preserved  in  literature,  mainly  through  Lucretius;  moreover,  he  was 
an  admirer  of  Galileo  and  an  opponent  of  Descartes.  In  Perrault  we  find  views 
on  all  these  questions  in  full  accord  with  Gassendi.  In  his  first  chapter  he 
states  matter  to  be  composed  of  individual  particles,  at  the  same  time  hard 
and  elastic;  the  air  in  particular  is  composed  partly  of  finer,  spherical  and 
partly  of  coarser,  cubiform  particles.  On  the  other  hand,  when  it  comes  to  a 
question  of  gravity,  Perrault  shows  himself  familiar  with  Galileo's  discover- 
ies in  that  field,  and  finally  he  sharply  criticizes  Descartes,  particularly  his 
theory  that  animals  lack  consciousness.  In  opposition  to  this  assertion 
Perrault  maintains  the  independent  and  peculiar  intelligence  of  animals, 
citing  numerous  examples. 

Perrault' s  philosophical  method 
With  regard  to  the  knowledge  of  animals,  as  also  with  regard  to  physics, 
Perrault  lays  down  two  scientific  methods:  the  "historical,"  which  is  purely 
descriptive,  and  the  "philosophical,"  which  seeks  to  ascertain  the  causes 
of  what  takes  place  in  nature.  Following  this  philosophical  method,  Per- 
rault deals  with  special  phenomena  in  the  animal  kingdom,  wherein  he 
endeavours  always  to  find  out  the  mechanical  connexion  of  causes,  declaring 
that  this  is  all  that  it  is  possible  for  m.an  to  discover.  He  entirely  disagrees 
with  both  the  older,  idealistic  philosophy,  which  scorns  to  have  anything 
to  do  with  natural  phenomena,  and  the  younger  philosophy  —  that  is,  that 
of  Descartes  —  which  denies  all  manifestations  of  soul  in  animals.  Perrault 
then  tries  to  ascertain  the  mechanical  course  in  quite  a  number  of  vital  func- 
tions; particularly  sense-impressions,  the  digestion,  and  the  external  move- 


SEVENTEENTH     AND     EIGHTEENTH     CENTURIES       155 

merits  of  the  body.  On  all  these  subjects  he  expresses  original  opinions, 
constantly  pointing  out  comparisons  with  mechanical  organizations  in  ani- 
mate nature,  and  in  doing  so  he  displays  throughout  his  capacity  as  a  prac- 
tical technician.  Thus,  he  compares  the  muscles  which  act  counter  to  one 
another  in  an  arm  with  the  shrouds  on  a  boat-mast  which  counterbalance 
one  another;  in  another  connexion  the  valves  of  the  heart  are  compared  with 
the  mechanism  of  a  sluice-gate.  His  study  of  the  mechanism  of  the  auditory 
organ  is  full  of  striking  observations;  in  regard  to  the  visual  organ,  too, 
he  makes  some  interesting  comparisons  —  for  instance,  between  the  lenses 
in  different  animals  —  although  naturally  the  results  of  modern  optics, 
founded  by  Huygens  and  Newton,  are  unknown  to  him.  In  every  case  he 
tries  in  the  first  place  to  ascertain  the  nature  of  the  movements  performed 
by  the  different  parts  of  the  body;  consequently  he  pays  special  attention  to 
the  structure  and  function  of  the  muscles;  in  contrast  to  Borelli,  however, 
he  entertains  the  false  idea  that  it  is  not  "the  flesh,"  but  the  interposed 
lengthwise  and  crosswise  fibres  —  that  is  to  say,  the  connective  tissue  — 
which  expands  and  contracts.  He  gives  a  detailed  description  of  this  proc- 
ess; he  believes  that  the  muscle  in  its  natural  position  is  contracted;  when 
it  relaxes,  it  does  so  because  the  nerves  convey  to  the  muscular  fibres  a 
"substance  sfiritueuse,'"  which  expands  them  just  as  metals  are  expanded  by 
heat.  The  motory  impulses  therefor  come  from  the  brain;  of  its  parts  he  con- 
siders the  medulla  oblongata  to  be  the  most  essential  and  the  great  brain  the 
least  important;  he  had,  indeed,  observed  that  it  is  possible  to  remove  the 
great  brain  from  a  live  dog  without  the  animal's  dying,  but  if  the  medulla 
oblongata  is  injured  the  dog  dies  at  once.  This  fact  the  physiology  of  our  own 
day  has,  of  course,  confirmed,  although  the  conclusion  which  Perrault  draws 
from  it  as  to  the  lesser  importance  of  the  great  brain  is  wrong.  To  "peris- 
taltics,"  by  which  he  means  the  movements  within  the  body,  he  devotes 
a  special  chapter,  which  likewise  contains  many  keen-sighted  observations, 
the  process  of  nutrition  as  a  w^hole  being  of  particular  interest  to  him;  natu- 
rally, however,  he  has  a  number  of  false  ideas  as  to  its  chemistry,  such  as 
his  belief  that  the  air  contains  directly  alimentary  constituents,  proved  by 
the  fact  that  some  broods  of  serpents,  which  were  kept  in  a  jar  without 
food,  developed  "on  air."  Owing  to  the  limited  possibilities  of  investi- 
gation in  those  days,  we  cannot  blame  him  for  being  unable  to  discover  that 
animals  have  an  embryonic  reserve  nutriment  to  live  on. 

In  spite  of  occasional  fallacies,  Perrault  may  thus  be  regarded,  side  by 
side  with  Borelli,  as  one  of  the  pioneers  of  modern  biology.  Besides  these, 
the  Danish  philosopher  Steno,  well  known  for  the  strange  fate  that  befell 
him,  is  worthy  of  mention  as  having  been  active  in  the  same  direction. 

Nils  Steensen,  known  under  the  latinized  form  of  his  name,  Nicolaus 
Steno,  was  born  in  Copenhagen  in  1638,  of  a  wealthy  family  of  goldsmiths. 


156  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

He  early  showed  an  inclination  for  medical  studies,  which  he  was  able  to 
carry  out  first  at  home  under  Bartholin,  and  then  in  Amsterdam  and  Leyden. 
He  soon  made  important  anatomical  discoveries,  which  gained  him  a  Euro- 
pean reputation.  After  this  he  spent  some  years  in  his  native  city  seeking 
employment  at  the  University,  but  as  he  was  constantly  passed  over  in  favour 
of  the  relations  of  Bartholin,  he  grew  weary  of  waiting,  and  having  received 
his  paternal  inheritance,  he  journeyed  to  Paris.  There  he  studied  cerebral 
anatomy  for  a  time,  publishing  a  treatise  on  that  subject,  and  then  went  to 
Italy,  where  he  worked  at  Pavia  and  Florence.  The  Grand  Duke  of  Tuscany 
was  very  gracious  to  him  and  gave  him  money  to  continue  his  studies  and 
his  publications.  Under  these  new  conditions,  however,  Steno  underwent 
a  severe  spiritual  crisis,  resulting  in  his  being  converted  to  Catholicism,  a 
step  which  brought  him  brilliant  worldly  advantages,  but  soon  completely 
upset  his  intellectual  balance.  After  spending  some  time  in  his  native  country, 
where  the  authorities  had  now  learnt  —  too  late  —  to  estimate  him  at  his 
true  value  and  offered  him  a  position  that  would  bring  in  a  good  income, 
though  at  the  same  time  they  naturally  did  not  look  with  favour  upon  his 
religious  conversion,  he  returned  to  Italy,  took  holy  orders,  and  was  soon 
appointed  bishop  and  chief  organizer  of  Catholic  propaganda  in  north  Ger- 
many. In  the  latter  capacity  he  displayed  fanatic  zeal;  he  addressed  a  letter 
to  Spinoza,  amongst  others,  with  whom  he  had  been  acquainted  in  his 
youth,  urging  him  to  become  converted,  which  the  latter  declined  to  answer. 
At  the  same  time  he  gave  himself  up  to  violent  asceticism,  which  rapidly 
undermined  his  health.  He  was  only  forty-eight  when  he  died  (in  the  year 
1686),  and  he  was  buried  with  great  pomp  at  Florence,  where  a  fine  monu- 
ment in  the  Church  of  San  Lorenzo  perpetuates  his  memory. 

As  an  anatomist  Steno  devoted  himself  principally  to  the  study  of  two 
organic  systems:  the  glandular  and  the  muscular  systems.  With  regard  to 
the  glands,  Glisson  and  Wharton  had,  of  course,  been  the  pioneers,  but  Steno 
at  any  rate  made  fresh  and  important  contributions  to  the  knowledge  of 
these  organs;  he  discovers  the  exit  of  the  parotid  gland,  which  has  been 
given  the  name  of  "  diictus  stenoniatius" ;  he  thoroughly  explained  the  anat- 
omy of  the  other  glands  of  the  mouth,  and,  lastly,  found  the  exit  of  the 
tear  gland.  As  an  anatomist  of  the  muscular  system  his  chief  aim  was,  as 
he  himself  says,  to  apply  to  anatomy  the  laws  of  mathematics  and  thus  to 
create  a  geometrical  system  for  the  muscles.  His  main  work  on  muscular 
investigation,  in  which  he  carefully  analyses,  along  the  lines  just  indicated, 
a  number  of  muscles,  starting  from  their  simple  component  parts,  was  pub- 
lished twelve  years  before  Borelli's  important  work.  In  this  book  Steno's 
theory  is  expounded,  though  Borelli  expressly  states  that  its  rules  apply  only 
in  certain  special  cases.  In  actual  fact  Steno's  work  deals  with  a  far  more 
limited  field  of  investigation  than  Borelli's;  in  method  it  is  more  speculative 


SEVENTEENTH     AND     EIGHTEENTH     CENTURIES       157 

and  less  experimental  than  the  latter's,  and  therefore,  though  published 
earlier,  it  has  not  the  same  universal  application  as  the  work  De  motu  animal- 

ium. 

Steno  as  a  paleontologist 
Besides  the  above  work  Steno  found  time  during  the  short  period  which  he 
devoted  to  natural  science  to  make  a  number  of  important  contributions. 
Thus,  he  discovered  the  ovaries  in  the  shark,  which,  as  is  well  known, 
produces  its  young  alive  —  a  discovery  the  importance  of  which  he  himself 
fully  realized;  up  to  that  time  people  had  thought  that  ovaries  existed  only 
in  oviparous  animals.  Steno's  greatest  service  to  biology,  however,  is  his 
creation  of  modern  palaeontology.  Already  during  his  first  visit  to  Florence 
he  had  had  an  opportunity  of  studying  a  kind  of  stone  images  found  in  great 
numbers  there,  which  the  inhabitants  called  " glossopetrf  or  stone-tongues, 
and  by  means  of  comparative  study  he  proved  that  they  must  have  been  the 
teeth  of  sharks.  During  his  later  sojourn  in  Tuscany  he  carried  out  a  system- 
atic study  of  that  district's  geological  strata,  and  thought  himself  justified 
in  concluding  from  their  position  and  appearance  that  they  had  been  strati- 
fied out  of  water,  a  fact  which  he  believed  to  be  still  further  confirmed  by 
the  quantity  of  animals  and  plants  found  in  them.  Supported  by  these  facts, 
he  outlines  a  theory  of  the  origin  of  the  earth's  strata  which  is  a  presage  of 
present-day  geological  science.  He  never  got  further  than  this  rough  out- 
line, however;  the  results  of  his  geological  investigations  would  not,  as 
the  times  were  then,  accord  with  the  Church  doctrine  that  he  had  so  zeal- 
ously embraced,  and,  indeed,  this  was  one  of  the  reasons  why  he  completely 
abandoned  a  science  which  he  had  initiated  and  studied  with  such  splendid 
results.  A  tragic  fate  indeed,  although  by  no  means  without  its  counterpart 
in  scientific  history.  In  this  his  last  natural-scientific  work,  however,  Steno 
deals  also  with  other  problems  besides  the  purely  geological  and  pateonto- 
logical.  His  geological  stratification  theory  is  really  only  one  link  in  a  gen- 
eral theory  regarding  transubstantiation  in  nature,  according  to  which  all 
things  that  exist  have  originally  been  and  are  still  being  precipitated  out  of 
fluids.  He  thus  comes  to  the  question  of  the  crystallization  process  in  the 
mineral  kingdom,  which  he  investigated  with  great  thoroughness  and  good 
results,  and  in  connexion  therewith  he  discusses  the  transubstantiation  and 
organic  formation  in  animals,  which  he  likewise  conceives  to  be  a  strati- 
ficational  process  similar  to  that  which  takes  place  in  inanimate  nature,  a 
precipitation  from  fluids,  of  which  he  distinguishes  various  kinds  in  the  ani- 
mal and  plant  organism.  Thus  he  reconciles  the  changes  in  substance  in  ani- 
mate and  inanimate  nature  under  the  same  point  of  view  and  without  giving 
any  idea  of  the  essential  diff^erence  between  the  growth  of  a  crystal  and  that 
of  a  living  organism.  This,  then,  clearly  denotes  the  limitation  in  the  me- 
chanical   conception  of  nature  in  the  seventeenth  century  —  a  limitation 


158  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

which  undoubtedly  contributed  to  the  fact  that  the  promising  ideas  which 
such  investigators  as  Borelli,  Perrault,  and  Steno  had  produced  were  not 
followed  up.  The  insignificant  progress  made  in  the  sphere  of  organic  chem- 
istry at  that  period  in  fact  rendered  impossible  the  expansion  of  experimental 
biology  beyond  the  purely  mechanical  sphere  in  which  the  scientists  here 
mentioned  achieved  such  splendid  results.  Another  reason  why  biological 
research  took  a  new  direction,  however,  proved  of  still  more  decisive  im- 
portance —  the  discovery  of  the  microscope,  and  its  constant  improvement, 
resulting  in  the  opening  up  of  hitherto  unguessed  possibilities  for  biology. 
We  shall  now  proceed  to  discuss  this  method  and  its  representatives. 


3.  Microscopies  and  Microtechnology 

The  fact  that  ground  lenses  magnify  the  vision  seems  to  have  been 
already  established  in  classical  antiquity.  Eye-glasses  and  simple  magnifying- 
glasses  came  into  use  in  the  sixteenth  century;  the  inventors  of  complex  len- 
ticular systems  are  commonly  said  to  have  been  two  Dutch  spectacle-makers, 
Janssen  by  name,  father  and  son.  These  earliest  microscopes  must  have  been 
extremely  primitive:  a  tube  with  a  plate  for  the  object,  without  any  adjust- 
ing apparatus,  and  the  lens  or  lenses  at  the  other  end  of  the  tube;  the  tube 
was  held  to  the  eye  and  directed  when  in  use  towards  the  light  like  a  tele- 
scope. The  magnification  was,  to  start  with,  not  more  than  ten  times,  but 
it  nevertheless  excited  general  wonder,  especially  when  tiny  live  creeping 
things  were  put  under  the  microscope  and  could  show  their  movements.  It 
was  considered  particularly  fascinating  to  watch  fleas,  from  which  the  earli- 
est type  of  microscope  received  the  name  of  "  vitrum  pulkare,"  or  flea-glass. 
During  the  seventeenth  century,  however,  the  construction  of  the  micro- 
scope, chiefly  the  system  of  lenses,  was  considerably  improved,  with  the 
result  that  good  individual  instruments  made  by  clever  masters  in  the  art, 
such  as  the  Dutchman  Leeuwenhoek,  mentioned  below,  could  magnify  up 
to  iyo  times.  But  throughout  the  eighteenth  century  and  for  a  good  part  of 
the  nineteenth,  microscope  construction  underwent  but  few  changes,  except 
for  isolated  improvements,  such  as  the  introduction  of  a  stand  and  mirror, 
and  it  was  not  until  the  thirties  that  the  long  line  of  new  inventions  that 
have  gradually  made  the  microscope  what  it  is  today  had  their  beginning. 
Microscopy  has  had,  therefore,  two  periods  of  brilliant  achievement  in  the 
course  of  its  history:  the  seventeenth  century,  and  the  latter  half  of  the  nine- 
teenth century  up  to  the  present  day. 

Even  Harvey,  according  to  his  own  statement,  used  a  " perspicillum" 
when  studying  the  circulation  of  the  blood  in  insects.  The  first  scientific 
treatise  that  is  based  exclusively  on  microscopical  investigations  was  the 


SEVENTEENTH     AND     EIGHTEENTH     CENTURIES       159 

Italian  Francisco  Stelluti's  study  of  the  structure  of  the  bee,  which  was 
published  in  Rome  in  16x5.  But  foremost  among  those  who  systematically- 
based  their  research  on  magnifying  apparatus  must  be  mentioned  the  Italian 
Malpighi. 

Marcello  Malpighi  was  born  in  i6i8  at  Cavalcuorc,  a  place  near  Bo- 
logna, where  his  father  owned  an  estate.  Here  Marcello  spent  his  childhood. 
At  an  early  age  he  became  a  student  at  Bologna  and  devoted  himself  to  the 
study  of  Aristotelean  philosophy.  He  had  to  break  off  his  studies,  however, 
upon  the  death  of  both  his  parents,  in  1649,  ^^'^  ^^'^  ^^  leave  the  University 
for  a  year  or  two  in  order  to  settle  his  father's  affairs  and  look  after  his 
younger  brothers  and  sisters.  With  this  latter  end  in  view  he  returned  to  the 
University,  after  a  short  time  graduated  as  a  doctor  (in  1653),  and  then 
devoted  himself  to  medical  practice  and  university  teaching.  His  brilliant 
gifts  were  soon  apparent,  but  certain  intrigues  delayed  his  advancement,  and 
when  at  last  —  in  1656  —  the  Senate  of  Bologna  instituted  a  professorship 
for  his  special  benefit,  he  preferred  to  accept  an  appointment  to  a  chair  of 
medicine  at  Pisa.  There  he  got  to  know  Borelli,  and  their  acquaintance  de- 
veloped into  a  lifelong,  firm  friendship,  Borelli  in  the  beginning  possessed 
a  tutorial  influence  over  his  colleague,  who  was  twenty  years  younger,  and 
taught  him  to  realize  the  defects  in  the  Aristoteleanism  which  he  had  till 
then  embraced.  Malpighi,  however,  considering  that  the  climate  of  Pisa  was 
bad  for  his  health,  returned  once  more  to  Bologna,  but  shortly  afterwards 
he  was  called,  upon  Borelli's  recommendation,  to  be  professor  at  Messina, 
at  a  good  salary.  After  four  years,  however,  he  relinquished  this  appoint- 
ment, owing  to  intrigues  and  troublesome  interference  on  the  part  of  the 
authorities.  So  for  the  third  time  —  in  1666  —  he  returned  to  Bologna, 
where  a  professorship  awaited  him,  which  he  held  with  honour  for  twenty- 
five  years.  In  1691,  being  then  in  his  sixty-fourth  year  and  in  failing  health, 
he  went  to  Rome  and  became  private  physician  to  the  Pope,  and  he  died 
there  of  apoplexy  three  years  later  —  in  1694. 

In  contrast  to  most  of  the  biologists  of  the  earlier  period,  but  like  so 
many  of  those  of  the  present  day,  Malpighi  published  his  observations  not 
in  large  consecutive  works,  but  in  the  form  of  short  reports,  sometimes  com- 
prising only  a  few  pages,  usually  sent  in  to  the  Royal  Society  of  London, 
of  which  he  was  a  member  and  which  undertook  the  printing  of  them.  Prac- 
tically every  one  of  these  small  papers  contained  some  important  discovery 
in  different  branches  of  biology.  The  connecting  link  in  this  literary  work 
is  not  any  common  idea  running  through  it  all,  but  is  represented  by  micro- 
scopical technology,  which  Malpighi  with  hitherto  unrivalled  genius  ap- 
plied to  every  imaginable  object  in  living  nature  that  came  within  his  range. 
Thus  Malpighi  was  the  founder  of  microscopical  anatomy  in  both  the  ;:nimal 
and  the  vegetable  kingdoms.  One  reason  for  the  disconnected  way  in  which 


l6o  THE     HISTORY     OF      BIOLOGY 

he  recorded  his  experiences  may  perhaps  be  found  in  his  lack  of  capacity 
as  a  writer;  indeed,  from  the  point  of  view  of  style  his  papers  were  not  of 
a  high  standard,  his  exposition  being  often  unclear  and  at  times  almost 
impossible  to  understand. 

Malpigbi's  investigations 
Of  Malpighi's  writings  the  first  in  point  of  time  and  undoubtedly  the  most 
important  as  to  contents  is  the  short  account,  in  the  form  of  two  letters 
addressed  to  Borelli,  of  his  investigation  of  the  structure  of  the  lungs.  In 
the  first  of  these  essays  he  declares  that  the  substance  of  the  lungs  had  till 
that  time  been  regarded  as  "fleshlike,"  which  was  incorrect;  the  lung  con- 
sists rather  of  a  network  of  extremely  thin-walled  cells,  which  are  connected 
with  the  finest  ramifications  of  the  windpipe.  This,  he  states,  can  best  be 
observed  by  flushing  out  with  water  the  blood  from  a  fresh  lung,  then  in- 
flating the  lung  through  the  windpipe,  and  afterwards  drying  it.  In  con- 
nexion with  this  discovery  he  advances  some  speculations  with  regard  to 
the  function  of  the  lungs,  which  he  assumes  to  be  to  keep  the  blood  flowing 
and  to  prevent  it  from  coagulating,  which  happens  when  it  has  run  out  of 
the  veins.  He  also  discusses  the  high  temperature  which  fever  produces  in 
the  blood  and  considers  it  to  be  due  to  a  process  of  fermentation.  In  the 
second  letter  he  gives  an  account  of  the  finer  structure  of  the  lung  of  the 
frog,  and  in  connexion  therewith  he  describes  his  discovery  of  the  capillary 
circulation  as  a  connecting  link  between  arteries  and  veins,  which  he  also 
observed  in  the  frog.  In  order  to  demonstrate  this  vascular  system  he  recom- 
mends that  a  frog's  lung  be  inflated,  then  dried,  and  in  that  state  examined 
under  a  magnifying-glass.  He  himself  emphasizes  the  importance  of  the  fact 
that  the  transition  between  the  venous  and  the  arterial  blood  had  been  dis- 
covered, and  posterity  has  confirmed  the  truth  of  his  discovery.  The  achieve- 
ment that  comes  next  in  importance  is  his  investigation  of  a  series  of  organs 
which  he  placed  in  the  category  of  the  glands.  These  investigations  he  carried 
out  partly  with  fresh  material,  partly  with  such  as  had  been  hardened  by 
cooking,  besides  which,  by  means  of  injections  into  the  blood-vessels  and 
the  preparation  of  the  tissues,  he  endeavoured  to  trace  the  minutest  elements 
of  the  organ.  In  the  liver,  with  which  he  started  his  investigation,  he  thus 
followed  the  blood-vessels  up  to  their  finest  ramifications,  which  he  con- 
nected with  a  mass  of  small  protuberances  which  may  be  brought  up  on 
the  cooked  liver.  By  establishing  the  existence  of  these  he  considered  the 
liver's  glandular  character  proved,  which  modern  science  has  shown  to  be 
correct,  although  the  small  protuberances  are  actually  pure  outgrowths 
without  any  equivalent  in  the  true  structure  of  the  liver.  Malpighi  also  in- 
cludes in  his  investigations  of  glands  his  observations  of  the  cortex  of  the 
cerebrum.  He  observed  in  this  organ  the  pyramid-cells,  which  he  believes 
to  be  glandular  elements  that  secrete  the  '  fluidum"  whereby  the  muscles  are 


SEVENTEENTH     AND     EIGHTEENTH     CENTURIES       l6l 

moved  to  contract.  The  nerves,  which  are  hollow,  form  the  passages  out- 
wards for  this  fluid,  the  nature  of  which  Malpighi  does  not  further  describe, 
although,  like  Willis,  he  seems  to  regard  it  mostly  as  some  kind  of  fugitive 
liquid.  For  the  rest,  he  has  made  contributions  to  the  knowledge  of  the 
blood-vessels'  ramifications  in  the  brain;  on  the  other  hand,  his  speculations 
in  regard  to  the  function  of  the  cerebral  cortex  are  not  very  enlightening, 
just  as,  on  the  whole,  Malpighi  was  more  of  a  practical  observer  than  a 
theoretician.  It  was  left  to  Swedenborg,  a  couple  of  generations  after  Mal- 
pighi, to  work  out  an  explanation  —  partly  based  on  the  latter's  observa- 
tions —  of  the  localizations  in  the  cortex  of  the  brain,  which  even  our  own 
age  might  well  think  remarkable.  —  Finally,  Malpighi  studied  the  kidney 
and  the  spleen,  using  the  same  methods  as  those  applied  to  his  observations 
of  the  above-mentioned  organs,  and  in  this  field,  too,  he  achieved  valuable 
results;  in  the  kidney  he  established  the  course  of  the  blood-vessels  and  of 
the  tubules  and  has  in  general  given  a  good  description  of  the  inner  structure 
of  the  organ  in  man  and  in  several  other  mammal  forms;  the  glomeruli  of 
the  kidney  still  bear  his  name,  and  likewise  the  name  of  the  Malpighian 
follicular  bodies  in  the  spleen  testify  to  his  powers  of  observation.  Extremely 
useful  has  been  Malpighi's  monograph  on  the  tongue,  the  muscles  and  nerves 
of  which  he  explained  and  the  papillas  of  which  he  described  and  charac- 
terized as  gustatory  organs.  And  finally  he  published  an  account  of  the  de- 
velopment of  the  hen's  egg,  which  forms  a  creditable  supplement  to  the 
investigations  previously  carried  out  by  Fabrizio  and  Harvey.  In  the  sphere 
of  invertebrate  biology  Malpighi  has  also  performed  a  service  by  investi- 
gating the  structure  and  history  of  the  development  of  the  silk-worm;  he 
discovered  in  this  subject  the  excretal  organs  characteristic  of  the  Tracheata, 
which  are  now  called  the  Malpighian  tubes,  and  in  other  respects,  too,  he 
laid  the  foundations  of  our  knowledge  of  the  anatomy  of  insect  larval  forms 
and  likewise  made  valuable  observations  regarding  the  butterfly's  evolution 
out  of  the  pupa  and  its  anatomical  structure. 

Malpighi's  works  on  vegetable  anatomy 
There  still  remains  to  give  an  account  of  Malpighi's  activities  as  a  pioneer 
in  a  quite  new  field  —  vegetable  anatomy.  Biology,  as  a  universal  science 
of  life  and  its  manifestations,  has  for  obvious  reasons  been  based  principally 
on  the  study  of  those  creatures  which  have  stood  in  the  closest  relation  to 
man  —  that  is  to  say,  first  and  foremost  man  himself,  and  secondly  the  higher 
and  lower  animals;  for  the  purposes  of  this  science  plants  have  as  a  rule  come 
last.  There  are  two  fields  of  biological  study,  however,  in  which  plants  have 
from  the  beginning  been  more  useful  for  standardizing  purposes  than  ani- 
mals —  namely,  classification  and  the  cell  and  tissue  principle.  The  fact  that 
plants  have  proved  a  more  convenient  starting-point  in  this  latter  sphere 
is,  of  course,  due  to  their  having,  on  account  of  their  cellulose  formations. 


l6l  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

such  extremely  easily  discernible  elements.  Thanks  to  the  resultant  structural 
conditions,  which  in  their  main  features  are  distinguishable  even  to  the 
naked  eye,  plants  have  constituted  the  starting-point  for  the  study  of  the 
elementary  nature  of  living  matter  as  a  whole.  And  the  honour  of  having 
introduced  this  study  into  science  is  due  to  Malpighi,  even  though  he  may 
have  had  to  share  it  to  a  certain  extent  with  another,  the  English  physician 
Grew. 

The  results  of  Malpighi's  investigations  into  the  subject  of  vegetable 
anatomy  were,  after  ten  years  of  preparation,  submitted  to  the  Royal  Society 
of  London  and  were  there  published.  They  consist  of  a  comparative  study  of 
the  anatomy  of  different  plants,  both  ligneous  plants  and  herbs.  First  the 
structure  of  the  bark  is  described,  then  that  of  the  wood  and  pith,  and  finally 
the  buds,  leaves,  flowers,  and  fruits.  The  different  parts  of  these  plants  are 
composed  of  small  "utriculi"  or  cells,  which  can  be  distinguished  by  means 
of  a  magnifying-glass  and  which  in  their  turn  form  a  larger  connective  group. 
The  cuticle  and  bast  of  the  bark,  the  vesicular  system  of  the  wood  and  its 
fibres  are  analysed,  special  interest  being  devoted  to  the  spiral  vessels,  whose 
inner  spiral  thickening  induces  a  comparison  with  the  tracheal  system  of 
insects,  in  regard  not  only  to  structure,  but  also  to  function.  Upon  this  chance 
similarity  Malpighi  now  bases  a  universal  theory  of  respiration  applicable 
to  all  living  creatures  —  which,  for  all  its  conjectural  ideas,  represents  a 
shrewd  guess  as  to  the  uniformity  of  life-phenomena  in  all  organisms.  He 
believes  that  the  more  perfect  the  living  beings  are,  the  smaller  their  re- 
spiratory organs  are:  man  and  the  higher  animals  do  with  a  pair  of  lungs 
of  comparatively  small  size,  whereas  fishes  have  numerous  closely  ramified 
gills,  and  the  tracheae  of  insects  spread  throughout  the  entire  body,  while 
again  the  spiral  vessels  in  plants  develop  in  such  quantities  that  they  fill 
up  even  the  most  insignificant  ramifications  of  the  individual  plant.  Plants, 
he  supposes,  take  up  air  out  of  the  soil  through  the  roots;  the  leaves  possess 
no  openings  that  could  serve  this  purpose.  With  regard  to  the  significance 
of  respiration  for  living  beings,  he  believes  that  it  consists  in  promoting  the 
mobility  and  "fermentation"  of  the  alimental  juices.  On  the  whole,  fermen- 
tation plays  much  the  same  part  in  Malpighi's  physiological  speculations 
as  "cooking"  does  in  Aristotle's;  at  any  rate,  it  constitutes  an  advance,  in 
spite  of  the  indefiniteness  of  the  idea,  which  was  inevitable  considering  the 
stage  of  development  which  chemistry  had  reached  in  those  days.  In  con- 
nexion with  his  account  of  the  elementary  constituents  of  plants  Malpighi 
advances  a  number  of  general  physiological  speculations,  all  intending  to 
demonstrate  similarities  between  vegetable  and  animal  organisms  and  their 
functions.  In  doing  so  he  only  follows,  it  is  true,  a  principle  which  was  pecul- 
iar to  a  botanist  of  that  time  and  which  had  its  origin  in  Cesalpino's  phys- 
iological speculations  on  plants,  to  which  we  shall  revert  later  on.  It  is, 


SEVENTEENTH  AND  EIGHTEENTH  CENTURIES  1 63 
however,  but  natural  in  the  circumstances  that  these  comparisons  should 
lead  to  false  conclusions,  and,  as  a  matter  of  fact,  they  did  to  a  great  extent 
prevent  Malpighi  from  taking  advantage  of  the  promising  material  for  study, 
which  otherwise  he  might  possibly  have  been  able  to  do.  Thus  he  compares 
the  buds,  out  of  which  gradually  sprout  leaves  and  branches,  with  the  ovary 
and  the  uterus;  then  he  deals  with  the  flowers  and  carefully  compares  their 
special  parts  in  different  plants;  as  he  fails  to  clear  up  the  question  of  their 
sexuality  he  advances  the  theory  that  the  flowers  serve  to  purify  the  juices 
of  the  plants  before  germination,  just  as  menstruation  precedes  pregnancy. 
He  studied  the  evolution  of  the  vegetable  substance  in  a  number  of  different 
seeds,  but  seeks  to  identify  therewith  the  uterus,  the  Fallopian  tube,  the 
umbilicus,  and  the  amnion,  which  naturally  leads  him  to  extravagant  con- 
clusions. Malpighi  devoted  special  attention  to  the  study  of  gall-formations 
in  a  number  of  vegetable  forms;  he  is  fully  convinced  that  they  are  produced 
by  insects,  but  on  the  other  hand  he  found  that  the  tubercles  on  the  roots  of 
pulse  plants  are  not  produced  by  insects,  though  he  failed  to  find  any  other 
explanation  of  their  origin.^  He  also  studied  and  speculated  on  a  number  of 
other  malformations  in  plants;  with  regard  to  the  tubers  in  many  plants, 
he  is  of  the  firm  opinion  that  they  contain  reserve  nutriment.  He  is  again 
tempted,  however,  by  the  theory  of  the  nutriment  of  plants,  with  which 
he  closes  his  work,  to  make  dangerous  comparisons  with  the  conditions  ob- 
taining in  the  animal  kingdom. 

The  other  creator  of  plant  anatomy 
At  the  same  time,  however,  as  Malpighi  submitted  the  first  part  of  his  vege- 
table anatomy  to  the  Royal  Society,  that  society  had  sent  to  the  printers 
another  work  on  the  same  subject  compiled  independently  of  Malpighi  by 
an  English  doctor,  Nehemiah  Grew.  Born  in  i6i8.  Grew  was  the  son  of  a 
clergyman  who  during  the  great  Civil  War  joined  the  opponents  of  the  Crown 
and  so,  upon  the  return  of  Charles  II,  was  deprived  of  his  benefice.  His  son, 
who  was  then  an  undergraduate  at  Cambridge,  went  (presumably  for  the 
same  reason)  to  continue  his  studies  abroad.  In  1671  he  graduated  at  Leyden, 
with  a  dissertation  on  the  fluids  of  the  nervous  system.  He  then  settled  down 
as  a  practitioner  in  a  provincial  town,  but,  thanks  to  the  reputation  he  gained 
by  his  work  in  vegetable  anatomy,  he  was  able  within  a  short  time  to  move 
to  London,  where  he  applied  himself  to  both  medical  practice  and  research, 
eventually  becoming  secretary  to  the  Royal  Society.  He  died  in  lyiz. 

As  a  scientist  Grew  concentrated  almost  exclusively  upon  vegetable  anat- 
omy, whereby  his  investigations  at  once  acquire  a  different  character  from 
those  of  Malpighi,  in  that  the  latter's  constantly  repeated  comparisons  with 
human  and  animal  anatomy  are  altogether  lacking.  Grew  also  studied  the 

^  It  is  only  in  our  own  time  that  it  has  been  established  that  they  are  produced  by 
bacteria. 


1 64  THEHISTORYOFBIOLOGY 

construction  of  the  fruit  substance  and  the  germination  of  the  seed  in  a 
number  of  plants,  but  in  doing  so  he  employs  a  terminology  of  his  own, 
nor  does  he  borrow  anything  from  animal  anatomy;  the  word  "paren- 
chyma," which  he  invented,  has  been  retained  in  vegetable  anatomy.  He 
describes  plants  organ  by  organ;  cells  and  vessels  in  the  stem  he  discovered 
independently  of  Malpighi  and  on  the  whole  describes  the  anatomical  details 
more  soberly  and  in  greater  detail,  though  with  less  fertility  of  ideas,  than 
the  latter.  He  advanced  a  theory  that  the  pistil  in  plants  corresponds  to  the 
female,  and  the  stamen,  with  its  pollen,  to  the  male,  and  pointed  out  their 
hermaphroditism,  but,  on  the  other  hand,  he  entered  into  speculations  upon 
male  and  female  ' '  juices ' '  in  plants,  which  are  of  no  interest  nowadays  except 
from  the  point  of  view  of  mere  curiosity.  He  voluntarily  abandoned  in  favour 
of  Malpighi  any  claim  to  priority  in  regard  to  the  discovery  of  the  vascular 
system  in  plants;  on  the  other  hand,  Malpighi  undertook  a  Latin  translation 
of  Grew's  writings.  These  two  scientists  improved  vegetable  anatomy  so 
far  it  was  to  take  more  than  a  century  before  any  important  addition  could 
be  made  to  their  work.  Through  them  biology  acquired  its  knowledge  of 
organized  matter  as  being  something  peculiar  in  its  structure;  the  idea  of 
tissue  was  established  —  for  the  time  being,  it  is  true,  only  in  the  sphere 
of  botany  —  and  in  the  vegetable  kingdom,  also,  the  simple  elements  of  the 
tissues  —  the  cells  —  were  observed  and  described.  It  was,  however,  to  be 
nearly  two  centuries  before  the  fundamental  value  of  these  achievements  was 
fully  appreciated;  true,  both  their  contemporaries  and  the  immediately  suc- 
ceeding age  admired  the  exactness  of  their  investigations,  but  it  considered 
the  results  more  from  the  point  of  view  of  curiosity.  All  the  greater  admira- 
tion is  due  to  those  scientists  who  at  any  rate  guessed  that  here  was  to  hand 
information  of  the  highest  importance  for  the  future  of  science.  The  fact 
that  their  contemporaries  failed  to  continue  along  the  line  they  had  laid 
down  was  undoubtedly  due  mostly  to  the  microscope's  having  at  the  same 
time  opened  up  a  field  in  the  sphere  of  animal  anatomy  of  such  considerable 
scope  and  of  greater  immediate  interest.  The  anatomy  of  the  lower  animals 
in  particular  was  an  entirely  unexploited  field,  possessing  vast  possibilities 
for  development,  of  which,  indeed,  splendid  advantage  was  taken  just  about 
that  time. 

Antony  van  Leeuwenhoek  was  born  in  1631  at  Delft  in  Holland  and  was 
sent  as  a  boy  to  Amsterdam  to  be  trained  for  business.  Having  worked  for 
a  time  in  the  cloth  trade,  he  returned  to  his  native  town  and  got  an  appoint- 
ment with  the  municipal  authorities,^  which  must  have  taken  up  very  little 
of  his  time,  since  he  was  able  to  devote  the  greater  part  of  his  days  to  indulg- 
ing his  interest  in  the  study  of  nature.  As  a  research-worker  Leeuwenhoek 

^  His  title  was  "  Kamerbewarer  der  Kamer  van  Heerea  Schepen  van  Delft." 


SEVENTEENTH     AND     EIGHTEENTH     CENTURIES       165 

was  a  self-taught  man;  he  had  never  received  any  scientific  training,  and  as 
he  knew  no  Latin,  in  which  language  most  natural  philosophers  of  that 
time  generally  published  their  works,  he  was  unable  in  his  old  age  to  come 
into  contact  with  the  scientific  life  around  him;  he  had  to  depend  entirely 
upon  himself.  It  was  the  remarkable  phenomena  revealed  by  the  magnifying- 
glass  that  fascinated  him  from  the  very  beginning;  he  taught  himself  to  grind 
lenses,  and  by  diligence  and  having  a  naturally  delicate  touch,  he  developed 
this  art  further  than  any  of  his  contemporaries.  Sparing  no  pains  to  find  out 
new  methods  and  combinations,  he  gave  to  his  magnifying  apparatus  all 
sorts  of  forms,  some  of  them  very  strange;  he  tried  glass,  rock-crystal,  and 
even  diamonds  for  his  lenses;  but  the  greatest  advance  he  made  was  in  the 
manufacture  of  simple  lenses  with  strong  magnification;  one  such  lens,  which 
is  still  in  existence,  is  said  to  magnify  as  much  as  irjo  times.  As  often  with 
self-taught  men,  he  was  extremely  jealous  of  his  inventions;  he  never  sold 
a  magnifying-glass  nor  even  lent  one  to  anyone;  on  the  other  hand,  scien- 
tists who  visited  him  were  permitted  to  use  a  number  of  his  instruments, 
though  never  the  most  powerful.  It  is  said  that  among  his  property  there 
were  found  more  than  four  hundred  microscopes  and  magnifying-glasses.  A 
number  of  them  he  had  bequeathed  to  the  Royal  Society  of  London,  of  which 
he  was  a  member  and  which  published  most  of  his  observations.  Busily  oc- 
cupied to  the  last,  Leeuwenhoek  reached  the  age  of  over  ninety;  he  died  in 
his  native  town  in  17x3. 

Leeuwenhoek' s  investigations 
Leeuwenhoek's  collected  writings  have  quite  an  extensive  range,  and  their 
contents  are  extraordinarily  varied.  The  only  connecting  link  that  unites 
them  is  the  microscopical  method;  this  Leeuwenhoek  applied  to  literally 
everything  that  came  within  his  range  of  vision:  crystals  and  minerals,  plants 
and  animals.  With  respect  to  the  last  he  developed  no  special  microtomical 
technique,  but  he  studied  and  illustrated  the  details  of  what  he  observed. 
This  detailed  study,  however,  he  advanced  further  than  anyone  of  his  time, 
and  if  he  possessed  the  most  powerful  magnifying  lenses  known  to  his  age, 
he  certainly  had  also  the  keenest  eye.  He  took  exact  measurements  of  every- 
thing that  he  examined;  unfortunately  there  was  in  his  time  no  unit  of  meas- 
ure which  could  have  served  his  purpose,  so  that  he  was  compelled  to  select 
such  objects  of  comparison  as  he  thought  suitable  —  a  hair,  a  grain  of  sand 
—  and  to  state  his  measurements  in  fractions,  often  thousandth  parts,  thereof. 
He  took  careful  notes  of  everything  that  he  examined  and  sent  them  in  the 
form  of  letters  to  the  Royal  Society,  to  which  he  had  been  introduced  by 
his  friend  de  Graaf,  and  of  which  he  soon  became  a  member.  It  often  hap- 
pened that  one  and  the  same  letter  contained  a  mass  of  different  notes  on 
various  observations  he  had  made.  It  was  undoubtedly  to  his  great  advantage 
that  he  so  seldom  engaged  in  theoretical  speculations,  but  only  described 


l66  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

and  illustrated  what  he  saw;  if  at  any  time  he  starts  theorizing,  he  generally 
fails,  but  usually  he  appears  conscious  of  his  limitations  and  holds  to  the 
realities  which  he  knew  so  well  how  to  master. 

Biology  has  Leeuwenhoek  to  thank  for  a  long  series  of  facts  of  funda- 
mental importance.  His  studies  on  the  circulation  of  the  blood  deserve  first 
consideration.  He  has  explained  and  completed  the  knowledge  of  the  capil- 
lary system  which  Malpighi  originated,  while  he  clearly  proved  that  the 
veins  and  arteries,  each  separately,  are  continued  on  immediately  through  the 
capillaries  and  thus  through  them  merge  directly  into  one  another.  More- 
over, Leeuwenhoek  for  the  first  time  clearly  recognized  the  blood  corpuscles 
and  described  them,  first  in  the  frog  and  then  in  man  and  a  number  of  animal 
forms.  Malpighi  had  thought  that  he  could  distinguish  in  the  blood   "fat 
globules,"  but  he  did  not  investigate  the  matter  further,  so  that  to  Leeu- 
wenhoek is  due  the  honour  of  having  really  solved  the  problem.  The  same 
is  the  case  with  the  spermatozoa,  which,  it  is  true,  a  Dutch  student  by  the 
name  of  Hamm  was  the  first  to  observe,  but  which  Leeuwenhoek  at  any  rate 
studied  more  closely  in  a  number  of  animal  forms.  In  this  connexion  he  made 
thorough  investigation  into  the  fertilization  of  various  animals,  especially 
fishes  and  frogs.  In  the  frog  he  noted  the  spermatozoon's  association  with 
the  egg  and  believes  —  like  Aristotle,  as  a  matter  of  fact  —  that  it  is  from 
the  male  that  the  actual  life  comes;  the  female  only  provides,  through  the 
egg,  nourishment  and  powers  of  development.  This  he  tries  to  prove  by  pair- 
ing different-coloured  rabbits :  if  a  white  female  is  paired  with  a  grey  male, 
all  the  young  will  be  grey  like  the  father.  Had  he  continued  the  experiment 
through  several  generations,  he  would  certainly  have  obtained  other  results. 
—  He  has  further  observed  a  number  of  histological  details  of  various  kinds: 
the  stripes  of  the  striated  muscles,  the  structure  of  dental  bone,  the  construc- 
tion of  the  optic  lens  in  man  and  the  higher  animals.  No  less  remarkable  are 
his  discoveries  in  the  lower  animal  world.  He  thus  discovered  the  Infusoria 
and  the  Rotatoria  in  water;  he  explained  the  reproduction  of  ants,  found 
their  true  eggs,  and  showed  that  what  had  hitherto  been  called  ants'  eggs 
are  really  the  pupas  of  the  insect.  He  very  definitely  opposes  the  hitherto 
prevalent  view  that  minute  creatures  of  all  kinds  arise  through  putrefaction 
or  fermentation  in  inanimate  matter.  Instead  he  declares  that  even  the  small- 
est animals  possess  reproductive  powers  and  propagate  solely  by  means  of 
them.  In  proof  of  this  he  demonstrated  particularly  the  evolution  of  fleas 
and  aphids.  If,  finally,  we  add  to  this  that  he  demonstrated  the  difference 
between  the  structure  of  the  stem  of  monocotyledons  and  dicotyledons  in  the 
vegetable  kingdom,  this  —  by  no  means  complete  —  sketch  will  have  given 
some  idea  of  a  life  of  activity  which,  without  making  any  important  theo- 
retical contributions,  advanced  the  knowledge  of  nature  in  an  unusually  high 
degree. 


SEVENTEENTH  AND  EIGHTEENTH  CENTURIES  167 
On  the  whole,  Holland  during  the  latter  half  of  the  seventeenth  century 
proved  a  centre  of  biological  research.  Of  the  many  prominent  scientists  who 
lived  and  worked  in  that  country  during  that  period  it  is  possible  to  mention 
only  a  few  of  the  most  important  —  those  who  in  one  way  or  another  led 
research  into  fresh  directions. 

Jan  Swammerdam  was  born  in  Amsterdam  in  the  year  1637.  His  father 
was  an  apothecary  who  by  saving  had  accumulated  a  considerable  fortune 
and  was,  moreover,  interested  in  natural  science.  He  possessed  a  natural  col- 
lection, which  he  augmented  and  looked  after  with  great  care.  He  had  in- 
tended his  son  to  take  orders,  but  as  the  study  of  nature  seemed  to  be  his 
sole  interest,  he  was  permitted  to  study  to  become  a  doctor.  After  preliminary 
studies  in  his  native  town  he  entered  the  University  of  Ley  den  in  1661.  Even 
then  he  had  already  proved  a  clever  technician  in  the  anatomical  sphere, 
and  he  rapidly  acquired  fame  for  his  splendid  dissecting  and  injection-work. 
He  formed  a  lifelong  friendship  with  Steno,  who  was  about  the  same  age 
and  who  happened  to  be  visiting  Leyden  at  the  time;  they  worked  together 
and  travelled  together  to  Paris  in  order  to  continue  their  studies  there.  Here 
Swammerdam  found  a  new  friend  in  the  person  of  the  King's  librarian,  The- 
venot,  a  friend  who  throughout  his  life  loyally  assisted  him  in  every  possible 
way.  Returning  to  his  native  country,  Swammerdam  graduated  at  Leyden  in 
1667  with  a  dissertation  on  respiration  and  then  settled  down  at  his  father's 
place  in  Amsterdam.  He  had  already  earlier  applied  himself  to  the  study  of 
the  anatomy  of  the  lower  animals,  and  this  interest  now  engaged  all  his 
powers.  During  the  short  years  that  remained  to  him  he  achieved  results 
which  not  only  left  all  his  predecessors  far  behind,  but  actually  remained 
unexcelled  for  the  space  of  more  than  a  hundred  years.  In  the  mean  while 
his  fortunes  took  an  extremely  unhappy  turn.  He  contracted  a  malarial  fever, 
which,  except  for  occasional  intervals,  never  left  him  for  the  rest  of  his  life. 
At  the  same  time  the  strain  entailed  on  him  by  his  work  impaired  his  health. 
Besides,  he  was  of  a  passionate  nature;  his  writings  are  full  of  bitter  con- 
troversy, and  his  quarrels  about  questions  of  scientific  priority  brought  him 
many  enemies.  On  the  other  hand,  he  had  several  loyal  friends,  who  stood 
by  him  to  the  end.  Worst  of  all,  however,  he  fell  out  with  his  own  family; 
his  father,  who  seems  to  have  been  an  economical  and  surly  old  man,  thought 
that  it  was  about  time  that  his  son,  whom  he  had  supported  for  more  than 
thirty  years,  applied  himself  to  medical  practice  or  some  other  profession 
that  might  provide  him  with  an  income.  In  preparation  for  this,  young 
Swammerdam  was  sent  into  the  country  to  recover  his  frail  health,  but  he 
spent  night  and  day  engrossed  in  his  investigations,  so  that  his  health  went 
from  bad  to  worse.  After  repeated  quarrels  his  father  finally  deprived  him 
of  all  financial  support.  Swammerdam  found  himself  in  dire  need  and  sought 
in  vain  to  sell  his  collections  in  order  to  buy  his  daily  bread.  Even  his  intel- 


l68  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

lectual  powers  had  now  waned;  in  about  the  year  1673  ^^  ceased  to  work 
at  his  science  and  became  abosrbed  in  religious  contemplation.  His  old  friend 
Steno  sought  to  take  advantage  of  this  state  of  affairs:  at  the  price  of  the 
same  religious  conversion  which  he  himself  had  just  undergone,  he  offered 
Swammerdam  splendid  prospects  in  Florence.  The  latter  refused,  but  instead 
sought  to  cure  his  distress  of  soul  by  visiting  Antoinette  Bourignon,  who 
was  very  notorious  at  that  time.  She  was  an  extremely  gifted  but  hysterical 
woman  who  in  virtue  of  personal  revelation  desired  to  reform  Christianity 
on  ascetic  and  mystical  lines,  and  who,  persecuted  by  both  Catholic  and 
Protestant  priests,  wandered  from  country  to  country  surrounded  by  a  small 
band  of  believers.  Swammerdam  joined  this  band,  but  was  unable  to  find 
the  peace  he  sought;  after  leading  a  roving  life  for  a  couple  of  years  he  re- 
turned in  the  deepest  spiritual  and  bodily  misery  to  his  native  country.  There 
at  last  he  obtained,  through  his  father's  death,  which  occurred  at  the  same 
time,  financial  independence,  but  then  quarrelled  with  a  sister  over  the  in- 
heritance, which  still  further  embittered  his  mind.  In  the  year  1680  he  found 
repose  in  death,  when  not  yet  forty-three  years  old.  In  1880  a  beau- 
tiful monument  was  raised  over  his  grave  and  there  was  created  to  his 
memory  a  fund,  which  is  used  for  the  purpose  of  giving  prizes  for  research 
work  carried  out  in  the  spheres  of  learning  in  which  he  had  studied. 

Swammerdam's  scientific  activities  thus  lasted  for  only  about  six  years, 
during  which  period  he  published  a  few  works  of  great  value  —  particularly, 
besides  the  dissertation  above  mentioned  and  an  essay  on  the  genital  organs 
of  woman,  a  work  on  the  anatomy  of  insects,  in  which  he  recorded  his 
earlier  researches  on  that  subject.  His  still  unpublished  manuscripts  he  be- 
queathed to  Thevenot;  after  the  latter's  death  they  passed  through  many 
hands  until  they  were  finally  purchased  by  the  famous  Boerhaave  of  Leyden 
and  were  published  by  him  together  with  the  already  printed  work  on  insects 
under  the  title  of  Bijbel  der  Natuure,  in  1737.  Although  it  thus  came  out  more 
than  half  a  century  after  it  had  been  written,  this  work  was  by  no  means 
out  of  date;  in  fact,  it  was  to  be  some  time  before  its  detailed  anatomical 
descriptions  were  improved  upon  —  a  proof  of  Swammerdam's  incomparable 
genius  as  an  anatomist  of  invertebrate  life.  The  title  of  the  work  was  prob- 
ably given  to  it  by  Boerhaave,  but  fully  reflects  the  state  of  mind  in  which 
the  author  found  himself  towards  the  close  of  his  life.  Nevertheless,  religious 
observations  do  not  form  any  disturbing  element  in  it;  on  the  contrary,  his 
presentation  is  purely  natural-scientific  with  the  exception  of  a  few  con- 
tributions of  the  religious  moralizing  character,  particularly  one  that  is  a 
reflection  upon  the  short  life  of  the  day-fly.  The  undoubtedly  valuable  col- 
lections on  which  Swammerdam  based  these  studies  were  after  his  death 
sold  by  auction  and  dispersed. 

What  still  strikes  the  reader  of  Swammerdam's  works  is  his  mastery 


SEVENTEENTH  AND  EIGHTEENTH  CENTURIES  1^9 
over  even  the  most  complicated  details  in  the  minute  creatures  he  investi- 
gated. This  he  could  not  possibly  have  acquired  without  a  high  standard 
of  knowledge  of  the  technique  of  dissection,  and,  indeed,  it  was  this  knowl- 
edge which  excited  the  admiration  of  his  contemporaries;  visitors  from  far 
and  near  were  amazed  at  his  fine  instruments  and  the  skill  with  which  he 
handled  them  —  glass  tubes  drawn  out  to  points  as  fine  as  hairs,  by  means 
of  which  organs  were  spread  out  and  canals  injected;  scalpules  so  fine  that 
they  had  to  be  ground  under  a  magnifying-glass,  and  so  on.  Extraordinary 
lightness  of  touch  and  unique  powers  of  observation  enabled  him  to  utilize 
the  methods  which  he  worked  out,  to  which,  finally,  we  must  add  his  love 
of  research,  for  which  he  literally  gave  his  life. 

Anato7ny  of  insects 
Swammerdam's  great  work  in  part  contains  a  collection  of  anatomical  mono- 
graphs on  insects  and  other  invertebrate  animals;  particularly  well  known 
is  his  exposition  of  the  anatomy  of  the  bee,  which  even  Cuvier  considered 
to  be  unsurpassed,  and  further  the  head-louse,  the  day-fly,  the  rhinoceros- 
beetle,  the  Helix  pomatia,  and  many  more.  These  monographs,  however, 
are  all  based  on  one  theory  of  the  evolution  of  insects  and  in  connexion 
therewith  that  of  all  living  creatures.  Supported  in  his  investigations  by 
the  development  of  a  number  of  different  insects'  larv«  to  pupa  and  imago 
and  adopting  a  sharp  controversial  attitude  towards  Harvey,  Swammerdam 
declares  that  the  insect  does  not  undergo  any  transformation,  but  that  merely 
growth  takes  place  of  parts  which  already  existed  before.  Again  and  again 
this  statement  is  emphasized,  that  no  generation,  but  only  an  excrescence 
of  parts  takes  place,  wherefore  accident  plays  no  part  in  the  evolution  of 
the  insect,  but  what  takes  place  is  predetermined.  This  evolutionary  prin- 
ciple is  then  applied  to  the  development  of  the  frog  from  the  egg  through 
the  various  larval  stages,  and  finally,  though  quite  summarily,  to  the  evolu- 
tion of  man,  which  is  likewise  made  dependent  on  predetermined  necessity. 
Lastly,  the  evolution  of  the  bud  of  plants  to  leaf  and  flower  is  compared 
in  detail  with  the  metamorphosis  of  insects.  In  order  to  facilitate  his  analysis 
insects  are  divided  according  to  their  metamorphosis  into   four   groups: 
(i)  those  that  come  from  the  tgg  with  all  their  feet  complete  —  spiders, 
lice;  (i)  the  animal  that  has  all  its  feet  when  it  is  hatched,  but  whose 
wings  develop  later  on  —  as,  for  instance,  day-flies;  (3)  those  from  whose 
egg  comes  a  larva,  either  with  or  without  feet,  which  becomes  a  pupa  after 
chrysalizing  —  as,  for  instance,  ants,  bees;  (4)  those  in  which  a  larva,  like 
the  foregoing,  becomes  a  pupa  without  chrysalizing  —  certain  flies.  In  this 
method  of  grouping  Swammerdam  laid  the  foundations  of  modern  insect- 
classification,  which,  as  is  well  known,  still  rests  to  a  great  extent  upon 
the  evolutionary  history  of  insects.  That  he  grouped  spiders  and  even  snails 
and  worms  under  his  first  category  is  not  to  be  wondered  at;  all  invertebrates 


lyo  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

were  at  that  time  lumped  together,  and  Swammerdam's  point  of  departure 
was  from  first  to  last  not  morphological,  but  evolutionary.  But  at  any  rate 
he  performed  a  service  —  as  also  did  Leeuv/enhoek  —  in  awakening  interest 
in  these  organisms,  which  had  hitherto  been  regarded  as  existences  not  only 
of  a  lower  type,  but  also  utterly  incomparable  with  the  higher;  they  still 
arose,  according  to  Harvey,  by  spontaneous  generation,  and  this  alone  was 
a  proof  that  no  conclusions  could  be  drawn  from  them  touching  the  life  of 
the  higher  animals. 

Sivammerdam  s  pejormation  theory 
SwAMMERDAM  showcd  that  on  the  contrary  it  was  just  the  life-conditions 
of  the  lower  animals  which,  if  viewed  in  a  proper  light,  gave  fresh  stimulus 
to  the  knowledge  of  life  in  its  entirety.  Particularly  does  he  insist  upon 
this  being  realized  in  embryonic  development.  The  theory  which  he  ad- 
vanced on  this  subject  —  growth  of  previously  created  parts  instead  of  new 
formation  —  came  to  exercise  immense  influence  during  the  immediately 
succeeding  period:  under  the  name  of  the  theory  of  preformation  or  evolution 
it  entirely  supplanted  Harvey's  theory  of  epigenesis.  True,  in  its  application 
it  was  in  its  turn  driven  to  sheer  absurdities,  particularly  by  certain  scientists 
who  will  be  named  later  on,  but  when  it  first  appeared,  it  was  certainly 
called  for  and  marked  an  advance  in  biological  science.  In  fact,  it  resulted 
in  the  assertion  for  the  first  time  of  the  obedience  of  ontogenetical  evolution 
to  law;  it  definitely  invalidated  the  old  ideas  of  the  spontaneous  genesis 
of  lower  animals;  it  established  the  fact  that  according  to  nature  the  off- 
spring must  resemble  the  parent,  whereas  in  earlier  times,  practically  speak- 
ing, anything  could  arise  out  of  anything  —  the  legendary  tales  of  women 
who  under  the  influence  of  witchcraft  were  delivered  of  kittens  and  puppies 
instead  of  children  had  at  any  rate  been  discussed  by  certain  scientists  — 
and,  finally,  it  satisfied,  as  far  as  embryology  was  concerned,  the  contem- 
porary demand  for  a  mechanical  explanation  of  nature.  But  it  is  true  that  a 
century  later  the  epigenetical  theory  was  again  to  appear  in  a  form  that  jus- 
tified its  acceptance  —  a  change  of  which  an  account  will  be  given  further  on. 
There  is  a  name  that  is  worthy  of  mention  by  the  side  of  Swammerdam 
—  that  of  his  contemporary  and  friend  Frederic  Ruysch.  He  was  born  at 
The  Hague  in  1638  of  a  highly  respected  family,  his  father  being  secretary 
in  the  States  General.  Having  when  still  young  contracted  an  advantageous 
marriage,  he  was  in  a  position  to  apply  himself  at  his  own  option  to  medical 
research;  he  became  a  doctor  at  Leyden  and  a  professor  in  Amsterdam,  in 
an  appointment  which  he  held  for  sixty-three  years.  Moreover,  he  had  an 
extensive  medical  practice.  He  died  in  173 1  in  his  ninety-third  year.  His 
long  life,  active  to  the  last,  is  reminiscent  of  Leeuwenhoek's,  as  is  also  the 
fact  that  his  greatest  service  to  the  world  consists  in  the  employment  of 
technical  methods,  which,  though  he  had  not  invented  them,  were  neverthe- 


SEVENTEENTH     AND     EIGHTEENTH     CENTURIES       171 

less  improved  by  him.  From  his  friend  Swammerdam  he  had  learnt  the  art 
of  using  coloured  wax  for  injections,  and  he  acquired  a  masterly  skill  in  this 
method,  such  as  few  attained  after  him.  He  was  able  to  fill  out  the  finest 
capillary  vessels  without  either  bursting  or  deforming  them,  and,  besides,  he 
preserved  the  preparations  thus  carried  out  in  a  wonderfully  natural  manner. 
And  he  was  as  jealous  of  his  method  as  Leeuwenhoek  was  of  his  microscopes, 
though  really  with  far  less  excuse  than  the  latter;  the  microscopes  survived 
the  man  who  made  them,  while  the  method  of  injection  went  down  with 
its  inventor  to  the  grave.  Even  with  regard  to  the  value  which  his  discoveries 
had  for  science,  the  learned  professor  is  no  match  for  the  untaught  function- 
ary, but  Ruysch,  in  the  application  of  his  method,  certainly  did  succeed  in  pro- 
viding science  with  a  mass  of  new  facts,  particularly  in  the  sphere  of  human 
anatomy.  He  discovered  the  bronchial  arteries  and  the  arachnoids  of  the 
brain,  besides  which  he  studied  and  extended  the  knowledge  of  the  iris  and 
retina  of  the  eye;  and,  further,  he  compared  the  male  and  female  skeleton  and 
investigated  the  changes  made  by  age  in  the  structure  of  bone.  He  made  a 
splendid  collection  of  anatomical  preparations,  of  which  he  published  a 
richly  illustrated  description.  The  objects  were  arranged  in  groups  —  human 
organs,  shells,  minerals,  and  other  things  all  together  —  in  a  manner  which 
in  our  time  would  be  considered  not  only  highly  unscientific,  but  also  utterly 
lacking  in  taste.'  His  contemporaries,  however,  were  ecstatic  over  it;  for- 
eigners visited  the  museum,  and  poets  lauded  it  in  verse.  Tsar  Peter  of 
Russia,  who,  as  is  well  known,  entertained  almost  childish  admiration  for  all 
products  of  technical  skill,  finally  purchased  the  entire  collection  for  thirty 
thousand  guilders,  but  naturally  neither  he  nor  any  of  his  subjects  could 
make  any  use  of  it.  A  second  collection,  which  was  made  later,  was  purchased 
by  the  opponent  of  the  Tsar,  the  Polish  king  Stanislaus  Leszczynski.  There  is 
now  nothing  left  of  these  collections:  it  is  only  through  Ruysch's  books  that 
we  in  modern  times  can  gain  any  idea  of  what  he  did.  And  it  cannot  be 
denied  that  there  was  in  him  but  little  in  the  way  of  ideas,  yet  at  the  same 
time  extraordinary  technical  ability  and  quite  a  lot  of  humbug. 

There  was  another  Dutch  physician  of  the  same  age  as  he,  Reinier  de 
Graaf,  who  possessed  far  sounder  qualities  as  a  scientist.  Born  in  1641  of 
Catholic  parents,  he  studied  at  Leyden  and  at  Angers  in  France,  where  he 
took  his  doctor's  degree.  When  still  quite  young  he  had  won  a  great  reputa- 
tion, but  owing  to  his  faith  he  was  prevented  from  obtaining  a  professorship 
at  Leyden,  which  was  a  strictly  Protestant  university,  and  he  therefore 
settled  down  as  a  practitioner  in  Delft.  His  unusually  promising  career  was 
cut  short  in  1673,  when  a  serious  illness  deprived  him  of  a  happy  domestic 
life  and  the  possibility  of  carrying  on  his  intensive  research-work.  He  had 

'  Thus  there  was  amongst  the  groups  the  skeleton  of  a  child  holding  a  piece  of  injected 
peritoneum  like  a  handkerchief  before  its  eyes. 


lyi  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

already  had  time,  however,  to  make  important  contributions  to  biology  in 
both  the  anatomical  and  the  physiological  sphere.  His  doctor's  dissertation 
deals  with  the  pancreatic  secretion.  In  it  he  shows  how,  by  introducing  a 
canula  into  the  duct  of  the  pancreatic  gland  in  a  live  dog,  it  is  possible  to 
obtain  some  of  the  secretion  for  the  purpose  of  closer  examination  —  a 
method  which  has  since  then  been  generally  adopted  in  physiology. 

The  work  on  which  de  Graaf's  fame  principally  rests,  however,  is  his 
study  of  the  sexual  organs,  both  male  and  female,  but  chiefly  the  latter.  The 
ovaries,  of  course,  had  already  been  described  before,  of  both  the  higher  and  the 
lower  vertebrates;  that  they  produced  eggs  in  birds  was  known,  but  a  great 
many  contradictory  theories  had  been  advanced  on  the  subject  of  what  kind 
of  function  they  possessed  in  man  and  the  other  mammals.  The  Aristoteleans 
naturally  supported  their  master's  doctrine  that  the  sexual  product  of  the 
woman  is  the  menstrual  blood  and  that  otherwise  the  male  semen  is  the 
essential  origin  of  the  embryo,  which  the  woman  then  nourishes  and  pro- 
duces. De  Graaf,  on  the  other  hand,  after  making  a  comparative  study  of  the 
ovaries  of  mammals  and  birds,  came  to  the  conclusion  that  the  cell-like 
protuberances  already  observed  by  Vesalius  and  Fallopio  in  the  ovary  of 
mammals  corresponded  to  the  egg  of  the  bird  ovary,  and  that  the  process  of 
fertilization  is  similar  in  every  animal  type;  just  as  a  bird's  fertilized  egg  in 
the  ducts  of  the  ovary  acquires  albumen  and  shell,  the  egg  of  the  mammal 
becomes  fertilized  through  the  Fallopian  tube,  finds  its  way  to  the  uterus, 
and  there  develops  further.  The  very  word  "ovary"  was  suggested  by  him; 
hitherto  the  female  sexual  gland  as  well  as  the  male  had  been  called  testis, 
a  word  which  he  still  employs  alternatively  with  the  new  one.  He  definitely 
rejects  the  assertion  of  the  Aristoteleans  that  the  embryo  originates  from  the 
man  alone;  in  disproof  of  that  assertion  he  cites  many  cases  in  which  demon- 
strably purely  external  characteristics  have  been  inherited  by  the  embryo 
from  the  mother,  both  in  human  beings  and  in  animals;  even  cases  of  extra- 
uterine gestation  are  cited  by  him  as  proof  that  the  embryo  is  derived  from 
the  ovaries  and  not  from  outside.  Likewise  in  regard  to  several  other  details 
in  the  structure  of  the  sexual  organs  he  records  valuable  fresh  observations. 
These  investigations  of  de  Graaf's  proved  of  fundamental  importance, 
although  he  was  wrong  in  his  assumption  that  the  follicles  in  the  ovary, 
which  now  bear  his  name,  correspond  to  the  eggs  in  the  ovary  of  a  bird  — 
the  true  eggs  of  mammals  were  not  discovered  until  a  century  and  a  half  after 
his  death.  Nevertheless,  the  explanation  he  gave  of  the  actual  phenomenon 
of  fertilization  was  of  decisive  significance  for  the  future  development  of  the 
knowledge  of  this  phenomenon.  It  was  impossible,  however,  either  for  his 
own  or  for  the  immediately  succeeding  age  to  reconcile  his  claim  as  to  the 
significance  of  the  egg  in  embryonic  development  with  the  important  part 
that  the  spermatozoa  should  be  assumed  to  play  in  the  same  process.  And  so 


SEVENTEENTH     AND     EIGHTEENTH    CENTURIES       173 

we  find  developing,  especially  in  the  eighteenth  century,  the  controversy 
between  ovists  and  animalculists,  as  the  champions  of  the  importance  of  the 
egg  and  the  spermatozoa  respectively  in  fertilization  were  called  —  a  con- 
troversy which  was  to  set  science  by  the  ears  for  decades.  In  some  of  the  fol- 
lowing chapters  more  light  will  be  thrown  on  this  controversy  as  well  as  on 
the  dispute  between  the  respective  champions  of  epigenesis  and  preformation 
which  was  raging  at  the  same  time. 

The  close  of  the  great  period  in  the  history  of  anatomy 
With  this,  our  account  of  the  brilliant  epoch  in  the  history  of  biology  repre- 
sented by  the  seventeenth  century  comes  to  a  close.  It  is  perfectly  natural  that 
towards  the  end  of  that  century,  and  during  the  decades  immediately  follow- 
ing, interest  should  wane  in  just  those  spheres  in  which  progress  had  been 
greatest;  the  forced  march  had  to  be  followed  by  a  period  of  mustering  of 
forces  and  reflection,  during  which  the  results  achieved  had  to  be  weighed 
from  the  theoretical  point  of  view  and  classified.  It  is  therefore  worth  while 
considering  what  were  the  solutions  which  the  next  age  sought  to  give  to 
the  theoretical  questions  that  had  arisen  in  connexion  with  the  great  practi- 
cal advance  made  in  the  field  of  anatomy  and  experimental  biology.  In  the 
following  chapter  some  samples  will  be  given  of  theories  of  this  kind. 


CHAPTER    V 

BIOLOGICAL    SPECULATIONS     AND     CONTROVERSIAL     QUESTIONS     AT 
THE    BEGINNING     OF     THE     EIGHTEENTH     CENTURY 

AS  HAS  BEEN  POINTED  OUT  it!  the  fofcgoing,  the  power  of  the  authori- 
ties of  antiquity  was  broken  during  the  seventeenth  century  as  the 
L  result  of  a  series  of  brilliant  scientific  discoveries;  in  its  stead  nat- 
ural scientists  based  their  researches  upon  the  knowledge  of  the  mechani- 
cal subjection  to  law  which  prevails  in  nature.  However,  the  need  was 
felt  for  a  definite  and  uniform  conception  of  nature  such  as  Aristoteleanism 
undeniably  possessed  and  which  was  lacking  in  the  new  systems  of  thought 
which  took  its  place.  In  actual  fact  these  systems,  whether  they  emanated 
from  Descartes,  Spinoza,  or  Leibniz,  were  quite  as  dogmatic  as  Aristote- 
leanism; they  were  pure  thought-structures,  which,  although  based  on  the 
new  natural  science,  were  yet  by  no  means  capable  of  satisfactorily  solv- 
ing the  problems  to  which  that  science  gave  rise.  As  far  as  biology  is  con- 
cerned, while  it  is  true  that  physicists  like  Borelli  or  Perrault  had  been 
able  with  the  aid  of  the  newly-discovered  mechanical  laws  to  find  solutions 
to  a  number  of  pure  problems  of  motion,  yet  as  soon  as  more  complicated 
processes  in  the  organism,  such  as  the  digestion,  the  circulation,  or  sense- 
impressions,  had  to  be  considered,  the  mechanical  principle  was  found  want- 
ing; nor  had  the  other  branches  of  physics  and  even  chemistry  as  yet  reached 
such  a  state  of  development  that  they  could  be  employed  as  a  means  of  ex- 
plaining such  phenomena  as  those  just  mentioned.  In  these  circumstances 
many  a  scientist  was  content  merely  to  study  the  new  facts  which  had  been 
brought  to  light  as  a  result  of  improved  experimental  technique,  but  there 
were  others  who  devoted  their  lives  to  seeking  firm  ground  on  which  to  base 
a  uniform  explanation  of  life-phenomena.  In  modern  times  it  is  not  easy  to 
appreciate  the  difficulties  with  which  these  biological  thinkers  had  to  con- 
tend in  their  efforts  to  reconcile  the  individual  results  of  past  research  work 
under  one  common  point  of  view.  Uniformity  in  the  conception  of  nature 
in  our  day,  of  course,  rests  essentially  upon  the  law  of  the  indestructibility 
of  energy,  to  which  may  be  added,  in  the  field  of  biology,  the  doctrine  of  the 
cell  as  a  unit  of  life.  But  the  theoretical  natural  science  of  the  seventeenth 
century  tended,  instead  of  to  these  ideas,  to  the  assumption  of  the  existence 
of  an  unknown  force  as  the  origin  of  life  and  a  basis  for  its  continuance.  This 
force  could  then  be  conceived  of  as  something  either  purely  mechanical  or 

174 


SEVENTEENTH     AND     EIGHTEENTH     CENTURIES       175 

more  idealistic;  in  the  former  case  one  was  bewildered,  since  mechanics  can- 
not provide  the  answer  to  more  than  a  small  fraction  of  the  questions  which 
the  new  discovery  brought  to  light;  while  in  the  latter  case  there  was  the 
risk  of  reverting  to  mysticism  in  one  form  or  another.  These  natural-scientific 
speculations  from  the  beginning  of  the  eighteenth  century,  which  we  shall 
now  discuss,  originated,  curiously  enough,  less  from  the  anatomists  and 
biologists  than  from  the  medical  practitioners,  who  sought  to  base  their 
medical  treatment  on  a  general  theory  of  the  functions  of  the  body.  Of  these 
latter  scientists  some  few  have  exercised  a  radical  influence  even  on  the  gen- 
eral development  of  biology  and  therefore  deserve  to  be  mentioned  in  this 
connexion. 

Thomas  Sydenham  lived,  it  is  true,  entirely  in  the  seventeenth  century  — 
he  was  born  in  162.4  ^^'^  ^^^'^  ^^  ^^^9  —  ^^^  ^^^  influence  did  not  really  make 
itself  felt  until  after  his  death,  and,  indeed,  it  has  increased  still  more  since 
then.  He  belonged  to  a  good  country-family  and  studied  for  a  time  at  Oxford, 
but  upon  the  outbreak  of  the  Civil  War  he  joined  the  Parliamentary  party 
and  became  an  officer  in  its  army.  Afterwards,  however,  he  continued  his 
medical  studies,  took  a  low  medical  degree,  and  settled  down  in  London  as 
a  pracititoner;  he  did  not  obtain  his  doctor's  degree  until  he  was  over  fifty 
years  old.  Personally  Sydenham  enjoyed  a  great  reputation;  he  counted  among 
his  friends  such  people  as  the  chemist  Boyle  and  the  philosopher  Locke.  On 
the  other  hand,  opinions  differed  as  to  his  capacity  as  a  physician;  his  auda- 
cious ideas  required  time  before  they  could  penetrate  the  ordinary  mind. 
Nowadays  he  is  universally  regarded  as  one  of  the  pioneers  of  medical 
science. 

Sydenham  s  medical  doctrine 
In  the  seventeenth  century  London  was  a  very  unhealthful  city;  one  plague 
followed  another  in  rapid  succession.  It  was  these  epidemics  that  inspired 
Sydenham  to  work  out  his  medical  theories;  he  studied  the  symptoms  of 
the  various  diseases  and  endeavoured  by  that  means  to  characterize  the  dis- 
ease itself  in  the  same  way  as  the  botanist  describes  a  plant-species.  "That 
botanist  would  have  but  little  conscience  who  contented  himself  with  the 
general  description  of  a  thistle  and  overlooked  the  special  and  peculiar  char- 
acteristics in  each  species."  He  places  a  higher  value  on  this  exact  study  of 
nature  than  on  any  theories;  this  study  should  take  into  account  all  factors 
affecting  the  disease  in  its  entirety.  Even  the  season  of  the  year  when  the  dis- 
ease is  most  widely  dispersed  should  be  carefully  observed,  as  indeed  all  other 
conditions  that  may  influence  the  plague  as  a  whole.  On  the  other  hand, 
purely  individual  variations  in  particular  cases  are  of  minor  interest.  Like 
Hippocrates  he  considers  that  it  is  the  nature  of  the  patient  that  cures  dis- 
ease; it  is  therefore  not  so  much  worth  while  worrying  about  trying  to 
diagnose  the  disorders  in  the  fluids  of  the  body  on  each  occasion  as  to  try  to 


1/6  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

discover  a  treatment  that  may  assist  the  working  of  nature.  What  he  really 
means  when  he  talks  of  "nature"  is  not  at  all  clear  —  whether  it  is  a  com- 
bination of  the  individual's  life-manifestations  or  some  special  life-force; 
similarly,  one  does  not  gain  a  very  clear  explanation  of  the  ideas  he  borrowed 
from  Hippocrates  concerning  the  fluids  of  the  body  and  the  balance  or  dis- 
turbances therein.  His  general  conception  of  nature  is  on  the  whole  purely 
empirical  —  in  this  he  was  influenced  by  Bacon,  whom,  indeed,  he  quotes 
with  admiration.  In  certain  cases,  it  is  true,  he  can  form  quite  daring  hy- 
potheses, but  as  a  rule  he  consistently  applies  his  principle  as  to  observa- 
tion's being  the  only  source  of  knowledge  in  disease.^  This  principle  has 
indeed  been  adopted  by  posterity,  but  he  also  exercised  a  powerful  influence 
on  the  medical  and  biological  thinkers  of  the  immediately  succeeding  age, 
although  these  latter  could  not  restrain  themselves  within  the  limits  which 
he  laid  down  for  research,  but  went  further  afield  in  the  world  of 
hypothesis. 

Among  these  medical  researchers  who  formed  general  theories  of  impor- 
tance to  the  development  of  biology,  two  men  are  conspicuous  at  the  begin- 
ning of  the  eighteenth  century  who,  born  in  the  same  year  and  working  in 
the  same  town,  yet  proved  in  all  essentials  strangely  contrasted.  These  two 
were  Hoffmann  and  Stahl. 

Friedrich  Hoffmann  was  born  in  Halle  in  1660,  the  son  of  a  wealthy 
physician.  At  the  age  of  fifteen  he  had  the  misfortune  to  lose  both  his  parents, 
who  died  of  the  plague,  as  well  as  his  inheritance,  as  a  result  of  a  fire,  and 
thus  early  had  to  fend  for  himself.  He  was  given  an  opportunity,  however, 
of  studying  medicine  at  the  University  of  Jena,  where  a  highly  reputed 
representative  of  the  chemical  and  medical  research  of  the  period,  G.  W. 
Wedel,  was  his  teacher.  Having  further  studied  at  Erfurt,  he  took  his  de- 
gree at  Jena,  spent  some  time  in  England,  where  he  made  the  acquaintance 
of  Boyle,  and  then  set  up  as  a  practitioner  in  a  couple  of  small  German  states 
until,  in  1693,  he  was  called  to  an  appointment  at  the  newly  founded  uni- 
versity in  his  native  town  of  Halle.  There  he  spent  the  rest  of  his  life  as  a 
professor,  with  the  exception  of  a  couple  of  years  which  he  spent  at  the  court 
in  Berlin.  His  work  both  as  a  teacher  and  as  a  physician  was  crowned  with 
extraordinary  success:  among  his  numerous  pupils  were  included  even  old 
doctors  who  sought  to  complete  their  training  with  him;  is  a  practitioner 
he  was  resorted  to  by  high  and  low  and  was  overwhelmed  with  consulta- 
tions and  loaded  with  brilliant  honours.  Considerate  even  towards  those  of 
different  opinion,  of  an  affectionate,  sympathetic  nature,  he  was  himself 
universally  beloved.  He  died  in  1741,  in  harness  to  the  last. 

^  In  his  own  circle  his  contempt  for  theories  seems  sometimes  to  have  been  expressed  in 
a  somewhat  original  way ;  thus,  a  colleague  who  asked  for  advice  regarding  the  choice  of  medical 
literature  was  told  to  read  Don  Quixete. 


SEVENTEENTH     AND     EIGHTEENTH     CENTURIES       1 77 
Hoffmann's  practical  ivork  and  bis  theory 
Undoubtedly  Hoffmann's  services  to  science  lie  principally  in  the  sphere  of 
practical  medicine.  He  described  several  diseases  hitherto  unaccounted  for; 
both  in  theory  and  in  practice  he  insisted  upon  accurate  diagnosis  based  upon 
natural-scientific  principles,  considerate  treatment  of  the  sick,  and  simple 
medicines.  He  himself  made  up  and  sold  at  a  great  profit  quite  a  number  of 
preparations,  which  still  play  their  part  in  popular  medicine.  He  was  a  very 
productive  writer  on  medical  subjects  in  every  conceivable  specialized  sphere, 
but  he  also  tried  to  combine  in  one  general  theory  of  the  functions  of  the  body 
the  principles  at  which  he  had  arrived  in  the  course  of  his  work,  and  this 
theory  has  not  been  without  its  importance  for  the  general  development  of 
biology.  It  takes  as  its  starting-point  the  so-called  chemiatric  theories  preva- 
lent in  the  seventeenth  century,  which  ultimately  originated  in  Paracelsus's 
fantastic  speculations  as  to  the  human  body's  being  composed  of  quicksilver, 
sulphur,  and  salt,  and  in  conformity  with  its  original  sought  to  explain  the 
functions  of  the  body  as  essentially  phenomena  of  chemical  change,  for  which 
purpose  recourse  was  had  either  to  the  mechanical  theories  of  the  movements 
of  the  body,  described  in  the  foregoing,  or  else  to  the  mass  of  mystical  specu- 
lations still  available  at  that  time,  to  fill  up  the  gaps  in  the  proposed  system. 
Hoffmann  takes  his  stand  at  the  very  start  on  chemico-mechanical  ground.  He 
himself  was  a  clever  chemist  and  besides  possessed  a  complete  mastery  of  the 
anatomical  literature  of  his  age,  in  which  sphere  both  Borelli  and  Perrault 
had  some  influence  on  him;  and,  finally,  he  had  not  neglected  the  discoveries 
of  either  Newton  or  Leibniz.  He  began  with  the  principle  that  matter  and 
motion  form  the  foundation  of  existence;  the  body  is  a  machine,  which  is 
kept  going  by  the  circulation  of  the  blood.  Life  is  thus  a  purely  mechanical 
process,  from  whose  functions  the  activities  of  the  soul  can  be  excluded; 
when  the  body  dies,  it  is  not  the  soul  that  leaves  the  body,  but  the  body  that 
abandons  the  soul,  so  that  the  latter  can  no  longer  use  the  organs  of  the  body 
as  its  tools.  The  movement  of  the  blood  is  caused  by  the  heart;  the  latter's 
action,  again,  is  regulated  by  the  movements  in  the  nervous  system,  in  the 
fibres  of  which  there  circulates  a  fluid,  "sfiritus  animalis,"  which  is  formed 
of  extremely  light  ether-particles  and  is  produced  in  the  brain  and  by  its 
movements  induces  and  regulates  the  muscular  functions,  sense-impressions, 
and  alimental  processes.  The  power  of  the  blood  to  maintain  life  is  due  to 
the  fact  that  it  contains  a  "spiritus"  formed  of  the  ether  constituents  of  the 
air  and  the  sulphurous  element  in  the  blood.  Chemically,  in  fact,  the  com- 
ponents of  the  blood  are  partly  sulphurous,  partly  ethereal,   and  partly 
earthy;  the  sulphur  element  is  the  cause  of  the  warmth  of  the  body,  both  the 
natural  warmth  and  that  increased  by  inflammation,  which  is  induced  by 
the  sulphur  particles  easily  becoming  extremely  mobile  through  the  action 
of  the  ether.  The  function  of  the  lungs  is  to  mingle  the  component  parts  of 


lyS  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

the  blood,  besides  which  the  inhaled  air  conveys  to  it  fresh  ether  particles, 
which  augment  its  power  to  keep  the  mechanism  of  the  body  working.  It 
would  take  too  long  to  record  here  the  complicated  accounts  of  the  produc- 
tion and  dispersion  of  the  nervous  fluid;  it  may  just  be  mentioned  that  the 
finest  and  most  vitally  essential  part  of  the  fluid  is  said  to  emanate  from  the 
cortex  of  the  great  brain.  The  male  semen  is  closely  akin  to  the  nervous  fluid, 
and  its  function  is  thus  to  give  life  to  the  egg,  so  that  it  may  start  developing. 

Hoffmann,  having  thus  described  the  mechanism  of  the  body,  declares 
that  man  naturally  possesses  an  immortal  soul,  given  him  by  God;  the  will  of 
this  soul  controls  the  movement  of  the  body,  and  through  it  we  understand, 
think,  and  act.  Following  many  other  old  authors  and  supported  by  the  Holy 
Scriptures,  he  divides  man  into  three  "principia" — namely,  corpus,  spiritus, 
and  anima  —  that  is,  the  body,  the  above-described  nervous  fluid,  and  the  con- 
sciousness. But  besides  these  man  possesses  a  higher  "substance,"  which  the 
ancient  philosophers  called  mens  and  which  Scripture  names  the  image  of 
the  spirit  of  God;  this  substance  makes  use  of  the  consciousness's  impression 
of  things  and  forms  them  into  ideas;  false  sense-impressions  may  be  rectified 
by  clear  reason,  but  a  mass  of  confused  sense-impressions  causes  madness. 
Concussion  of  mind  may  also  disturb  the  circulation  of  the  blood  and  produce 
a  condition  of  sickness  in  the  body.  But  Hoffmann  resolutely  denies  that 
the  movement  and  function  of  the  body  originate  in  the  soul;  "although  the 
human  soul  possesses  a  certain  limited  influence  over  the  bodily  parts,  never- 
theless medicine  both  in  theory  and  in  practice  is  pure  mechanics,  in  that  it 
is  based  upon  purely  mechanical  principles  —  namely,  motion  and  matter." 
The  inconsistencies  and  the  arbitrary  constructions  of  thought  in  this  attempt 
to  form  a  mechanical  conception  of  life-phenomena  will  be  easily  realized  by 
the  modern  reader,  but  should  not  in  any  way  detract  from  the  respect  due 
to  this  attempt  —  which  at  any  rate  is  based  on  very  substantial  experiences, 
considering  the  age  —  to  find  a  natural  connexion  in  the  life-process.  The 
assumption  of  an  immortal  soul  is  explained  by  the  fact  that  Hoffmann  was 
a  devout  Christian  with  a  markedly  pietistic  temperament;  Halle  was  the 
source  and  centre  of  pietism,  and  Hoffmann  was  a  warm  friend  of  its  founders, 
Spener  and  Franke.  He  also  displays  in  many  places  a  naive  childlike  piety, 
as  when  he  dedicates  one  of  his  books  to  "The  Holy  Trinity,  the  Supreme 
Physician."  Thus  we  have  here  a  proof  that  a  mechanical  conception  of  life 
and  ancient  theological  dogmas  were  formerly  capable  of  being  reconciled, 
which  would  hardly  be  considered  possible  in  our  own  day. 

One  of  Hoffmann's  first  steps  when  elected  professor  at  Halle  was  to 
bring  about  the  appointment  of  an  old  fellow  student  from  Jena,  Georg 
Ernst  Stahl,  to  be  assistant  professor  of  medicine;  Hoffmann  retained  for 
himself  the  position  of  teacher  in  practical  medicine,  while  Stahl  took  over 
the  theoretical  side.  Stahl  was  born  in  1660  of  a  Protestant  family  at  Ansbach 


SEVENTEENTH  AND  EIGHTEENTH  CENTURIES  179 
in  Bavaria,  receiving  a  strictly  religious  upbringing,  which  left  its  mark  on 
his  entire  life.  He  studied  at  Jena,  where  be  became  a  doctor  and  for  a  time 
gave  lectures.  After  having  been  for  some  years  court  physician  at  Weimar, 
he  came,  as  mentioned  above,  to  Halle  and  taught  there  for  about  twenty 
years.  At  first  his  relations  with  Hoffmann  were  in  every  way  friendly,  but 
gradually  the  good  feeling  between  them  changed,  and,  finding  that  Hoff- 
mann's personal  superiority  excluded  all  possibility  of  competition,  Stahl 
resigned  from  his  professorship  and  in  1716  accepted  an  appointment  as 
physician  to  the  court  in  Berlin.  He  died  there  in  1734.  Hoffmann  and  Stahl 
possessed  their  pietistic  devoutness  in  common,  but  otherwise  they  were 
highly  contrasted:  Hoffmann,  of  stately  build,  lovable,  and  popular;  Stahl, 
in  his  appearance  insignificant,  in  his  manner  austere  and  inaccessible,  in- 
tolerant towards  his  opponents,  and  bitter  in  controversy.  At  any  rate  he 
was  a  sincere  seeker  after  truth,  who  was  honest  enough  —  a  quality  other- 
wise not  very  common  amongst  scientists  —  when  he  changed  his  opinion, 
openly  to  admit  the  incorrectness  of  his  former  views,  and  he  likewise 
possessed  that  rare  habit  of  gratefully  acknowledging  his  predecessors' 
contributions  to  the  problems  he  dealt  with, 

Reformer  of  chemistry 
As  a  scientific  writer  Stahl  was,  like  Hoffmann,  extraordinarily  productive 
and  he  dealt  with  a  considerable  number  of  different  medical  problems.  As 
a  scientist  he  was  undeniably  superior  to  his  rival;  in  fact,  his  name  is  one 
of  the  foremost  in  the  history  of  the  natural  sciences  —  principally  on  ac- 
count of  his  work  as  a  chemist.  At  the  close  of  the  seventeenth  century  there 
was  still  being  commonly  taught  at  the  German  universities  the  subject  of 
alchemy  —  belief  in  the  transformation  of  metals,  in  the  philosophers' 
stone,  and  all  the  rest  of  the  mediasval  mysticism  which  in  western  Europe, 
thanks  to  Boyle  and  his  successors,  had  already  been  disestablished.  Even 
Stahl  had  begun  as  an  alchemist,  and  in  his  earliest  writings  he  discusses 
the  usual  alchemistic  problems,  but  by  his  own  efforts  he  undeceived  himself 
and  thereafter  never  hesitated  to  point  to  the  treatises  of  his  youth  as  a 
warning.  That  uniform  conception  of  the  changes  in  nature  which  the 
alchemists  sought  to  produce  by  means  of  their  mystical  speculations  Stahl 
now  endeavoured  to  attain  by  a  comparison  of  those  processes  that  take 
place  in  combustion  on  the  one  hand  and  the  calcination  of  metals  on  the 
other.  Finally  he  obtained  a  common  ground  of  explanation  for  these  phe- 
nomena by  postulating  the  existence  of  a  fluid  substance,  phlogiston,  in  both 
combustible  substances  and  metals;  in  combustion  phlogiston  disappeared 
from  the  burnt  material,  as  it  did  also  from  the  metal  in  calcination;  the 
metal  calces  were  thus  like  the  metal,  minus  phlogiston.  If  the  metal  calces 
were  heated  with  a  substance  containing  phlogiston  —  as,  for  instance, 
coal  —  the  metal  was  recovered  by  the  reintroduction  of  phlogiston.  — 


l8o  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

This  theory  rendered  possible  a  uniform  conception  of  a  number  of  processes 
of  conversion  in  inorganic  nature;  it  constituted  a  working  hypothesis 
which  had  a  great  influence  upon  the  science  of  chemistry  in  succeeding  ages 
and  made  the  eighteenth  century  a  period  of  brilliant  achievement  in  chemi- 
cal history;  names  such  as  Priestley,  Bergman,  Scheele,  bear  witness  to  the 
progress  made  in  chemistry  when  the  phlogiston  theory  was  dominant;  and 
when  eventually  Lavoisier,  by  introducing  the  weighing  method,  proved 
that  the  theory  was  untenable  and  substituted  the  idea  of  oxidation  for  cal- 
cination, the  new  theory  could  be  applied  directly  to  the  discovery  that  had 
been  made  when  the  old  theory  prevailed.  Were  it  only  for  the  advance  he 
thus  brought  about  in  chemistry  alone,  Stahl  would  deserve  a  place  in  the 
history  of  biology,  which  has  been  so  essentially  dependent  upon  the  prog- 
ress of  chemistry,  and  indeed  will  always  be  so. 

StahVs  medical  theory 
What  constitutes  Stahl's  principal  claim  to  be  mentioned  as  a  biologist, 
however,  is  the  theory  of  life  which  he  expounds  in  his  great  work  Tbeoria 
rnedica  vera,  in  which  he  seeks  to  formulate  a  general  theory  of  the  human 
body  and  its  functions,  both  in  its  normal  state  and  in  sickness.  He  himself 
has  declared,  and  it  has  been  repeated  after  him,  that  his  chemical  theories 
exercised  no  influence  upon  his  ideas  on  the  subject.  This  is  true  in  so  far  as 
he  does  not  —  like  his  predecessors  amongst  medical  chemists,  Paracelsus, 
van  Helmont,  and  others  —  base  his  entire  conception  of  the  human  body 
upon  speculation  as  to  its  chemical  composition,  but,  on  the  other  hand,  the 
essential  part  of  his  work  gives  ample  proof  that  chemistry  is  the  science  on 
which  he  bases  his  ideas.  Above  all,  he  is  no  anatomist;  he  scorns  the  result 
of  ordinary  macroscopical  anatomy  and  he  can  hardly  find  words  to  express 
his  contempt  for  Leeuwenhoek's  and  de  Graaf's  microscopical  investigation 
of  the  sexual  products;  he  likewise  strongly  contemns  the  discovery  of  the 
capillary  system,  the  existence  of  which  he  simply  denies.  On  the  other  hand, 
he  displays  a  very  keen  interest  in  the  "mixing  {nnxtio)"  of  the  body  and  its 
parts  —  that  is,  their  chemical  composition  —  and  he  believes  that  a  true 
conception  of  the  phenomena  of  life  should  be  based  on  the  knowledge  of 
this  ' 'mixtio.' '  Indeed,  it  is  in  this  direction  that  he  has  performed  his  greatest 
services  to  biology. 

The  first  chapter  of  Stahl's  principal  work,  mentioned  above,  is  entitled 
"An  Examination  of  the  Difi^erence  between  Mechanism  and  Organism." 
This  title  might  well  hold  good  for  the  whole  of  Stahl's  literary  work 
on  general  science;  the  contrast  mechanism--organism  is  to  him  the  main 
point  in  both  biology  and  medical  science;  he  discusses  it  from  every  con- 
ceivable point  of  view,  and  in  support  of  his  views  thereon  cites  a  number 
of  arguments,  both  good  and  bad.  The  main  argument,  which  he  repeats 
again  and  again  in  proof  of  his  theory,  is  that  organism  is  something  funda- 


SEVENTEENTH  AND  EIGHTEENTH  CENTURIES  l8l 
mentally  different  from  mechanism,  that  consequently  the  mechanical 
physiology  which  his  contemporaries  universally  accepted  must  be  utterly 
repudiated.  In  the  living  organism  the  soul  is  the  essential  part;  the  body 
exists  for  the  sake  of  the  soul  and  is  controlled  by  the  soul.  As  a  proof  of 
this  assertion  he  quotes,  to  start  with,  a  number  of  ancient  Aristotelean 
arguments  on  the  finality  of  the  structure  of  the  body.  Further,  he  declares 
that  the  existence  of  the  body  is  due  to  a  thing  which  is  in  itself  foreign  to  the 
essence  of  the  body,  but,  on  the  other  hand,  is  akin  to  the  essence  of  the  soul, 
owing  to  its  immateriality  —  namely,  motion.  The  soul's  function  consists 
in  going  from  object  to  object  and  comparing  them,  and  the  maintenance 
of  the  body  by  means  of  mental  activity  and  constant  moving  goes  on,  sub- 
ject to  the  will  of  the  soul,  as  the  result  of  motions  suited  to  the  objects  that 
the  soul  requires.  The  fact  that  Stahl  thus  calls  motion  "thing"  and  com- 
pares it  with  the  soul  in  contrast  to  the  body  proves  that  at  any  rate  he  had 
learnt  nothing  from  Galileo  and  Newton.  If,  then,  we  find  in  this  and  other 
similar  arguments  the  utter  hollowness  of  Stahl's  philosophical  speculations, 
he  has  on  other  occasions  an  exceptionally  keen  eye,  trained  through  his 
chemical  studies  for  the  essential  in  the  composition  of  organism.  As  some- 
thing essential  to  all  the  constituents  of  the  body  he  points  out  the  extreme 
easiness  and  rapidity  with  which  they  are  chemically  decomposed.  This 
property  evidently  made  a  great  impression  on  him;  he  constantly  reverts 
to  it  and  searches  for  an  explanation  for  it,  but  it  is  obvious  that,  with  the 
fundamental  ideas  that  he  once  embraced,  it  is  always  the  soul  which  ulti- 
mately keeps  the  body  together  and  prevents  it  from  disintegrating.  This 
easy  deccmposability  is  considered  to  be  due  to  a  very  complicated  chemical 
combination  in  its  constituent  parts  —  a  fact  that  differentiates  it  from 
ordinary  chemical  associations.  The  chemical  quality  is  different  in  different 
forms  of  life  and  peculiar  to  each  individual.  Finally,  the  constituent  parts 
of  the  body  possess,  besides  their  chemical  quality,  a  special  "texture"  and 
"structure":  the  former  an  arrangement  of  the  smallest  parts  of  the  body, 
the  latter  a  combination  of  the  elements  thus  formed,  these  two  factors  being 
characteristic  for  every  living  being.  "Living  body  is  nothing  else  than  that 
which  has  structure,"  he  declares.  It  is  hardly  necessary  to  lay  special  stress 
on  the  fact  that  as  a  result  of  all  this  investigation  into  the  chemical  nature 
of  organism  Stahl  advanced  science  a  long  way;  both  the  complex  composi- 
tion and  the  resultant  easy  decomposability  of  the  constituent  parts  of  the 
living  body  are  indeed  facts  of  fundamental  importance  for  modern  biology, 
and  of  still  greater  importance  is  his  postulate  that  structure  is  something 
peculiar  to  the  living  organism  in  contrast  to  dead  natural  objects.  Here 
Stahl  has  without  doubt  had  some  presentiment  as  to  the  significance  of 
tissue  structure  as  a  basis  of  life  in  all  its  forms;  that  he  was  unable  to  follow 
up  the  idea  to  a  conclusion  of  immense  value  to  science  was  certainly  due 


iSz  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

to  his  lack  of  interest  in  anatomy.  Nor,  indeed,  did  his  contemporary  age 
realize  the  importance  of  this  question;  it  was  not  until  sixty  years  after 
Stahl's  death  that  Bichat,  basing  his  results  on  anatomical  studies  along 
many  different  lines  of  inquiry,  established  the  vital  part  played  by  the 
tissues  in  maintaining  the  functions  of  the  body,  but,  as  we  shall  see  later 
on,  he  had  come  from  a  school  in  France  that  adopted  and  developed  Stahl's 
ideas. 

Doctrine  of  the  soul  as  cause  of  life-phenomena 
The  theory  of  Stahl's  which  aroused  most  interest  in  his  time  —  that  is, 
which  evoked  most  applause  and  most  controversy  —  was  his  doctrine  of 
the  soul  as  the  cause  of  all  life-phenomena,  as  their  one  supreme  condition 
and  their  final  aim.  This  "animistic"  conception  of  the  structure  and  func- 
tions of  the  body,  according  to  which  every  manifestation  of  life,  whether 
it  is  a  question  of  the  absorption  of  food,  the  blood-circulation,  the  processes 
of  secretion  and  excretion,  or  simple  movements  from  one  place  to  another, 
muscular  activity  and  sensations,  takes  place  exclusively  for  the  sake  of  the 
soul,  is  induced  by  it,  controlled  by  it,  and  pursues  its  normal  course  thanks 
to  it  —  this  theory,  so  utterly  opposed  to  the  contemporary  mechanical  con- 
ception of  life,  was  in  reality  the  one  main  factor  for  Stahl,  the  very  founda- 
tion on  which  he  built  up  his  medical  system.  For  Stahl  aimed  at  creating 
a  new  medical  science,  and  his  speculations  in  common  biology  were  in- 
tended merely  to  lay  the  foundations  of  that  science.  Naturally,  the  dis- 
eases of  the  body  are  also  caused  by  the  soul;  if  it  relaxes  its  control  of  the 
body  or  any  part  thereof,  there  at  once  ensues  general  or  local  decomposition 
of  the  inconstant  chemical  associations  of  which  the  body  is  made  up,  and 
sickness  or  death  results.  And  Stahl  does  not  hesitate  to  follow  up  this  theory 
to  its  ultimate  conclusions:  if  the  soul  desires  to  do  so,  it  can  naturally  keep 
the  body  whole,  but,  as  it  happens,  the  soul  is  wayward,  inconstant,  and 
inconsiderate,  and  the  body  has  to  suffer  for  it.  The  soul  of  animals  possesses 
in  this  respect  less  freedom  of  action  than  the  human  soul,  with  the  result 
that  animals  are  less  often  sick.  One  would  suppose  that  in  these  circum- 
stances any  kind  of  medical  treatment  would  be  superfluous,  since  it  has  to 
deal  with  the  body,  which  is  in  any  case  powerless,  but  Stahl  does  not  draw 
this  conclusion;  like  the  homoeopaths  of  a  later  period,  however,  he  pre- 
scribes remedies  having  a  mild  action,  with  which  he  believes  it  possible  to 
help  the  soul  in  its  functions  to  the  improvement  of  the  body;  violent 
remedies,  such  as  quinine  and  opium,  he  deprecates.  There  is  one  con- 
clusion that  he  draws  from  his  system  which  does  him  honour  —  namely, 
when  he  prescribes  mild  treatment  in  mental  cases;  otherwise  the  physicians 
of  his  age,  even  the  most  humane,  generally  employed  violent  and  sometimes 
brutal  methods  in  their  attempt  to  drive  out  the  mental  disease  from  the 
unfortunates  who  were  thus  afflicted. 


SEVENTEENTH  AND  EIGHTEENTH  CENTURIES  183 
Those  of  Stahl's  contemporaries  who  adopted  his  ideas  were  at  any  rate 
not  compelled  to  associate  themselves  with  the  peculiar  theories  referred  to 
above.  His  criticism  of  that  age's  mechanistic  conception  of  life  is  indeed 
often  of  such  penetrating  keenness  that  it  must  have  proved  attractive  to 
those  who  sought  to  probe  the  contemporary  controversial  problems  in  that 
sphere.  Especially  does  he  inveigh  against  the  theories  of  these  "vital 
spirits"  on  which  his  opponents'  explanations  of  the  phenomena  of  life 
rested  and  which  they  could  not  possibly  do  without.  Compared  with  these 
theories  his  soul-theory  was  at  least  simple  and  easy  to  comprehend;  it  cleared 
up  satisfactorily  enough  the  question  of  the  relation  of  the  psychical  phe- 
nomena to  the  material,  a  problem  on  which  all  previous  attempts  to  explain 
mechanically  the  phenomena  of  life  came  to  grief.  Stahl  also  had  a  sharp 
eye  for  other  weaknesses  in  the  contemporary  explanations  of  life  and  demon- 
strated their  inanity,  as,  for  instance,  the  pan-sperma  theories  that  were  so 
common  at  the  time.  Besides  his  above-mentioned  keen  analysis  of  the  con- 
trasts between  living  and  inorganic  natural  objects,  which  is  only  briefly 
summarized  here,  these  critical  contributions  relating  to  the  controversial 
biological  questions  of  his  age  constitute  Stahl's  great  service  to  science. 
This  is,  it  is  true,  counterbalanced  by  his  vague,  yet  subtle,  natural  philosophy, 
which  has  also  been  but  briefly  recounted  here,  and  the  understanding  of 
which  is  rendered  all  the  more  difficult  by  a  very  obscure  and  badly  arranged 
method  of  presentation.  He  gained  many  followers  among  his  contempora- 
ries; several  of  his  own  pupils  gave  practical  demonstrations  of  the  dangers  of 
regarding  the  soul  as  an  instrumental  component  in  the  functions  of  the  body 
and  the  treatment  of  disease  by  indulging  in  extravagant  speculations  along 
mystical  and  theosophical  lines.  The  valuable  parts  of  his  theories  were 
most  strictly  adhered  to  and  most  faithfully  developed  at  the  University  of 
Montpellier,  where  an  entire  school  of  physicians  embraced  his  ideas.  Among 
his  opponents  may  be  especially  mentioned,  besides  his  old  friend  Hoffmann, 
Leibniz,  who  in  a  contentious  pamphlet  sharply  inveighed  against  his  con- 
tempt of  anatomy,  chemistry,  and  other  exact  methods  of  research,  and,  from 
the  standpoint  of  his  own  monad  theory,  rejected  Stahl's  theories  of  the  soul 
and  motion  as  being  separate  from  the  material  part  of  living  beings  and  as 
factors  operating  independently  thereof.  The  influence  that  Stahl  had  on  the 
development  of  biology  in  later  times  may  at  first  glance  seem  small;  in- 
directly, however,  he  has  certainly  been  of  greater  significance  than  many  of 
those  who  are  more  frequently  quoted.  Among  those  who  have  openly 
acknowledged  their  indebtedness  to  him  may  be  mentioned  such  a  compara- 
tively well-known  scientist  as  the  embryologist  Caspar  Friedrich  Wolff. 

The  man  who,  of  the  medical  and  biological  theorists  of  that  time, 
undoubtedly  enjoyed  the  highest  reputation  among  his  contemporaries  was, 
however,  Hermann  Boerhaave.  He  was  born  in  1668,  the  son  of  a  country 


184  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

parson,  near  Leyden  in  Holland;  and  there  he  studied,  first  of  all,  theology; 
but  after  becoming  acquainted  with  Spinoza's  theories  he  soon  put  an  end 
to  all  idea  of  entering  the  clergy.  So  he  had  to  look  about  him  for  a  new- 
means  of  livelihood.  After  taking  a  degree  in  philosophy  at  Leyden  he  moved 
to  the  small  university  of  Harderwijk  and  there  very  quickly  passed  a  medi- 
cal examination,  after  which  he  settled  down  in  Leyden  as  a  practitioner 
and  teacher.  At  first  he  had  a  hard  struggle,  but  he  assiduously  carried  on  his 
profession,  and  his  reputation  rose  year  by  year  until  he  was  finally  elected 
cO  the  first  chair  of  medicine  at  Leyden  and  became  universally  acknowledged 
as  the  foremost  physician  in  Europe.  In  that  position  he  acquired  an  influ- 
ence such  as  few  have  ever  possessed  before  or  since;  his  advice  was  sought 
not  only  from  every  corner  of  this  hemisphere  but  even  from  the  most  distant 
parts  of  the  East.  He  made  a  vast  income  and  died  a  multi-millionaire.  These 
successes  were  made  possible  owing  to  his  brilliant  gifts  and,  in  spite  of 
lifelong  physical  ill-health,  his  unfailing  energy.  But  above  even  these 
merits  his  contemporaries  valued  his  noble  character;  he  lived  extremely 
simply,  while  he  used  his  great  wealth  to  render  help  to  the  poor  and  sick 
and  to  give  generous  support  to  science;  thus,  he  rescued  Swammerdam's 
writings  from  destruction  and  enabled  Linnaeus  to  carry  out  his  work  in 
Holland;  he  was  friendly  and  modest  in  society,  but  when  the  necessity 
arose,  he  could  stand  upon  his  dignity  against  even  the  highest  in  the  com- 
munity. He  died  in  1738,  having  during  the  last  years  of  his  life  had  to  give 
up  his  professorial  duties  owing  to  ill  health. 

Boerhaave' s  theory:  limitation  of  natural-scientific  research 
Boerhaave's  attitude  towards  the  general  biological  problems  of  his  time 
was  undoubtedly  dictated  by  the  fact  that  he  had  studied  Spinoza  in  his 
youth  and  was  throughout  his  life  a  keen  admirer  of  Sydenham.  Reminiscent 
of  the  former  is  his  clearly  and  vigorously  expressed  characterization  of  the 
relation  between  body  and  soul.  In  man  everything  that  involves  thought  is 
to  be  ascribed  entirely  to  the  soul  as  its  starting-point.  Whatever,  on  the 
other  hand,  involves  extension,  impenetrability,  form,  or  motion,  must  be 
referred  entirely  to  the  body  and  its  motion.  Again,  he  is  reminiscent  of 
Sydenham  in  his  realization  of  the  limitations  of  natural-scientific  research. 
"The  investigation  of  the  ultimate  metaphysical  and  the  primary  physical 
causes  is  neither  necessary  nor  useful  nor  possible  for  a  physician.  Examples 
of  these  causes  are:  the  elements,  the  first  forms,  the  origin  of  procreation, 
movement,  etc."  This  quotation,  moreover,  shows  his  decidedly  practical 
nature,  also  resembling  Sydenham's.  He  actually  placed  it  as  the  foremost 
aim  of  his  science  to  create  capable  practical  physicians.  To  gain  this  end, 
however,  he  considered  that  a  grounding  in  general  science  was  indispensa- 
ble, and  he  therefore  made  a  close  study  of  the  general  structure  and  func- 
tions of  the  body,  his  work  being  based  on  what  was  a  rare  thing  in  those 


SEVENTEENTH  AND  EIGHTEENTH  CENTURIES  185 
days,  a  thorough  knowledge  of  the  entire  range  of  the  then  known  medical 
and  biological  literature.  The  common  biological,  or,  as  he  termed  it,  phys- 
iological, section  of  his  principal  work,  Institutiones  medicce,  gives  the  im- 
pression, owing  to  the  mass  of  second-hand  information  that  he  imparts 
when  quoting  his  sources,  of  being  to  a  certain  extent  a  compilation  —  in 
fact,  it  was  published  with  the  expressed  intention  of  providing  a  handbook 
for  instructional  purposes  —  but  the  ideas  he  presents  in  it  are  at  any  rate 
thought  out  on  entirely  original  lines,  and  the  whole  work  seems,  in  com- 
parison with  Hoffmann's  or  Stahl's  theoretical  speculations,  strikingly 
modern.  The  abstract  theories  are,  as  a  matter  of  fact,  entirely  thrust  into 
the  background  in  favour  of  a  close  analysis  of  all  the  known  facts  relating 
to  the  functions  of  the  body.  First  he  describes  the  digestion,  starting  with  a 
detailed  account  of  mastication;  then  the  functions  of  the  digestive  canal 
and  its  glands;  then  the  circulation  of  the  blood,  and  respiration,  the  brain 
and  nervous  system,  several  glandular  systems,  the  muscles,  the  skin,  sen- 
sations, and  reproduction.  From  a  purely  anatomical  point  of  view  the 
presentation  does  not  on  the  whole  differ  from  the  results  achieved  in  modern 
times;  we  find  here  that  he  has  taken  full  advantage  of  every  step  of  progress 
made  by  such  people  as  Borelli,  Malpighi,  and  Ruysch.  In  particular 
Ruysch's  careful  dissections  and  injections  Boerhaave,  who,  indeed,  was  a 
personal  friend  of  his,  was  able  to  take  advantage  of  in  a  masterly  way. 

Hij"  mechanical  conception  of  life 
When  he  comes  to  explain  the  functions  of  the  different  organs,  he  bases  his 
ideas  on  a  strictly  mechanical  conception:  the  action  of  the  body  is  motion; 
"the  power  to  exert  movement  is  called  function,  which  takes  place  in  ac- 
cordance with  mechanical  laws  and  only  by  them  can  be  explained."  Thus 
both  the  disintegration  and  assimilation  of  food  in  the  body  are  purely 
mechanical  — ■  he  denies  that  the  gastric  juices  have  any  chemical  reaction  — 
the  principal  agent  is  the  body's  own  heat  and  the  constant  movements  of 
the  digestive  canal  and  its  surrounding  organs,  but  the  nervous  fluid  also 
plays  a  predominant  part  in  the  functions  of  the  body.  With  regard  to  the 
question  of  the  "cooking"  of  food  in  the  digestive  canal,  as  assumed  by 
ancient  authors,  Boerhaave  takes  up  a  somewhat  sceptical  attitude.  On  the 
other  hand,  he  believes  that  acrid  and  unsuitable  food-substances  become  ex- 
cluded by  contracting  the  openings  of  the  chyle  vessels  into  the  bowel.  Such 
food  as  has  been  taken  into  the  chyle  vessels  is  conveyed  through  the  thorax 
to  the  venous  system;  there  blood  and  chyle  are  mingled,  and  this  mixture 
becomes  complete  through  the  blood's  passing  into  the  lungs,  whose  porous 
structure  serves  to  render  the  mixture  as  thorough  as  possible.  In  a  conten- 
tious article  written  against  Borelli,  who  believed  it  to  be  the  case,  he  denies 
that  the  air  from  the  lungs  passes  into  the  blood;  Boerhaave  is  unable  to 
explain  why  it  is  that  living  creatures  cannot  breathe  in  an  unventilated 


l86  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

room.  The  brain  also  serves  to  purify  the  blood,  which  passes  through  it  for 
that  purpose.  Moreover,  the  cerebral  cortex  collects  from  the  blood  its  finest 
constituents,  which  give  rise  to  the  fluid  that  is  conveyed  from  the  brain 
through  the  tubular  nerve-threads  out  into  all  the  different  parts  of  the  body 
and  induces  movements  in  them.  In  particular  Boerhaave  inquired  deeply 
into  the  problem  of  muscular  contraction  and  its  relation  to  impulses  derived 
from  the  nervous  system;  he  gives  an  account  of  an  experiment  to  show  that 
muscular  action  is  dependent  upon  the  nerve  and  he  considers  that  this  in- 
fluence of  the  nerve  is  due  to  the  flowing  of  fluid  from  the  brain.  With  regard 
to  the  mechanical  action  of  the  muscles,  Boerhaave  highly  commends  Borelli's 
mechanical  investigations;  the  affluxion  of  the  nervous  fluid  he  believes  takes 
place  in  accordance  with  Mariotte's  law.^  Boerhaave  gives  a  detailed  de- 
scription of  the  structure  and  function  of  the  genital  organs,  which  is  based 
on  the  discoveries  of  Leeuwenhoek  and  de  Graaf.  He  holds  that  the  sperm 
is  "refined"  blood;  its  small,  living  "animalcula"  contain  rudiments  of  the 
organs  of  the  future  embryo;  as  eggs  he  regards  the  follicles  in  the  ovary, 
in  this  following  de  Graaf;  conception  takes  place  as  a  result  of  the  "living 
elements"  of  the  sperm  penetrating  the  pores  of  the  egg. 

As  a  whole  Boerhaave 's  biological  theory  must  be  considered  to  come 
far  nearer  our  modern  ideas  than  either  Hoffmann's  or  Stahl's  —  this  both 
on  account  of  what  he  knows  and  above  all  on  account  of  what  he  considers 
it  impossible  to  know.  His  insight  into  the  limitations  of  natural  science 
really  testifies  more  than  anything  else  to  his  greatness;  as  regards  facts,  we 
cannot  expect  of  him  more  than  it  was  possible  for  his  age  to  attain.  But  it 
is  just  his  deliberateness  that  it  has  been  difficult  both  for  his  contemporaries 
and  for  posterity  to  understand;  the  desire  to  solve  the  ultimate  riddle  of 
life  has  again  driven  the  philosopher  beyond  the  limits  of  what  science  can 
attain  with  the  means  available.  We  shall  leave  Boerhaave,  clear-sighted 
and  conscious  of  his  own  limitations,  and  shall  proceed  to  consider  a  scientist 
who  sought  to  solve  the  riddle  of  life  along  speculative  lines  and  who  ex- 
pended on  this  endeavour  one  of  the  richest  and  most  fertile  geniuses  known 
to  history  —  namely,  Swedenborg. 

The  son  of  Bishop  Jesper  Swedberg,  a  famous  hymn-writer  and  preacher 
of  the  Swedish  Church,  Emanuel  Swedenborg  was  born  in  1688  and  received 
a  thorough  school  and  university  education  at  Upsala,  where  he  grew  up; 
having  completed  which,  he  spent  several  years  in  England  and  on  the 
Continent,  studying  principally  natural  sciences,  both  theoretical  and  ap- 
plied. Having  returned  home,  he  served  as  a  military  engineer  during  the 
last  fighting  years  of  Charles  XII,  then  became  assessor  of  the  board  of  mines, 

^  Boerhaave  undoubtedly  refers  to  the  hydrostatic  experiment  which  goes  by  the  name  of 
Mariotte's  bottle;  how  its  phenomena  are  to  be  applied  to  the  nervous  and  muscular  functions 
is,  however,  not  clearly  stated. 


SEVENTEENTH  AND  EIGHTEENTH  CENTURIES  187 
and  was  elevated  to  the  nobility,'  displaying  during  the  next  decades  inde- 
fatigable energy  as  an  official,  member  of  the  House  of  Nobles,  and  scientific 
writer.  Then  during  the  years  1744-5  ^^  underwent  a  severe  spiritual  crisis; 
after  repeated  phases  of  alternate  depression  and  exaltation  he  beheld  in  a 
vision  the  Saviour  Himself  and  learnt  from  Him  that  he  was  henceforth  to 
devote  himself  entirely  to  spiritual  matters.  He  at  once  resigned  his  post  of 
assessor  and  devoted  his  whole  life  to  spreading  the  new  doctrine  that  he 
believed  he  had  received  direct  from  heaven  through  repeated  spiritual 
revelations.  Pestered  by  the  priesthood  in  his  native  country,  he  lived  his 
last  years  mostly  abroad,  and  died  in  deep  poverty  in  London  in  the  year 
1772.,  misunderstood  by  his  own  age,  but  honoured  as  a  religious  founder  by 
a  small  group  of  believers. 

Swedenborg's  natural-scientific  works  are  extraordinarily  extensive;  he 
published  books  on  mathematics,  physics  and  chemistry,  geology  and  cos- 
mology, anatomy  and  physiology,  and,  besides  this,  much  of  what  he  wrote 
remained  unprinted  and  has  not  been  published  until  our  own  time,  as,  for  in- 
stance, his  anatomical  work  De  Cerebro,  which,  contains  his  most  important  in- 
vestigations regarding  the  brain.  All  these  works  are  full  of  ideas  and  genius, 
the  true  value  of  which  was  not  appreciated  until  our  own  day,  but  which, 
on  the  other  hand,  contain  very  little  in  the  way  of  original  observations. 
He  himself  considered  that  he  possessed  more  talent  for  thinking  about 
already  existing  facts  and  their  interrelation  than  for  making  observations 
of  his  own;  but  for  the  very  reason  that  he  did  not  support  his  speculations 
upon  facts  which  he  himself  had  observed,  he  ran  the  risk  of  letting  his 
thinking  be  influenced  by  that  attraction  for  the  mystical  which  he  had 
always  felt  and  which  had  been  encouraged  by  the  religious  environment  of 
his  childhood.  Among  the  students  of  nature  who  thus  impressed  him  must 
especially  be  mentioned  Olof  Rudbeck,  who  in  Swedenborg's  youth  was  the 
predominant  figure  in  the  University  of  Upsala  and  from  whom  he  learnt 
not  only  his  love  of  nature,  but  also  a  tendency  to  many-sided  activities  and 
fantastic  conclusions.  As  we  have  already  seen,  Rudbeck  was  an  upholder  of 
the  seventeenth  century's  mechanical  conception  of  natural  phenomena, 
both  inanimate  and  animate,  and  this  conception  was  also  adopted  by 
Swedenborg.  It  was  developed  in  the  course  of  his  foreign  tour  by  studying 
both  the  philosophy  of  Descartes  and  the  writings  of  contemporary  physicists 
and  anatomists. 

Swedenborg  s  vieivs  of  the  life-problem 
His  views  of  life  are  at  first  much  the  same  as  those  we  found  in  Hoffmann; 
the  body  is  a  mechanism,  to  which  is  added  a  vegetative  life-force,  animus, 
which  consists  of  a  fine  material  substance,  and  finally  a  higher  soul,  tnens. 

^  After  being  ennobled  he  called  himself  Swedenborg,  having  previously  borne  the  family 
name  of  Swedberg. 


l88  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

But  while  Hoffmann  leaves  the  latter  to  the  metaphysicians,  Swedenborg 
becomes  involved  in  speculations  upon  it;  he  holds  that  it  likewise  consists 
of  a  fine  material  substance,  which  leaves  the  body  at  death  and  continues 
to  live  in  space;  during  life  it  receives  mental  impressions  from  the  animus 
and  forms  them  into  knowledge.  But  what  interests  him  most  deeply  is  the 
question  why  knowledge  is  limited;  like  van  Helmont  he  concludes  that  this 
is  due  to  the  Fall,  for  before  the  Fall  Adam  was  omniscient,  and  it  now  be- 
came Swedenborg's  aim  to  acquire  this  omniscience.  He  mainly  sought  to 
gain  it  by  studying  the  function  of  the  brain  and  its  relation  to  the  life  of 
the  soul. 

Swedenborg's  investigations  of  the  brain  really  constitute  the  principal 
part  of  his  activities  as  a  natural  scientist.  In  this  field  he  succeeded,  by 
brilliant  comparison  of  conclusions  drawn  from  the  results  of  clinical  post- 
mortem examinations  and  from  contemporary  anatomical  works  —  mainly 
Malpighi's  and  Vieussens's  researches  referred  to  above  • —  in  creating  a 
theory  to  explain  the  function  of  the  central  nervous  system,  which  is  far 
superior  to  any  that  the  anatomical  specialists  of  his  time  were  capable  of 
forming.  Thus  he  localized  the  functions  of  the  soul  entirely  in  the  cortex  of 
the  great  brain  and  was  of  the  opinion  that  the  corpuscula  of  the  latter  (the 
pyramid-cells)  discovered  by  Malpighi  are  connected  by  means  of  threads 
with  the  various  parts  of  the  body  and  with  one  another,  so  that  definite  parts 
of  the  body  and  definite  parts  of  the  cerebral  cortex  are  conjoined  to  one 
another  and  form  the  substructure  for  the  functions  of  the  soul ;  it  is  through 
this  apparatus  that  the  sensations  are  put  into  motion.  This  theory  of  the 
brain,  the  value  of  which  has  been  appreciated  only  in  modern  times,  was, 
however,  made  the  basis  for  the  most  fantastic  speculations  on  the  soul, 
which  Swedenborg  now  believes  to  consist  of  a  "fluidmn  spirituostim,''  a 
substance  of  exceptional  fineness  and  directly  derived  from  the  eternal  light. 
It  is  impossible,  owing  to  the  existence  of  sin,  for  man  during  his  earthly 
life  to  come  into  contact  with  this  supreme  soul-substance,  '' anima,''  which 
possesses  entirely  ideal  qualities,  but  he  must  be  content  w4th  such  lower 
experiences  as  his  mens  and  animus  give  him  through  the  senses.  Swedenborg 
himself  sought  by  way  of  desperate  spiritual  struggles  to  acquire  that  ideal 
knowledge  which  man,  in  his  view,  had  inaccessibly  preserved  within  him, 
but  when  he  thought  that  he  had  attained  his  object  after  the  vision  men- 
tioned above,  his  victory  led  merely  to  an  initiation  into  the  secrets  of  the 
spiritual  world,  which  has  certainly  conduced  to  the  edification  of  the  few 
members  of  the  Church  he  founded  and  of  the  far  more  numerous  followers 
of  spiritualism,  but  which  has  proved  absolutely  useless  to  science  and  to 
humanity  at  large,  and  which  besides  was  the  cause  of  the  really  splendid 
contributions  he  made  in  the  field  of  natural  research  being  considerably 
underestimated  for  a  long  time  afterwards.  It  has  been  left  to  our  own  time 


SEVENTEENTH     AND     EIGHTEENTH     CENTURIES       189 

to  do  him  justice  in  this  respect  and  to  give  him  the  place  due  to  him  in  the 
history  of  scientific  research. 

As  will  have  been  realized  from  the  above,  the  theoretical  speculations 
to  which  reference  has  been  made  here  led,  on  the  whole,  to  poor  results. 
The  general  theories  of  life  and  its  manifestations  which  were  formed  at  the 
period  under  discussion  received  a  decidedly  dogmatic  stamp  and  became  as 
numerous  as  those  who  formulated  them. 

On  those  lines,  therefore,  it  was  impossible  in  the  long  run  to  achieve 
any  satisfactory  results.  Simultaneously  with  these  efforts,  however,  there 
appeared  others  which  succeeded  bettet  in  satisfying  humanity's  craving  for 
knowledge,  and  which  during  the  immediately  succeeding  period  won  a 
very  large  number  of  adherents  —  those  works  which  comprised  a  systematic 
description  and  classification  of  living  creatures  on  earth.  To  these,  then,  we 
shall  now  proceed. 


CHAPTER    VI 

THE    DEVELOPMENT    OF    SYSTEMATIC    CLASSIFICATION 

BEFORE     LINN^US 

Primitive  systematic  categories  of  animals  and  plants 

AS  LONG  AS  man's  KNOWLEDGE  OF  NATURE  is  limited  to  what  he  can  ob- 
serve in  his  immediate  vicinity,  he  has  little  difficulty  in  controlling 
L  the  objects  of  his  knowledge,  but  when  his  range  of  vision  widens, 
there  arises  the  irresistible  need  for  combining  the  individual  objects  that 
have  been  observed  under  general  expressions,  which  serve  to  fix  the  knowl- 
edge of  them  and  to  impart  it  to  others,  "since  no  language  would  suffice  to 
denote  everything  individually,  and  since  in  a  language  which  did  so,  no 
understanding,  no  common  knowledge,  nor  retention  of  such  an  infinity  of 
terms  would  be  possible"  (F.  A.  Lange).  Those  categories  in  which  natural 
objects  are  thus  grouped  by  the  most  primitive  peoples,  out  of  sheer  practical 
necessity,  are  naturally  based  on  such  qualities  in  animals  and  plants  as  well 
as  the  inanimate  things  that  are  observed  as  are  easily  comprehended,  strik- 
ing to  the  eye,  and  of  special  importance  to  the  observers,  and  such  terms  are 
also  used  and  invented  even  today  among  civilized  peoples  by  all  those  who 
are  concerned  with  nature  in  a  purely  practical  way.  On  the  other  hand,  a 
grouping  of  natural  objects  based  on  scientific  principles  has  taken  a  long 
time  to  develop.  In  this  respect  the  ancient  Greek  natural  philosophy  was 
content  with  the  primitive  popular  nomenclature.  Practically  the  first  to 
devote  scientific  study  to  these  groupings  were,  as  far  as  we  know,  Plato 
and  Aristotle.  From  Plato  originates  grouping  in  species  and  genera  —  that 
is  to  say,  laterally  arranged  and  superordinated  terms  —  and  his  school  still 
further  extended  this  grouping  of  terms:  the  dichotomical  determination- 
tables  which  even  today  play  such  an  important  part  in  plant  and  animal 
systematization  originate  from  his  school.  But  the  further  this  grouping  of 
terms  went  on,  the  more  abstract  became  the  result;  the  higher  one  came  in 
the  series  of  terms  arranged  one  above  another,  the  further  away  has  one 
come  from  the  things  which  one  started  from.  This  is  a  fact  which  the 
biological  systematicians  have  not  always  realized;  the  practical  advantage 
of  systematic  categories  has  led  to  the  zoologist's  and  the  botanist's  for- 
getting how  artificial  their  system  has  really  become. 

System  of  Aristotle 
In  this  direction  Aristotle  did  not  go  beyond  what  Plato  had  initiated;  in  his 
biological  works  there  are,  as  is  well  known,  only  two  systematical  terms: 

190 


K 

O 

I— I 
a, 

< 


o 
u 


jtf^p^^'-- 


w 
Pi 
o 

o 

:^ 

o 

h-I 


2 

> 

o 

I— ( 

o 


SEVENTEENTH     AND    EIGHTEENTH     CENTURIES       191 

eidos  or  species,  and  gems,  the  family,  in  which  are  included  all  combinations 
of  forms  which  come  above  the  notion  of  species.  Nor  indeed  has  he  given  us 
any  really  worked-out  system;  the  animal  system  which  is  counted  for  his 
has  been  compiled  by  others  from  his  writings.  His  knowledge  of  forms  was 
also  so  slight  that  there  seems  to  have  been  no  difficulty  in  following  the 
simple  grouping  which  he  employed.  As  a  matter  of  fact,  during  the  centuries 
that  followed  there  was  no  need  for  a  more  detailed  classification;  the  ani- 
mals and  plants  which  became  known  in  late  antiquity  and  the  Middle  Ages 
were  not  so  numerous  that  they  could  not  be  covered  by  the  Aristotelean 
natural  philosophy.  It  was  not  until  the  great  geographical  discoveries  of 
the  sixteenth  and  seventeenth  centuries  introduced  the  knowledge  of  a  great 
number  of  new  life-forms  that  it  was  an  inevitable  necessity  to  widen  the 
biological  classification  if  the  material  collected  was  not  to  accumulate 
into  an  absolutely  intractable  mass. 

The  classification  of  plants  especially  demanded  revision  and  expansion. 
Actually  it  was  long  after  zoology  had  done  so  that  botany  attained  the 
rank  of  an  independent  science.  In  antiquity  and  the  Middle  Ages  botanical 
knowledge  was  essentially  supplementary  to  pharmacology.  Aristotle's 
botanical  writings  are,  except  for  a  few  fragments,  entirely  lost.  His  disciple 
Theophrastus'  great  work  on  plants  was  adopted  by  later  writers  as  a  model; 
in  it  he  thoroughly  discusses  the  difference  between  plants  and  animals, 
higher  plants  and  higher  animals  being  exclusively  compared  and  the  com- 
parison developing  into  abstract  and  fruitless  speculations.  The  old  primitive 
division  into  herbs,  bushes,  and  trees  is  the  only  one  to  be  found  here.  Be- 
sides Theophrastus'  work  there  was  during  classical  antiquity  a  purely 
pharmacological  account  of  plants  which  was  very  celebrated  and  which 
was  ascribed  to  a  philosopher  named  Dioscorides,  whose  character  and  period 
are  unknown  (he  probably  lived  at  the  beginning  of  the  Christian  era);  it 
was  on  Theophrastus  and  him  that  Pliny  based  the  account  of  plants  which 
is  included  in  his  great  Natural  History.  In  the  Middle  Ages  these  writings, 
which  were  believed  to  contain  all  the  plants  in  existence,  were  closely  stud- 
ied and  commented  upon;  attempts  to  find  the  plants  from  central  Europe 
in  these  works,  which  applied  only  to  the  Mediterranean  countries,  led  to 
the  most  absurd  speculations.  Only  some  few  Arabian  authors  ventured 
through  all  this  long  period  to  describe  new  plants.  It  was  not  until  the 
Renaissance  that  a  change  took  place  in  this  respect.  One  pioneer  in  this 
field  was  Otto  Brunfels,  born,  probably  in  1488,  in  south  Germany.  In  his 
youth  he  was  a  monk;  then  he  became  a  Lutheran  and  a  schoolmaster  at 
Mainz;  he  died  at  Berne  in  1534.  He  published  an  important  work  entitled 
Herbarum  viva  eicones,  which  inspired  Linnasus  to  call  him  the  father  of  bot- 
any. In  this  work,  which  was  illustrated  with  excellent  woodcuts,  Brunfels 
describes  all  the  plants  he  knows.  In  his  botanical  descriptions  he  still  partly 


I9i  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

takes  his  stand  by  the  old  point  of  view;  he  begins  each  description  with  a  list 
of  names  in  different  languages,  followed  by  an  account  of  what  ancient 
authors  have  said  of  the  plant  in  question;  finally  he  gives  his  own  "judg- 
ment" on  the  plant  and  ends  with  a  statement  as  to  its  "powers."  Compared 
with  Gesner's  exposition  of  the  individual  forms  of  animals  (Part  I,  p.  93), 
this  is  certainly  clumsy,  but  as  being  the  first  of  its  kind  the  work  at  any 
rate  deserves  respect.  There  is  no  system  in  it  whatever;  the  book  begins 
with  Plantago,  plantain,  "because  it  is  common  and  because  more  than  any 
other  plant  it  bears  witness  to  God's  omnipotence." 

Thus  it  was  at  all  events  the  medicinal  powers  of  plants  which  most  in- 
terested Brunfels,  and  the  same  is  true  of  his  numerous  successors  in  the  six- 
teenth century.  The  most  interesting  of  these  is  Leonard  Fuchs  (1501-66), 
who  after  working  at  humanistic  studies  under  Catholic  guidance  went  over 
to  Protestantism,  devoted  himself  to  medicine,  and  finally  became  professor 
at  Tubingen.  His  important  botanical  work  Historia  Stirpum,  profusely  and 
beautifully  illustrated,  was  published  in  1541.  Its  chief  interest  lies  in  the 
fact  that  he  gives  a  list  of  all  the  terms  he  uses:  an  enumeration  followed  by 
short  descriptions  of  the  names  of  the  different  parts  of  plants.  Curiously 
enough,  the  word  "flower"  is  entirely  absent.  His  description  of  individual 
plants,  as  compared  with  Brunfels's,  indicates  an  important  advance;  of 
every  plant  an  account  is  given  of  the  (i)  form,  (2.)  habitat,  (3)  season 
(when  it  should  be  collected),  (4)  "temperament,"  (5)  powers.  It  is  only 
under  the  last  heading  that  the  views  of  the  ancient  authorities  are  referred 
to.  Occasionally  also  the  author,  after  the  fashion  of  Aristotle,  differen- 
tiates to  some  extent  between  species  and  genus. 

Cesalpino's  -plant-system 
The  first  to  deal  with  botany  as  a  truly  independent  science,  however,  was 
Andrea  Cesalpino  (15 19-1603).  His  life  was  described  in  the  first  section 
(Part  I,  p.  113),  as  also  his  general  scientific  point  of  view  —  strict  Aristo- 
teleanism.  His  great  work  on  botany,  De  Plantis,  is  based  on  the  same  sys- 
tem. Not  only  the  fundamental  ideas,  but  even  the  actual  formal  treatment 
of  the  subject  is  entirely  on  the  Aristotelean  model:  exhaustive  comparative 
analysis  of  the  forms,  concisely  worded  theoretical  definitions,  and,  based 
on  these,  abstract  conclusions,  without  any  idea  of  such  practical  utility  as 
was  the  main  point  with  the  old  herbalists  of  the  type  of  Brunfels.  He  begins 
a  definition  of  the  difference  between  plants  and  animals  in  the  true  Aris- 
totelean style:  plants  feed,  grow,  and  produce  offspring,  but  lack  the  sensi- 
bility and  motion  of  animals  and  therefore  also  need  smaller  organs  than 
animals.  Then  follows  a  comparison  between  vegetable  and  animal  organs, 
which,  owing  to  its  abstract  one-sidedness,  leads  to  curious  results:  the 
alimental  organs  of  plants  are  the  roots;  thus  these  correspond  to  the  stomach 
and  intestinal  canal  in  animals.  Stalk  and  stem  produce  the  fruit;  thus  they 


SEVENTEENTH     AND     EIGHTEENTH     CENTURIES       1 93 

belong  to  the  reproductive  system.  The  plant  is  composed  of  several  layers: 
bark,  liber,  wood,  pith;  of  these  the  pith  is  the  innermost  and  thus  corre- 
sponds to  the  intestines  of  animals  and  is  physiologically  the  most  important. 
He  is  at  much  pains  to  discover  which  part  of  the  plant  corresponds  to  the 
heart  in  animals  —  we  have  previously  pointed  out  (Part  I,  p.  1 13)  the  great 
importance  which  Cesalpino  attaches  to  the  heart  as  the  centre  of  the  body 
and  of  life.  Finally,  the  plant's  centre  of  life  is  found  to  be  the  collar  of  the 
root  —  the  place  where  the  stem  and  the  root  system  join.  Thence  extend 
the  vessels  of  the  plant,  of  which  the  lacteal  vessels  especially  are  observed 
and  compared  with  the  veins  in  animals.  Propagation  by  means  of  cuttings 
shows,  however,  that  the  central  point  of  the  plant  is  not  as  absolute  as  that 
of  the  animal;  with  true  Aristotelean  terminology  it  is  maintained  that  this 
central  point  "actu"  (actually)  is  in  the  root-collar,  but  "potentia"  (po- 
tentially) can  be  everywhere.  Cesalpino,  moreover,  is  particularly  interested 
in  the  fruits  of  plants,  in  which  he  sees  the  equivalent  of  the  animal  embryo; 
the  function  of  the  leaves  is  to  protect  the  fruits,  and  the  flower-petals  are 
modified  foils  —  an  idea  which  was  later  adopted  by  Goethe.  But  Cesalpino 
does  not  admit  the  existence  of  sex  in  plants:  the  fruit  is  formed  from  buds 
and  these  again  are  produced  out  of  the  pith  and  the  liber;  the  pith,  which  is 
the  most  vital  part  of  the  plant,  provides  the  actual  ovule,  and  the  liber  gives 
rise  to  the  flower-leaf.  Different  kinds  of  fruits  are  carefully  analysed  and 
the  plants  are  classified  in  accordance  therewith,  though  the  traditional 
division  into  trees,  shrubs,  half-shrubs,  and  herbs  is  retained  as  the  main 
division.  These  four  categories  are  then  divided  in  their  turn,  according  to 
the  nature  of  the  fruit,  into  a  number  of  subdivisions.  Cesalpino,  however, 
like  Aristotle,  makes  no  summary  of  his  system,  not  even  in  the  form  of 
chapter  headings;  nor  is  there  any  special  systematic  nomenclature.  The 
mulberry-tree,  the  hazel-bush,  and  other  fruit-trees  are  thus  described  each 
by  itself;  nevertheless,  there  sometimes  occur  divisions  into  lower  categories 
than  those  named:  of  the  carrot.  Caucus,  for  instance,  three  forms  are  men- 
tioned, Creticus,  Montanus,  Campestris,  a  division  which  has  the  character 
of  a  determination  of  species,  or  rather  of  variety.  Nevertheless,  these  and 
other  categories  occurring  in  Cesalpino  are  not  sharply  defined;  he  was  un- 
doubtedly more  concerned  with  anatomical  and  physiological  than  with 
systematic  problems. 

Cesalpino's  system,  in  spite  of  its  deficiencies,  is  the  first  to  have  been 
really  based  on  the  comparative  study  of  forms;  in  this  connexion  Linnasus, 
who  made  a  summary  of  it,  expresses  the  opinion  that  Cesalpino  is  the  first 
to  lay  down  a  definite  basis  for  plant  classification.  In  later  times,  however, 
this  basis  has  been  regarded  as  artificial,  since  it  rests  merely  upon  the  con- 
sideration of  one  single  organ,  and  in  contrast  thereto  have  been  adduced 
contributions  to  a  natural  system  of  classification  made  by  certain  of  the  old. 


194  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

and  otherwise  not  particularly  systematic,  herbalists.  Independently  of 
Cesalpino,  plant  classification  was  actually  developed  in  a  new  direction 
through  Caspar  Bauhin.  He  was  born  at  Basel  in  1550  and  studied  medicine 
and  botany,  as  did  also  an  elder  brother,  under  the  above-mentioned  Fuchs 
at  Tubingen.  He  afterwards  worked  for  a  number  of  years  as  a  professor  in 
Basel,  until  his  death,  in  1614.  His  chief  botanical  works,  Prodromus  and 
Pinax  theatri  botanici,  constitute  the  first  attempts  at  a  critical  compilation 
of  all  the  then  known  scientific  names  and  descriptions  of  plants. 

Bauhin  s  system 
Bauhin  is  entirely  independent  of  Cesalpino;  he  bases  his  principles  on  his 
master  Fuchs  and  those  like  him,  the  semi-medical  herbalists  of  the  sixteenth 
century.  But  he  differs  from  the  latter  in  his  keen  eye  for  the  natural  affinity 
of  plants;  he  groups  together  such  plants  as  resemble  one  another  generally 
in  their  external  form  and  discusses  them  in  order,  starting  with  those  he 
considers  the  most  primitive:  the  Graminaceas,  then  the  Liliaceas,  the 
Zingiberaceas,  after  which  the  dicotyledons,  and  finally  shrubs  and  trees. 
These  groups  are,  however,  neither  characterized  nor  given  names.  Only  the 
individual  plants  are  described,  which  are  combined  under  one  genus-name, 
after  which  they  are  characterized  in  respect  of  all  the  forms  that  belong  to 
each  one  of  those  names.  These  diagnoses  are  brief  and  concise  and  are  ac- 
companied by  short  accounts  of  earlier  authors'  statements  on  each  plant. 
On  the  other  hand,  the  actual  genus-names  are  not  in  any  way  characterized, 
any  more  than  the  larger  groups  mentioned  above;  there  is  therefore  no  justi- 
fication for  the  assertion  that  is  sometimes  made  that  Bauhin  clearly  grasped 
the  contrast  between  genus  and  species.  With  greater  reason  he  has  been 
called  the  originator  of  natural  plant  classification  based  on  the  common 
likeness  between  the  plant  forms,  as  opposed  to  the  artificial  systematization 
founded  by  Cesalpino,  which  is  based  on  an  individual  organic  system  — 
a  contrast  that  has  proved  of  great  significance  in  botany,  whereas  in  zoology 
it  has  not  been  of  such  consequence.  And  above  all  as  a  critic  of  earlier  botani- 
cal literature  Bauhin  carried  out  a  work  of  lasting  value. 

Joachim  Jung,  generally  called  Jungius,  holds  a  peculiar  position 
amongst  the  botanists  of  the  seventeenth  century.  Born  at  Liibeck  in  1587, 
he  became,  while  still  young,  professor  in  mathematics  at  Giessen,  but  soon 
relinquished  his  appointment,  and  thereafter,  for  more  than  ten  years,  he 
lived  a  somewhat  restless  life,  until  in  162.8  he  became  rector  of  a  gymnasium 
in  Hamburg.  He  displayed  extraordinarily  keen  and  many-sided  activity 
both  as  a  scientist  and  as  a  tutor,  but  eventually  he  came  to  work  in  rather 
difficult  circumstances,  partly  owing  to  quarrels  with  the  Hamburg  priests, 
who  accused  him  of  heresy.'  For  these  and  other  reasons  most  of  what  he 

'  In  the  course  of  his  education  in  Greek,  Jung  had  studied,  besides  the  New  Testament, 
profane  classical  authorsi  when  challenged  on  this  point,  he  defended  himself  by  saying  that 


SEVENTEENTH  AND  EIGHTEENTH  CENTURIES  195 
wrote  remained  unprinted  and  was  partially  dispersed  after  his  death  (in 
1657).  Some  few  treatises  were  published  by  his  pupils,  among  them  one 
entitled  Isagoge  pbytoscopica  (^Handbook  of  Botanical  Study).  This  work,  com- 
prising a  volume  of  forty-six  quarto  pages,  must  be  regarded  as  one  of  the 
pioneer  works  in  botany.  It  gives  a  concentrated  account  of  the  theory  of 
botany,  under  the  obvious  influence  of  Cesalpino's,  but  without  the  latter's 
profitless  Aristotelean  speculations;  to  begin  with,  the  plant  is  characterized 
as  such,  after  which  an  account  is  given  of  the  various  organs,  each  of  which 
is  briefly  diagnosed  in  a  manner  that  is  striking,  though  abstract.  "A  leaf 
is  that  which  stretches  out  from  its  place  of  attachment  in  height  and  length 
so  that  the  surfaces  of  the  third  dimension  are  dissimilar  to  one  another;  it 
is  the  leaf's  inner  surface  that  is  differentiated  from  the  outside."  —  The 
whole  exposition,  with  its  concise,  vigorous  sentences  and  its  analyses  of 
different  parts  of  the  plant  drawn  up  in  tabular  form,  is  more  reminiscent 
of  Linn^eus's  work  than  that  of  any  other  of  the  early  botanists.  Linnsus, 
in  fact,  mentions  Jung  as  his  precursor  as  far  as  the  drawing  up  of  rules  for 
the  description  of  flowers  is  concerned  and  actually  took  up  the  characteristic 
description  of  plant-organs  at  the  point  where  Jung  had  finished  and  certainly 
brought  it  up  to  a  far  higher  standard. 

One  who  in  his  time  was  of  considerable  importance  as  a  classifier  of 
plants  was  Augustus  Quirinus  Rivinus  (i65Z-i7i3).  Born  in  Leipzig  of  a 
family  of  scholars,  which  really  bore  the  name  of  Bachmann,  he  studied 
medicine  in  his  native  town,  ultimately  becoming  a  professor  there.  He  was 
a  many-sided  scholar,  working  in  widely  differing  spheres;  his  chief  fame, 
however,  rests  on  his  great  botanical  work  Ordo  flantarujn,  which  he  pub- 
lished in  two  large  folio  volumes,  illustrated  with  fine  copper  engravings, 
entirely  at  his  own  expense.  He  was  the  first  to  insist  that  the  old  division 
into  trees,  bushes,  and  herbs  should  be  done  away  with;  in  its  place  he  would 
classify  plants  exclusively  according  to  their  corolla,  and  he  thus  created  an 
artificial  system,  which,  however,  was  not  very  practical.  He  likewise  urged 
the  adoption  of  a  simplified  nomenclature  for  the  plants  themselves,  but 
in  this,  too,  his  criticism  of  the  old  system  was  more  successful  than  his 
attempts  at  reform. 

A  far  greater  service  to  classification  was  rendered  by  Joseph  Pitton  de 
TouRNEFORT,  at  just  about  the  same  time.  He  was  born  at  Aix  in  the  south 
of  France  in  1656  and  was  destined  by  his  father  for  the  priesthood  —  much 
against  his  will.  When  his  father  died,  therefore,  he  gave  up  theology  and 

the  latter  wrote  purer  Greek  than  that  of  the  New  Testament,  whereupon  the  priests  in  Hamburg 
and  theologians  at  Wittenberg  accused  him  of  blasphemy,  because  he  had  reproached  the  Holy 
Spirit,  which  had  inspired  the  words  of  the  Bible,  with  a  deficient  knowledge  of  languages. 
Jung  had  to  abridge  his  school  education,  but,  thanks  probably  to  his  high  reputation,  escaped 
the  sentence  of  excommunication  with  which  he  was  threatened. 


1 96  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

applied  himself  to  botany,  which  had  always  interested  him.  In  order  to  be 
able  to  earn  his  living  he  started  by  taking  the  degree  of  doctor  of  medicine. 
His  botanical  works  soon  gained  him  a  wide  reputation;  he  was  appointed 
professor  at  the  Jardin  des  Plantes  in  Paris  and  had  an  opportunity  of  making 
many  long  journeys  for  research  purposes.  He  died  in  1708  as  the  result  of  an 
accident. 

In  the  introduction  to  the  important  botanical  work  in  which  he  sum- 
marized the  results  of  his  research  activities  he  expounds  his  principles  of 
plant  classification.  He  defines  the  plant  as  an  organic  body,  which  always 
possesses  roots,  practically  always  seeds,  and  nearly  always  stalk,  leaves, 
and  flowers.  He  bases  his  ideas  of  the  structure  of  plants  on  Cesalpino  and 
Malpighi.  When  later  it  comes  to  classifying  and  giving  characters  to  plants, 
he  maintains,  under  the  manifest  influence  of  Cesalpino,  that  only  the  flowers 
and  fruits  can  come  into  question;  he  seeks  far  and  wide  for  proofs  as  to  why 
root,  stalk,  and  leaf  do  not  provide  reliable  characters.  In  particular,  the 
plant  genera  should  be  based  on  similarities  in  the  structure  of  the  flowers 
and  fruits,  but  as  the  same  genus  includes  forms  whose  remaining  parts  are 
different,  so  the  genera  must  in  their  turn  be  divided  into  sub-categories. 
Tournefort  pays  great  attention  to  his  description  of  the  genera,  and  his 
diagnoses  of  them  are  often  so  striking  that  subsequent  systematicians,  up 
to  our  own  time,  have  been  able  to  accept  them,  though  they  are  only  based 
on  the  characteristics  of  flower  and  fruit;  on  the  other  hand,  the  "species" 
into  which  the  genera  are  divided  are  mentioned  with  only  a  few  words 
regarding  the  form  of  the  stalk  and  the  leaf,  without  any  further  description. 
His  method  of  procedure  is  thus  the  exact  opposite  of  Bauhin's.  But  over  and 
above  this,  Tournefort  works  out  for  the  first  time  a  systematic  classification 
of  categories  higher  than  the  genera  —  that  is  to  say,  he  divides  the  plants 
into  a  number  of  classes,  which  again  are  severally  divided  into  sections; 
each  of  these  is  characterized  in  a  few  words,  but  is  not  given  a  name.  The 
characters  of  these  higher  categories  are  derived  from  the  peculiarities  of  the 
flower;  several  categories  of  flowers  which  still  to  some  extent  hold  good 
today  are  determined  by  him:  with  and  without  corolla,  with  or  without  a 
gamopetalous  corolla,  and,  again,  cruciform,  Ungulate,  and  other  flower- 
forms.  The  division  into  herbs,  bushes,  and  trees  abolished  by  Rivinus  he 
himself,  however,  was  never  able  entirely  to  reject;  his  system  comprises 
seventeen  classes  of  herbs  and  five  classes  of  bushes  and  trees.  With  regard 
to  anatomy  and  physiology  Tournefort  has  not  much  to  ofi'er  that  is  new;  in 
the  course  of  his  journeys  he  had  observed  the  artificial  fertilization  of  date- 
palms  practised  in  very  remote  periods  and  already  described  by  Theophras- 
tus.  They  are,  as  is  well  known,  both  male  and  female,  and  the  cultivators 
facilitate  fertilization  by  suspending  male  clusters  over  the  females,  but 
Tournefort  is  unable  to  derive  any  theoretical  conclusions  of  importance 


SEVENTEENTH     aND     EIGHTEENTH     CENTURIES       1 97 

from  the  fact.  It  was  left  to  another  scientist,  Camerarius,  to  prove  the  sexu- 
ality of  plants. 

Sexuality  of  plants 
It  was  known  of  old  that  in  certain  plants  the  individuals  are  of  two  differ- 
ent kinds,  both  of  which  must  concur  before  any  reproduction  by  means  of 
fertilization  can  take  place.  The  classical  example  of  this,  known  to  all  the 
natural  philosophers  of  antiquity,  is,  as  mentioned  above,  the  date-palm, 
the  fruitful  specimens  of  which  have  been  quite  correctly  called,  by  the 
peoples  who  cultivate  them,  females,  while  those  that  are  required  for 
fertilization  have  been  called  males.  But  other  plants  of  the  same  kind  have 
also  been  known  since  ancient  times,  though  many  plants  that  resembled  one 
another,  but  were  differentiated  by  varying  size  and  development  were  taken 
for  females  and  males.  A  well-known  instance  of  this  was  that  of  the  two 
ferns  Filix  mas  and  Filix  femina,  which  are  still  retained  as  names  of  species 
in  two  different  fern-genera.  But  these  ideas  mostly  belong  to  popular  belief; 
scientists,  both  those  of  the  classical  period  and,  on  their  authority,  those 
of  the  sixteenth  and  seventeenth  centuries,  denied,  or  at  any  rate  overlooked, 
the  existence  of  sexuality  in  plants,  owing  mostly  to  the  fact  that  the  great 
majority  of  plants  are  hermaphrodites.  When  no  difference  can  be  found  in 
the  male  and  female  specimen,  what  is  the  use  of  assuming  sexual  reproduc- 
tion? Grew  was  the  first  to  believe  that  plants  reproduce  themselves  sex- 
ually, "like  snails"  (these  are,  of  course,  also  hermaphrodites).  His  opinion 
in  this  case,  however,  was  based  mostly  upon  theoretical  speculation,  and, 
as  a  rule,  such  speculations  are,  of  course,  less  convincing  than  direct  obser- 
vation. The  scientist  who  proved  the  sexuality  of  plants  as  the  result  of 
convincing  experiments  was  Rudolph  Jacob  Camerarius  (1665-17^1).  He 
belonged  to  an  old  scholarly  family,  known  since  the  Renaissance  period, 
which  had  originally  been  called  Cammerer,  and  he  worked  throughout  his 
life  at  Tubingen,  where  he  was  for  many  years  professor  of  medicine.  He 
generally  recorded  the  results  of  his  work  in  small  articles,  frequently  writ- 
ten, according  to  the  custom  of  the  period,  in  the  form  of  letters  to  other 
scholars.  The  essay  which  alone  justifies  the  mention  of  his  name  in  a  history 
of  biology  is  a  "Letter  on  the  Sex  of  Plants,"  dated  1694.  In  this  article  he 
gives  an  exhaustive  account  of  all  the  ancient  authorities'  ideas  of  the  re- 
production of  plants  and  of  the  parts  of  flowers;  he  himself  arrives  at  the 
conclusion  that  the  pollen  is  the  male,  and  the  ovary  is  the  female,  element 
and  discusses  in  connexion  therewith  a  number  of  theories  on  sexuality  and 
fertilization  in  general,  without,  however,  contributing  anything  of  special 
value  from  a  theoretical  point  of  view.  Of  all  the  greater  significance  are 
the  experiments  by  which  he  proves  his  theory  of  the  sexual  properties  of 
plants.  He  cultivated  for  this  purpose  a  fairly  large  number  of  both  monoe- 
cious and  dioecious  plants  and  found  that  i^  the  male  flowers  are  picked  off 


198  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

in  time,  there  will  be  no  fruit,  while  fruit  will  certainly  develop  if  the  pistils 
of  the  female  flowers  are  provided  with  pollen.  These  proofs  had  undoubtedly 
a  convincing  effect,  if  not  on  all  his  contemporaries,  at  any  rate  on  succeeding 
ages.  Linnasus  in  particular  has  acknowledged  the  contribution  he  made  to 
the  development  of  plant  physiology. 

Animal  system  neglected 
While,  then,  during  the  first  two  centuries  of  the  new  era  plant  classification 
was  splendidly  reorganized,  during  the  same  period  animal  classification  on 
the  whole  made  no  progress.  The  zoography  of  the  Renaissance  period  has 
already  been  described  (Part  I,  pp. 31-8);  it  was,  generally  speaking,  not  very 
systematic;  in  the  best  event  one  adhered  to  Aristotle,  and  in  the  latter's 
Historia  animalium  zoology  had,  in  fact,  an  old  and  sound  foundation,  which 
contemporary  botany  lacked  —  a  careful  comparison,  based  on  unique  pow- 
ers of  observation  and  sense  of  form,  between  the  individual  animal  forms, 
the  value  of  which  is  manifest  from  the  fact  that  most  of  the  groups  into 
which  animals  are  there  divided  still  hold  good  in  the  present  system  of 
classification.  Particularly  in  regard  to  vertebrate  animals,  which  have  for 
obvious  reasons  been  of  primary  interest  to  humanity,  Aristotle  had,  as  has 
already  been  pointed  out,  a  keen  eye  for  the  natural  affinity  between  the 
different  forms,  which  is  based  upon  agreement  in  the  general  structure  and 
functions  of  the  body.  Thus  there  was  opened  up  to  animal  biology  during 
this  period  an  important  and  fruitful  field  for  research  in  the  anatomical 
and  physiological  sphere-,  and  this,  again,  caused  the  comparison  between 
the  life-forms  in  the  animal  kingdom  to  receive  a  different  character  from 
that  between  the  life-forms  in  the  vegetable  kingdom;  in  the  former  a  com- 
parison between  internal  organs,  the  complex  structure  of  which  it  was  pos- 
sible to  make  out  only  after  exhaustive  investigations;  in  the  latter,  a  study 
for  the  most  part  of  problems  of  the  purely  external  form.  In  zoology,  too, 
however,  it  was  absolutely  necessary  to  develop  form  classification,  mainly 
owing  to  the  fact  that  the  different  categories  into  which  the  known  animal 
world  is  divided  required  a  more  definite  determination  than  that  given  it 
by  Aristotle  and  his  successors.  And  this  undoubtedly  demanded  co-opera- 
tion between  zoology  and  botany  in  order  to  find  a  common  ground  of  com- 
parison and  valuation  for  all  the  forms  in  which  life  on  earth  manifests 
itself.  The  very  first  to  make  an  attempt  to  deal  with  vegetable  and  animal 
classification  on  similar  principles  was  Ray;  the  scientist  who  finally  worked 
out  a  uniform  system  for  all  living  creatures  was  Linn^us. 

John  Ray  was  born  in  16x7  or  i6x8  at  Black  Notley,  a  village  near  Brain- 
tree,  in  Essex.  His  father  was  a  well-to-do  blacksmith  who  could  afford  to 
send  his  eldest  son  to  college.  In  1644  young  Ray  went  up  to  Cambridge 
and  at  first  studied  the  classical  languages  and  theology;  but  he  was  also 
interested  in  mathematics  and  natural  science.  He  gave  lectures  to  the  under- 


SEVENTEENTH  AND  EIGHTEENTH  CENTURIES  199 
graduates  on  Greek  and  mathematics  alternately,  and  was  eventually  or- 
dained, after  which  he  held  many  college  offices.  His  university  period  was 
not  to  last  long,  however;  the  reactionary  Government  of  Charles  II  required 
the  English  clergy  to  subscribe  to  an  Act  of  Uniformity  drawn  up  with  a 
view  to  suppressing  liberty  of  conscience;  and  Ray  was  one  of  those  who 
preferred  to  give  up  office  rather  than  to  submit.  It  thus  came  about  that, 
like  so  many  of  England's  best  scientists,  he  had  to  spend  the  greater  part  of 
his  life  following  the  profession  of  a  private  scholar.  This  Ray  was  enabled  to 
do  thanks  to  his  connexion  with  Francis  Willughby,  a  very  wealthy  young 
man  of  noble  family,  who,  eight  years  younger  than  Ray,  had  been  a  pupil 
of  his  at  Cambridge  and  was  his  constant  companion  throughout  his  life, 
their  friendship  being  based  on  a  common  interest  in  natural  science.  After 
Ray's  resignation  the  two  friends  went  for  a  several  years'  tour  through 
Europe,  during  the  course  of  which  Ray  applied  himself  especially  to  botany, 
Willughby  to  zoology.  Having  returned  home  laden  with  collections,  they 
settled  down  in  Willughby's  country-house  in  order  to  work  up  the  material 
they  had  collected.  In  1672.,  however,  Willughby's  death  abruptly  terminated 
their  collaboration;  by  his  will  he  appointed  Ray  one  of  his  executors  and 
left  him  sixty  pounds  a  year  for  life,  with  the  charge  of  educating  his  two 
sons,  for  which  purpose  Ray  remained  for  some  years  in  his  friend's  family. 
Having  married,  he  finally  settled  down  in  his  parents'  cottage,  which  he 
had  inherited,  and  there  for  several  decades  he  continued  his  researches, 
universally  respected  in  scientific  circles  in  England  and  contented  with  his 
lot  in  spite  of  his  modest  circumstances.  He  died  in  1705,  three  daughters 
surviving  him. 

Kay's  Methodus  plantarum 
Ray's  literary  work  was  extensive  and  many-sided  —  sermons  and  religious 
essays,  handbooks  on  the  classics,  treatises  on  folk-lore,  and,  finally,  the 
works  on  natural  science  on  which  his  fame  entirely  rests.  The  greatest  of 
these,  in  both  volume  and  importance,  is  his  Historia  plantarum  generalis, 
a  work  of  i, 860  closely  printed  folio  pages,  in  which  he  summarized  the  entire 
botanical  knowledge  of  his  time.  At  an  earlier  date  he  published  a  resume  of 
the  system  in  which  he  arranged  the  plants  in  his  Historia,  under  the  title 
of  Methodus  plantarum.  This  great  history,  which  contains  a  systematic  de- 
scription of  all  the  then  known  plants,  starts  with  a  general  survey  of  the 
nature  and  conditions  of  plants.  He  quotes  Aristotle's  principle  as  to  the 
division  of  the  organs  into  simple  and  complex,  similar  and  dissimilar.  As 
regards  the  various  parts  of  the  plants  he  bases  his  system  on  Jung's  defini- 
tions and  terminology,  which  are  regularly  quoted,  but  are  in  each  individual 
case  considerably  extended  and  thoroughly  investigated.  He  cites  the  plant 
classification  which  Cesalpino  originated,  according  to  fruits  and  seeds,  but 
he  points  out  that  the  form  of  leaves  and  other  parts  must  also  be  taken  into 


XOO  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

account,  so  that  plants  which  resemble  one  another  are  grouped  together 
although  the  seeds  are  different.  Above  all,  he  reminds  us  that  nature  never 
makes  any  jumps;  on  the  contrary,  the  extremes  are  connected  by  middle 
forms,  just  as  the  zoophytes  come  between  the  vegetable  and  animal  king- 
doms. In  regard  to  the  anatomy  of  plants,  in  all  essentials  Ray  follows  Mal- 
pighi;  Grew's  ideas  on  the  sexuality  of  plants  are  also  accepted,  without, 
however,  being  further  developed;  Ray  was  ignorant  of  Camerarius's  obser- 
vations. On  the  other  hand,  he  describes  the  germination  of  plants,  making 
original  observations  of  considerable  value;  the  difference  between  plants 
with  one  and  those  with  two  cotyledons  was  established  by  him.   Ray 
discussed  the  notion  of  species  more  thoroughly  than  any  previous  biolo- 
gist. In  his  view,  plants  belong  to  the  same  species  if  they  give  rise  through 
their  seed  to  a  new  plant  similar  to  themselves,  in  the  same  way  as  bulls 
and  cows  are  the  same  species  because  in  mating  they  produce  creatures 
which  resemble  themselves.  The  number  of  species  is  invariable,  for  God 
rested  on  the   seventh  day  from   all  his   work  —  that   is,    from  creating 
new  species.  On  the  other  hand,  the  different-coloured  flowers  in  plants 
should  not  be  regarded  as  separate  species,  any  more  than  the  different- 
coloured  calves  born  of  cows;  in  the  former  this  is  proved  by  the  fact  that 
the  colour  variations  are  not  reproduced  through  seed,  but  only  through 
cuttings.  The  invariability  of  species  is,  however,  not  absolute;  plant  species 
can  be  varied  through  the  "degeneration"  of  the  seeds  —  thus  it  has  cer- 
tainly occurred  that  the  seed  of  the  cauliflower  has  produced  leaf-cabbage 
and  that  from  the  seed  of  frimula  veris  t?iajor  has  arisen  primula  fratensis  in- 
odora.  Ray  even  includes  in  the  discussion  a  number  of  ancient  stories  as  to 
grain's  having  degenerated  into  weed:  wheat  to  Lolium  and  maize  to  other 
kinds  of  weed.  True,  he  doubts  the  truth  of  a  number  of  these  statements, 
but  he  nevertheless  believes  the  thing  to  be  possible.  This  belief  of  his  in 
the  variability  of  species  has  been  cited  as  proof  of  an  unprejudiced  view,  in 
contrast  to  the  theory  that  arose  later  as  to  the  absolute  constancy  of  species. 
The  examples  quoted  rather  go  to  show  clearly  enough  that  Ray  was  unable 
to  rid  himself  of  a  certain  amount  of  primitive  superstition. 

As  far  as  actual  classification  was  concerned,  Ray  retained  the  division 
into  herbs  and  trees,  or,  more  correctly,  herbaceous  plants  and  ligneous 
plants,  maintaining  that  the  latter  are  differentiated  from  the  former  by  the 
existence  of  winter  buds  —  in  actual  fact,  an  incorrect  assumption.  In  a  later 
edition  of  his  Methodus,  however,  influenced  by  Rivinus,  he  abandoned  this 
division.  Herbs  are  then  divided  into:  tm-perfecta  (fungi,  alga;,  lichens,  and 
corals)  and  perfect  a  (plants  bearing  flowers,  which  are  again  divided  intu 
those  having  tw^o  and  those  having  one  cotyledon).  The  sub-groups  under 
these  categories  are  numerous,  some  natural  and  well  characterized,  others 
composed  of  all  sorts  of  plants,  massed  together  owing  to  some  purely  ac- 


SEVENTEENTH  AND  EIGHTEENTH  CENTURIES  2.0I 
cidental  character.  Trees  are  also  divided  according  to  the  number  of  cotyle- 
dons, and  then  again  into  sub-groups.  The  actual  genera  are  mentioned  by 
one  name  and  are  described  with  a  short  diagnosis;  the  species  into  which 
they  are  divided  are  characterized  in  a  few  words,  followed  by  a  more  de- 
tailed description.  Ray  was  thus  the  first  to  describe  both  genus  and  species 
at  the  same  time. 

Ray's  zoological  system 
As  a  zoologist  Ray  left  no  comprehensive  work  corresponding  to  the  bo- 
tanical work  above  mentioned.  During  his  period  of  coUabc ration  with 
Willughby  the  latter  took  over  the  zoological  side,  and  after  his  premature 
death  Ray  published  in  his  name  a  couple  of  works  on  birds  and  fishes;  how 
much  in  th  .se  works  originated  from  the  one  or  from  the  other  of  the  two 
friends  it  is  not  easy  to  decide.  In  his  own  name,  on  the  other  hand,  Ray 
promulgated  two  zoological  works:  a  survey  of  the  quadrupeds  and  reptiles, 
and  a  work  on  insects.  The  former  of  these,  a  small  cctavo  vclume,  is  his 
most  important  contribution  to  the  knowledge  of  the  animal  kingdom.  He 
begins  with  some  general  reflections  on  the  characteristics  of  animals;  he 
defines  the  animal  as  a  body  having  life  and  powers  of  perception  and  of 
independent  motion,  and  he  then  discusses  Descartes's  assertion  that  animals 
lack  sensibility,  the  incorrectness  of  which  is  proved.  As  regards  the  repro- 
duction of  animals,  he  denies  spontaneous  generation  and  then  deals  with 
the  theories  of  epigenesis  and  preformation,  ovism  and  animalculism,  with- 
out making  any  very  important  contributions  in  that  connexion.  The  theory 
of  fabulous  creatures,  which  had  always  up  to  then  been  included  on  the 
authority  of  classical  authors,  is  examined  and  entirely  exploded.  In  regard 
to  systematic  classification,  which  comprises  the  greater  part  of  the  work, 
Ray  follows  Aristotle  in  essentials,  and  this  for  good  reasons,  since  the  lat- 
ter's  division  of  the  quadrupeds  is  on  the  w^hole  both  natural  and  well 
founded.  Ray,  however,  did  not  venture  to  follow  up  the  consequences  of 
the  comparative  anatomical  method  which  Aristotle  founded;  like  the  latter 
he  refers  whales  to  the  fishes,  although  he  is  quite  well  aware  of  their  closer 
anatomical  affinity  with  the  mammals.  On  the  other  hand,  in  certain  respects 
Ray  goes  deeper  into  the  characteristics  of  the  individual  animal  groups 
which  he  adopted;  above  all,  he  takes  account  of  the  structure  of  the  circula- 
tory organs  and  on  this  basis  divides  animals  first  of  all  into  sanguiferous 
and  bloodless  —  he  quite  realized  that  the  last-mentioned  group  possesses 
blood  of  a  kind,  though  colourless,  but  he  prefers  to  retain  the  Aristotelean 
nomenclature.  The  sanguiferous  animals  are  divided  into  those  that  breathe 
wit'i  lungs  and  those  that  breathe  with  gills;  those  provided  with  lungs  are 
again  divided  into  animals  having  two  heart- ventricles  and  animals  with  only 
one  To  the  last  belong  oviparous  quadrupeds  and  reptiles;  the  first  is  divided 
into  oviparous  (birds)  and  viviparous  (partly  land  animals  —  mammals  — 


2.0-L  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

partly  aquatic  animals  —  whales).  Land  animals  are  also  characterized  by 
their  hairy  covering,  as  the  result  of  which  the  manatee,  which  lives  in  the 
water,  can  be  included  among  them.  The  bloodless  animals  are  divided  into 
small  (the  insects)  and  large  (molluscs,  crayfish,  crustaceans).  In  examining 
this  system  we  may  pass  over  the  ' '  bloodless ' '  animals,  of  which  Ray  himself 
only  studied  the  insects;  aquatic  animals  were,  on  the  whole,  of  no  interest 
to  him,  and  as,  moreover,  Willughby  had  devoted  himself  to  birds  and  fishes, 
there  remained  only  the  quadrupeds,  which,  as  mentioned  above,  formed 
the  subject  of  his  principal  zoological  work.  The  hairy  quadrupeds  are  di- 
vided into  Ungulata  or  hoofed  animals,  and  Unguiculata  or  clawed  animals. 
Among  the  former  are  reckoned  one-hoofed  (equine),  pair-hoofed  (Rumi- 
nantia  and  swine),  and  multi-hoofed  (rhinoceros  and  hippopotamus). 
Amongst  the  Unguiculata  are  included  pair-clawed  (the  camel)  and  multi- 
clawed;  (i)  with  claws  grown  together  (the  elephant);  (x)  with  separate 
claws,  of  which  there  are:  flat  claws  (apes)  and  narrow  claws  (carnivorous 
animals  and  Rodentia).  Moreover,  a  number  of  mammals  are  classified  as 
"anomalous" — namely,  the  hedgehog,  the  molcj  the  shrew-mouse,  the 
armadillo,  the  sloth,  and  the  bat.  The  oviparous  quadrupeds  are  finally 
divided  into  frogs  (including  tortoises),  lizards,  and  snakes.  In  this  system 
each  genus  is  then  characterized  with  a  diagnosis  —  for  instance,  the  genus 
Ovis,  the  genus  Martes  —  and  the  species  of  the  genera  are  likewise  given 
each  a  separate  diagnosis.  On  the  other  hand,  the  genera  of  frogs,  lizards, 
and  snakes  are  not  diagnosed,  only  a  common  characteristic  being  named, 
followed  by  diagnosis  of  the  species. 

To  measure  Ray's  work  as  a  systematician  by  modern  standards  would 
naturally  be  entirely  unhistorical,  but  his  system  can  by  no  means  bear  com- 
parison even  with  that  of  Linnasus.  And  yet  for  his  age  it  constitutes  an 
extraordinary  advance,  primarily  in  that  he  clearly  realized  the  difference 
between  species  and  genus,  secondly  on  account  of  his  possessing  what  was 
undeniably  —  in  comparison  with  his  predecessors  —  an  extremely  keen  eye 
for  the  similarities  on  which  the  assumption  of  affinity  in  its  wider  sense 
may  be  based;  several  of  his  larger  groups,  both  in  the  vegetable  and  in  the 
animal  kingdom,  are  "natural"  in  the  best  sense  of  the  word.  In  the  sphere 
of  botany,  also,  the  difference  discovered  by  him  between  mono-  and  dicoty- 
ledons is  of  essential  importance.  On  the  other  hand,  several  of  the  sub- 
divisions which  he  formed  are  highly  artificial,  as  will  be  clearly  seen  from 
a  glance  at  his  division  of  mammals,  according  to  claws  and  nails.  And  in 
any  case  he  established  no  common  systematic  categories  to  cover  all  living 
creatures.  The  one  who  by  doing  so  paved  the  way  for  a  completely  uniform 
conception  of  life-form  on  this  earth  was  Linnasus,  the  founder  of  modern 
plant  and  animal  classification. 


CHAPTER    VII 


LINN^US     AND     HIS     PUPILS 


Linnaus's  life  and  ivork 

NILS  Ingemarsson  was  a  peasant  lad  from  Sunnerbo,  in  the  province 
of  Smaland  in  Sweden,  who  was  destined  for  the  priesthood.  When  at 
school,  not  having  previously  had  any  family  name,  as  was  the  case 
with  the  country  people  in  general  in  Sweden,  he  adopted  the  name  of  Lin- 
nasus,  after  a  mighty  linden-tree  growing  near  his  home,  which  was  regarded 
by  the  country  folk  as  a  sort  of  sacred  tree.  After  a  long  period  of  study  at 
Lund  University  —  frequently  interrupted,  owing  to  his  poverty  —  he  was 
ordained  priest  in  1704  at  the  age  of  thirty,  and  two  years  later  he  was  ap- 
pointed curate  at  Rashult.  At  the  same  time  he  married  Christina  Brodersonia, 
daughter  of  the  Vicar  of  Stenbrohult.  Some  years  later  he  succeeded  his  father- 
in-law  as  vicar  of  that  place.  While  following  his  vocation  he  also  devoted 
himself  with  keen  enthusiasm  to  horticulture  and  the  study  of  herbs;  in  his 
large  garden  grew  many  a  herb  that  was  not  to  be  found  in  his  neighbours' 
gardens  and  with  the  peculiar  properties  of  which  he  was  well  acquainted. 
The  eldest  of  his  large  family  was  a  son,  Carl,  born  on  the  2.3rd  May  1707. 
Even  in  his  earliest  childhood  Carl  displayed  the  same  keen  interest  in  botany 
that  his  father  had  done;  his  greatest  joy  was  to  work  in  the  small  garden 
he  had  had  laid  out  and  there  to  cultivate  as  many  remarkable  plants  as 
possible.  At  his  school,  at  Vaxio,  however,  he  was,  as  he  himself  relates, 
far  from  happy;  "crude  schoolmasters  in  a  crude  manner  gave  the  children 
a  mind  for  sciences  enough  to  make  their  hair  stand  on  end."  In  humanistics, 
which  at  that  time  were  the  most  important,  he  likewise  made  but  little 
progress,  but  he  was  all  the  more  successful  in  the  physical-mathematical 
subjects.  His  teacher  in  physics,  Rothman,  quickly  recognizing  his  great  gift 
for  natural  science,  gave  him  Boerhaave's  and  Tournefort's  works  to  read 
and  urged  Carl's  family  to  accept  his  plan  to  devote  himself  to  medicine 
instead  of  studying  for  the  priesthood.  In  172.7  he  became  an  undergraduate 
at  Lund,  where  he  found  a  paternal  friend  in  Stobasus,  professor  of  medicine. 
On  the  advice  of  Rothman,  however,  he  removed  for  the  next  academical 
year  to  Upsala,  where  the  medical  teaching  was  considered  to  be  of  a  higher 
standard  according  to  the  requirements  of  the  age,  which,  however,  is  not 
saying  very  much.  Linnasus  had  for  the  most  part  to  carry  on  his  studies  by 
himself.  During  his  first  term  at  Upsala  he  lived  in  dire  want,  but  he  soon 

103 


2.04  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

succeeded  in  procuring  patrons  there:  the  dean,  Celsius,  who  was  likewise 
interested  in  botany,  took  him  into  his  family  and  undertook  to  procure 
him  further  advancement.  Even  as  a  young  student  Linnaeus  had  always 
shown  that  capacity  which  never  left  him  throughout  his  life,  of  exciting 
the  admiration  and  sympathy  of  those  he  met  who  possessed  interests  simi- 
lar to  his  own  —  a  quality  based  on  the  keenness  with  which  he  himself 
embraced  the  work  he  had  made  his  own.  When  once  he  had  acquired  friends 
at  the  University  he  gained  one  success  after  another.  Though  not  yet  a 
graduate,  he  obtained  permission  to  lecture  on  botany  and  he  used  to  attract 
large  audiences.  He  received  a  number  of  grants,  and  with  the  aid  of  public 
funds  he  made  journeys  of  exploration  to  the  Lapp  district  and  Dalecarlia, 
in  the  course  of  which  he  collected  material  for  research  consisting  not  only 
of  natural  objects,  but  also  of  human  customs  and  habits.  During  the  latter 
expedition  he  made  the  acquaintance  of  his  future  wife,  daughter  of  the 
wealthy  town-physician  of  Falun,  Morasus.  In  order  to  secure  further  ad- 
vancement in  the  career  he  had  chosen,  Linnasus  had  to  obtain  the  degree  of 
doctor  of  medicine,  but  there  was  no  such  degree  in  Sweden  at  that  time. 
He  accordingly  made  a  journey,  with  the  financial  support  of  his  future 
father-in-law,  to  Holland,  where  at  the  small  university  of  Harderwijk, 
which  never  attained  to  a  very  high  standard  of  scholarship,  he  took  his 
doctor's  degree  in  a  couple  of  weeks.  By  that  time,  however,  the  money  he 
had  brought  with  him  had  become  exhausted  and  Linnasus  had  no  other 
resource  than  to  chance  his  luck  elsewhere.  He  accordingly  went,  in  company 
with  a  fellow-countryman,  to  Amsterdam  and  thence  to  Leyden.  There  he 
became  acquainted  with  several  scientists  and  people  interested  in  science, 
chief  of  whom  was  Boerhaave,  who  treated  him  with  paternal   kindness. 
With  the  assistance  of  one  or  two  patrons  Linnasus  was  able  to  print  his 
most  epoch-making  work,  the  Sy sterna  ncitura,  which  he  had  already  begun 
in  Sweden  and  which  brought  him  immediate  fame.  He  then  spent  three 
years  visiting  the  principal  centres  of  learning  in  Holland,  publishing  one 
work  after  another  with  marvellous  rapidity,  supported  by  patrons  and  often 
almost  persuaded  to  settle  in  Holland  for  good.  He  longed  to  return  home, 
however,  and  after  paying  visits  to  both  England  and  France,  he  returned  to 
Sweden  with  a  European  reputation,  but  without  any  very  brilliant  prospects 
for  the  future.  He  succeeded,  though  with  some  difficulty  at  first,  in  making 
a  living  as  a  physician  in  Stockholm,  until  in  1741  he  won  the  position  for 
which  he  had  striven  so  long  —  the  professorship  of  botany  at  Upsala. 
During  his  Stockholm  period  he  had  taken  part  in  the  founding  of  the  Acad- 
emy of  Science  and  had  been  its  first  principal;  at  Upsala,  from  the  day  of 
his  arrival,  he  became  the  foremost  member  of  the  University.  His  time  and 
capacity  for  work  sufficed  for  everything  —  for  his  teaching,  which  went 
on  summer  and  winter,  before  ever-increasing  audiences,  both  of  Swedes  and 


SEVENTEENTH  AND  EIGHTEENTH  CENTURIES  XO<^ 
foreigners;  for  the  reorganization  of  the  botanical  garden  (which  existed 
in  Rudbeck's  time,  but  which  had  now  fallen  into  decay),  making  it  one 
of  the  finest  in  Europe;  for  the  production  of  extraordinarily  fine  scientific 
works  and  an  extensive  correspondence.  As  a  founder  of  schools  and  an  organ- 
izer of  work  he  has  had  few  equals  in  the  history  of  biology.  Every  year 
he  sent  out  pupils  on  research  expeditions,  whose  collections  and  observa- 
tions were  afterwards  worked  up  under  the  master's  own  guidance.  He  him- 
self was  acknowledged  throughout  the  whole  civilized  world  as  an  authority 
on  natural-scientific  questions,  his  advice  being  sought  by  governments  as 
well  as  private  individuals.  His  native  country  also  learnt  to  appreciate  him; 
he  received  several  high  honours;  among  other  things  he  was  ennobled  and 
took  the  name  of  von  Linne. 

The  climax  of  Linnxus's  greatness  falls  within  the  period  of  the  seven- 
teen-fifties;  then  he  published  the  last  of  his  great  works,  and  then,  too, 
he  received  his  highest  honours.  The  quarter  of  a  century  of  life  that  still 
remained  to  him  was  a  period  of  decline.  The  hardships  suffered  in  his  youth 
and  the  cares  of  his  m^turer  years  had  undermined  his  health.  By  the  begin- 
ning of  the  fifties  he  had  already  become  seriously  ill,  but  he  still  managed 
to  work  during  the  succeeding  decades  —  in  part  producing  results  of  con- 
siderable importance  —  although  his  powers  of  movement ■  began  to  fail. 
During  the  seventies,  however,  he  was  subject  to  repeated  paralytic  strokes, 
which  dulled  his  intelligence  and  finally  paralysed  him  entirely.  In  1778 
death  brought  release. 

In  1763  Linnaeus  had  taken  a  step  which  was  certainly  the  most  unfor- 
tunate he  ever  took  in  his  life;  he  had  obtained  from  the  Government  the 
right  to  recommend  his  successor  and  he  appointed  his  only  son,  Carl  von 
Linne  the  younger,  who  thus  at  the  age  of  twenty-two  became  aspirant  to 
the  professorship,  possessed  no  brilliant  gifts  and  had  never  passed  any  tests 
of  scholarship.  Although  his  promotion  was  by  no  means  so  ridiculous  in 
the  eyes  of  his  contemporaries  as  it  would  have  been  in  modern  times  —  it 
was  quite  usual  for  people  to  purchase  a  "survivance"  to  an  official  post 
similar  to  that  which  young  Linne  obtained  on  account  of  his  father's  serv- 
ices —  nevertheless  this  step  had  the  most  unfortunate  consequences.  The 
feelings  entertained  by  the  large  crowd  of  far  more  competent  pupils  were 
naturally  very  bitter  and  were  enhanced  the  more  the  worthlessness  of  young 
Linne's  character  manifested  itself,  as  it  unfortunately  did  very  soon,  no 
doubt  hastened  on  by  his  unmerited  promotion.  And,  to  make  matters  worse, 
it  caused  also  a  division  in  the  Linne  family.  On  his  father's  death  the  son 
laid  claim  to  his  collections,  which  his  mother  and  sisters,  supported  by  a 
will,  refused  to  allow.  The  quarrel  was  finally  settled  by  arrangement,  and 
shortly  afterwards  Linne  the  younger  died,  at  the  early  age  of  forty-two, 
after  a  life  which  brought  little  honour  to  the  name  he  bore  and  which  died 


io6  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

out  with  him.  The  unlucky  position  into  which  he  got  himself  as  regards 
both  his  family  and  his  colleagues  was  also  no  doubt  responsible  for  the 
sale  (ignominious  indeed  for  his  country)  of  the  collections  of  Linnasus  — 
his  herbarium,  library,  and  correspondence  —  to  England,  where  they  are 
still  preserved  by  the  Linnean  Society,  which  was  founded  for  that  purpose. 

His  fame 
LiNN^us  has  in  the  course  of  years  been  very  differently  judged.  Already 
in  his  youth  he  had  been  hailed  by  his  contemporaries  as  the  "  princeps  botan- 
icorum,''  a  title  that  he  succeeded  in  holding,  not  only  throughout  his  life, 
but  long  after  his  death.  But  the  reverse  came  in  connexion  with  the  accept- 
ance of  the  descent  theory  in  the  middle  of  last  century,  for  the  opponents 
of  this  doctrine  quoted  Linnaeus  as  their  chief  authority,  and  that  not  only 
on  scientific  grounds  but  also  from  motives  which  lay  far  removed  from  all 
that  natural  science  means:  his  primitive  Christian  piety  was  thrust  into 
the  breach  by  religious  and  social  conservatism  against  the  "unbelief"  of 
the  new  biology.  It  was  naturally  inconceivable  that  in  such  circumstances 
Linnasus  and  his  works  should  be  judged  with  impartiality;  in  the  eyes  of 
many  he  became  simply  the  arch-enemy  of  the  new  science,  and  the  judg- 
ments passed  on  him  at  the  time  were  often  not  only  spiteful,  but  also  utterly 
absurd.  Towards  the  close  of  the  century,  however,  a  calmer  atmosphere 
prevailed,  as  was  clearly  manifested  when  in  1907  the  bicentenary  of  Lin- 
naeus's  birth  was  celebrated  by  the  entire  civilized  world  as  a  red-letter 
day  in  the  annals  of  human  culture. 

Linnasus  is  universally  reckoned  among  the  examples  of  early  scientific 
maturity,  and  it  is  true  that  by  the  time  he  had  reached  about  his  twenty- 
fifth  year,  he  had  already  fully  worked  out  the  principles  on  which  his  sub- 
sequent work  rests.  Less  remarked  has  been  the  steady  development  which 
he  underwent  so  long  as  he  was  generally  capable  of  working;  the  Linnasus 
whom  we  meet  in  the  first  edition  of  the  Systetna  natura  and  writings  contem- 
porary therewith  is  not  in  the  least  the  same  person  as  the  one  who  composed 
the  final  editions  of  that  work.  This  may  to  some  extent  explain  why  such 
contradictory  judgments  have  been  passed  on  him;  the  one  has  sought  sup- 
port for  its  opinion  of  him  in  the  work  of  his  youth,  the  other  in  that  of 
his  old  age. 

His  general  conceptions  of  nature 
If  on  the  basis  of  Linnasus's  writings  we  were  to  try  to  form  an  opinion  as 
to  his  general  conception  of  nature,  we  should  soon  discover  that  he  never 
formulated  any  elaborate  theory  of  the  phenomena  of  life  in  their  entirety, 
such  as  Hoffmann,  Stahl,  and  Boerhaave  did,  each  in  his  own  way.  In  the 
works  of  his  youth  there  appears  only  a  naively  popular  conception  of  nature, 
which,  as  a  matter  of  fact,  he  retained,  practically  speaking,  throughout 
his  life :  nature  is  created  by  God  to  His  honour  and  for  the  blessing  of  man- 


SEVENTEENTH  AND  EIGHTEENTH  CENTURIES  107 
kind,  and  everything  that  happens  happens  at  His  command  and  under  His 
guidance.  No  other  explanation  of  natural  phenomena  is  looked  for.  How- 
little  Linnieus  actually  interested  himself  in  the  general  scientific  questions 
that  occupied  the  minds  of  his  contemporaries  is  at  once  shown  by  the  fact 
that  even  in  the  twelfth  edition  of  his  Sy sterna  natura  he  still  lets  the  universe 
consist  of  the  ancient  four  elements,  fire,  air,  water,  and  earth;  he  seems  not 
to  have  been  aware  of  the  fact  that  many  decades  earlier  Stahl  had  published 
his  new  theory  of  the  process  of  combustion.  On  the  other  hand,  in  this  and 
in  other  works  of  his  later  years  there  occur  a  number  of  ideas  contributing 
to  a  mechanical  explanation  of  life  that  are  in  striking  contrast  to  his  ro- 
mantic piety.  In  the  above-mentioned  edition  of  Systema  natura  he  defines 
(on  p.  1 5)  animal  life  as  a  hydraulic  machine  which  is  kept  going  by  an 
ethereal-electric  fire  maintained  by  breathing  ;i  on  the  other  hand  there  comes 
in  here  the  universally  known,  sublimely  poetical  description  of  God's  om- 
nipotence: how  he  saw  the  Eternal  wherever  he  went,  and  how  his  brain 
reeled  when  he  saw  traces  of  Him  in  everything,  from  the  life  of  the  minutest 
creatures  here  on  earth  to  the  movements  of  the  heavenly  bodies,  "which 
are  upheld  in  their  empty  nothingness  by  the  first  movement,  the  essence 
of  all  things,  the  mainspring  and  director  of  all  causes,  the  Lord  and  Master 
of  this  world;  should  we  call  Him  Fate,  we  should  not  be  wrong,  for  every- 
thing hangs  upon  His  finger;  should  we  call  Him  Nature,  we  should  not  be 
wrong  either,  for  all  things  have  emanated  from  Him;  should  we  call  Him 
Providence,  we  should  likewise  be  right,  for  everything  happens  according 
to  His  nod  and  His  will."  The  strange,  half-pantheistic  conception  of  God 
that  is  here  apparent  occurs  in  Seneca,  whose  Quastiones  naturales  Linnaeus 
cites  in  this  connexion  and  often  elsewhere;  besides  which  he  quotes  in  the 
work  in  question  the  Bible,  Aristotle,  Cesalpino,  and  van  Helmont  in  support 
of  his  theory  of  the  universe  and  of  life-phenomena.  To  Galileo's  physics, 
Newton's  astronomy,  and  Stahl's  chemistry,  on  the  other  hand,  he  has  paid 
no  attention;  at  any  rate,  there  are  no  quotations  that  would  indicate  his 
having  done  so. 

His  gifts  as  a  systematician 
At  the  time  when  polemics  were  levelled  at  him,  Linnasus  was  accused  of 
Aristoteleanism  in  a  derogatory  sense.  This  accusation  may  have  a  certain 
amount  of  justification,  but  it  is  likely  in  all  ages  to  be  laid  at  the  door  of 
everyone  desirous  of  arranging  things  according  to  formal  principles,  and 
that  was  what  Linnasus  desired,  just  as  it  was  exactly  what  biology  in  his 
time  needed.  Far  from  blaming  him  for  it,  therefore,  posterity  should,  on 
the  contrary,  be  grateful  to  him  for  having,  instead  of  working  out  specu- 

^  Is  it  possible  that  the  "fire-machine"  constructed  by  Triewald,  which  Linnaeus  saw  in 
his  youth  in  the  mine  at  Dannemora,  may  have  been  recalled  to  his  mind  and  have  given  rise 
to  this  curious  definition? 


Xo8  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

latively  some  doubtless  unproductive  system  of  thought,  devoted  himself 
entirely  to  ascertaining  the  relation  of  forms  to  one  another  —  an  investi- 
gation which  was  so  suited  to  his  peculiar  gifts.  That  in  doing  so  he  accepted 
the  old  biblical  conception  of  nature  was  as  natural  in  his  day  as  for  a  system- 
atist  of  our  own  day  to  embrace  the  theory  of  descent  without  going  closely 
into  the  question  of  its  justification.  He  was  thereby  able,  unhindered  by  any 
theoretical  barriers,  freely  to  develop  and  take  advantage  of  that  extraor- 
dinary capacity  for  observing  natural  objects  and  summarizing  his  obser- 
vations which  was  peculiar  to  him,  and  thus  to  establish  the  mastery  over 
research-material  on  which  modern  biology  is  based. 

Linnxus  was,  as  has  already  been  mentioned,  essentially  autodidactic, 
in  so  far  as  the  education  he  received  from  others  was  highly  deficient  and 
fragmentary.  Nevertheless,  the  conditions  under  which  he  was  trained  for 
his  life's  work  were  particularly  suited  to  his  natural  genius.  The  powers 
of  observation  which  formed  one  of  his  most  conspicuous  characteristics  had 
received  from  his  very  earliest  years  in  his  father's  garden,  under  his  guidance 
and  under  the  influence  of  the  love  of  the  vegetable  world  imparted  by  him, 
such  stimulating  exercise  as  to  afford  every  opportunity  for  the  full  develop- 
ment of  his  extraordinary  sense  of  form.  During  his  youth  his  teachers  gave 
him  a  knowledge  of  such  biological  literature  as  then  existed,  without  at 
the  same  time  burdening  him  with  any  theories  out  of  which  he  would 
afterwards  have  had  to  work  himself  up,  while  at  an  early  age  he  gained 
that  liberty  of  action  which  is  the  indispensable  condition  for  anyone  who, 
in  whatever  sphere  his  work  may  lie,  wishes  to  create  something  new.  The 
works  of  his  youth,  the  small  lists  of  plants  which  he  drew  up  and  which 
were  not  printed  until  our  own  day,  already  give  clear  evidence  of  where 
his  chief  interest  lay;  he  enumerates  the  plants  he  collected  in  various  places, 
with  observations  as  to  their  occurrence,  and  by  means  of  them  he  tests  the 
various  systems  which  he  found  amongst  his  predecessors,  principally  Tour- 
nefort,  but  also  Ray  and  Rivinus,  without,  however,  finding  any  real  satis- 
faction in  them.  On  the  contrary,  we  find  from  his  notes  that  he  felt  himself 
called  upon  to  reform  the  science  of  botany,  which  he  considered  to  have 
seriously  degenerated.  Thus  he  became  aware,  through  a  criticism  in  a  jour- 
nal, of  Camerarius's  discovery  of  sex  in  plants,  which  a  French  naturalist 
had  accepted,  and  he  was  so  excited  by  the  news  that  he  at  once  devoted 
himself  to  making  a  close  study  of  the  problem.  He  immediately  realized 
that  in  the  hitherto  neglected  stamens  and  pistils  one  had  to  do  with  the 
flower's  most  vital  organs,  and  from  that  point  of  view  alone  their  employ- 
ment as  a  basis  for  systematic  classification  was  justified.  Thus  arose  his 
sexual  system,  the  first  step  towards  the  realization  of  the  ambition  he  had 
set  himself  to  attain:  a  general  system  for  natural  objects.  And  at  the  same 
time  he  made  himself  quite  clear  as  to  the  principles  on  which  such  a  system- 


SEVENTEENTH     AND     EIGHTEENTH     CENTURIES       109 

atic  classification  would  have  to  be  worked  out,  the  result  being  the  second 
of  the  important  works  written  in  his  youth,  Methodus  plantariun,  wherein 
he  presented  most  of  the  principles  which  have  since  then  been  the  common 
property  of  plant  and  animal  classification.  He  first  of  all  laid  down  an  ex- 
planation and  a  definition  of  the  various  parts  of  the  plant,  after  the  model  of 
Jung  and  Ray,  whom,  however,  he  far  surpasses  in  the  matter  of  precision, 
both  of  observation  and  of  expression.  Further,  he  worked  out  in  an  incom- 
parable manner  the  principles  of  nomenclature,  synonymy,  and  character- 
istics of  the  various  categories  of  the  system,  all  of  which  have  since  then 
been  the  common  property  of  all  systematicians  of  any  ability,  but  which 
in  his  time  reacted  with  all  the  overwhelming  force  of  a  novel  idea.  With 
all  these  ideas  partly  written  down,  partly  in  his  head,  Linnaeus  came  to 
Holland,  and  was  able,  under  the  unusually  favourable  conditions  which 
he  enjoyed  there,  to  make  them  fully  available  for  research.  But  before 
giving  an  account  of  those,  the  greatest  works  of  his  life,  we  must  devote 
a  few  words  to  a  man  with  whom  he  closely  collaborated  and  who  made  a 
strong  and  lasting  impression  on  him. 

Peter  Artedi  was  born  in  1705  at  Anundsjo,  in  northern  Sweden,  the 
son  of  a  priest  named  Arctxdius.  He  entered  Upsala  University  in  17x4  and, 
like  Linnasus,  had  difficulty  in  obtaining  his  father's  consent  to  his  studying 
medicine  in  preference  to  theology.  It  was  natural  science,  however,  that 
chiefly  attracted  him,  and  in  that  field  he  too,  like  Linn^us,  had  for  the 
most  part  to  study  on  his  own.  At  the  time  when  Linnasus  came  to  Upsala, 
Artedi  was  considered  the  most  promising  naturalist  in  the  University  and 
there  soon  arose  a  firm  friendship  between  them,  resulting  in  a  co-operation 
which  proved  of  great  benefit  to  both.  Artedi  was  especially  interested  in 
zoology,  chiefly  in  icthyology,  while  Linnaeus  applied  himself  to  botany, 
so  that  there  was  no  necessity  for  them  to  encroach  upon  one  another's  fields 
of  activity,  but  at  the  same  time  they  could  exchange  ideas  and  observations. 
In  their  characters,  too,  they  were  fortunate  in  being  able  to  complement 
one  another;  Linnasus  was  lively  and  enthusiastic,  Artedi  calm  and  critical. 
Financially  they  were  both  in  an  equally  bad  way  and  they  had  recourse 
to  one  another's  assistance.  In  1734  Artedi  received  a  grant  to  enable  him 
to  travel  abroad  and  he  went  to  London,  where  he  studied  zoology,  mainly 
icthyology.  A  year  later  he  came  to  Amsterdam  without  resources  and  with- 
out the  slightest  prospect  of  getting  home.  Linnasus,  who  had  already  ac- 
quired some  connexions  in  the  city,  introduced  his  friend  to  a  wealthy 
apothecary  who  possessed  a  large  collection  of  fishes.  This  museum  Artedi 
was  now  commissioned  to  catalogue  and  was  able  at  the  same  time  to  com- 
plete a  large  work  on  fishes  on  which  he  had  long  been  engaged.  His  career, 
however,  was  short;  one  evening,  upon  returning  from  a  visit  to  his  bene- 
factor, he  fell  into  a  canal  and  was  drowned  (autumn,  1735). 


iio  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

The  icthyology  of  Artedi 
His  work  was  published  by  Linnasus  with  the  assistance  of  a  Dutch  patron. 
It  was  probably  in  all  essentials  the  work  of  Artedi,  though  Linnasus  made 
some  additions  here  and  there.  The  work  purports  to  be  a  complete  mono- 
graph on  fishes;  the  anatomical  section,  however,  is  of  minor  importance. 
The  chief  interest  lies  in  the  presentation  of  the  theory  of  the  system,  which 
is  incorporated  in  the  part  entitled  "  Philosophia  ktbyologka.''  In  this  are 
discussed  with  sharp  criticism  the  various  systematical  categories.  He  starts, 
after  the  model  of  Tournefort,  with  the  genus,  which  is  defined  as  a  collec- 
tion of  species  that,  as  regards  the  shape,  position,  number,  and  mutual 
relation  of  the  parts,  agree  with  one  another  and  differ  from  other  genera. 
The  species,  moreover,  he  bases,  not  like  Ray  and  Linnasus  on  common  ori- 
gin, but  on  dissimilarity  in  the  same  genus  in  respect  of  some  individual 
part  of  the  body,  a  principle  the  weakness  of  which  in  comparison  with 
Linnicus's  becomes  at  once  apparent.  As  higher  categories  he  adduces  classes 
and  orders;  the  classes  should  be  "natural"  —  that  is,  be  based  upon  agree- 
ment in  several  essential  parts  and  not  upon  unessential  factors,  such  as  oc- 
currence, size,  and  the  like.  Fishes  form  one  such  "natural"  class,  owing 
to  the  shape  of  their  body  and  their  fins,  whales  nevertheless  still  being 
counted  in  the  "natural"  class.  The  orders  into  which  the  class  is  divided 
are  on  the  whole  the  same  as  those  still  in  use  today  —  a  proof  of  Artedi 's 
systematical  acumen;  selachians,  acanthopterygian  and  malacopterygian 
osseans  are  categories  invented  by  him.  Linnasus  adopted  his  icthyological 
system  unaltered  in  his  Systema  natura. 

Linnaus's  first  great  work:  Systema  naturae 
This  great  work  of  Linnasus,  the  natural  system  "in  which  nature's  three 
kingdoms  are  presented  divided  into  classes,  orders,  genera,  and  species," 
was  published,  as  already  mentioned,  in  Leyden  in  1735.  At  the  same  time 
was  printed  the  above  referred  to  Fundamenta  botanka,  and  three  years  later 
the  important  work  Classes  flantarum.  These  three  really  contain  all  that 
is  essential  in  the  reform  of  classification  which  Linnasus  carried  out.  Like 
Ray,  but  in  contrast  to  Tournefort,  Linnasus  as  a  systematician  takes  as  his 
starting-point  the  idea  of  species.  He  adopts  Ray's  theory  of  the  species  as 
created  from  the  very  beginning  and  immutable,  laying  this  down  as  a  fun- 
damental principle  without  limitations  or  exceptions.  "We  count  as  many 
species  as  have  been  created  from  the  beginning;  the  individual  creatures 
are  reproduced  from  eggs,  and  each  egg  produces  a  progeny  in  all  respects 
like  the  parents."  Thus  there  is  no  room  for  spontaneous  generation,  no 
possibility  for  the  seeds  of  one  plant  to  give  rise  to  a  plant  of  a  different 
kind.  Rather  it  was  expressly  maintained  that  in  the  beginning  there  was 
created  of  each  species  one  single  pair,  one  of  each  sex,  so  that  all  individuals 
of  the  same  species  possess  a  common  origin.  Again,  there  exist  as  many 


SEVENTEENTH  AND  EIGHTEENTH  CENTURIES  XII 
genera  as  there  are,  among  the  natural  vegetable  species,  flowers  (or  fructi- 
fications, as  they  are  termed  in  these  works)  differing  in  number,  shape,  and 
position.  Classes  are  defined  as  a  collection  of  genera  that  agree  in  regard  to 
fructification  in  certain  main  features.  The  order,  again,  is  a  subdivision  of 
the  class  which  embraces  a  number  of  more  easily  summarized  genera.  The 
application  of  these  principles  is  Linnasus's  universally  known  sexual  system, 
in  which  the  classes  are  essentially  determined  according  to  the  number  of 
stamens,  and  the  orders  according  to  the  number  of  pistils.  The  practical 
utility  of  the  system  is  sufficiently  evidenced  by  the  fact  that  it  is  used  to 
this  day  in  school  education,  although  it  was  long  ago  abandoned  in  actual 
scientific  work.  That  this  system,  based  as  it  was  on  only  one  organic  system, 
was  one-sided,  Linnaeus  was  very  well  aware,  and  in  several  instances  he 
departed  from  the  fundamental  principle  merely  in  order  to  preserve  the  con- 
nexion in  certain  groups  which  he  found  to  be  natural,  as,  for  instance,  the 
classes  Didynamia,  Tetradynamia,  and  Gynandria,  which,  it  is  true,  are 
characterized  by  the  stamens,  but  not  only  by  their  number,  and  which  com- 
prise forms  that  even  the  system  of  classification  of  our  own  day  keeps  to- 
gether. For  Linnaeus  was  fully  aware  that  what  should  really  be  striven  for 
in  botany  was  a  "natural  system":  a  classification  of  genera  into  groups 
on  account  of  a  common  similarity,  not  merely  on  account  of  the  relations 
of  certain  organs.  He  spent  his  whole  life  working  out  this  natural  system; 
the  results  he  achieved  will  be  mentioned  later  on. 

Linnasus's  systematic  classification  of  the  animal  kingdom  cannot  be 
said  to  have  turned  out  as  successfully  as  his  plant  system.  He  divides  animals 
into  six  classes:  (i)  Quadrupedia,  (2.)  Aves,  (3)  Amphibia,  (4)  Pisces,  (5)  In- 
secta,  and  (6)  Vermes.  Quadrupeds  are  characterized  as  follows:  "the  body 
hairy,  four  legs,  females  producing  live  young,  which  they  suckle";  birds: 
"the  body  feathered,  two  legs,  two  wings,  beak,  females  laying  eggs"  — 
that  is  to  say,  purely  external  characteristics.  Linnasus's  precursor  Ray  based 
his  system,  as  we  have  seen,  essentially  upon  anatomical  characteristics:  the 
structure  of  the  respiratory  organs  and  of  the  heart;  moreover,  he  differen- 
tiated, although  with  faulty  characterization,  between  vertebrates  and  in- 
vertebrates; the  latter  he  divides  into  four  groups,  while  Linnaeus  has  only 
two  —  all  details  in  which  Linnasus  was  undeniably  inferior  to  his  pre- 
cursor. Fishes  Linnasus  has  dealt  with  entirely  in  accordance  with  Artedi's 
system,  which  he  in  fact  acknowledges.  Of  the  lower  animals  the  only  ones 
that  interest  him  are  the  insects.  Moreover,  Linnaeus  has  not  laid  down  any 
general  principles  for  animal  classification  similar  to  his  Fundamenta  botanica. 
Artedi's  "  Philosophia  kthyologka"  might  certainly  be  said  to  have  filled  the 
gap,  but  the  latter's  method,  as  we  have  already  seen,  differs  not  a  little 
from  Linnasus's,  primarily  in  the  fact  that  his  system  is  based  on  the  genus 
and  not  on  the  species  —  and  in  these  circumstances  it  only  remains  to  show 


■LIZ  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

that  the  Linnasan  reform  was  from  the  beginning  more  adapted  to  vegetables 
than  to  animals. 

The  conception  of  species:  their  immutability 
But,  all  the  same,  Linnjeus's  contribution  to  the  development  of  biology 
has  been  of  vital  importance  to  science  as  a  whole.  In  the  first  place,  by  fixing 
the  term  ' '  species  "  as  he  did,  he  laid  the  foundation  for  the  system  of  classi- 
fication as  it  exists  today.  At  the  time  when  the  dispute  on  the  descent  theory 
was  raging  at  its  hottest,  Linnasus,  it  is  true,  was  exposed  to  the  severest 
censure  just  because  he  had  declared  the  species  to  be  immutable,  as  they 
were  created  from  the  beginning  —  the  dispute,  in  fact,  raged  just  as  much 
over  the  belief  in  the  creation  as  over  the  constancy  of  the  species  itself  — 
but  in  spite  of  the  fact  that  the  immutability  theory  is  now  abandoned, 
the  Linnasan  species  is  used  in  practice  by  systematic  science  even  today, 
because  it  has  not  been  possible  to  find  any  better  substitute  for  it;  a  species 
is  regarded  as  the  sum  total  of  those  individuals  which  resemble  one  another 
as  if  they  had  a  common  origin.  The  other  systematical  categories  which 
Linnasus  created  also  remain  to  this  day,  although  some  new  ones  have  come 
into  existence  as  well.  And  quite  as  remarkable  is  Linnasus's  influence  on 
what  may  be  called  the  technical  side  of  the  classification  system,  which 
he  himself  actually  founded,  exactly  as  it  is  applied  today :  his  rules  regarding 
nomenclature,  description,  characterization,  and  synonymy  have  really 
proved  so  complete  that  in  principle  posterity  has  had  but  little  to  add  to 
them.  Moreover,  the  whole  of  this  radical  reform  was  carried  out  at  one 
stroke  by  a  hitherto  unknown  young  man  after  only  a  few  short  years  of 
utterly  inadequate  scientific  training.  This  wonderful  result  was  rendered 
possible  only  by  the  fact  that  Linnasus  combined  exceptionally  well-trained 
powers  of  observation  with  an  unparalleled  natural  genius  for  the  formal 
side  of  science.  This  latter  gift  was,  so  to  speak,  in  his  very  blood:  he  had 
a  passion  for  classifying  everything  that  came  within  his  grasp;  his  medical 
writings  consist  of  groups  of  diseases  in  tabular  form;  his  predecessors  in 
science  he  likewise  classified  under  various  headings,  and  once  he  even  ar- 
ranged, mostly  as  a  joke,  all  his  contemporary  botanists  according  to  mili- 
tary rank,  with  himself  as  their  general.  For  the  fact  that  this  mania  for 
classification  never  degenerated  into  mere  dull  pedantry  he  had  to  thank 
his  extraordinary  love  of  nature  and  his  passion  and  gift  for  observing  life 
in  all  its  manifestations.  It  was  this  quality  that  prevented  him  from  stag- 
nating at  the  point  to  which  he  had  so  rapidly  attained,  instead  of  which 
he  spent  his  whole  life  striving  to  extend  and  perfect  the  science  that  he  had 
already  so  thoroughly  recreated.  These  efforts,  which,  with  the  aid  of  his 
pupils,  he  continued  as  long  as  his  powers  lasted,  consisted  in  improving 
the  system  he  had  already  created,  extending  and  perfecting  the  natural 
vegetable  system  that  he  had  already  made  it  his  ambition  to  work  out, 


SEVENTEENTH     AND     EIGHTEENTH     CENTURIES       ^13 

and,  finally,  in  making  a  number  of  observations  of  life  in  nature  and  the 
interrelation  of  its  different  phenomena. 

The  binary  nomenclature 
The  most  important  purely  formal  improvement  of  the  system  which  Lin- 
naeus effected  was  the  binary  nomenclature,  introduced  in  1753  into  the 
classification  of  the  vegetable  kingdom  and  somewhat  later  into  that  of  the 
animal  kingdom.  Previously  he  had  followed  the  example  of  Tournefort  in 
characterizing  every  genus  by  a  single  term,  while  the  character  of  the  species 
was  designated  by  a  short  diagnosis  of  some  few  words.  Now  he  introduced 
instead  one  single  character  word  for  the  species  also,  so  that  every  plant 
or  animal  received  its  character  and  its  fixed  place  in  the  system  by  means 
of  only  two  words.  This  reform  is  certainly  the  most  important  of  his  con- 
tributions in  the  purely  formal  sphere.  Thanks  to  this  alone  biology  has 
been  able  to  master  the  vast  amount  of  form-material  that  has  been  col- 
lected up  to  the  present  day,  which  could  certainly  never  have  been  handled 
if  it  had  been  necessary  to  employ  diagnoses  in  order  to  denote  the  species. 
His  other  reforms  in  connexion  with  the  system  applied  not  so  much  to 
botany  as  to  zoology;  he  left  his  botanical  sexual  system  for  the  most 
part  undisturbed  and  contented  himself  with  incorporating  into  it  the  new 
species  which  were  sent  to  him  from  all  over  the  world.  Of  the  improve- 
ments which  he  introduced  into  the  animal  system  the  most  worthy  of 
mention  is  the  fact  that  he  at  last  associated  whales  with  the  quadrupeds, 
which  resulted  in  the  latter's  receiving  the  name  they  have  since  borne  — 
Mammalia  —  that  is,  animals  which  feed  their  young.  The  orders  into  which 
he  divided  this  class,  mainly  after  the  dental  structure,  were,  however,  still 
somewhat  artificial  and  were  long  ago  rearranged;  on  the  other  hand,  his 
method  of  associating  man  with  the  apes  in  the  order  Primates  has  been 
retained.  Birds,  which  were  essentially  classified  according  to  their  beaks, 
have,  as  is  well  known,  been  still  further  regrouped.  His  transfer  in  the  last 
editions  of  Sy sterna  natures  of  the  Cartilaginei  to  the  amphibians,  which  was 
at  variance  with  Artedi's  system,  was  extremely  unfortunate,  based  as  it 
was  on  a  misconception  of  those  fishes'  gills.  On  the  whole,  Linnasus  dis- 
liked cold-blooded  animals;  as  a  motto  for  the  amphibians  he  chose  the 
words:  "Terrible  are  Thy  works,  O  Lord,"  and  he  assures  us  that  there 
are  not  many  who  would  wish  to  collect  these  animals.  In  regard  to  the  inver- 
tebrate animals  he  let  his  system  stand  unaltered;  only  the  species,  in  par- 
ticular the  insects,  were  reduplicated  like  the  plants. 

The  ' '  natural  method  of  -plants 
In  spite  of  the  enormous  amount  of  work  entailed  in  describing  these  new 
animals  and  plants  from  all  parts  of  the  world,  Linnasus  found  time  to  apply 
himself  to  theoretical  problems  of  great  importance.  Chief  among  these 
should  be  mentioned  his  work  on  the  natural  vegetable  system.  As  early 


114  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

as  in  the  work  Classes  plantarum,  published  in  Holland  in  1738,  he  promul- 
gated what  he  called  "fragments  of  a  natural  method  of  arrangement":  a 
list  of  sixty-five  "orders,"  each  embracing  a  number  of  vegetable  genera, 
but  without  any  characterization  of  the  peculiarities  that  warranted  their 
being  grouped  together.  By  way  of  introduction  he  describes  the  natural 
system  as  the  highest,  but  hitherto  unattained,  aim  of  botany,  which  he 
exhorts  all  truly  distinguished  botanists  to  strive  after.  For  the  creation 
of  such  a  system  no  particular  parts  of  plants  or  flowers  should,  he  maintains, 
be  used  as  a  standard,  but  only  the  common  agreement  existing  between  all 
parts  of  the  plant.  Several  of  the  groups  which  he  founded,  such  as  palms, 
grasses,  Liliaceas,  Umbellata,  are  still  regarded  as  entirely  natural.  Through- 
out the  whole  of  the  rest  of  his  life  Linnasus  never  let  the  natural  system  out 
of  sight,  although  he  never  thought  that  he  would  complete  it.  In  his  Philo- 
sophia  botanica(i-j'^i)hc  again  cites  a  number  of  natural  groups,  now  provided 
with  names,  and  in  doing  so  points  out  that  the  vegetable  groups  everywhere 
border  on  one  another,  like  the  countries  on  a  map  of  the  world.  In  point  of 
fact,  his  realization  of  the  difficulty  of  trying  in  a  comprehensible  way  to 
present  the  natural  affinities  of  living  creatures  was  a  proof  of  his  keen  eye 
for  the  infinite  multiplicity  of  nature;  his  caution  might  well  be  borne  in 
mind  by  many  a  biologist  of  our  own  time  who  has  rashly  drawn  up  a  genea- 
logical tree  for  some  animal  group  or  other.  In  connexion  with  this  feeling 
of  Linnxus  for  the  difficulty  of  determining  natural  affinity,  it  is  worth 
mentioning  that  in  his  later  writings  he  discusses  with  far  greater  caution 
than  in  his  earlier  years  the  question  of  the  bordering  of  the  species  on  one 
another.  It  was  not  only  that  he  had  seen  masses  of  varieties  overlapping  one 
another,  but  he  had  also  observed  the  altered  forms  produced  by  hybridiz- 
ing —  he  himself  was  very  successful  in  hybridizing  in  his  own  garden  — 
and  as  a  result  of  all  this  the  delimitations  of  species,  which  he  once  felt  to 
be  so  certain,  began  to  be  obliterated.  The  doctrine  of  the  original  creation 
he  certainly  could  not  abandon,  but  he  began  to  consider  the  possibility  of 
the  genera's  having  been  created  and  only  one  or  a  few  species  of  each,  and 
afterwards  new  species'  being  able  to  arise  out  of  the  old.  In  the  final  edition 
of  Systema  natura  he  has  omitted  the  definite  assertion  that  no  new  species 
arise.  He  who  has  so  often  been  accused  of  dogmatism  was  really  less  dog- 
matic than  many  modern  scientists  who  have  proved  themselves  ready  to 
accept  blindly  the  prevailing  theories  of  the  day. 

In  the  above-mentioned  Philosophia  botanica  Linnasus  has  also  expounded 
an  organic  theory  in  respect  of  the  vegetable  kingdom.  A  great  many  of  his 
clearly  formulated  characters  of  the  various  parts  of  plants  are  still  valid  to- 
day. Many  consider  the  anatomical  section  of  this  work  to  be  weak,  even  as 
compared  with  the  investigations  of  the  earlier  botanical  anatomists  Mal- 
pighi  and  Grew.  This  may  be  true,  for  Linnasus  was,  generally  speaking,  no 


SEVENTEENTH  AND  EIGHTEENTH  CENTURIES  115 
anatomist;  true,  he  did  not  fail  to  urge  the  study  of  anatomy  as  well,  but  his 
own  gifts  lay  far  rather  in  work  upon  living  nature  than  at  the  dissecting- 
table.  Of  his  purely  morphological  observations,  on  the  other  hand,  many 
are  of  lasting  value;  he  thus  established  the  fact  that  all  leaves,  both 
plant  leaves  and  flower-petals,  go  through  a  common  process  of  develop- 
ment, a  discovery  very  often  attributed  to  Goethe.  But  when  he  tries 
his  hand  at  comparative  anatomy,  he  usually  fails,  as  when  he  com- 
pares the  parts  of  plants  and  animals:  marrow  and  spinal  marrow,  skin  and 
bark,  etc. 

Phenologkal  and  geographical  biology 
On  the  other  hand,  Linnreus's  contributions  to  the  knowledge  of  the  con- 
ditions under  which  plants  and  animals  live  in  their  natural  state  are  excep- 
tionally many-sided.  These  natural  observations  of  his,  which  occur  scattered 
throughout  his  disputations  and  platform  speeches,  bear  witness  not  only  to 
his  keenness  of  observation,  but  still  more  to  his  ability  to  combine  and  draw 
conclusions  from  what  he  observed.  Thus  in  the  course  of  a  graduation  speech 
' '  On  the  Rise  of  the  Habitable  Earth, ' '  which  begins  with  a  discussion  of  how 
all  vegetable  species  were  able  to  grow  at  once  in  paradise  —  they  must 
have  existed  there,  for  otherwise  Adam  would  not  have  been  able,  as  stated 
in  the  Bible,  to  give  them  names  —  he  expounded  a  theory  of  the  propaga- 
tion of  plants,  based  on  universal  research-material,  which  was  so  well  ar- 
ranged that  it  still  has  its  value  at  the  present  day.  In  other  dissertations  he 
has  contributed  to  the  knowledge  of  the  "stations"  of  plants  (nowadays 
termed  "locations")  and  has  described  the  influence  of  external  conditions 
upon  the  size,  florescence,  and  distribution.  All  that  is  now  called  pheno- 
logical,  ecological,  and  geographical  zoology  and  botany  has  consequently 
its  origin  in  him.  Finally,  in  the  disputations  "Politia  natura"  and  "  CEconomia 
naturx"  he  gives  a  radical  explanation  of  all  that  we  moderns  call  harmony 
in  nature:  that  all  living  creatures  are  adapted  to  certain  conditions  of  life 
and  that  the  various  plants  and  animals  through  their  activities  keep  nature 
in  equipoise,  so  that  "every  vegetable  species  has  been  given  its  special  insect 
for  the  purpose  of  keeping  her  under  control  and  to  prevent  her  from  spread- 
ing too  much  and  ousting  her  neighbours,"  while  the  Hymenoptera  Para- 
sitica and  small  birds  look  after  the  insects,  and  birds  of  prey  after  the  small 
birds.  That  he  lets  all  this  take  place  under  God's  constant  guidance,  to  His 
honour  and  for  the  benefit  of  man,  should  not  in  our  time  detract  from 
the  value  of  the  observations  and  the  wealth  of  ideas  expressed  in  these 
works. 

The  balance  which  Linnaeus  thus  found  in  nature  he  sought  also  in  the 
ethical  sphere  through  his  well-known  speculations  upon  the  "Nemesis 
divina,"  which,  however  childish  they  may  be  in  their  detail,  are  neverthe- 
less typical  both  of  the  man  himself  and  of  his  time;  both  Leibniz  and  Vol- 


Xl6  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

taire^  likewise  ruminated  over  the  righteousness  governing  the  cosmic 
process.  And  in  this,  too,  Linnjeus  perceived  the  divine  guidance  that  he  so 
earnestly  sought  in  natural  phenomena.  He  was  an  optimist  all  through  — 
one  of  the  few  happy  beings  who  could  see  harmony  everywhere  because  they 
have  had  such  a  harmonious  disposition  themselves.  He  regarded  his  life's 
work  with  a  mixture  of  naive  self-satisfaction  and  humble  gratitude  to  the 
Almighty,  under  whose  guidance  he  was  always  conscious  of  living.  And  he 
may  well  have  been  satisfied,  for  in  the  science  he  so  faithfully  served,  few 
have  exercised  so  great  an  influence  as  he. 

Pupils  of  Linnceus 
It  has  been  pointed  out  above  that  Linnaeus  possessed  an  extraordinary 
power  of  gathering  pupils  round  him  and  interesting  them  in  facts  and  ideas 
in  the  science  he  represented.  Naturally  they  were  for  the  most  part  Swedes, 
but  a  number  of  foreigners  also  came  to  hear  him.  His  Swedish  pupils,  after 
receiving  their  education,  were  generally  sent  to  various  foreign  countries 
in  order  to  make  collections  and  to  describe  the  places  they  visited.  Linnasus 
had  drawn  up  for  them  special  instructions,  which  might  serve  equally  well 
today  as  a  guide  for  research-workers  in  a  foreign  country.  These  pupils  were 
travellers  and  collectors;  as  a  general  rule,  they  made  no  independent  dis- 
coveries. Several  of  them  fell  the  victims  of  hardship  and  disease,  some  ob- 
tained distinguished  appointments  abroad,  and  others  returned  home.  As 
examples  of  these  collectors  may  be  mentioned  F.  Hasselqvist,  who  travelled 
for  three  years  in  the  East  and  died  in  Smyrna  in  1751,  and  P.  Lofling,  whom 
Linnasus  called  his  most  beloved  pupil  and  who,  on  the  invitation  of  the 
Spanish  Government,  worked  first  on  the  Pyrenean  peninsula  and  then  in 
South  America,  where  he  died  in  1757.  Further,  Per  Kalm  (1716-79),  the 
first  biologist  in  Finland  to  work  independently,  who  in  the  course  of  a 
three  years'  sojourn  in  North  America  made  valuable  contributions  to  that 
country's  natural  history  and  national  economy,  and  who  afterwards  acted 
as  professor  of  economics  at  Abo,  strove  incessantly  by  the  application  of 
natural  science  to  practical  life  to  further  the  material  development  of  his 
country.  Kalm's  fellow-countryman  Peter  Forskal  (i73x-63)  first  studied 


2  Voltaire,  it  will  be  remembered,  after  the  terrible  earthquake  that  took  place  in  Lisbon 
in  1755,  wrote  a  poem  in  which  he  asks  Providence  of  what  those  innocent  men  were  guilty 
who  perished  in  it.  Linnaeus  takes  up  the  same  question;  he  consoles  himself  with  the  considera- 
tion of  the  many  innocent  people  whom  the  Inquisition  had  burnt  at  the  stake  in  that  city  and 
recalls  that  the  earthquake  took  place  on  All  Saints'  Day  —  the  same  day  on  which  the  autos- 
da-fe  used  to  be  held.  A  genuine  Old  Testament-like  idea;  the  city  had  sinned  and  was  punished 
accordingly.  Undeniably  more  attractive  are  some  of  the  innumerable  examples  of  Nemesis 
which  Linnaeus  cites  from  private  life,  such  as  the  story  of  the  lady  who  struck  her  servant  for 
having  fallen  downstairs  and  dropped  a  precious  china  bowl;  the  same  evening  the  lady  herself 
fell  down  the  same  stairs  and  broke  her  leg.  Generally  speaking,  Linnxus  possessed  a  strongly 
democratic  turn  of  mind,  a  lively  sympathy  for  the  poor  and  oppressed. 


SEVENTEENTH     AND     EIGHTEENTH     CENTURIES      xiy 
natural  science  at  Upsala,  then  philosophy  at  Gottingen;  owing  to  an  essay- 
he  wrote  attacking  the  Wolffian  philosophy,  which  was  predominant  at 
that  time,  he  was  unable  to  obtain  an  appointment  in  Sweden,  with  the 
result  that  he  went  into  Danish  service  as  natural  scientist  on  an  expedition 
to  the  East.  There  he  died,  leaving  behind  him  singularly  valuable  collec- 
tions. Another  who  took  a  post  abroad  was  Daniel  Solander,  who  had  an 
appointment  in  the  British  Museum,  London,  and  died  there  in  lySz;  and 
finally  may  be  mentioned  Karl  Peter  Thunberg  (1743-1818),  who  held 
Linnasus's  professorship  from  1784,  after  having  travelled  for  nine  years  in 
eastern  Asia,  particularly  in  the  then  unknown  country  of  Japan,  and  col- 
lected a  rare  amount  of  material  in  the  way  of  plants  and  animals.  More 
independent  than  any  of  these  others,   however,  was  the  Dane,  Johan 
Christian  Fabricius  (1745-180S).  The  son  of  a  physician,  he  became  an  un- 
dergraduate in  Copenhagen  in  1761  and  afterwards  spent  two  years  at  Upsala 
with  Linnasus,  with  whom  he  formed  a  lifelong  friendship.  After  returning 
home  he   published  several  valuable  works  on  entomology,  in  which  he 
applied  Linnasus's  method  to  the  insects  —  the  titles  of  his  works  corre- 
spond to  Linnasus's,  as  will  be  seen  from  the  bibliography  at  the  end  of  this 
book  —  and  greatly  increased  the  knowledge  of  that  class  of  animals.  Abroad 
he  was  highly  esteemed;  at  home,  on  the  other  hand,  he  received  but  little 
encouragement.  After  a  long  period  of  waiting  he  eventually  became  professor 
at  Kiel,  on  very  poor  terms,  wherefore  he  spent  most  of  his  later  years  abroad, 
chiefly  in  Paris,  where  he  had  many  friends.  Of  Linnasus's  personal  pupils 
he  was  perhaps  the  one  who,  besides  strictly  applying  his  master's  system, 
likewise  understood  best  how  to  employ  it  for  his  own  researches,  which 
were  of  lasting  value. 

Development  of  systematic  biology  after  Linnaus 
For  it  was  not  long  before  the  Linnasan  natural  science  began  in  a  general 
way  to  degenerate  into  a  spiritless  task  for  collectors  and  describers,  who 
merely  aimed  at  discovering  and  incorporating  in  the  system  as  many  fresh 
species  as  possible,  at  the  very  highest  in  the  hope  of  being  able  to  use  them 
to  some  practical  purpose  for  the  benefit  of  mankind  —  an  idea  which  very 
much  attracted  that  "age  of  utility"  and  which,  it  is  true,  Linnaeus  himself 
also  strongly  emphasized.  On  the  other  hand,  they  neglected  to  cherish  and 
develop  those  ideas  for  the  future  by  which  Linnasus  himself  set  such  store  — 
the  natural  system  and  the  study  of  the  conditions  of  life  in  nature.  The 
result  was  that  the  system  of  descriptive  classification,  which  has  so  often 
been  called  Linnasan  science,  actually  became  an  expression  for  a  quite 
limited  part  of  the  master's  high  aims;  it  certainly  became,  and  has  remained 
so  to  this  very  day,  a  necessary  basis  for  the  future  progress  of  biology,  as 
it  is  also  a  pedagogically  indispensable  introduction  to  that  science;  but  it 
has  also  been  possible  to  practise  it  without  any  deep  insight  into  the  phe- 


Il8  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

nomena  of  life  and  has  thereby  not  infrequently  acquired  the  character  of 
merely  a  collector's  hobby. 

In  fact,  this  seems  to  have  been  the  fate  which  threatened  biology  as  a 
whole  during  the  era  at  present  under  discussion;  that  it  did  not  actually  do 
so  is  due  to  a  large  extent  to  the  fact  that  contemporaneously  with  Linn^us 
there  was  another  scientist  at  work  who  was  aiming  at  leading  science  into 
a  direction  entirely  different  from  his,  and  who,  at  any  rate  partially,  suc- 
ceeded in  his  efforts.  This  man  was  Buffon. 


CHAPTER    VIII 


BUFFON 


His  Studies  and  career 

GEORGES  Louis  Leclerc  de  Buffon  was  born  in  1707  at  Montbard,  in 
Burgundy.  His  father  was  councillor  of  the  Burgundian  parlement 
•  at  Dijon,  the  capital  of  the  province,  and  thus  belonged  to  that 
bureaucratic  nobility  which  was  so  influential  in  France  in  earlier  times  and 
which  gave  to  the  country  many  of  its  finest  men,  who  were  often  remark- 
able for  their  cultural  interests  and  their  wealth.  Both  existed  indeed  in  the 
home  in  which  young  Buffon  was  brought  up;  he  received  a  thorough  educa- 
tion in  his  native  city  and  had  good  prospects  in  the  career  which  his  family 
had  long  followed,  when  chance  turned  his  footsteps  into  a  different  direc- 
tion. He'  made  the  acquaintance  of  a  young  Englishman,  Lord  Kingston, 
who  was  travelling  on  the  Continent  accompanied  by  a  tutor  who  had 
studied  natural  science,  and  travelled  with  him  through  France  and  Italy. 
During  this  tour  Buffon's  interest  in  nature,  which  was  to  be  the  dominating 
factor  in  his  life,  ripened.  He  accompanied  his  friend  to  England  and  spent 
a  year  in  London  studying,  particularly  mathematics,  physics,  and  botany  — 
sciences  which  were  at  the  height  of  their  development  in  the  country  that 
gave  birth  to  Newton  and  Ray.  Having  returned  to  France,  Buffon  published 
a  translation  of  Newton's  fluxions,  as  well  as  of  the  English  botanist  Hales's 
Vegetable  Staticks  —  two  works  which  presaged  the  direction  that  his  own 
activities  were  to  take.  As  he  was  wealthy,  he  was  able  to  devote  himself  to 
regular  scientific  labour,  first  of  all  directing  his  attention  to  mathematics 
and  physics.  In  1739  ^^  '^^^  elected  an  associate  of  the  French  Academy  of 
Sciences  and  in  the  same  year  was  appointed  "keeper  of  the  Jardin  du  Roi," 
a  post  of  some  distinction,  which  was  still  further  enhanced  by  his  activities 
that  resulted  in  the  Jardin  du  Roi,  now  the  Jardin  des  Plantes,  becoming  the 
centre  of  biological  research  in  France.  In  the  period  that  followed,  his  great 
gifts  proved  of  benefit  both  to  himself  and  to  the  science  he  had  chosen:  he 
succeeded  in  arousing  a  general  interest  for  natural  science  amongst  the  lead- 
ing circles  in  France,  so  that  even  the  King,  Louis  XV,  who  was  so  indifferent 
and  such  a  stranger  to  all  ideal  interests,  granted  large  sums  for  the  improve- 
ment of  his  garden  and  to  assist  the  scientific  work  carried  out  there,  while 
many  other  eminent  personages  likewise  patronized  this  science  and  its  dis- 
tinguished representative.  Buffon  himself  was  created  a  count,  was  made  a 

119 


XIO  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

member  of  the  French  Academy,  and  was  in  many  other  ways  honoured  by 
the  great.  It  was  also  his  fortune  to  play  a  brilliant  part  at  a  time  when  bril- 
liant qualities  were  valued  more  than  usual.  He  was  of  handsome  person  and 
stately  presence,  which  was  further  enhanced  by  the  exquisite  care  devoted  to 
his  dress  and  outward  appearance;  he  was  an  excellent  stylist  and  orator, 
and,  although  comparatively  reticent  in  society,  he  knew  how  to  entertain 
in  a  manner  befitting  his  social  position.  Naturally  he  also  had  his  enemies  in 
the  scientific  world,  who  caused  him  much  annoyance  both  in  public  and  in 
private.  Even  the  theological  faculty  in  Paris  was  not  satisfied  with  him,  as 
his  views  did  not  seem  to  be  entirely  orthodox,  and  there  was  once  a  ques- 
tion of  arraigning  him.  The  distinguished  man  of  the  world,  however,  who 
naturally  had  not  the  least  inclination  to  become  a  martyr,  parried  the  ac- 
cusation with  a  few  elegant  courtesies  about  the  infallible  authority  of  the 
Church,  and  so  the  matter  was  allowed  to  drop.  At  the  same  time,  in  pri- 
vate letters  to  trustworthy  friends  he  expressed  extremely  sceptical  opin- 
ions, which  place  him  in  utter  contrast  to  Linnasus,  with  his  childishly 
naive  piety.  These  two  were  destined  to  become  antagonists  in  other  spheres 
also.  —  Active  to  the  last,  BufFon  attained  an  age  of  over  eighty,  dying  in 
1788.  His  only  son,  whom  he  desired,  but  in  vain,  to  become  his  successor, 
died  by  the  guillotine  during  the  Revolution. 

His  Histoire  naturelle 
At  quite  an  early  age  BufFon  had  believed  it  to  be  his  mission  in  life  to  write 
a  general  natural  history,  an  account  of  all  the  knowledge  of  nature  that 
could  be  amassed,  and  in  1749  the  first  part  of  his  Histoire  nafurelle  was  pub- 
lished —  a  work  upon  which  he  was  engaged  for  the  rest  of  his  life.  In  the 
preparation  of  this  work  he  associated  himself  with  the  eminent  anatomist 
Louis  Daubenton  (1716-1800),  who  was  for  a  long  time  conservator  under 
him  and  afterwards  became  a  professor  at  the  College  de  France.  He  carried 
out  the  anatomical  and  morphological  detail-work,  while  BufFon  had  the 
management  of  the  whole  and  was  responsible  both  for  the  ideas  incorpo- 
rated in  it  and  for  the  method  of  presentation.  The  original  edition  comprised 
fifteen  volumes,  the  first  of  which  dealt  with  general  natural  science,  and  the 
remainder  with  man,  the  mammalians,  and  the  birds.  BufFon  got  no  further 
in  the  sphere  of  biology.  In  some  supplementary  volumes,  which  came  out 
later,  a  number  of  general  natural-scientific  questions  were  discussed,  includ- 
ing mineralogy,  a  science  on  which  BufFon  was  weakest,  as  he  was  no  chem- 
ist. Later  on,  several  editions  of  the  great  work  were  published  —  a  proof  of 
how  popular  it  was,  in  spite  of  its  expense.  The  main  reason  for  this  was 
undoubtedly  BufFon's  brilliant  style.  Not  only  did  he  produce  vivid  descrip- 
tions of  the  nature  and  habits  of  animals,  the  like  of  which  had  never  been 
read  before  and  seldom  have  been  equalled  since,  but  he  also  succeeded  in 
dealing  with  the  most  difficult  physical  and  cosmological  problems  in  a 


SEVENTEENTH     AND     EIGHTEENTH     CENTURIES      XZI 

clear  and  easily  comprehensive  style.  Moreover,  besides  these  external  quali- 
ties, his  work  possesses  immense  practical  advantages:  it  contains  the  idea 
of  a  new  and  magnificent  conception  of  natural  science,  and  particularly  of 
biology,  and  its  influence  on  the  future  development  of  the  latter  science  has 
been  exceedingly  great. 

BufTon  began  as  a  physicist;  as  we  have  already  seen,  he  translated  a 
work  of  Newton's,  and  he  also  studied  Leibniz;  he  had  at  once  been  struck 
by  the  wonderful  obedience  to  law  that,  according  to  the  then  new  physical 
and  astronomical  discoveries,  governs  the  universe.  In  the  light  of  these 
discoveries  the  cosmos  appears  as  a  mighty  piece  of  mechanism,  which  works 
according  to  given  laws,  and  in  which  both  the  past  and  the  future  can  be 
mathematically  calculated.  Is  it  not  likely  that  in  such  circumstances  the 
phenomena  here  on  earth,  both  in  inanimate  and  animate  nature,  would  also 
be  subject  to  a  similar  obedience  to  law?  That  is  the  question  Buffon  has  put; 
he  has  answered  it  in  the  affirmative  and  he  has  tried  to  give  proofs  of  it. 
His  lasting  service  to  science  lies  in  the  fact  that  he  thus  endeavoured  to 
incorporate  biological  phenomena  in  their  entirety  as  a  link  in  the  great  law- 
bound  world-process;  thereby  he  made  a  great  advance  towards  the  goal  that 
our  modern  natural  science  has  set  itself,  and  progressed  far  beyond  the  mech- 
anistic biologists  of  the  seventeenth  century,  the  Borellis,  the  Perraults,  and 
others  who  only  sought  to  apply  the  laws  of  mechanics  to  the  human  body, 
without  any  more  universal  objects  in  view.  That  Buffon,  with  the  limited 
material  of  facts  available,  could  not  succeed  in  creating  a  theory  capable  of 
passing  the  test  of  modern  knowledge  is  quite  obvious,  but  that  does  not 
prevent  us  from  acknowledging  the  greatness  inherent  in  his  very  ideas,  and 
the  ingenuity  with  which  he  attempted  to  carry  them  out. 

His  general  vieivs 
Buffon  introduces  his  natural  history  with  an  account  of  the  general  princi- 
ples on  which  he  considers  such  a  history  should  be  written.  Here  he  at  once 
expresses  his  view  of  nature  as  one  whole,  all  of  whose  forces  gear  into  one 
another  and  all  of  whose  manifestations  stand  in  mutual  causal  connexion. 
But  at  the  same  time  he  utters  a  warning,  in  words  reminiscent  of  Bacon, 
against  bringing  the  multiplicity  of  nature  under  too  simple  points  of  view; 
with  an  obvious  allusion  to  Linnasus  he  warns  us  against  those  who  speak, 
for  instance,  of  a  mineral  growing,  and  who  compare  in  detail  the  organs  of 
animals  with  those  of  plants;  it  is,  he  says,  trying  to  compel  nature  to  come 
under  our  arbitrary  laws,  not  ascribing  to  the  Creator  more  ideas  than  we 
ourselves  possess.  The  vast  wealth  of  nature  must  rather  be  realized  and  ac- 
knowledged from  the  beginning;  the  first  causes  of  its  phenomena  will  always 
be  hidden  from  us,  and  what  remains  to  be  done  is  to  observe  a  number  of 
particular  phenomena,  compare  them,  and  in  them  try  to  find  a  regular  course 
of  events.  It  is  thus  impossible  to  create  any  universal  system  covering  all 


±1.2.  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

natural  phenomena;  its  forms  and  manifestations  imperceptibly  merge  into 
one  another,  wherefore  vegetable  systems  in  particular,  such  as  those  set  up 
by  Tournefort  and  Linnaeus,  are  utterly  unnatural.  Buffon  is  very  keenly  op- 
posed to  Linnasus;  he  asks  ironically  what  is  the  use  of  the  sexual  system 
when  the  plants  have  ceased  to  flower.  In  fact,  the  whole  of  the  Linnasan 
system  of  species  classification  was  intrinsically  repugnant  to  Buffon;  it 
seemed  to  him  to  be  an  arbitrary  decimation  of  unified  nature  into  little  bits; 
Linnasus's  efforts  to  create  a  natural  system  and  his  emphasis  upon  the  in- 
completeness of  the  classification  system,  in  which  he  did  not  vary  very 
much  from  Buffon's  own  ideas,  were  simply  neglected  by  him;  apparently 
they  appeared  to  him  merely  as  slight  inconsistencies  in  a  falsely  founded 
view.  He  criticizes  Linn^eus's  animal  classification  with  similar  asperity  and 
undeniably  touches  its  weakest  point  when  he  rejects  the  two  great  classes, 
insects  and  worms;  no  one,  he  says,  can  imagine  that  crayfish  are  insects, 
and  shells  worms.  Instead  of  six  Linnasus  should  have  set  up  twelve  classes, 
or  even  still  more,  for  the  more  groups  there  are  the  nearer  we  arrive  at  the 
truth.  In  fact,  in  nature  there  are  only  individuals;  genera,  orders,  and  classes 
exist  only  in  our  imagination.  In  this  Buffon  is  undoubtedly  right  in  theory, 
but  he  overlooks  the  practical  advantage  of  the  "imagined"  categories, 
without  which  the  various  life -forms  could  not  possibly  be  dealt  with  by 
science.  Instead  of  the  artificial  classification-system  which  he  thus  rejects, 
Buffon  presents  an  introduction  to  the  study  of  nature  that,  to  some  extent, 
is  reminiscent  of  the  modern  intuitive  method  of  instruction;  the  description 
of  nature  should  follow  the  course  which  a  man  ought  to  pursue  if,  after 
having  forgotten  all  that  he  ever  knew,  he  were  put  in  a  place  surrounded 
by  natural  objects;  he  would  first  learn  to  differentiate  between  animals, 
plants,  and  stones,  and  then,  as  regards  animals,  he  would  observe  the  most 
essential  features  in  their  habitat  and  mode  of  life  and  would  group  the  in- 
dividual animals  accordingly  in  his  mind  and  finally  would  learn  to  compare 
the  different  animals  with  one  another  in  greater  detail,  first  distinguishing 
the  tame  animals  from  the  wild,  then  among  the  wild  those  who  lead  the 
same  mode  of  life  and  resemble  one  another  in  their  structure.  He  glorifies 
the  ancient  biologists  Aristotle  and  Pliny,  just  because  they  followed  a 
similar  natural  plan  of  dealing  with  living  creatures.  In  his  opinion,  how- 
ever, modern  research  should  in  no  way  confine  itself  merely  to  observing 
and  describing;  the  scientist  should  rather  confirm  his  observations  by  means 
of  experiment;  he  should  know  how  to  combine  observations  and  to  gen- 
eralize facts,  to  make  individual  phenomena  obedient  to  general  laws,  and, 
finally,  to  compare  the  most  comprehensive  phenomena  of  nature  with  one 
another.  The  ultimate  aim  is  to  bring  all  phenomena  under  the  general  laws 
of  physics,  those  laws  whose  causes  remain  incomprehensible  to  man,  while 
only  their  effects  are  perceptible.  Here  Buffon  has  undoubtedly  learnt  from 


SEVENTEENTH     AND     EIGHTEENTH     CENTURIES       ^2.3 
Newton  and,  either  through  him  or  directly  also,  from  Galileo;  at  any  rate, 
he  here  displays  an  insight  into  both  the  aims  and  the  limitations  of  natural 
science  that  few  scientists  before  his  age  possessed  and  that  many  have  lacked 
even  in  our  own  time. 

His  history  of  the  earth 
BuFFON,  having  thus  given  an  account  of  the  general  principles  on  which 
naturalists  should  work,  proceeds  to  give  a  theory  of  the  earth  and  its  de- 
velopment into  a  habitation  for  living  creatures.  This  problem  was  mani- 
festly of  very  great  interest  to  him;  in  fact  he  has  dealt  with  it  repeatedly  — 
in  an  essay  at  the  beginning  of  this  great  work,  called  "Theorie  de  la  terre," 
and  in  another,  more  extensive  essay,  written  considerably  later,  entitled 
"Des  epoques  de  la  nature."  In  this  sphere,  it  is  true,  he  had  precursors;  Steno, 
whose  geological  works  have  been  mentioned  previously,  Ray,  who  wrote 
a  treatise  on  the  changes  in  the  earth,  and,  the  greatest  genius  of  them  all, 
Swedenborg;^  but  Buffon  must  nevertheless  be  mentioned  as  the  first  who 
thought  to  investigate  the  earth's  history  with  special  reference  to  the 
development  of  living  creatures. 

Moreover,  in  his  latter  work  he  had  the  temerity  to  reject  the  biblical 
six-thousand-year  age  of  the  world  and  to  attribute  to  the  earth  a  far  higher 
age  —  certainly  small  in  comparison  with  the  length  of  the  epochs  which 
modern  geology  assumes,  but  at  least  entailing  a  break  with  the  till  then 
incontrovertible  theory  of  the  creation  —  a  break  induced  by  the  impossi- 
bility of  fitting  the  geological  and  biological  evolution  on  the  earth  within 
such  a  short  space  of  time  as  six  thousand  years.  Steno  had  already  faced  this 
dilemma,  but,  pious  Catholic  as  he  was,  he  preferred  to  abandon  geology 
rather  than  Church  doctrine;  BufFon  courageously  took  the  step  in  spite  of 
his  previous  contretemps  with  the  French  theologians.  Even  as  early  as  in  his 
"Theorie  de  la  terre"  he  expounds  his  ideas  as  to  the  origin  of  the  earth, 
expressly  emphasizing,  however,  their  purely  hypothetical  character.  He  as- 
sumes, in  agreement  with  Leibniz,  that  the  earth  evolved  from  an  incandes- 
cent state,  but  while  the  latter  believed  that  the  earth  itself  had  from  the 
beginning  been  a  "sun,"  Buffon  derives  it  from  the  sun's  mass,  assuming  that 
once  upon  a  time  a  comet  collided  with  the  sun,  with  the  result  that  pieces 
broke  off  which  gave  rise  to  the  earth  and  the  other  planets.  This  hypothesis 
has  often  been  cited  as  a  proof  of  Buffon' s  extravagant  imagination;  really, 
it  is  no  more  eccentric  than  many  contemporary  cosmogonies,  in  which 
comets  in  general  quite  often  played  a  part,  and  in  fact  Buffon's  is  presented 
with  much  more  reservation  than  the  others.  After  the  incandescent  state 
there  followed  a  period  when  the  seas  covered  the  earth,  when  the  tide 
exercised  great  influence  upon  earth-formation.  As  a  proof  of  this  theory  of 

^  Buffon  is  said  to  have  known  Swedenborg's  cosmological  theories;  he  never  quotes 
them,  however,  though  he  does  quote  Steno  and  Ray  and  some  other,  less  important  authors. 


Z2.4  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

the  seas'  wide  distribution  BufTon  cites  the  discovery  of  fossilized  marine 
animals,  especially  shells,  up  in  the  mountains,  and  even  the  stratified 
nature  of  the  geological  formation  in  general. ^  In  the  essay  "Epoques  de  la 
nature"  BufFon  divides  the  history  of  the  earth  into  seven  periods:  (i)  when 
the  earth  and  the  planets  were  formed,  (x)  when  the  great  mountain-ranges 
were  created,  (3)  when  water  covered  the  mainland,  (4)  when  the  water 
subsided  and  the  volcanoes  began  their  activity,  (5)  when  elephants  and 
other  tropical  animals  inhabited  the  North,  (6)  when  the  continents  were 
separated  from  one  another,  (7)  when  man  appeared.  It  would  take  too 
long  to  give  a  more  detailed  account  of  his  description  of  these  periods.  In 
this  geological  theory  he  makes  Vulcanism  in  general  play  a  more  important 
part  than  in  the  earlier  work,  and  the  tide  becomes  of  less  significance.  The 
greatest  service  he  rendered,  however,  is  that  he  clearly  realized  the  change 
in  the  animal  and  vegetable  kingdoms  from  epoch  to  epoch;  he  tried  to  work 
out  a  "natural  history  of  creation,"  based  on  law-bound  evolution;  he  specu- 
lates upon  the  origin  of  the  various  life-forms  and  the  place  of  their  appear- 
ance and  combines  these  two  circumstances  with  calculations  as  to  climatic 
changes  and  other  purely  physical  conditions  —  in  all  this  a  pioneer  of  the 
conception  of  nature  which  was  not  generally  accepted  until  a  century  after 
his  time. 

His  biological  theory 
BuFFON  has  expounded  his  biological  theories  in  a  volume  bearing  the  title 
Historic  naturelle  des  animaux.  It  begins  with  an  investigation  into  the  differ- 
ence between  animals,  vegetables,  and  minerals  and  establishes  the  fact  that 
there  is  no  absolutely  definite  boundary  between  the  animal  and  the  vegetable 
kingdoms,  but  that  transition  forms  may  exist;  common  to  both  kingdoms 
is  the  individuals'  power  of  giving  rise  by  means  of  reproduction  to  new 
individuals  like  themselves.  Another  common  property  is  the  power  of 
growth;  this  shows  that  a  fundamental  agreement  prevails  amongst  all  liv- 
ing creatures,  in  spite  of  differences  in  detail,  whereas  only  matter  as  a 
fundamental  substance  is  common  to  animate  and  inanimate  things.  Both 
animals  and  vegetables  arise  as  species,  the  criterion  of  which  is  that  they 
propagate;  on  the  other  hand,  there  is  no  question  of  a  common  creative 
origin.  On  the  whole  BufFon  refuses  to  see  in  the  origin  of  life  the  result  of  a 

^  As  an  example  of  the  lengths  to  which  it  was  still  possible  to  go  during  the  " '  enlightened 
eighteenth  century  in  explanation  of  natural  phenomena,  it  may  be  mentioned  that  Voltaire, 
who,  however,  would  pass  as  a  disciple  of  Newton's,  declared  that  Buffon's  theory  of  the  origin 
of  fossils  up  in  the  mountains  was  irrational;  the  shells  that  had  been  found  there  had  probably 
been  left  there  by  pilgrims  who  took  them  from  the  East.  The  two  geniuses  consequently  came 
into  serious  disagreement;  but  later  they  were  reconciled  and  Voltaire  declared  BufFon  to  be 
a  second  Archimedes.  Buffon  capped  this  compliment  with  the  assurance  that  no  one  would 
ever  be  called  Voltaire  the  Second.  Voltaire's  flattery  shows,  however,  that  BufFon  was  con- 
sidered, and  indeed  wished  to  be  considered,  primarily  a  physicist. 


SEVENTEENTH     AND     EIGHTEENTH     CENTURIES      1x5 

particular  act  of  creation;  life,  says  he,  is  not  a  metaphysical  characteristic 
of  living  creatures,  but  a  physical  quality  of  matter. 

Since,  then,  the  most  vital  quality  of  life  is  the  power  of  reproduction, 
Buffon  devotes  very  close  study  to  it.  For  this  purpose  he  does  not  start  from 
the  most  highly  organized  creatures,  but  begins  his  investigation  —  this, 
too,  a  modern  feature  —  with  the  most  primitive  form  of  reproduction  — 
that  by  means  of  division  in  plants  and  primitive  animals.  Why  is  it  that  a 
severed  branch  of  a  twig  of  a  tree  grows  up  into  a  new  tree,  that  a  piece  of 
polypus  gives  rise  to  a  new  polypus?  Buffon  answers  this  question  by  assum- 
ing that  the  plant  and  the  animal  are  composed  of  a  mass  of  particles  formed 
like  the  individual  in  its  entirety,  and  which  therefore,  when  they  become 
detached,  can  develop  further  and  form  a  new  individual  of  the  same  kind. 
This  theory  of  independent  particles,  the  idea  for  which  he  undoubtedly  got 
from  Leibniz's  monad  theory,  Buffon  further  develops  to  form  the  basis  of 
his  conception  of  all  the  phenomena  and  functions  of  life;  just  as  inanimate 
matter  is  composed  of  an  incalculable  mass  of  minute  particles,  so  there 
exists  in  nature  a  vast  number  of  organic  particles  that  are  animate  and 
formed  like  animate  beings.  '  'Just  as  there  may  be  required  perhaps  a  million 
minute  salt  cubes  to  form  one  grain  of  sea-salt,  so  it  would  take  millions  of 
organic  particles  similar  to  the  whole  to  form  a  bud  containing  the  individual 
of  a  tree  or  a  polypus."  By  making  this  assumption  Buffon  also  seeks  to  get 
rid  of  the  preformation  theory,  which  was  generally  embraced  by  his  con- 
temporaries and  which  he  keenly  criticizes,  maintaining  among  other  things 
that  it  would  presuppose  an  infinite  number  of  daughter  individuals  con- 
tained in  the  original  mother  animal,  which  in  itself  is  an  entirely  irrational 
supposition.  But  when  it  comes  to  setting  up  an  acceptable  theory  of  sexual 
reproduction  in  place  of  the  preformation  theory,  Buffon  comes  to  realize, 
as  he  himself  openly  acknowledges,  that  it  is  easier  to  destroy  than  to  build 
up.  He  founded  a  general  physiological  hypothesis  according  to  which 
animals  through  the  food  absorb  a  quantity  of  these  ubiquitous  organic 
particles  and  in  the  various  organs  of  the  body  assimilate  from  these  what  the 
body  requires;  whatever  is  left  is  collected  in  the  genital  organs  and  gives 
rise  to  individuals  like  the  parents.  That  the  embryo  is  thus  formed  by  a 
combination  of  a  mass  of  minute  independently  living  particles  he  believes 
to  be  proved  by  the  spermatozoa  existing  in  the  seminal  fluid;  that  the  female 
sexual  product  actually  consists  of  similar  minute  beings  he  also  believes  he 
had  proved  by  a  microscopical  study  of  the  ripe  follicles  in  the  mammalian 
ovary;  in  their  fluid  he  believed  that  he  had  found  mobile  life-elements 
similar  to  those  in  the  semen  which  he  actually  illustrates^  and  which  in  his 

^  What  Buffon  and  his  collaborators  —  he  quotes  several,  including  the  English  micro- 
scopist  Needham  —  actually  saw  in  the  follicular  fluid  it  is  difficult  to  say;  perhaps  detached 
cells  from  the  follicular  epithelium;  maybe  also  coagulation  products. 


il6  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

view  combine  with  the  spermatozoa  to  form  the  new  individual.  In  connexion 
with  the  question  of  evolution,  reproduction,  and  growth,  BufFon  sets  up  a 
very  abstract  and  difficult  hypothesis  concerning  the  mutual  connexion  of  the 
different  parts  within  the  organism;  he  believes  that  each  individual  repre- 
sents a  "moule  interieur,"  by  which  he  apparently  means  the  constant  form  of 
every  living  creature,  attained  with  the  co-operation  of  the  organs,  which 
are  fed  and  grow  by  assimilating  these  living  particles  that  fill  the  whole 
of  nature  and  are  the  one  essential  in  the  assimilation  of  food  —  of  both 
animals  and  vegetables  —  in  growth,  and  in  reproduction.  This  theory  of 
living  particles  thus  forms  the  very  corner-stone  of  Buffon's  biological 
speculation  and  is  both  its  strength  and  its  weakness;  with  its  aid  he  avoids 
the  difficulty  of  explaining  the  origin  of  life  without  the  assumption  of  a 
supernatural  act  of  creation  —  he  does  not  expressly  deny  such  an  act,  it  is 
true  (that  would  have  been  too  daring  for  his  age),  but  it  is  quite  obvious 
that  he  will  have  nothing  to  do  with  it  —  on  the  other  hand,  he  had  to  make 
good  with  assumptions  which  very  much  resemble  the  ancient  spontaneous- 
generation  hypotheses,  which  had  already  been  rejected  by  the  biologists  of 
the  seventeenth  century.  At  any  rate,  of  greater  value  than  the  results  of  these 
speculations  is  his  criticism  of  the  actual  method  of  natural  research,  which 
even  in  modern  times  makes  profitable  reading;  his  own  theories  he  in  no 
wise  propounds  as  if  they  were  proved  truths,  and  his  warnings  against  con- 
fusing hypotheses  and  facts  many  a  modern  biologist  might  well  take  seri- 
ously to  heart. 

Besides  these  purely  biological  questions  Buffon  also  discusses  psy- 
chological problems.  His  speculations  on  animal  psychology  are,  however, 
of  little  importance;  he  certainly  admits  the  existence  of  intelligence  in 
animals,  in  contrast  to  Descartes,  but  he  denies  that  they  possess  memory 
and  reflection.  On  the  other  hand  he  has  some  striking  observations  to  make 
on  the  domestic  animals'  intellectual  dependence  upon  human  training,  as 
well  as  on  their  sense-impressions  and  the  varying  power  of  the  latter. 

On  man 
Like  Linn^us,  Buffon  treats  man  as  a  natural-history  subject  and  gives  a 
detailed  description  of  man's  evolutional  history,  alimentary  conditions, 
and  habits  of  life,  which  has  justly  become  famous,  not  merely  for  its  impor- 
tant formal  merits,  but  also  as  being  the  first  attempt  at  anthropology  in  the 
modern  sense.  Though  human  anatomy  had  already  been  thoroughly  dealt 
with  in  the  sixteenth  and  seventeenth  centuries,  nevertheless  a  universal 
treatment  of  man  in  regard  to  his  entire  relation  to  nature  was  something 
quite  new.  From  an  anatomical  and  physiological  point  of  view  he  certainly 
has  not  very  much  that  is  fresh  to  relate,  but  he  conscientiously  and  critically 
summarizes  the  existing  scientific  material;  he  gives  an  account  of  the  devel- 
opment of  man  from  embryonic  life  through  the  various  ages;  he  tries  to 


SEVENTEENTH  AND  EIGHTEENTH  CENTURIES  2.Z7 
analyse  the  growth  of  speech  in  the  child,  and  the  influence  of  mental  emo- 
tions upon  facial  expression;  he  discusses  the  power  of  mental  perceptions  to 
reproduce  reality  and  insists  on  science's  dependence  upon  them.  He  investi- 
gates the  circumstances  of  death  at  various  ages;  he  gives  statistics  showing 
the  mortality  in  certain  French  provinces  and  seeks  with  the  aid  of  "proba- 
bility calculations"  to  ascertain  the  longevity  of  various  ages;  he  compiles 
data  with  regard  to  the  peculiarities  of  wild  tribes  and  abnormal  phenomena 
in  civilized  peoples.  Above  all,  he  maintains  that  man  has  his  bodily  func- 
tions in  common  with  the  animals,  but  that,  on  the  other  hand,  there  is  a 
fundamental  psychical  difference  between  them,  which  renders  it  impossible 
to  compare  human  and  animal  intellectual  qualities. 

His  Xoogra-phy 
Of  the  animals  Buffon,  as  already  mentioned,  had  time  to  complete  only  the 
quadrupeds  and  birds,  which  are  dealt  with  in  detailed  monographs  covering 
each  species.  Naturally,  these  are  each  of  varying  value;  all  of  them  however 
share  in  common  a  brilliant  exposition  and  a  universal  treatment  of  the  sub- 
ject, in  striking  contrast  both  to  the  earlier  zoographers'  motley  mass  of 
notes  and  to  Linnasus's  brief,  summary  diagnoses.  As  a  describer  of  nature 
Buffon  is  of  fundamental  importance,  in  certain  respects  still  unexcelled.  It 
would  take  too  long  to  enter  into  the  peculiarities  of  his  zoography;  it  need 
only  be  pointed  out  that  it  is  not  merely  formal  services  that  have  earned  it 
its  well-merited  fame,  but  in  many  of  his  descriptions,  particularly  in  those 
of  birds,  there  are  a  number  of  keen  and  striking  detailed  observations  as  to 
mode  of  life,  reproduction,  and  other  biologically  interesting  factors. 

Daubenton  s  cofnparative  anatomy 
To  each  monograph  on  mammalian  animals  Buffon 's  collaborator,  Dauben- 
ton, has  added  an  account  of  the  animal's  anatomy.  By  way  of  introduction 
he  sets  forth  the  principles  on  which  to  base  this  kind  of  general  —  nowa- 
days we  should  say  "comparative"  —  anatomy,  in  contrast  to  the  descrip- 
tive, which  had  hitherto  been  practised.  He  considers  that  all  animals  should 
be  investigated  in  respect  of  their  most  vital  organs  —  bone-structure,  heart, 
brain,  respiratory,  digestive,  excretive,  and  sexual  organs  —  and  the  results 
thus  obtained  compared.  Following  this  principle,  an  account  is  given  of 
every  mammal's  anatomy,  particularly  the  bone-structure:  the  bone-struc- 
ture of  the  horse  is  compared  in  detail  with  that  of  man,  and  the  bones  of 
other  animal  species  are  mutually  compared.  Such  a  comparative  examination 
of  the  anatomy  of  various  animals  carried  out  on  a  uniform  plan  was  at  that 
period  something  new  and  proved  of  great  significance  for  the  future;  the 
part  played  by  comparative  anatomy  in  modern  biology  is  too  well  known  to 
need  any  special  emphasis  here. 

Thus  Buffon  carried  out  his  plan  of  presenting  nature,  both  inanimate 
and  animate,  as  one  whole,  evolved  and  held  together  by  purely  mechanical 


1X8  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

laws.  In  this,  however,  he  was  not  entirely  consistent.  In  a  curious  treatise 
entitled  Homo  duplex  he  has  described  man  as  composed  of  two  principles, 
fundamentally  distinct  from  one  another,  one  spiritual  and  the  other  material, 
of  which  the  material  develops  first  and  predominates  in  the  embryonic  stage 
and  during  childhood,  while  the  spiritual  appears  later  and  is  developed  by 
means  of  education  and  training,  without  which  it  would  lead  to  stupidity 
and  vain  delusions.  This  dualistic  conception  of  man  might  well  appear  to  be 
fully  in  accordance  with  the  principles  that  had  till  then  been  and  were  still 
at  that  time  officially  recognized  —  it  might  be  suspected  that  BufFon  here 
made  a  concession  to  the  ecclesiastical  authorities  who  had  persecuted  him  — 
had  not  the  style  of  the  whole  been  so  utterly  different  from  all  that  is  under- 
stood by  conventional  religion.  Instead  we  here  come  across  a  trait  in  Buffon 
which  we  should  not  expect  to  find  in  that  exceedingly  brilliant  and  suc- 
cessful man  —  namely,  a  deep  pessimism.  To  his  mind,  the  contrast  between 
spiritual  and  material  appears  most  marked  in  those  attacks  of  melancholy 
and  listlessness  when  one  lacks  all  power  of  decision,  when  one  "does  what 
one  would  not  and  would  do  what  one  does  not ' ' :  when  one  feels  that  the 
personality  is  divided  into  two,  of  which  the  one  part,  reason,  indicts  the 
other  without  being  able  to  overcome  its  resistance;  sometimes  reason  wins, 
and  then  one  performs  one's  duties  gladly;  sometimes  the  flesh  wins,  and 
then  one  indulges  in  pleasure,  but  sooner  or  later  these  unhappy  hours  and 
days  return  when  disharmony  prevails.  Especially  vivid  is  the  passage  in 
which  Buffon  describes  how  love,  which  makes  animals  happy,  simply 
makes  men  wretched;  in  words  of  wild  despair  he  depicts  the  vainness  and 
folly  of  this  passion,  which  certainly  brings  with  it  bodily  satisfaction,  but 
is  morally  valueless  and  only  calls  forth  jealousy  and  other  degenerate  feel- 
ings. This  melancholy  conception  of  life  was,  as  a  matter  of  fact,  in  no  way 
peculiar  to  Buffon;  it  was,  on  the  contrary,  as  we  shall  see  later  on,  a  wide- 
spread view  during  the  epoch  to  which  he  belonged. 

Buffon' s  influence 
Buffon  has  played  a  fundamental  part  in  the  history  of  biology,  not  on  ac- 
count of  the  discoveries  he  made,  but  on  account  of  the  new  ideas  he  produced. 
Those  ideas  that  he  brought  out,  which  he  was  able  only  imperfectly  to 
realize  in  detail,  have  since  then  been  taken  up  by  others,  who,  having  better 
opportunities  for  obtaining  actual  scientific  material,  have  applied  them  in  a 
wider  sense:  thus,  Cuvier,  the  pioneer  of  comparative  anatomy  and  paleon- 
tology, adopted  many  of  Buffon's  fundamental  ideas;  similarly  Bichat,  the 
originator  of  the  tissue  theory,  in  his  sphere,  as  well  as  Lamarck,  with  his 
theories  of  the  evolution  of  living  organisms,  in  that  field,  has  manifestly 
felt  the  influence  of  Buffon's  speculations.  Through  these  scientists  many  of 
the  ideas  produced  by  Buffon  have  now  been  incorporated  in  the  general 
knowledge  of  natural  science.  If  in  spite  of  this  he  has  often  been  depicted, 


SEVENTEENTH     AND     EIGHTEENTH     CENTURIES      ^19 

especially  beyond  the  borders  of  France,  as  a  talented  dilettante,  a  witty 
popular  scientist  and  writer,  this  is  mainly  due  to  the  relations  in  which  he 
stood,  both  in  his  lifetime  and  long  afterwards,  to  the  representatives  of  the 
Linnnsan  system  of  classification;  these  latter,  who  for  a  long  time  felt  that 
they  were  the  sole  upholders  of  a  truly  exact  natural  science,  looked  compas- 
sionately down  upon  BufTon's  unsystematic  descriptions  and  imaginative 
speculations.  When,  then,  the  dominion  of  Linnasanism  fell,  the  comparative 
and  speculative  lines  of  research  which  succeeded  it  already  possessed  entirely 
different  intellectual  material  to  build  upon,  and  Buffon's  theories  thereafter 
necessarily  appeared  vague  and  childish.  His  services,  however,  must  in  all 
fairness  be  duly  acknowledged;  in  the  purely  theoretical  sphere  he  was  the 
foremost  biologist  of  the  eighteenth  century,  the  one  who  possessed  the 
greatest  wealth  of  ideas,  of  real  benefit  to  subsequent  ages  and  exerting  an 
influence  stretching  far  into  the  future. 


CHAPTER    IX 

INVERTEBRATE     RESEARCH     IN     THE     EIGHTEENTH     CENTURY 

Successors  of  the  great  seventeenth-century  biologists 

THE  EIGHTEENTH  CENTURY  displays  OH  the  whole  great  activity  in  the 
sphere  of  the  natural  sciences.  In  physics  and  chemistry  the  successors 
of  Newton  and  Stahl  worked  at  extending  the  spheres  to  which 
their  masters  had  opened  the  way.  In  the  realm  of  biology  Linnasus  and  his 
disciples  held  sway  and  were  fully  occupied  in  incorporating  known  species 
into  the  system  and  in  discovering  fresh  ones.  As  already  mentioned,  Buffon's 
activities  belonged  rather  to  the  future.  But  besides  this  there  worked  during 
the  eighteenth  century  a  number  of  naturalists  whose  achievements  connected 
them  more  or  less  directly  with  the  great  biologists  of  the  preceding  century. 
Towards  these  pioneer  anatomists,  microscopists,  and  physiologists  their 
successors  during  the  eighteenth  century  have  to  some  extent  the  character  of 
Epigoni:  they  made  no  such  epoch-making  discoveries  as  Harvey's  or  Mal- 
pighi's,  but,  on  the  other  hand,  they  took  advantage  in  many  and  various 
ways  of  the  discoveries  that  had  already  been  made;  the  problems  which 
had  already  been  of  direct  importance  were  discussed  from  various  points  of 
view,  while  at  the  same  time  ideas  were  expressed  in  more  than  one  field  of 
research  which  gave  a  presage  of  future  ends  to  be  gained.  Malpighi's  and 
Swammerdam's  investigations  into  the  anatomy  of  the  lower  animals  were 
thus  resumed  and  carried  a  step  further,  as  also  Borelli's  and  his  successors' 
physiological  work;  Leeuwenhoek's  and  de  Graaf's  discoveries  in  the  field 
of  reproduction  were  elaborated,  and  the  discussion  between  the  animalcul- 
ists  and  the  ovists  went  on,  particularly  in  the  first  half  of  the  eighteenth 
century,  with  undiminished  liveliness;  the  epigenesis  and  preformation  theo- 
ries were  also  keenly  debated,  although  at  first  with  the  balance  decidedly 
in  favour  of  the  supporters  of  preformation.  Later  in  the  century,  however, 
contributions  were  made  in  these  very  spheres  which  put  a  different  complex- 
ion on  those  questions.  And  even  for  several  other  spheres  of  biology  the 
latter  half  of  the  eighteenth  century  represents  a  period  of  decisive  prepara- 
tion for  the  development  that  took  place  during  the  nineteenth  century.  — 
In  the  following  paragraphs  we  shall  review,  to  begin  with,  some  of  the 
more  important  contributions  to  the  biology  of  the  lower  animals,  and 
afterwards  the  advances  made  in  the  spheres  of  anatomy,  physiology,  and 
evolution. 

130 


SEVENTEENTH  AND  EIGHTEENTH  CENTURIES  131 
Rene  Antoine  Ferchault  de  Reaumur  was  born  of  noble  and  wealthy 
parents  in  the  year  1683.  He  received  his  education  at  a  Jesuit  college,  after- 
wards studying  jurisprudence  in  Paris,  but  he  soon  abandoned  that  career  and 
applied  himself  whole-heartedly  to  natural  science.  Having  inherited  a  for- 
tune, he  was  able  to  lead  the  life  of  a  private  scholar;  membership  in  the 
French  Academy  of  Science  was  the  only  distinction  he  obtained.  He  died  in 

1757- 

Reaumur  was  active  in  many  branches  of  natural  science,  both  theoreti- 
cal and  applied.  He  invented  improved  methods  of  iron-refining  and  made 
important  contributions  to  our  knowledge  of  the  expansion  of  gases  and 
fluids  and  of  specific  heat.  He  is  best  known  for  his  invention  of  the  eighty- 
degree  thermometer  scale,  which  bears  his  name  and  which  is  still  used  in 
many  countries.  In  biology,  too,  his  activities  have  been  many-sided  and 
important.  His  greatest  and  most  famous  work  is  his  Memoires  pour  servir  a 
rhistoire  des  insectes,  a  work  in  six  large  quarto  volumes.  This  work  is  un- 
doubtedly of  fundamental  importance  in  insect  biology  and  is  in  fact  one  of 
the  most  monumental  works  written  in  this  field  of  research.  It  offers  a 
number  of  extremely  valuable  contributions  to  the  knowledge  of  the  anatomi- 
cal structure  of  the  insects,  their  evolutional  history  and  conditions  of  life. 
His  chief  master  is  Swammerdam,  whose  system  he  in  the  main  adopts,  but 
he  considerably  widens  the  sphere  of  the  latter's  researches.  True,  he  did 
not  possess  the  master's  incomparable  ability  in  the  work  of  preparing  mater- 
ial, but  instead  he  had  at  his  disposal  a  greater  wealth  of  material  for  his 
researches,  while  a  long  life  made  it  possible  for  him  to  carry  out  lengthy 
and  laborious  series  of  observations  and  experiments  on  the  living  habits  of 
insects.  The  community  life  of  the  social  insects,  in  particular  of  the  bees, 
the  development  of  the  parasitic  Hymenoptera,  and  the  activities  of  leaf- 
mining  and  gall-forming  in  ects  may  be  specially  mentioned  among  the  sub- 
jects dealt  with  by  Reaumur  in  his  great  work  —  subjects  to  which  he  made 
important  contributions.  Besides  these  his  book  contains  a  mass  of  valuable 
detailed  descriptions  of  larval  and  imaginal  forms  from  practically  all  in- 
sect groups. 

Reaumur's  physiological  researches 
Moreover,  outside  the  sphere  of  insects  he  has  presented  biology  with  the 
results  of  important  discoveries.  Thus,  he  has  established  the  fact  that  the 
shell  of  molluscs  is  formed  by  means  of  a  secretive  process,  and  in  connexion 
therewith  he  studied  the  formation  of  pearls  in  mussels.  He  studied  also  the 
movements  of  a  number  of  primitive  animal  forms,  he  investigated  the  elec- 
tric phenomena  in  the  ray,  and  he  further  observed  the  regeneration  of  the 
extremities  and  other  parts  of  the  body  of  crayfish,  in  regard  to  this  latter 
phenomenon  producing  a  theory  reminiscent  of  Buffon's  hypothesis  as  to  the 
body's  being  composed  of  organized  particles.  And,  finally,  he  carried  out 


132.  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

several  interesting  experiments  on  the  digestion,  principally  on  the  influence 
of  the  gastric  juices;  he  obtained  gastric  juice  from  a  chicken  by  letting  the 
bird  swallow  a  sponge  attached  to  a  piece  of  thread,  with  which  the  sponge 
was  after  a  time  recovered  from  the  stomach  drenched  with  gastric  juice, 
which  was  afterwards  used  for  the  purpose  of  acting  upon  various  kinds  of 
food  substances.  Among  his  contemporaries  he  justly  enjoyed  a  great  reputa- 
tion; Linnasus  cites  him  often  and  with  recognition,  while  he  had  many 
pupils,  of  whom  de  Geer  in  particular  at  once  carried  on  his  work. 

Charles  de  Geer  was  born  in  172.0  at  Finspong,  in  the  Swedish  province 
of  Ostergotland.  He  was  a  descendant  of  the  rich  merchant  and  manufacturer 
Louis  de  Geer,  who  had  emigrated  from  Holland,  and  consistently  with  his 
family's  origin  he  received  his  education  in  that  country.  He  studied  at  the 
University  of  Utrecht,  where  he  devoted  himself  to  both  physics  and  biology. 
As  a  child  he  inherited  Lovsta  Foundry,  in  Uppland,  and  as  soon  as  he  came 
of  age  he  took  over  its  management.  He  introduced  a  number  of  improve- 
ments in  the  iron-manufacture  and  thereby  acquired  considerable  wealth. 
Regarded  as  one  of  the  richest  and  most  brilliant  noblemen  in  Sweden,  he 
became  in  course  of  time  Court  Marshal  and  baron  and  received  many  other 
distinctions.  He  showed  great  consideration  for  his  workers,  founding  schools 
for  their  benefit  and  improving  their  wage  conditions.  He  was  highly 
reputed  in  scientific  circles  in  Europe  and  was  a  member  of  several  learned 
societies.  He  died  in  1778. 

At  an  early  age  de  Geer  had  been  interested  in  entomology.  In  this  field 
he  continued  the  investigations  begun  by  Reaumur,  and  published  under  the 
same  title  a  sequel  to  the  latter's  great  work,  which  it  in  every  way  equals 
in  value.  It  comprised  seven  volumes,  containing  observations  upon  the 
systematic  classification  of  insects,  their  habits  of  life  and  evolutionary  his- 
tory. Although  contemporary  with  Linn^us,  de  Geer  did  not  adopt  his 
nomenclature,  but  retained  the  old  method  of  characterizing  the  species  by 
means  of  diagnoses.  Otherwise  he  was  a  keen  observer,  who  in  more  spheres 
than  one  made  contributions  of  lasting  value,  not  least  in  regard  to  the 
lower  and  hitherto  neglected  insect-forms. 

Among  the  naturalists  who  during  this  period  made  valuable  contribu- 
tions to  the  knowledge  of  the  lower  animals  should  also  be  mentioned 
Abraham  Trembley  (1700-84).  He  was  born  at  Geneva,  studied  first  of  all 
there,  then  in  Holland  and  England,  was  for  a  time  private  tutor  in  certain 
distinguished  families,  and  finally  became  a  librarian  in  his  native  town.  His 
reputation  as  a  biologist  is  based  upon  his  important  monograph  on  the 
fresh-water  polypi.  In  this  work  he  gives  a  careful  account  of  a  number  of 
"polypus-forms"  —  he  includes  both  Hydra  and  Plumatella  in  the  same 
genus.  He  closely  studied  their  habits,  particularly  their  movements  and 
food,  and  was,  properly  speaking,  the  first  who  clearly  realized  their  animal 


SEVENTEENTH     AND     EIGHTEENTH     CENTURIES       133 
character.  He  observed  their  natural  propagation,  but  above  all  he  carried 
out  systematic  and  extensive  experiments  in  regard  to  their  power  of  re- 
generation, thereby  opening  up  for  research  a  field  that  has  been  cultivated, 
especially  in  modern  times,  with  splendid  results. 

August  Roesel  von  Rosenhof  (1705-59)  was  born  in  Thuringia,  but 
worked  mostly  at  Nuremberg,  first  of  all  as  a  painter  an-d  afterwards  as  a 
naturalist.  Under  the  striking  title  of  Monafliche  Insectenbelustigungen  he 
published  in  the  seventeen-fifties  a  series  of  observations  on  the  life  of  the 
lower  animals,  illustrated  with  beautiful  engravings  done  by  himself.  A 
number  of  sound  detailed  observations  regarding  the  life-habits  and  develop- 
ment of  insects  are  given  in  these  writings,  but  he  paid  special  attention  to 
the  evolutionary  history  of  frogs,  from  their  mating  and  egg-laying  through 
all  their  larval  stages,  and  has  thus  given  to  posterity  valuable  additions 
to  the  knowledge  of  these  creatures,  which,  as  is  well  known,  are  much  used 
in  modern  experimental  physiology.    - 

Pierre  Lyonet  (1707-89)  was  also  a  highly  reputed  biologist  among  his 
contemporaries.  Born  at  The  Hague  of  French  parents,  he  was  given  a  very 
extensive  education;  he  was  a  brilliant  linguist  and  at  one  time  followed  the 
career  of  a  diplomat.  As  a  biologist  he  applied  himself  most  actively  to  the 
sphere  of  insect-anatomy,  in  the  spirit  of  Swammerdam;  an  admirable  work 
of  unsurpassed  brilliance  even  in  our  own  time  is  his  great  monograph  on  the 
larva  of  Cossus  lig?iiperda  or  goat-moth  caterpillar,  the  anatomy  of  which  he 
studied  and  illustrated  with  extraordinary  conscientiousness  and  keenness  of 
observation 


CHAPTER    X 

EXPERIMENTAL     AND     SPECULATIVE     BIOLOGY     IN     THE 
EIGHTEENTH     CENTURY 

BESIDES  THESE  MONOGRAPHisTs,  who  Were  highly  regarded  in  their  own 
day  and  are  still  well  worth  reading  even  nowadays,  there  lived  dur- 
ing the  eighteenth  century  many  scientists  whose  works  embraced 
fields  of  research  of  wide  extent  in  regard  to  both  the  material  investigated 
and  the  problems  dealt  with.  In  particular,  experimental  biology  and  theo- 
retical questions  in  connexion  therewith  were  developed  on  a  considerable 
scale  during  this  period  by  scientists  who  have  merited  the  attention  both  of 
their  own  age  and  of  posterity.  Foremost  among  these  should  be  mentioned 
Haller,  a  great  man  in  his  own  age  and  a  scientist  for  all  time,  famous  as 
a  botanist,  anatomist,  physiologist,  statesman,  and  poet. 

Albrecht  von  Haller  was  born  at  Berne  in  1707.  His  father  was  a 
wealthy  and  highly  reputed  lawyer,  who  gave  his  son  a  thorough  education, 
at  first  in  his  own  home  with  a  private  tutor,  then  at  the  University  of  Tub- 
ingen, and  finally  at  Leyden  under  Boerhaave.  Young  Albrecht  was  an  infant 
prodigy;  at  the  age  of  ten  he  had  a  thorough  knowledge  of  Greek  and 
Hebrew,  at  fifteen  he  had  written  an  epic  poem  and  some  tragedies,  at  nine- 
teen he  was  a  doctor  of  medicine.  It  was  obvious  that  a  young  man  thus 
equipped  would  in  time  become  something  quite  out  of  the  ordinary;  un- 
fortunately, as  so  often  happens,  none  of  the  successes  that  he  actually  at- 
tained fully  reached  the  height  of  his  dreams.  Having  taken  his  degree, 
Haller  studied  for  a  time  in  Paris,  afterwards  settling  down  in  Berne  as  a 
physician.  He  there  became  universally  known  as  a  botanist  and  poet  and  in 
1736  was  appointed  a  professor  of  medicine  at  the  then  newly-founded 
University  of  Gottingen,  where  he  did  splendid  work;  he  laid  out  a  botanical 
garden  and  built  an  anatomical  theatre,  founded  a  still  existing  and  much 
thought-of  scientific  society,  and  besides  found  time  for  scientific  author- 
ship of  an  extraordinarily  many-sided  character.  But  he  never  won  content- 
ment; he  was  troubled  with  melancholy  and  a  longing  for  his  native  country, 
and  finally  he  resigned  his  professorship  and  returned  home  to  Berne  (in 
1753).  There  he  was  elected  to  the  municipal  council  and  made  a  name  as 
a  distinguished  official;  his  services  were  utilized  as  a  diplomat  and  he  per- 
formed his  duties  in  that  capacity  with  honour.  Meanwhile  he  continued 
his  scientific  writing  with  undiminished  zeal;  his  productivity  was  nothing 

^34 


o 

2 

w 

H 

C/5 

D 
< 

O 
U 


O 


f«^  /-^ 


fpii 


ay 


.^^ 


SEVENTEENTH  AND  EIGHTEENTH  CENTURIES  2.35 
short  of  amazing;  a  list  of  his  writings  gives  a  total  of  650,  among  them 
many  very  extensive  works.  But  during  this  period  the  melancholy  that 
had  pursued  him  since  his  youth  increased.  He  felt  dissatisfied  with  the  re- 
sults he  obtained,  as  also  with  the  new  ideas  that  were  becoming  more  and 
more  common.  In  particular,  the  increasing  free-thinking  in  the  world 
troubled  him  and  called  forth  a  number  of  pamphlets  in  defence  of  Chris- 
tianity from  his  hand.  He  himself,  however,  in  spite  of  his  firm  belief  in 
the  Gospel,  had  no  internal  peace,  but  ruminated  over  the  Tightness  of  what 
he  had  done  in  his  life;  the  vivisections  which  he  had  performed,  and  which 
always  troubled  his  sensitive  mind,  now  appeared  to  be  specially  repugnant 
to  him.  After  some  years  of  decline  in  health  he  died  in  1777. 

In  his  youth  Haller  devoted  himself  principally  to  botany  and  verse- 
writing.  This,  of  course,  is  not  the  place  to  criticize  his  poetry;  this  much, 
however,  may  be  mentioned,  that  he  is  considered  to  have  discovered  the 
poetical  value  of  Alpine  beauty;  otherwise  his  poems  are  now  read  apparently 
only  by  students  of  literature.  As  a  botanist  Haller  appears  in  conscious 
rivalry  with  Linnasus;  he  seeks  to  set  up,  in  opposition  to  Linnaeus 's  arti- 
ficial system,  a  natural  system  based  primarily  on  the  character  of  the  fruit. 
It  was  not  successful;  Linnxus's  investigations  into  the  possibilities  of  the 
natural  system  clearly  proved  that  the  time  was  not  yet  ripe  for  such  a  one, 
whereas  the  sexual  system  in  every  respect  fulfilled  the  requirements  of  the 
period.  Haller  was  embittered  by  defeat;  and  although  his  criticism  of  his 
successful  rival  may  be  partially  justified,  nevertheless  his  disappointment 
over  his  failure  is  clearly  apparent.  1  In  actual  fact  the  two  rivals  were  in- 
commensurable; in  contrast  to  Haller's  magnificent  but  divided  many-sided- 
ness is  Linn^us's  consummate  limitation  —  the  former  never  touched 
supremacy  at  any  point;  the  latter  possessed  only  one  sphere,  but  there  he 
was  master. 

Haller' s  physiological  researches 
The  branch  of  biology  in  which  Haller  made  his  finest  contribution  is  un- 
doubtedly physiology;  in  this  field  he  has  not  only  developed  the  method, 
he  also  established  new  and  important  facts,  made  valuable  additions  of  a 
purely  theoretical  nature,  and  finally  compiled  the  results  hitherto  attained 
in  a  comprehensive  manner,  which  should  be  a  pattern  for  all  time.  His 
writings  on  this  subject  consist  partly  of  a  mass  of  articles  written  for  jour- 
nals, in  which  he  recorded  the  results  of  his  direct  observations,  partly  of  an 
immense  physiological  compendium,  and,  finally,  of  a  smaller  and  extremely 
concise  handbook  on  physiology,  which  was  still  in  use  for  educational 
purposes  until  the  nineteenth  century.  In  the  foreword  to  the  last-mentioned 

1  Curiously  enough,  Haller  published  his  bitterest  attacks  against  Linnxus  in  the  form  of 
a  series  of  disputations  (Dubia  exLinnai  fundamentis  hausta,  Gottingen,  175 1-3)  which  purported 
to  have  been  written  by  his  son,  a  young  medical  student. 


Z36  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

work  he  defines  physiology  as  "  animata  anato??ie,"  a  vitalized  anatomy,  and 
it  is  in  fact  the  phenomena  of  life  that  he  seeks  to  discover  in  his  special 
investigations.  The  most  remarkable  of  these  is  without  doubt  his  treatise 
on  the  irritable  and  sensible  parts  of  the  body,  which  he  published  simul- 
taneously in  several  languages.  In  this  investigation  he  first  establishes  the 
fact  that  the  organs  of  the  body  are  partly  irritable,  partly  non-irritable; 
why  this  is  so,  science  cannot  discover;  it  can  only  show  that  it  is  so.  As 
irritable  (jnitahilis)  he  mentions  such  a  part  of  the  body  as  contracts  upon 
being  touched;  as  sensible  (sensibiUs),  again,  he  defines  a  part  of  the  body, 
contact  with  which  induces  an  impression  in  the  mind.  Which  organs  belong 
to  the  one  or  the  other  category  is  a  question  which  can  be  answered 
only  by  experiment.  The  performing  of  such  experiments  on  live  animals 
Haller  finds  highly  revolting,  but  in  the  interests  of  truth  it  cannot  in  this 
case  be  avoided.  Thus  he  has  proved  that,  of  the  two  layers  of  skin,  the 
epidermis  is  non-sensitive,  the  cutis  on  the  other  hand  has  feeling,  and  adi- 
pose tissue  is  non-sensitive.  Muscles  are  sensible,  but  this  is  due  not  to  the 
actual  muscular  substance,  but  to  the  nerves  which  are  in  connexion  there- 
with; the  tendons,  again,  are  non-sensible,  because  they  are  not  connected 
with  nerves.  Bones  and  periosteum  are  insensible,  the  cerebral  membrane, 
the  peritoneum,  and  the  veins  likewise.  The  intestines  are  sensible,  but  not 
the  liver,  the  spleen,  or  the  kidneys.  Irritability  exists  in  muscles,  but  is 
induced  through  the  nervous  system;  thus  the  diaphragm  has  been  made 
to  contract  by  irritating  a  severed  nerve.  Therefore  the  irritability  cannot 
have  anything  to  do  with  the  mind,  for  that  is  indivisible.  Haller  then  enu- 
merates a  number  of  irritable  organs  —  veins,  intestines,  sexual  organs.  Fi- 
nally he  discusses  the  question  of  what  it  is  that  induces  irritability.  Muscle 
is  composed  of  lime  and  earth;  if  it  is  asked  which  component  part  is  irritable, 
the  answer  must  be  the  lime.  Lastly  he  deals  with  the  question  of  vital 
organs,  which  serve  the  unconscious  manifestations  of  life,  and  voluntary 
organs,  which  serve  the  will. 

The  investigation  here  referred  to  must  without  doubt  be  regarded  as 
one  of  those  that  have  led  biology  into  new  directions.  Not  only  the  scheme 
of  the  work,  but  also  the  method  of  presentation  he  employs  and  the  con- 
clusions he  draws  are  each  of  fundamental  importance;  irritability  and  sen- 
sibility are  facts,  which  hold  true  to  this  very  day,^  and  the  experimental 
method  by  means  of  which  the  phenomena  have  been  established  is  still 
used  today.  There  occur,  indeed,  in  the  examples  just  given  one  or  two  actual 
mistakes  —  thus  the  peritoneum  is,  as  a  matter  of  fact,  sensible  and  the  in- 
testines insensible  —  while  the  actual  theoretical  treatment  suffers  from  the 

^  Instead  of  irritability  the  characteristic  property  of  muscle  is  nowadays  termed  "con- 
tractility." Haller's  irritability  theory  was  later  applied  without  distinction  to  various  organs 
in  the  body,  thereby  causing  considerable  confusion. 


SEVENTEENTH  AND  EIGHTEENTH  CENTURIES  137 
fact  that  Haller  did  not  succeed  in  producing  any  term  for  tissue  —  muscles, 
intestines,  and  other  viscera  are  quoted  as  organs  of  the  same  category. 
Moreover,  the  chemical  basis  of  his  muscular  theory,  the  composition  of 
lime  and  earth,  is  extremely  primitive.  But  in  spite  of  all  this  Haller,  as 
a  result  of  his  work  in  this  field,  has  won  a  brilliant  name  in  the  history 
of  science. 

His  comfendiums  of  physiology 
The  compendiums  which  Haller  produced  still  further  extended  the  services 
he  has  rendered  to  the  development  of  biology.  In  the  two  works  on  general 
physiology  cited  above  he  has  summarized  all  the  then  known  physiological 
facts  in  a  concise  and  easily  accessible  form.  He  starts  by  taking  the  simplest 
component  parts  of  the  body,  which  are  divided  into  solid  and  fluid.  The 
simplesi^elements  of  the  solid  components  are,  according  to  him,  the  fibres, 
the  composition  of  which  has  already  been  mentioned  —  lime  and  earth. 
By  cell-tissue,  a  word  which  often  occurs,  is  meant  what  modern  histology 
terms  adipose  tissue.  Haller  considers  the  most  vital  part  of  the  organism 
to  be  the  blood-vessel  system;  it  represents  the  element  that  connects  together 
his  whole  physiological  theory.  In  his  description  of  each  organ  he  always 
starts  with  its  blood-vessels.  The  more  blood-vessels  an  organ  has,  the  more 
important  it  is.  Of  the  thyreoidea  he  says  that  we  do  not  know  its  fuxiction, 
but  it  must  be  an  important  one,  since  the  organ  in  question  is  so  rich  in 
blood-vessels.  Out  of  the  blood  are  produced  all  the  fluids  of  the  body  in 
an  entirely  direct  manner;  thus  he  claims  to  have  found  direct  passages  be- 
tween the  arteries  and  the  salivary  ducts  in  the  salivary  gland;  even  the 
lymph  he  believes  to  emanate  from  the  arteries.  The  purpose  of  respiration 
is  to  give  the  blood  warmth.  Haller  was  keenly  interested  in  the  structure 
of  the  brain,  but  the  results  he  attained  are  not  to  be  compared  with  those 
gained  by  Swedenborg  at  the  same  time  on  purely  speculative  lines.  Haller 
has  only  vague  ideas  on  the  cerebral  cortex;  the  medulla  is  the  most  vital 
part  of  the  brain,  and,  in  his  view,  the  nerves  are  filled  with  a  fluid  which 
gives  rise  to  mental  impressions.  Towards  many  of  the  biological  points  of 
dispute  of  his  own  time  Haller  tries  to  adopt  a  somewhat  neutral  attitude; 
as,  for  instance,  in  the  dispute  between  the  ovists  and  the  animalculists, 
in  which,  however,  he  sided  on  the  whole  with  the  latter,  since  he  held 
that  the  spermium —  "  vermiculus  seminalis,"  as  he  calls  it  —  is  the  origin 
of  man,  just  as  the  larva  is  that  of  the  fly.  On  the  other  hand,  he  describes 
the  follicle,  or  the  egg,  as  he,  like  his  contemporaries,  calls  it,  as  partaking 
in  the  production  of  the  embryo.  As  regards  the  question  of  preformation 
or  epigenesis,  he  is  on  the  side  of  preformation.  On  the  whole,  he  gives  a 
conscientious  account  of  such  views  as  he  himself  does  not  accept  and  dis- 
plays in  these  works  both  creditable  impartiality  and  a  universal  knowl- 
edge of  literature.  He  has  taken  special  advantage  of  the  latter  quality  in 


138  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

his  bibliographical  works  —  Bibliotheca  anatomica,  botanka,  and  chirurgica  — 
in  which  he  has  compiled  information  regarding  all  the  literature  published 
till  then  in  various  spheres  of  science.  These  "bibliotheca"  are  even  in  modern 
times  of  importance  to  the  student  of  scientific  literature  and  are  remarkable 
for  their  completeness,  though  also  unfortunately  for  the  mass  of  misprints 
which  mar  their  utility. 

Mailer's  refutation 
Haller  has  been  very  diversely  judged.  On  the  one  hand,  he  has  been  re- 
garded both  by  his  own  age  and  by  posterity  as  the  foremost  anatomist 
and  physiologist  of  his  century  and  as  the  founder  of  modern  experimental 
physiology,  while  on  the  other,  as  has  so  often  been  the  case  with  scientists 
of  many-sided  interests,  he  has  been  accused  by  specialists  of  unreliability 
in  points  of  detail.  His  great  service,  particularly  to  the  development  of 
physiology,  can,  however,  never  with  justice  be  denied;  his  experimental 
method  and  its  results  are  undoubtedly  of  fundamental  significance.  As  re- 
gards his  general  conception  of  life,  on  the  other  hand,  Haller  has  to  a 
certain  extent  stood  at  an  old-time  view-point,  just  as  in  his  writings  he 
summarized  the  results  hitherto  attained.  This  to  some  extent  explains  how  it 
came  about  that  the  immediately  succeeding  age  picked  a  quarrel  with  him; 
thus,  Goethe  finds  fault  with  him  for  his  views  on  the  limitations  of  the 
knowledge  of  nature,  which,  it  is  true,  are  but  little  in  accordance  with 
natural-philosophical  speculation;  but  above  all  he  fell  foul  of  a  contem- 
porary scientist  who,  starting  out  from  an  entirely  different  standpoint  and 
having  different  preconceptions,  arrived  at  an  entirely  opposed  fundamental 
view  in  regard  to  science  —  namely.  La  Mettrie. 

JuLiEN  Offroy  de  La  Mettrie  was  born  in  1709  at  Saint-Malo  in  Brit- 
tany. His  father  was  a  wealthy  merchant,  who  had  his  son  brought  up  to  be 
a  priest.  He  studied  theology  in  Paris  and  there  joined  the  Jansenistic  sect,  a 
movement  in  the  French  Church  known  for  the  strictness  of  its  rules  and 
ideas,  but  disfavoured  and  persecuted  by  the  Government.  A  physician  in 
his  native  town,  however,  succeeded  in  awaking  in  the  young  theologian 
an  interest  in  his  profession,  and  so  it  came  about  that  La  Mettrie  began 
to  study  medicine,  first  in  Paris  and  then  at  Leyden  under  Boerhaave.  Having 
passed  his  examination,  he  set  up  in  practice  for  a  time  in  his  native  town 
and  then  became  physician  to  a  regiment  of  guards  in  Paris;  by  that  time 
he  seemed  to  have  prospects  of  making  a  brilliant  career,  as  he  was  well 
known  both  for  his  successful  cures  and  as  a  witty  and  refined  man,  with 
social  aptitudes.  But  these  high  hopes  soon  had  to  be  abandoned.  He  had 
begun  his  scientific  writing  by  translating  into  French  some  of  his  master 
Boerhaave's  more  important  works.  This  was  viewed  with  disfavour  by  the 
high-conservative  medical  faculty  in  Paris,  which  had  consistently  opposed 
Boerhaave's  theories,  just  as  at  one  time  it  had  opposed  those  of  Vesalius 


SEVENTEENTH     AND     EIGHTEENTH     CENTURIES      139 

and  Harvey.  And  La  Mettrie  still  further  increased  their  irritation  by  pub- 
lishing a  number  of  satirical  pamphlets  against  his  opponents.  Eventually 
the  latter  found  an  opportunity  of  taking  their  revenge;  in  a  work,  L'His- 
toire  naturelle  de  I' dme,  he  had  expressed  views  that  were  considered  to  be 
at  variance  with  the  Christian  faith.  The  theologians  rushed  to  battle  and 
La  Mettrie's  friends  advised  him  to  go  to  Holland  until  the  storm  should 
blow  over.  At  Leyden,  however,  he  printed  a  new  pamphlet,  which  still 
further  aggravated  his  position;  this  was  the  famous  treatise  L' Homme  ma- 
chine, which  was  published  anonymously,  it  is  true,  but  which  was  immedi- 
ately recognized.  Its  contents  were  such  that  the  author  could  by  no  means 
count  upon  even  Dutch  tolerance;  he  had  to  take  precipitate  flight  and  to 
remain  in  hiding  for  a  time.  His  fate  would  now  have  been  deplorable  had 
not  Europe  possessed  a  reigning  monarch  who  was  absolutely  indifferent 
to  religious  problems,  but  who,  on  the  other  hand,  was  amused  by  witty 
companions;  this  was  Frederick  II  of  Prussia.  La  Mettrie  was  summoned  to 
Berlin,  was  appointed  lecturer  at  the  royal  court,  and  besides  was  given  an 
opportunity  of  practising  as  a  physician.  He  enjoyed  these  privileges  only 
for  a  space  of  three  years;  in  175 1  he  died  as  the  result  of  an  accident.  He 
had  always  boasted  with  some  pride  of  his  power  of  enjoying  life's  pleasures 
both  qualitatively  and  quantitatively;  so  at  a  feast,  just  to  show  off,  he 
ate  enormous  quantities  of  truffle  pasty,  immediately  fell  ill,  and  died  in 
terrible  pain;  probably  the  pasty  had  contained  septic  poison.  This  tragic 
end,  however,  still  further  increased  the  ill  fame  caused  by  his  writings;' 
his  name  has,  in  fact,  been  one  of  the  blackest  in  the  whole  of  the  eighteenth 
century.  In  many  respects,  however,  he  paved  the  way  for  ideas  which  mod- 
ern biological  research  has  adopted  and  it  is  therefore  worth  while  paying 
some  attention  to  his  views. 

La  Mettrie's  polemical  ivorks 
In  his  writings  La  Mettrie  shows  himself  to  be  a  marked  oppositionist. 
It  is  destructive  work  that  amuses  him  most,  and  he  likes  best  to  pit  his 
strength  against  what  his  contemporaries  regarded  as  the  most  unshakable 
foundations  both  of  the  knowledge  of  existence  and  of  the  social  order  and 
good  manners.  His  polemical  writings  are  sometimes  brutally  frank,  some- 
times subtly  insidious,  but  he  invariably  challenges  deep-rooted  ideals,  both 
scientific  and  traditional,  and  is  quite  prepared  to  call  white  black  and  black 
white.  His  love  of  truth  goes  just  so  far  as  serves  his  immediate  purpose, 
but  undaunted  courage  we  cannot  deny  him,  and  he  has  a  firm  faith  in  the 

^  In  ancient  times  it  was  held  to  be  a  matter  of  fact  in  High-Church  quarters  that  no  one 
can  die  in  peace  without  the  Church's  blessing.  In  this  connexion  it  has  been  related  that  Luther 
hanged  himself  (a  Catholic  statement),  that  Spinoza  died  under  the  influence  of  opium,  and 
Voltaire  in  a  fit  of  madness.  In  furtherance  of  this  kind  of  propaganda  La  Mettrie's  above- 
described  death,  which  is  historically  confirmed,  was  a  good  find  indeed. 


X40  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

subject  that  he  made  his  own.  What  his  writings  seek  to  create  is  a  general 
cosmic  view  based  entirely  upon  "philosophical"  —  that  is  to  say,  natural- 
scientific  —  principles,  for  to  him  philosophy  and  natural  science  are  iden- 
tical. In  contrast  to  the  teachings  of  theology,  politics,  and  the  morality 
that  is  based  on  them,  he  wished  to  create  another  ideal  of  justice  and  virtue 
based  on  "natural"  principles,  and  in  contrast  to  the  explanation  of  life 
and  nature  which  priests  (and  "philosophers"  dependent  upon  them)  have 
given  in  support  of  ancient  authorities,  he  would  set  up  another  explana- 
tion, founded  upon  direct  observation  of  the  phenomena  of  life.  He  is  thus 
the  first  to  enunciate  a  purely  natural-scientific  view  of  life,  and  in  doing 
so  became  the  precursor  of  many  similar  endeavours  in  our  own  time.  Herein 
lies  his  greatest  originality,  for  in  most  of  his  subjects  he  merely  sets  forth 
in  detail  observations  recorded  by  others,  and  his  writings  can  hardly  be 
said  to  possess  scientific  form  in  the  stricter  sense  of  the  term;  they  are  pam- 
phlets published  for  agitational  purposes,  often  more  likely  to  persuade  than 
to  prove.  Of  these  the  two  which  have  been  cited  above  won  the  greatest 
notoriety;  among  his  other  publications  there  is  really  only  one  —  entitled 
Systeme  d' Epicure  —  that  is  of  any  great  interest.^  His  work  on  the  natural 
history  of  the  soul,  published  before  he  had  finally  broken  with  his  native 
country,  maintains  a  somewhat  cautious  tone  and  is  therefore  written  in 
a  more  scientific  form.  UHomme  machine,  again,  is  nothing  but  a  piece  of 
agitation,  and  Systmie  d' Epicure  is  a  collection  of  aphoristic  contributions 
to  a  general  knowledge  of  nature.  The  view  of  the  functions  of  the  human 
body  on  which  La  Mettrie  bases  his  speculations  is  by  no  means  a  new  one; 
it  is  the  mechanistic  theory  of  the  bodily  functions,  which,  founded  by 
Descartes,  had  been  developed  by  Borelli  and  Perrault,  by  Hoffmann  and 
Boerhaave.  To  their  observations  La  Mettrie  has  but  little  to  add;  the  most 
valuable  contribution  is  an  exposition  of  the  independence  of  the  vital  func- 
tions in  the  various  parts  of  the  body,  confirmed  by  observations  of  the 
manifestations  of  life  in  detached  organs  and  bodily  parts  even  in  the  highest 
animal  forms.  His  theory  of  fertilization  may  be  worthy  of  mention;  he 
believes  that  one  single  "  j-^^^rw^-animal "  penetrates  each  ^gg  and  is  there 
further  developed  into  a  new  individual;  he  thus  belongs  to  the  animal- 
culist  party.  But  it  is  not  the  life  of  the  body  that  interests  La  Mettrie  most; 
it  is  the  functions  of  the  soul  that  forms  the  chief  subject  of  his  literary  pro- 
duction. With  regard  to  the  soul  his  views  are  quite  clear;  it  does  not  exist, 
or  at  any  rate  not  in  a  form  that  the  theologians  and  suchlike  would  have 
it.  As  a  matter  of  fact.  La  Mettrie  is  not  quite  certain  what  the  soul  is; 

■*  There  would  be  no  point  in  dealing  herewith  La  Mettrie's  strictly  medical  writings;  of  his 
philosophical  treatises,  L'Hommt  plantt  is  a  development,  driven  to  absurd  lengths,  of  the  com- 
parison between  the  vegetable  and  animal  organs  which  Linnasus  had  already  arawn  up;  again,  Lts 
Animaux  plus  que  machines  contains  little  more  than  answers  to  his  opponents'  accusations. 


SEVENTEENTH  AND  EIGHTEENTH  CENTURIES  X4I 
sometimes  he  goes  so  far  as  expressly  to  point  out  that  its  essence  must  al- 
ways remain  unknown,  while,  on  the  other  hand,  he  is  quite  convinced  as 
to  what  it  is  not:  it  is  not  the  immortal  spirit,  distinct  from  the  body,  that 
it  is  officially  declared  to  be.  During  a  fever  La  Mettrie  had  observed  how 
the  faculties  of  the  soul  within  him  were  affected  by  the  course  of  his  sick- 
ness, and  in  his  medical  practice  he  had  remarked  the  same  phenomenon 
in  many  of  his  patients.  By  thus  making  the  influence  of  the  bodily  functions 
upon  the  intellectual  life  a  subject  for  investigation  and  even  experiment 
La  Mettrie  discovered  that  field  of  research  which  in  modern  times  is  termed 
psycho-physics  and  which  has  been  so  successfully  investigated  by  research- 
workers  with  what  are,  in  principle,  the  same  methods  as  his,  though  with 
an  entirely  different  standard  of  scientific  criticism.  La  Mettrie,  in  fact, 
suffered  the  usual  fate  of  a  pioneer  in  not  being  able  to  free  himself  from 
the  prejudices  he  attacked. 

His  general  conception  of  the  human  soul 
He  begins  by  accepting  the  old  division  into  a  vegetative,  a  sensitive,  and 
a  rational  soul;  he  analyses  the  first  two  and  finds  that  their  functions  are 
dependent  upon  those  of  the  body,  which  indeed  his  predecessors  had  also 
taken  for  granted.  He  devotes  the  main  part  of  his  investigation  into  the 
soul  to  trying  to  discover  the  operation  of  the  sensitive  soul;  he  gives  an 
account  of  mental  impressions  and  their  mechanisms,  in  the  course  of  which 
he  makes  several  striking  observations,  inter  alia  regarding  the  subjectivity 
of  mental  perceptions.  He  discusses  the  localization  of  the  mental  functions 
in  the  brain  with  extraordinary  keen-sightedness  and  thence  goes  straight 
over,  with  a  somewhat  daring  mental  jump,  to  ideas,  which  he  treats  —  very 
naively  —  as  bodily  entities,  the  grandeur  of  which  he  tries  to  estimate. 
After  having  thus  converted  ideas  in  general  into  bodily  phenomena,  he  dis- 
cusses in  connexion  therewith  a  number  of  such  ideas  —  memory,  imagina- 
tion, talent,  etc.  —  all  of  which  are  to  him  likewise  material,  so  that  finally 
there  is  nothing  left  of  the  rational  and  immortal  soul  that  the  theologians 
have  made  it  their  mission  to  cherish.  Thus  he  accumulates  a  mass  of  evi- 
dence to  show  that  the  soul  of  man  is  fundamentally  the  same  as  that  of  the 
animal;  he  cites  examples  of  animal  affection,  gratitude,  and  such  feelings, 
and  seeks,  on  the  other  hand,  to  adduce  proofs  that  man  possesses  animal 
qualities.  He  quotes  in  all  seriousness  a  number  of  miraculous  stories  of 
human  beings  who  have  lived  like  animals  in  the  forests  —  probably  em- 
broidered tales  of  runaway  lunatics  —  he  describes  the  orang-utan  with  the 
entirely  human  characteristics  which  were  at  that  time  ascribed  to  that  ani- 
mal, and  hopes  that  it  will  be  possible  to  teach  it  to  talk  by  a  method  of 
teaching  the  deaf  and  dumb  to  speak  which  had  just  been  invented.^  And 

^  Why  the  deaf-and-dumb  method  should  have  to  be  used  for  an  ape  which  can  hear  just 
as  well  as  a  man  is  not  explained;  probably  it  was  the  novelty  of  the  method  that  made  it  seem 
so  wonderful  and  induced  the  hope  of  its  performing  further  miracles. 


X42.  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

finally  he  expounds  a  quite  extraordinarily  childish  theory  regarding  the 
"natural"  origin  of  man  and  the  living  creatures  here  on  earth. 

The  ' '  natural ' '  origin  of  man 
Starting  from  Buffon's  above-mentioned  idea  of  the  living  particles  scattered 
about  in  space,  out  of  which  all  living  creatures  have  arisen,  he  assumes  that 
similar  particles,  intended  to  form  human  beings,  have  accumulated  in  the 
earth  and  given  rise  to  a  number  of  human  individuals,  some  defective,  others 
perfect.  To  the  question  why  the  earth  no  longer  produces  human  beings 
in  this  wise  he  would  answer  that  the  earth  is  now  old  and  weary;  in  answer 
to  the  question  how  the  human  babies  thus  produced  eventually  developed, 
it  may  be  supposed  that  they  were  brought  up  by  kindly  beasts  of  prey, 
just  as  a  small  child  had,  it  was  said,  recently  been  brought  up  by  a  she-bear 
in  Poland. 

On  reading  such  absurdities  one  recalls  the  days  of  old  Empedocles,  but 
there  is  nothing  to  indicate  that  La  Mettrie  was  not  serious,  as  far  as  he 
could  be  serious  over  anything.  There  is,  it  is  true,  no  sign  of  scientific  criti- 
cism apparent  in  speculations  such  as  these  —  in  comparison  with  them 
even  Buffon's  most  daring  assumptions  are  temperate  and  founded  on  facts  — 
but  at  least  they  have  their  interest  as  a  sign  of  the  times,  and  the  endeavour 
which  finds  expression  therein  points  ahead  to  the  "natural-creation  sto- 
ries" of  our  own  day.  No  one  before  had  ever  dared  so  openly  and  so  rashly 
to  break  with  the  old,  officially  accepted,  traditions,  then  upheld  by  the 
whole  authority  of  the  State,  and  even  among  La  Mettrie's  contemporaries 
there  was  no  one  who  would  have  dared  to  abandon  the  belief  in  a  God  as 
the  Creator  of  the  world  and  in  the  immortality  of  the  soul;  both  were  re- 
garded as  indispensable  bases  for  even  the  most  liberal-minded  morality. 
But  La  Mettrie  would  even  reform  morals  and  social  life;  he  desired  to  create 
a  natural  and  philosophical  system  of  ethics  in  place  of  the  official  theo- 
logical and  juridical  system.  Like  others  of  his  contemporaries,  he  believed 
in  man's  natural  inclination  to  virtue  and  happiness  and  he  propounds 
certain  quite  justifiable  suggestions  for  reform.  He  would  forbid  wearisome 
memorizing  in  the  schools,  maintaining  that  child  education  should  be  based 
upon  the  exercise  of  the  natural  powers  of  observation,  and  he  urges  the 
courts  of  law  to  differentiate  between  deeds  committed  by  the  mentally  de- 
ficient and  ordinary  crimes.  The  highest  aim  should  be  to  make  the  world 
happy,  but  the  main  point  of  the  art  of  living  that  he  preaches  is  first  and 
foremost  "la  volupte  "  —  that  is  to  say,  in  fact,  sexual  desire,  the  satisfaction 
of  which  with  the  greatest  possible  enjoyment  and  the  least  possible  risk 
he  discusses  in  a  lengthy  treatise,  claiming  thereby  to  lead  humanity  to  the 
height  of  rational  worldly  wisdom.  This  philosophy  of  licence  became,  as 
is  well  known,  widely  popular  during  the  latter  half  of  the  eighteenth  cen- 
tury; in  itself  it  would  of  course  have  no  concern  with  this  present  work 


SEVENTEENTH  AND  EIGHTEENTH  CENTURIES  143 
had  not  several  of  its  champions,  like  La  Mettrie,  based  their  philosophy 
upon  arguments  derived  from  natural  science,  which  contributed  to  bring 
the  latter  into  double  discredit  —  both  as  hostile  to  revealed  religion  and 
as  promoting  all  kinds  of  flippancy  and  social  disorganization.  In  this  the 
contempt  shown  for  natural  science  in  the  age  of  romanticism,  at  least  in 
part,  finds  its  explanation.  And  yet  even  La  Mettrie  possessed  one  feature 
that  is  reminiscent  of  romanticism,  or  rather  of  the  "  Stunn  und  Drang' 
period:  he  has  left  us  a  characteristic  description  of  himself,  in  which  he 
talks  of  his  kindly,  innocent  heart,  which  never  committed  any  sin,  even 
though  his  thoughts  did  so,  and  he  counsels  us  not  to  judge  his  morals  by 
his  writings.  There  are,  however,  reasons  for  supposing  that  his  life  and 
his  teachings  were  not  inconsistent  with  one  another.  He  was  certainly  no 
paragon  of  virtue,  but  he  was  a  child  of  his  age  and  he  had  ideas  that  were 
in  advance  of  those  of  that  period. 

On  the  whole,  we  find  during  the  eighteenth  century  a  great  number  of 
philosophical  speculations  widely  differing  from  one  another;  certain  of 
them  broke  boldly  away  from  all  the  old  traditional  ideas,  while  others 
sought  to  reconcile  the  old  and  the  new.  To  the  latter  type  belong  in  a 
marked  degree  those  attempts  to  explain  the  nature  and  development  of 
living  organisms  that  were  published  by  Bonnet,  who  in  a  remarkable  way 
combines  ideas  of  value  for  the  future  with  conceptions  based  on  a  cosmic 
theory  which  had  already  been  abandoned  by  most  thinkers. 

Charles  Bonnet  was  born  at  Geneva  of  wealthy  parents  in  1710.  The 
family  had  emigrated  from  France  at  the  time  of  the  persecution  of  the  Hu- 
guenots. He  studied  law  and  was  elected  to  the  council  of  his  native  town, 
but  at  the  same  time  he  evinced  a  lively  interest  in  natural  science  and  even- 
tually devoted  himself  entirely  to  that  pursuit.  As  a  pupil  of  Reaumur  he 
applied  himself  chiefly  to  insect  biology  and  in  this  field  carried  out  work 
of  lasting  value.  A  serious  ophthalmic  disease,  however,  soon  compelled 
him  to  give  up  making  direct  observations  and  all  practical  work  of  any 
kind,  so  that,  being  a  man  of  independent  means,  he  spent  the  rest  of  his 
days  engaged  in  purely  theoretical  speculations  in  natural  science  and  phi- 
losophy. He  died  in  1793  on  his  estate  in  the  neighbourhood  of  Geneva. 

Even  in  his  earliest  works  Bonnet  shows  himself,  apart  from  his  ac- 
counts of  actual  observations,  a  natural  philosopher,  and  in  his  last  works 
speculation  alone  predominates.  As  a  thinker  Bonnet  is  entirely  in  accord 
with  the  Christian  point  of  view,  and  his  writings,  by  contrast  to  the  free- 
thinking  that  was  so  prevalent  in  his  time,  acquire  a  sharply  polemical 
and  religiously  fervent  tone,  with  the  result  that  sometimes  even  his  purely 
practical  declarations  are  made  in  a  form  that  sounds  more  like  those  of  a 
lay  preacher  than  a  scientist.  His  writings  are  extremely  difficult  for  a  modern 
reader  to  appreciate;  one  has  to  search  through  scores  or  even  hundreds  of 


X44  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

pages  full  of  enthusiastic  praise  of  the  Creator,  of  effusive  outpourings  re- 
garding the  life  of  the  angels  and  the  existence  of  the  human  soul  in  another 
life,  in  order  to  find  amongst  it  all  biological  observations  of  lasting  value 
and  shrewd  theoretical  discussions  on  natural-scientific  problems.  Bonnet 
bases  the  whole  of  this  speculation,  so  widely  at  variance  with  the  spirit  of 
his  age,  on  Leibniz,  who,  we  may  remember,  strove  to  reconcile  the  Christian 
beliefs  with  the  results  of  natural  science  and  philosophical  thought.  Haller's 
fervently  Christian  conception  of  nature  also  strongly  influences  Bonnet, 
who,  having  sprung  from  the  high-conservative  and  strictly  Calvinistic 
patrician  class  of  Geneva,  was  perhaps  even  in  his  youth  opposed  to  that 
tendency  to  free-thinking  which  prevailed  in  most  contemporary  scientific 
circles. 

Bonnet's  discovery  of  parthenogenesis 
Bonnet  takes  his  place  in  the  history  of  biology  primarily  as  the  discoverer 
of  parthenogenetic  reproduction.  For  years  he  studied  the  reproduction  of 
the  aphides,  and  succeeded  in  establishing  the  existence  of  a  number  of  sum- 
mer hatches  of  females  who  without  fertilization  propagate  by  producing 
live  offspring;  towards  the  autumn  a  new  generation  arises,  this  time  con- 
sisting of  males  and  females,  which  mate,  the  females  then  laying  eggs, 
which  hibernate.  He  also  discovered  and  studied  other  peculiarities  of  insect 
reproduction,  as,  for  instance,  the  peculiar  propagation  of  the  pupiparous 
flies.  Further,  Bonnet  followed  up  with  great  care  the  study  of  the  phenomena 
of  division  and  regeneration  which  Trembley  had  discovered;  he  observed 
a  large  number  of  lower,  colonizing  animals,  belonging  to  the  Coelentera  and 
the  Bryozoa,  and  experimented  with  them,  as  also  with  fresh-water  Annel- 
ida and  common  earthworms,  observing  not  only  the  regeneration  which 
results  in  normal  individuals,  but  also  such  as  results  in  malformations  — 
in  this  respect  a  precursor  in  a  special  field  of  research,  which  has  been 
very  highly  developed  in  modern  times.  He  studied  with  great  exactness 
the  metamorphosis  of  insects,  endeavouring  to  discover  what  changes  the 
parts  and  organs  of  the  body  undergo  in  the  process  of  evolution  from  larva, 
through  the  pupal  stage,  to  the  imago;  and  at  least  as  far  as  the  intestinal 
canal  is  concerned  he  made,  on  the  whole,  correct  observations.  Again,  he 
studied  the  adipose  tissue  and  the  part  it  plays  during  the  metamorphosis 
period  of  insects  as  reserve  nutriment  for  the  prospective  individual.  Bonnet 
also  experimented  with  plants  and  was  one  of  the  first  to  study  their  tropisms 
and  growth-movements.  The  whole  of  this  valuable  collection  of  facts, 
however,  he  accumulated  to  form  the  basis  of  his  theoretical  speculations 
upon  life  on  the  earth  —  one  might  even  say,  in  the  universe  —  which  were 
to  him  the  most  essential  function  of  science. 


SEVENTEENTH     AND     EIGHTEENTH     CENTURIES      145 

His  preformation  theory 
Of  Bonnet's  scientific  theories  the  best  known  is  his  thoroughly  worked- 
out  preformation  theory.  His  "incapsulation"  theory,  according  to  which 
every  female  individual  contains  within  her  the  "germs"  of  all  the  creatures 
that  originate  from  her,  the  one  generation  within  the  other,  and  that  thus 
the  first  female  of  every  species  contained  within  her  all  the  individuals  of 
that  species  that  have  ever  been  produced  and  that  will  be  produced  until 
the  end  of  time  —  this  theory  is  really  the  very  foundation  on  which  all 
his  biological  speculation  was  built.  He  found  actual  support  for  it  in  his 
observations  of  the  reproduction  of  the  Aphididre;  in  the  parthenogeneti  ally 
produced,  new-born  female  of  the  plant-louse  he  saw  the  ready-formed  rudi- 
ments of  a  new  generation,  and  even  the  metamorphosing  insect  shows  the 
imago  ready  formed  beneath  the  pupal  skin.  In  the  plant,  on  the  other  hand, 
the  germ  and  the  cotyledons  are  visible  in  the  seed,  and  the  bud  encloses 
the  leaves  that  are  to  emanate  from  it.  He  therefore  considered  himself  fully 
justified  in  seeing  in  these  facts  a  universal  law  governing  the  whole  of  ani- 
mate nature;  he  is  strongly  opposed  to  all  epi genetic  theories  and  character- 
izes as  legends  the  observations  purporting  to  show  that  in  the  embryo  of 
the  chicken  certain  organs  are  developed  before  others.  However,  it  is  never 
made  quite  clear  whether  these  germs,  which  thus  exist  in  infinite  numbers 
incapsulated  within  one  another,  are  to  be  regarded  purely  corporeally  or 
whether  they  are  some  kind  of  ideal  entities  after  the  manner  of  Aristotle. 
Bonnet,  as  a  matter  of  fact,  draws  quite  a  number  of  his  theories  from  Aris- 
totle, starting  from  that  of  the  ultimate  cause,  God  or  the  supreme  intelli- 
gence, and  of  the  harmony  and  finality  of  the  universe.  At  all  events,  the 
germs  exist  not  only  in  the  ovaries  of  the  females,  but  also,  in  some  animals 
at  any  rate,  scattered  all  over  the  body.  There  is,  in  fact,  no  other  way  by 
which  Bonnet  can  explain  how  the  bits  of  a  cut-up  earthworm  are  regen- 
erated into  new  individuals;  for  the  earthworm  must,  like  all  animals,  be 
assumed  to  possess  a  soul,  and  the  soul  is  always  one  and  indivisible;  if, 
then,  the  earthworm  is  to  be  regenerated,  germs  possessing  soul-rudiments 
must  lie  scattered  throughout  the  body.  Indeed,  even  a  separate  extremity 
that  is  regenerated,  as  in  the  crayfish,  for  instance,  must  possess  a  separate 
germ  which  is  intended  to  replace  it  when  it  is  lost,  and  the  same  holds 
good  for  individual  muscles  and  fibres,  which  are  capable  of  growing  again 
even  in  the  highest  animal  forms.  —  The  whole  of  this  germ  theory  is  clearly 
reminiscent  of  Leibniz's  monad  theory  and  thus  has  its  origin  in  common 
with  both  BufFon's  and  La  Mettrie's  doctrines  of  living  particles  filling  the 
universe;  but  while  the  two  latter  sceptics  utilized  the  hypothesis  to  estab- 
lish a  theory  of  primal  creation  (spontaneous  generation),  thereby  abandon- 
ing the  personal  creator,  the  fervently  religious  Bonnet  strongly  repudiates 
all  idea  of  spontaneous  generation  and  gives  a  number  of  reasons  against 


-L^G  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

it,  which  are  in  part  valid  at  the  present  day  —  an  instance  among  many 
of  how  the  scientist's  personal  conceptions  influence  his  purely  scientific 
theories. 

His  descent  theory 
The  preformation  theory,  however,  represents  only  one  side  of  Bonnet's 
curious  speculative  investigations.  One  idea  that  occupies  his  mind  quite 
as  much  is  the  thought  of  the  progressive  development  going  on  in  nature. 
His  firm  conviction  as  to  the  wisdom  of  the  Creator  has  made  of  him  an 
incorrigible  optimist;  he  is  absolutely  convinced  that  nature  is  advancing 
towards  a  high  goal;  he  believes  that  there  are  heavenly  bodies  in  which 
this  development,  which  he  expects  that  the  earth  will  eventually  experience, 
has  already  been  attained  —  in  which  the  stones  possess  organic  structure, 
the  plants  are  sensible,  the  animals  talk,  and  men  are  angels.  And  just  as 
he  expects  an  advance  beyond  the  present  stage,  so  he  believes  that  this  is 
the  result  of  a  process  of  evolution;  the  "germs"  that  are  incapsulated 
within  one  another  in  an  individual  are  not  alike  and  never  have  been;  on 
the  contrary,  he  expressly  maintains  that  if  one  were  to  see  a  horse,  a  hen, 
a  snake,  under  the  form  they  had  when  they  first  came  into  existence,  they 
would  be  unrecognizable.  These  changes  he  accounts  for  by  a  series  of  stages 
of  development  which  the  earth  has  undergone  and  each  of  which  has  been 
cut  short  by  some  vast  natural  catastrophe,  which  destroyed  all  living  things, 
but  always  spared  the  germs  out  of  which  fresh  life -forms  arose.  The  last 
of  these  catastrophes  was  the  one  that  destroyed  the  earth  before  the  six 
days  of  the  Creation  referred  to  in  the  Books  of  Moses,  the  historical  authen- 
ticity of  which  Bonnet  was  naturally  careful  to  maintain,  but  which  he 
interprets  somewhat  freely,  according  to  the  orthodox  view.  As  the  result 
of  a  coming  catastrophe  he  expects  the  perfecting  of  the  world's  existence, 
as  indicated  above,  while  he  assumes  from  the  presence  of  fossils  in  the  moun- 
tains a  series  of  previous  epochs  of  existence  with  living  creatures  that  did 
not  resemble  those  now  existing  and  from  which  these  latter  have  originated. 
Just  as  Bonnet  manifestly  bases  this  geological  theory  on  Buffon,  so  he 
is  the  precursor  of  both  Cuvier  and  Lamarck  in  the  same  way;  Cuvier's 
famous  catastrophe-theory  corresponds  too  closely  with  Bonnet's  to  justify 
the  assertion  that  the  similarity  was  accidental,  while,  on  the  other  hand, 
Bonnet  in  his  express  statements  regarding  the  change  that  takes  place  in 
species  has  forestalled  Lamarck's  descent  speculations,  though,  it  is  true, 
both  the  biologists  mentioned  succeeded  in  elaborating  their  ideas  into  a 
far  more  perfect  whole.  But  in  still  another  respect  Bonnet  foreshadows  these 
two  great  pioneers  of  biological  science:  he  maintains  —  again  an  obvious 
connexion  with  Buffon  —  that  nature  draws  no  sharply  defined  lines  between 
the  species,  but  that  all  life-forms  on  the  earth  pass  into  one  another.  He 
draws  up  what  he  calls  ' '  une  khelle  des  etres  naturels  "  —  a  series  proceeding 


SEVENTEENTH  AND  EIGHTEENTH  CENTURIES  Z^J 
from  the  simple  elements  through  the  mineral  kingdom,  vegetable  kingdom, 
and  animal  kingdom  in  a  long  line  right  up  to  man.  The  transitions  in  the 
series  are,  from  the  modern  point  of  view,  ingenuously  chosen:  the  flying 
fish  provides  the  transition  between  fishes  and  birds;  the  ostrich,  the  bat, 
and  the  flying  squirrel  between  birds  and  quadrupeds;  the  polypus  and  the 
sensitive  plant  between  animals  and  vegetables.  But  then  he  also  declares 
that  the  whole  of  this  division  is  only  approximate  and  that  perhaps  the 
series  is  not  as  uniform  as  he  has  made  it;  that  perhaps  molluscs  and  insects, 
lizards  and  frogs  do  not  follow  one  another  consecutively,  but  are  in  reality 
collateral  with  one  another.  Just  as  the  long  evolutionary  series  of  Bonnet 
clearly  foreshadows  Lamarck's  evolutionary  theory,  so  the  assumption  of 
parallel  evolutionary  groups  represents  a  first  hint  of  the  type  theory  that 
Cuvier  founded  and  whereby  he  reformed  the  entire  zoological  system  of 
classification  and  rendered  possible  the  approach  of  the  modern  descent- 
theory.  And  as  has  already  been  pointed  out,  the  points  of  agreement  are 
certainly  not  accidental;  Bonnet  enjoyed  a  great  reputation  amongst  his  con- 
temporaries and  the  immediately  succeeding  age  and  was  diligently  studied. 
Cuvier  in  particular  has  expressed  his  warm  admiration  for  him  and  recom- 
mended his  writings  for  careful  study;  and  other  contemporary  biologists 
certainly  knew  his  works  and  were  to  some  extent  influenced  by  them. 

In  the  foregoing  have  been  mentioned  those  theories  of  Bonnet  that 
have  proved  to  be  the  most  vital  for  the  development  of  biology,  and  con- 
siderations of  space  forbid  a  detailed  account  of  all  the  shrewd  utterances 
which  this  imaginative  man  of  genius  scattered  throughout  his  writings; 
for  example,  his  striking  criticism  of  vitalism.  In  spite  of  his  religious  fa- 
naticism he  gives  a  purely  mechanical  explanation  of  the  bodily  functions 
and  cites  the  pointed  objection  to  the  vitalists  —  mostly  Stahl  and  his 
school  —  that  "souls"  are  particularly  convenient  to  have  when  it  is  a 
question  of  explaining  the  phenomena  of  life;  they  do  everything  that  is 
asked  of  them  and  their  non-existence  can  never  be  proved.  Another  time 
he  gives  a  detailed  analysis  of  the  different  organs  in  the  same  body  that 
are  dependent  upon  one  another  and  shows  how  a  change  in  one  organ  must 
inevitably  react  upon  the  others;  and  on  still  another  occasion  he  describes 
his  observations  regarding  different  mental  impressions  —  a  problem  which, 
as  is  well  known,  Goethe  made  the  subject  of  exhaustive  study.  Thus  Bon- 
net was  a  man  full  of  ideas;  and  though  in  a  great  deal  he  must  appear  out 
of  accord  with  our  age,  yet  undoubtedly  many  of  his  ideas  are  nowadays 
incorporated  in  the  general  consciousness. 

The  experimental  biological  investigations  that  Bonnet  made  the  basis 
of  his  speculations  were  continued  and  considerably  widened  by  Lazzaro 
Spallanzani  (172.9-99).  Born  at  Reggio,  the  son  of  a  lawyer,  he  studied  law 
at  Bologna  and  at  the  same  time  took  orders.  He  afterwards  devoted  himself 


X^S  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

to  natural-scientific  studies  and  became  professor  of  philosophy,  first  at  Mo- 
dena  and  later  at  Pavia.  He  applied  himself  to  experimental  research,  particu- 
larly in  regard  to  regeneration  and  fertilization,  and  left  all  his  predecessors 
far  behind  him,  in  both  method  and  results.  In  the  amphibians,  especially 
salamanders  and  tritons,  he  found  suitable  subjects  for  the  study  of  regenera- 
tion even  among  the  vertebrates,  and  he  made  as  exhaustive  a  use  of  them 
as  was  possible  under  the  conditions  in  which  he  worked;  he  studied  the 
re-formation  of  the  tail,  extremities,  and  jaws,  and  this  not  merely  for  the 
purpose  of  establishing  the  fact,  but  by  means  of  dissection  and  microscopic 
investigation  he  followed  the  re-forming  of  the  various  components  of  the 
body:  muscles,  nerves,  and  bones.  He  observed  the  time  that  the  regenera- 
tion lasted  and  endeavoured  to  influence  the  process  by  means  of  altering 
the  conditions  of  food  and  temperature.  He  even  experimented  with  the 
phenomena  of  fertilization;  by  filtering  the  sperm  of  particular  animals  he 
proved  that  the  presence  of  the  spermatozoa  was  essential  if  fertilization 
was  to  take  place;  nevertheless  he  could  not  be  induced  to  assume  a  direct 
influence  of  these  components  upon  the  egg,  but  believed  that  the  accompany- 
ing fluid  was  the  substance  that  stimulated  the  egg's  development.  For  he 
adhered  as  stubbornly  as  Bonnet  to  the  preformation  theory:  he  closely 
studied  the  development  of  the  frog's  egg  and  followed  the  formation  of 
the  backbone  channel,  but  merely  for  the  purpose  of  seeking  evidence  of 
the  entire  animal's  having  been  ready-formed  in  the  egg.  Eventually  he  be- 
lieved that  he  had  discovered  incontestable  proof  thereof,  when  he  saw  the 
frog's  egg  increasing  in  size  within  the  body  of  the  mother  animal  and  before 
it  had  been  fertilized,  and  as  growth  is  not  possible  without  organs,  the 
larva  of  the  frog  must  have  been  ready-made  in  the  egg  before  fertilization. 
Just  as  Spallanzani  was  thus  convinced  that  he  had  found  an  undeniable 
argument  in  favour  of  the  preformation  theory,  another  scientist  published 
a  treatise  which  was  to  form  the  basis  of  a  new  conception  of  embryonic 
development. 

Caspar  Friedrich  Wolff  was  the  name  of  the  naturalist  who  led  the 
science  of  embryology  into  fresh  paths.  He  was  born  in  Berlin  in  1733,  ^^^ 
son  of  a  tailor.  He  went  through  a  course  of  medical  training  at  the  College 
of  Medicine  there  and  thence  proceeded  to  Halle,  where  he  studied  philos- 
ophy after  the  system  of  Leibniz  and  his  pupil  Christian  WolfF,^  and  finally, 

^  Christian  Wolff  (1679-1754)  was  professor  of  mathematics  at  Halle,  whence  he  was 
ejected  through  the  intrigues  of  the  Pietists  (Stahl  seems  to  have  taken  part  in  the  persecution 
directed  against  him)  and  then  became  professor  at  Marburg,  but  later  he  returned  to  Halle 
and  there  worked  as  professor  of  philosophy.  Under  the  general  title  Vernunftige  Betrachtungen  he 
published  a  series  of  essays  covering  many  different  fields  of  human  knowledge,  in  which  he 
expounds  Leibniz's  theories  in  a  popularized  form,  in  particular  maintaining  that  everything 
that  happens  must  possess  adequate  reason  for  doing  so,  because  otherwise  something  might 


SEVENTEENTH     AND     EIGHTEENTH     CENTURIES      X49 

for  his  doctor's  degree,  he  published  in  1759  the  essay  which  was  to  make 
his  name  famous.  Having  served  for  a  time  as  an  army  surgeon,  he  applied 
for  and  obtained  permission  to  hold  lectures  in  medicine  in  Berlin,  which, 
however,  resulted  in  his  coming  into  serious  conflict  with  the  professors 
at  the  Collegium  Medicum.  Being  of  a  peaceful  disposition  he  was  much 
troubled  at  this  and  was  delighted  when  he  received  a  summons  to  St.  Peters- 
burg, where  he  became  an  academician  and  spent  the  rest  of  his  life  carrying 
on  his  research  work  in  peace.  He  died  in  1794. 

Woljf's  generation  theory 
Caspar  Friedrich  Wolff  is  one  of  those  who  did  not  win  fame  until  after 
death.  His  own  age  paid  little  attention  to  him.  Haller,  to  whom  he  dedi- 
cated his  afterwards  famous  treatise  Theoria  generationis,  accepted  the  honour 
in  a  friendly  spirit,  but  paid  little  attention  to  the  work,  as  also  did  other 
biologists  of  the  period.  That  Wolff  was  thus  misunderstood  by  his  con- 
temporaries was  due  mostly  to  the  fact  that  from  the  very  outset  he  adopted 
a  course  directly  opposed  to  the  then  prevailing  conception  of  the  phenomena 
of  life;  he  began  with  a  ready-made  theoretical  program,  and  the  facts  he 
presents  are  collected  for  the  express  purpose  of  proving  his  already  firmly 
established  convictions.  By  way  of  introduction  he  lays  down  the  plan  of 
his  work;  by  the  body's  '' generatio,"  or,  as  we  should  now  call  it,  "evolu- 
tion," is  meant  its  creation  Q' fonnatio"^  in  all  its  parts,  and  its  principle 
is  the  force  that  brings  about  this  creation.  The  upholders  of  the  doctrine 
of  "predelineation"  thus  deny,  he  adds,  that  any  "generation"  takes  place 
at  all.  He  starts,  therefore,  by  declaring  war  on  the  preformation  theory; 
he  does  not  base  his  rejection  of  it  on  the  evidence  of  the  facts  he  has  ob- 
served, but  on  purely  theoretical  reasons  adduced  by  Christian  Wolff's  philo- 
sophical methods.  "He  gives  a  true  explanation  of  generation  who  derives 
the  parts  of  the  body  and  their  composition  from  the  fixed  principles  and 
laws  governing  them;  .  .  .  and  he  has  perfected  a  theory  of  generation 
who  has  succeeded  in  tracing  the  entire  ready-formed  body  from  these  prin- 
ciples and  laws."  The  principles  on  which  the  fresh  formation  of  organism 
takes  place  are  food  and  growth;  food  re-creates  the  simple  components  of 
the  organism,  while  through  growth  are  formed  entire  parts  of  the  body  or 
fresh  bodies.  Reproduction  is,  in  fact,  brought  about  by  a  "weakened  growth 
(yegetatio  languescens),"  whereby  the  newly-formed  seed  or  embryo  is  sepa- 
rated from  the  mother  plant  or  animal  and  is  prevented  from  growing  further 
in  union  with  the  latter.  And  that  which  produces  all  nourishment  and 
growth  is,  according  to  Wolff,  the  "inner  force  (vis  essentialis^,"  a  term 
which  he  constantly  uses  to  mean  the  ultimate  cause  of  all  that  takes  place 

arise  out  of  nothing,  which  is  impossible.  For  the  rest,  he  was  a  clever  mathematician  and,  for 
his  age,  a  sound  botanist,  and  contributed  much  towards  inculcating  an  interest  in  natural 
science  in  Germany. 


X50  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

in  the  organism,  the  idea  of  which  he  himself  states  that  he  borrowed  from 
Stahl.  For  just  as  the  basis  of  Wolff's  research  work  is  the  rejection  of  pre- 
formation, so  its  final  object  is  the  abolition  of  "mechanical  medicine"  — 
the  theory  that  holds  that  the  living  body  should  be  regarded  and  treated 
as  a  machine,  which  finds  the  explanation  of  the  phenomena  of  life  in  the 
form  and  composition  of  the  bodily  parts,  or,  as  it  is  expressly  stated,  in 
anatomical  principles.  This  theory  Wolff  declares  to  be  a  product  of  the 
imagination  and  produces  a  number  of  arguments  to  prove  its  falseness. 
Wolff,  howe''  .:,  never  arrives  at  any  properly  worked-out  vitalistic  theory; 
after  all,  he  deals  with  the  phenomena  of  the  body  along  mechanical  lines 
and  his  "vis  essetifialis"  he  does  not  identify,  as  Stahl  did,  with  the  soul.  On 
the  whole,  Wolff's  theory  is  vague  and  inconsistent  if  we  compare  it  with 
Stahl's  mode  of  thought,  which  is  certainly  hard  to  apprehend,  but  is  never- 
theless in  its  way  loftily  conceived.  The  most  serious  result  of  Wolff's  phil- 
osophical method,  however,  is  that  he  fancies  it  capable  of  explaining 
practically  anything;  with  a  couple  of  phrases  he  throws  a  bridge  across 
even  the  deepest  abysses  of  natural  science;  he  has  a  theory  ready  to  hand  to 
explain  even  such  phenomena  as  those  in  the  face  of  which  modern  biology 
has  to  be  content  with  merely  establishing  the  fact.  In  all  this  he  is  a  pre- 
cursor of  the  natural  philosophy  of  romanticism,  and  it  was,  in  fact,  this 
that  eventually  procured  for  his  views  the  honour  they  deserved. 

His  cellular  theory 
Wolff's  treatise  deals  with  the  development  of  both  plants  and  animals  in 
a  constant  endeavour  to  find  factors  common  to  both.  In  his  opinion,  the 
growth  of  plants  is  due  to  the  inner  life-force  drawing  up  moisture  out  of 
the  earth  through  the  roots  and  into  all  the  various  parts  of  the  plants;  at  the 
points  of  growth  this  moisture  is  collected  in  especially  large  quantities; 
through  evaporation  it  acquires  greater  density  and  forms  cuticles,  which, 
through  fresh  supplies  of  moisture,  assume  the  form  of  ampulla;,  the  walls 
of  which  are  further  thickened  by  evaporation,  and  the  new  ampulla  force 
themselves  in  between  the  earlier  ones,  whereby  the  substance  of  the  plant 
is  renewed.  The  plant's  vesicular  system  is  formed  through  the  circulating 
sap's  hollowing  out  ducts  in  the  vegetable  substance,  the  walls  of  these 
ducts  being  likewise  thickened  by  evaporation.  The  plant  is  then  formed 
by  these  ampulla;  and  ducts  through  a  system  of  growth-forms,  the  abstract 
and  involved  details  of  which  it  would  take  too  long  to  follow.  As  mentioned 
above,  the  florescence  and  germination  are  caused  by  a  weakened  growth  — 
"The  adequate  reason  why  within  a  certain  period  frondescence  ceases  and 
germination  begins  is  a  diminution  of  the  supply  of  alimental  sap  at  the 
point  of  growth,  as  is  at  once  seen  from  the  very  definition  of  growth." 
This  is  Wolff's  scientific  adduction  of  evidence.  Similarly  it  is  proved  that 
the  germination  and  embryonic  development  consist  in  a  renewed  growth 


SEVENTEENTH     AND     EIGHTEENTH     CENTURIES       151 

induced  by  the  " perfecfum  nutrimentum"  with  which  the  pollen' provides  the 
seeds;  lengthy  arguments  are  brought  forward  to  show  why  the  pollen  is 
and  must  be  the  most  perfect  form  of  nourishment  that  exists.  Sexual  re- 
production, then,  is  nothing  more  than  a  renewed  growth. 

The  fundamental  principles  on  which  growth  proceeds  in  the  vegetable 
kingdom  Wolff  discovers  in  detail  in  the  animal  kingdom;  in  the  embryo 
of  the  chicken,  which  is  his  only  subject  of  investigation  in  animal  embry- 
ology, he  finds  reproduced  the  same  phenomenon  of  growth;  the  inner 
force  derives  nourishment  from  the  yolk  of  the  embryonic  lamina,  this  ali- 
mental  fluid  coagulating,  as  in  the  plant,  into  ampullar  and  ducts,  the  latter 
here  represented  by  heart  and  vesicular  system.  Here,  too,  the  details  of  the 
embryonic  development,  which  is  described  much  less  fully  than  that  of 
the  plant,  are  of  no  particular  interest;  here  again  Wolff  gives  full  rein  to 
his  speculative  imagination  at  the  expense  of  detailed  observation.  Such  an 
assertion  as  that  no  one  has  discovered  anything  with  a  powerful  magni- 
fying-glass  that  could  not  equally  well  have  been  observed  with  a  lower 
magnification  is  sufficient  evidence  of  how  his  speculations  are  out  of  accord 
with  reality.  And  still  worse  is  his  habit  of  comparing  the  structure  of  plants 
and  animals  in  detail;  his  comparison  of  a  plant's  vessels  with  the  arteries, 
of  its  suckers  with  the  veins,  rivals  in  absurdity  most  of  what  had  hitherto 
been  perpetrated  in  that  sphere  —  which  was  by  no  means  little. 

And  yet  it  is  just  through  his  comparison  of  plant  and  animal  develop- 
ment that  Wolff  made  his  most  important  contribution  to  biological  history. 
He  was  the  first  to  compare  the  elements  of  which  the  plant  and  the  animal 
are  composed,  and  though  the  details  of  this  comparison  are  for  the  most 
part  incorrect,  it  was  at  any  rate  he  before  anyone  else  who  pointed  out  the 
ampullar  -like  structure  —  in  other  words,  the  cell-tissue  —  that  is  common 
to  both.  He  thus  carried  science  a  considerable  step  further  along  the  road 
marked  out  by  Malpighi  and  his  immediate  successors. 

His  epigenesis  doctrine 
Wolff's  second  service  to  science  is  generally  said  to  be  his  introduction 
of  the  doctrine  of  epigenesis  into  biology  in  place  of  the  preformation  theory. 
We  have  previously  found  that  the  epigenesis  theory  is  actually  older  than 
the  preformation  theory;  even  Aristotle  was  an  epigenetic,  and  his  doctrine 
was  promulgated  without  contradiction  even  by  Harvey,  whereas  the  first 
champion  of  the  preformation  theory  was  Swammerdam.  It  was  thus  an 
ancient  theory  that  Wolff  adopted,  and  from  the  very  outset  he  made  it  his 
own  on  purely  theoretical  ground;  it  was  only  natural,  therefore,  that  his 
observations  should  eventually  accord  with  the  preconceived  ideas.  But  the 
progress  of  science  was  facilitated  by  the  fact  that  —  whether  with  pre- 
conceptions or  not  —  he  saw  more  correctly  in  his  microscope  than  his  con- 
temporary preformationists;  for  their  part,  they  considered  an  embryological 


Z52.  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

Study  to  be  in  the  main  superfluous,  since  everything  was  ready-formed 
before,  whereas  Wolff  showed  that  in  this  sphere  there  was  still  an  immense 
amount  to  be  discovered  and  investigated,  thereby  opening  up  fresh  fields 
of  research,  in  which  very  successful  work  was  done  during  the  succeeding 
epoch.  It  has  frequently  been  said,  however,  that  in  this  question  Wolff  was 
entirely  in  the  right  and  his  opponents  in  the  wrong.  This  view  is  utterly 
at  variance  with  historical  facts.  When  it  first  arose,  the  preformation  theory 
not  only  was  fully  justified  and  compatible  with  the  scientific  standpoint 
of  the  time,  but,  as  has  been  pointed  out  above,  also  constituted  a  real 
advance,  whereas  the  epigenesis  theory,  as  Wolff  formulated  it,  certainly 
shot  far  beyond  the  mark.  He  who  denied  to  the  undeveloped  egg  all  trace 
of  organic  structure  would  undoubtedly  have  found  modern  ontogenetical 
research,  with  its  strong  emphasis  on  the  orientation  of  the  egg  and  its 
various  parts  and  with  the  maintenance  of  the  immutability  of  the  factors 
of  heredity,  highly  preformational. 

His  romantic  conception  of  nature 
It  is,  however,  by  no  means  in  his  epigenesis  theory  alone  that  Wolff  shows 
himself  at  variance  with  his  age  and  foreshadows  a  new  era;  the  whole  of 
his  scientific  matter  and  his  entire  conception  of  nature  differ  in  a  marked 
degree  from  those  of  his  contemporaries.  He  is,  as  has  already  been  pointed 
out,  a  precursor  in  the  course  which  natural  science  took  at  the  end  of  the 
eighteenth  century  and  which  is  termed  natural  philosophy;  this  course  was 
directed,  particularly  in  Germany,  towards  an  entirely  new  knowledge  of 
nature,  with  the  utter  rejection  of  both  the  aims  and  the  means  with  which 
natural  research  had  been  carried  out  up  to  that  time.  Biological  natural- 
philosophy,  however,  is  only  a  link  in  a  universal  cultural  movement  of  far 
wider  influence,  which  will  be  explained  later  on.  But  first  we  must  devote 
some  words  to  the  application  of  the  experimental  method  to  botany  during 
the  eighteenth  century,  as  well  as  to  one  or  two  anatomical  and  morpho- 
logical scientists  who  were  at  work  during  the  same  period. 

In  the  eighteenth  century  the  science  of  botany  was  governed,  far  more 
than  animal  biology,  by  Linnasanism.  During  the  same  period,  however, 
one  or  two  naturalists  employed  in  their  study  of  the  vegetable  kingdom 
methods  other  than  the  purely  systematic;  as  a  rule  they  worked  in  obscu- 
rity and  their  results  were  appreciated  only  by  succeeding  ages.  One  excep- 
tion to  this  was  the  English  experimental  scientist,  Stephen  Hales,  whose 
work  was  highly  appreciated  by  his  contemporaries;  his  writings  were 
translated  into  French  by  Buffon  and  into  German  by  Christian  Wolff.  And 
he  was  well  worthy  of  the  attention  paid  to  him,  for  he  is  without  doubt 
one  of  the  most  remarkable  biologists  of  the  eighteenth  century. 

Hales  was  born  in  1679  ^^  Beckesbury  in  the  south  of  England.  He  was 
of  good  family,  and  after  studying  theology  at  Cambridge  he  took  holy 


SEVENTEENTH     AND     EIGHTEENTH     CENTURIES       153 

orders  in  the  Church  of  England.  He  held  various  posts  and  finally  became 
vicar  of  Teddington,  a  parish  in  Middlesex,  where  he  died  in  1761.  He  was 
known  as  a  zealous  priest,  who  worked  for  the  advancement  of  his  parish 
from  both  a  moral  and  a  material  point  of  view,  and  besides  found  time  to 
devote  himself  to  important  philanthropical  works,  such  as  the  improve- 
ment of  prison  conditions,  the  administration  of  charitable  societies,  and 
inventions  likely  to  prove  of  benefit  to  mankind.  By  those  who  knew  him 
personally  he  was  extolled  for  his  kindness  and  simplicity. 

At  Cambridge  Hales  had  been  attracted  to  the  study  of  natural  science, 
particularly  physics,  chemistry,  and  botany;  indeed,  during  his  undergrad- 
uate days  Cambridge  was  primarily  regarded  as  Newton's  town.  He  main- 
tained this  interest  throughout  his  life;  it  thus  occurred  to  him  to  try  by 
way  of  physics  to  discover  the  conditions  of  the  life  and  growth  of  plants, 
an  idea  that  he  realized  after  experimental  studies  lasting  many  years.  He 
published  his  results  in  the  year  1717  under  the  title  of  Vegetable  Staticks. 
In  his  ability  to  organize  biological  experiments  and  to  draw  conclusions 
therefrom  he  was  excelled  by  none  of  his  contemporary  scientists  and  by 
but  few  of  those  that  have  come  after  him;  it  has  been  possible  even  in  mod- 
ern times  to  apply  his  experimental  methods  with  profitable  results.  In  re- 
gard to  his  general  cosmic  conceptions  Hales  was,  naturally,  in  conformity 
with  his  profession  and  his  age,  a  pious  Christian,  but  like  his  master  Newton 
he  strove  conscientiously  to  discover  the  law-bound  mechanical  processes 
undergone  by  the  phenomena  be  investigated;  he  would  never  involve  him- 
self in  hypothetical  explanations  of  the  manifestations  of  life. 

Hales' s  quantitative  experiments 
What  Hales  wished  to  discover  by  means  of  his  experiments  was,  first  of 
all,  the  renewal  of  substance  in  plants,  both  quantitatively  and  qualitatively. 
It  is  above  all  his  quantitative  investigations  that  merited  and  also  won 
general  admiration;  he  was  the  first  to  apply  systematically  and  on  a  large 
scale  the  exact  method  of  physics  to  animate  nature.  By  watering  previously 
weighed  potted  plants  for  a  given  length  of  time  with  a  fixed  quantity  of 
water,  and  by  weighing  the  plant  daily  during  that  period,  he  found  out 
its  water-consumption;  then  he  measured  the  leaf-  and  stem-surface  of  the 
plant  and  calculated  therefrom  the  relation  between  the  surface  of  the  plant 
and  the  quantity  of  w^ater  that  it  absorbed  daily.  Similarly,  by  means  of 
measuring  and  weighing  he  calculated  the  quantity  of  moisture  that  differ- 
ent plants  absorb  out  of  the  earth  through  their  roots,  as  well  as  the  speed 
with  which  the  sap  circulates  in  the  interior  of  the  plant;  and  finally  he 
proved  that  plants  absorb  air  through  their  leaves  and  stems  and  not  only 
through  their  roots,  as  earlier  botanists  declared.  He  was  quite  specially 
interested  in  the  problem  of  the  relation  of  the  air  to  living  creatures.  He 
definitely  maintains  that  the  air  contains  component  parts  which  are  ab- 


^54  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

sorbed  by  the  plant  through  the  leaves  and  are  converted  into  solid  sub- 
stances. Likewise  he  states,  though  with  less  certainty,  that  light  penetrates 
the  leaves  and  co-operates  in  the  alimental  processes  in  them.  In  these  asser- 
tions attempts  have  been  made  to  find  definite  proof  of  Hales's  genius,  and 
there  is  undeniably  in  them  a  brilliant  guess  at  facts  that  were  established 
at  a  later  period,  but  in  regard  to  points  of  detail  his  speculations  on  the 
properties  of  air  are  undoubtedly  far  more  deficient  than  his  quantitative 
experiments.  It  is  true  that  gas-chemistry  had  been  but  little  developed  in 
his  time,  but  it  would  seem  that  he  scarcely  took  advantage  of  what  actually 
was  known;  he  certainly  cites  Boyle  quite  frequently,  but  he  evidently  knew 
nothing  of  van  Helmont's  gas-experiments.  To  him  all  gases  are  "air,"  both 
that  which  arises  from  the  dry  distillation  of  wood  and  that  which  is  formed 
by  treating  lime  with  acid.  In  such  circumstances  it  was  inevitable  that  the 
great  trouble  he  went  to  in  investigating  the  influence  of  the  air  upon  vege- 
table, and  even  animal,  life  was  to  a  great  extent  in  vain.  What  he  achieved 
as  an  experimenter,  however,  is  quite  enough  to  ensure  for  him  considerable 
fame  in  the  history  of  biology,  and  it  was  to  be  long  before  science  advanced 
beyond  his  point  of  view.  For  this  to  happen  there  was  required  above  all 
else  a  reformation  of  the  science  of  chemistry  —  which  indeed  actually  took 
place  at  the  end  of  the  eighteenth  century.  This  will  be  described  in  a  fol- 
lowing chapter.  During  the  latter  part  of  his  life  Hales  also  worked  at  ex- 
periments on  animals,  particularly  in  regard  to  the  blood-circulation,  and  he 
displayed  in  this  sphere  the  same  power  of  arranging  experiments  and  draw- 
ing conclusions  therefrom  that  he  showed  in  his  botanical  investigations. 
He  measured  the  blood-pressure  in  live  mammals  by  introducing  into  a  vein 
a  tube  in  which  the  blood  was  made  to  rise;  he  calculated  the  speed  of  the 
blood-stream  in  the  veins  and  capillaries  from  the  volume  of  the  vessels, 
the  rate  of  movement  of  the  blood-mass,  and  the  resistance  of  the  walls. 
To  these  investigations  he  added  a  quantity  of  notes  on  medicinal  and  hy- 
gienic subjects,  with  particular  reference  to  the  injuriousness  of  alcoholic 
liquors,  for  he  was  a  keen  supporter  of  temperance.  This  fact  gives  his 
Hamasfaficks,  as  he  called  his  investigations  into  the  blood,  a  far  more 
motley  character  than  his  treatise  on  vegetable  physiology;  nevertheless, 
even  these  investigations  are  of  some  value  and  he  holds  a  place  of  honour  in 
the  history  of  physiology. 

Among  the  plant-physiologists  who,  after  Hales,  distinguished  them- 
selves during  the  eighteenth  century  there  are  one  or  two  who  carried  out 
important  experimental  observations  regarding  plant-reproduction,  and  who 
deserve  special  mention. 

Joseph  Gottlieb  Koelreuter  was  born  at  Sulz,  Wiirttemberg,  in  1733. 
We  know,  on  the  whole,  very  little  about  his  life;  he  seems  to  have  studied 
in  Berlin  and  Leipzig  and  spent  some  time  in  St.  Petersburg;  in  1764  he  was 


SEVENTEENTH  AND  EIGHTEENTH  CENTURIES  155 
made  professor  in  natural  history  and  curator  of  the  botanical  gardens  at 
Karlsruhe.  He  died  in  1806.  Before  his  appointment  to  the  professorship  he 
had  already  published  the  first  series  of  notes  in  which  he  recorded  the 
results  of  his  experiment  with  the  artificial  fertilization  of  plants.  As  we 
have  seen,  Camerarius  was  the  first  to  experiment  in  this  field.  Linnxus  fol- 
lowed in  his  footsteps,  carrying  out,  it  will  be  remembered,  the  hybridization 
of  plants,  but  not  being  otherwise  an  experimental  naturalist-worker  in  the 
true  sense. 

Koelreuter  s  experiments  in  plant-life  fertilization 
KoELREUTER  was  the  first  who  exclusively  applied  himself  to  experimenting 
with  the  cultivation  of  plants  with  a  view  to  explaining  their  fertilization 
and  development.  To  begin  with  he  investigated  the  act  of  fertilization 
itself;  he  examined  the  pollen  under  the  microscope  and  came  to  the  con- 
clusion that  its  fertilizing  property  is  due  to  an  oily  fluid  that  it  secretes; 
on  the  stigma  of  the  pistil  he  found  a  similar  fluid  and  concludes  therefrom 
that  fertilization  consists  in  a  union  of  these  fluids,  just  as  an  acid  and  a  base 
form  a  salt.  Of  greater  value  than  these  speculations  are  his  careful  observa- 
tions of  the  method  of  transmitting  the  pollen;  he  is  the  first  to  explain 
clearly  that  certain  flowers  are  invariably  fertilized  by  insects,  and  he  also 
pointed  out  the  part  played  by  the  wind  in  the  fertilization  of  other  forms. 
Of  greatest  interest,  however,  are  his  investigations  in  connexion  with  hy- 
brid formations,  a  problem  to  which  he  eventually  devoted  all  his  attention. 
In  this  sphere  he  paved  the  way  for  a  field  of  research  that,  as  is  well  known, 
has  at  the  present  day  attracted  the  interest  of  both  the  scientific  world 
and  the  public  more  than  most  others.  To  start  with,  for  a  number  of  years 
he  crossed  different  types  of  tobacco-plants  with  one  another,  afterwards, 
however,  proceeding  to  other  plant  genera:  pinks,  aquilegia,  verbascum,  and 
others.  Moreover,  he  was  able  to  vary  his  experiments  and  to  observe  the 
results  thereof;  he  carefully  compared  the  hybrids  with  the  parent  individ- 
uals and  noted  similarities  and  dissimilarities  between  them;  he  mated  the 
hybrids  with  their  parent  species  and  observed  the  reversion  to  similarity 
with  the  latter;  he  fertilized  the  hybrids  with  one  another  and  obtained 
results  that  foreshadowed  Mendel's  famous  observations;  he  likewise  even 
noted  cases  which  would  be  regarded  at  the  present  day  as  mutations.  How- 
ever, he  naturally  did  not  succeed  in  utilizing  theoretically  the  results  of 
his  experiments;  besides,  his  ideas  of  the  actual  essence  of  fertilization  were 
all  too  vague  —  he  believed,  for  instance,  that  by  fertilizing  a  species  with 
a  mixture  of  its  own  and  foreign  pollen  it  would  be  possible  to  obtain  a  kind 
of  semi-hybrids,  which  would  be  somewhat,  but  not  very  much  unlike  the 
mother  species.  Further,  he  mixed  his  speculations  up  with  certain  mystical 
ideas,  particularly  in  the  sphere  of  alchemy;  he  expressly  compares  the  change 
that  the  characters  of  the  species  undergo  in  hybridization  with  the  con- 


156  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

version  of  metals  effected  by  the  alchemists,  and  presumes  that,  just  as  a 
vegetable  species  can,  by  repeated  unilateral  crossing,  be  transformed  into 
another,  one  day  man  will  learn  to  convert,  by  a  necessarily  gradual  process, 
one  metal  into  another;  in  further  evidence  of  which  he  finds  a  correspond- 
ence between  the  pollen  and  the  sulphur  of  the  alchemists,  proved  by  the 
fact  that  pollen  can  be  used  as  a  means  of  reducing  metal  oxides,  though  this 
is  easily  explained  when  the  pollen  is  burned  to  coal,  which  has  a  reducing 
effect.  Moreover,  the  female  sexual  product  is,  in  his  opinion,  "mercurial." 
It  is  thus  in  the  sphere  of  practical  experiment  that  Koelreuter's  greatness 
lies;  in  this  he  is  a  pioneer,  and  his  experiments  in  crossing  were  justly  taken 
as  a  model  until  Mendel's  far  more  deeply  thought-out  experiments  became 
known.  Koelreuter  shared  the  fate  of  the  latter,  the  greatest  of  his  succes- 
sors, in  his  works'  being  for  a  long  time  entirely  neglected;  it  was  not  until 
long  after  his  death  that  they  were  rescued  from  oblivion  and  accorded  the 
appreciation  they  deserved. 

The  same  fate  of  being  neglected  by  contemporary  and  immediately  suc- 
ceeding ages  was  suffered  by  Christian  Conrad  Sprengel,  whose  investi- 
gations into  the  fertilization  of  flowers  were  carried  out  in  association  with 
Koelreuter's.  Born  in  1750  at  Brandenburg,  the  son  of  a  clergyman,  Sprengel 
studied  theology  and  languages,  afterwards  devoting  himself  to  the  tutor's 
profession.  He  was  for  some  years  a  schoolmaster  in  Berlin  and  later  became 
rector  at  Spandau.  After  several  quarrels  with  his  superiors,  his  pupils,  and 
their  parents  he  was  dismissed  with  a  pension  in  1794  and  then  lived  in 
Berlin  in  a  solitude  that  increased  year  by  year  until  he  died  in  1816.  His 
irascible  temperament  contributed  both  to  his  failure  as  a  teacher  and  to 
his  subsequent  isolation;  it  was  aggravated  by  the  utter  lack  of  understanding 
with  which  his  contemporaries  received  the  results  of  the  botanical  re- 
searches that  had  represented  the  chief  interest  of  his  life.  He  was  unable 
to  print  his  last  botanical  writings,  with  the  result  that  during  his  last  few 
years  he  applied  himself  to  philology,  apparently  with  but  little  success. 

Sprengel' s  experiments  on  plant-jertilixation 
The  work  which  at  last  brought  his  name  to  the  knowledge  of  posterity 
is  his  Das  entdeckte  Geheimnis  der  Natur  im  Ban  und  in  der  Bejruchtting  der  Blumen, 
published  in  1793.  Under  this  somewhat  pretentious  title  he  collected  a  large 
number  of  observations  in  connexion  with  the  florescence  of  plants,  and  on 
them  bases  a  general  theory  of  fertilization  in  the  vegetable  kingdom,  which 
in  its  essentials  still  holds  good  today.  In  conformity  with  his  theological 
upbringing  he  was  fully  convinced  of  nature's  having  been  preconceived  by 
the  wisdom  of  the  Creator  down  to  the  minutest  detail,  and  he  consequently 
set  about  trying  to  discover  for  what  useful  purpose  the  different  parts  and 
properties  of  the  flower  were  intended.  As  a  result  of  his  inquiries  into  this 
subject  he  found,  to  begin  with,  that  the  flowers'  nectaries  are  always  pro- 


SEVENTEENTH  AND  EIGHTEENTH  CENTURIES  157 
tected  from  the  rain,  and  further  that  they  are  often  characterized  by  special 
colours,  whence  he  concludes  that  their  object  must  be  to  attract  insects 
to  the  flowers;  but  then  the  insects  must  themselves  have  some  object  in 
their  visits,  and  this  he  found,  as  did  Koelreuter  before  him,  to  be  the 
conveyance  of  pollen  from  stamen  to  pistil.  He  now  studied  in  detail  the 
relation  of  the  insects  to  the  flowers  and  noticed  that  certain  flowers  are  in- 
variably fertilized  by  special  insect  forms,  others  again  by  several  different 
forms,  and  that  the  position  of  the  nectaries  in  each  flower  is  adapted  not 
only  to  the  flower's  general  conditions  of  life,  but  also  to  the  insects  that 
visit  it.  Further,  he  discovered  that  in  a  number  of  bisexual  flowers  stamen 
and  pistil  actually  develop  during  different  periods,  and  that  therefore  the 
flower  cannot  be  fertilized  by  its  own  pollen,  but  that  pollen  is  conveyed 
by  the  insects  from  flower  to  flower.  This  fact  he  calls  dichogamy,  a  name 
which  is  still  used,  and  he  concludes  from  it  that  "Nature  does  not  appear 
to  desire  that  a  flower  be  fertilized  by  its  own  pollen."  Finally,  he  explains 
more  lucidly  than  any  of  his  predecessors  the  contrast  between  flowers  fer- 
tilized by  insects  and  those  fertilized  by  the  wind;  on  this  subject,  too,  he 
makes  many  striking  observations. 

Space  forbids  a  more  detailed  account  of  the  numerous  shrewd  and  far- 
reaching  observations  which  Sprengel  adduces  in  support  of  his  theories. 
Through  his  work  he  has  laid  a  lasting  foundation  for  one  of  the  most 
important  sections  of  vegetable  biology,  and  besides,  in  regard  to  insect 
research,  he  has  pointed  out  a  method  of  far  greater  theoretical  importance 
than  mere  classification  and  collecting.  And  so  the  utter  lack  of  understand- 
ing shown  for  his  work  by  his  own  age  was  all  the  more  tragic.  The  natural 
philosophers  of  the  Romantic  Age  deeply  despised  detailed  research  work  of 
this  kind,  and  the  succeeding  generation,  which  endeavoured  to  revive  the 
mechanistic  conception  of  nature  of  the  eighteenth  century,  felt  embarrassed 
by  the  detailed  finality  which  Sprengel  sought  and  found  in  the  structure 
and  life  of  the  flowers.  It  was  only  Darwin's  authority  that  succeeded  in 
rescuing  Sprengel  from  oblivion;  in  the  flowers'  and  insects'  mutual  depend- 
ence upon  one  another  he  found  support  for  his  theory  of  selection  and 
himself  carried  out  investigations  in  this  field,  which  will  be  described  in 
a  later  chapter.  Thus  Sprengel  found  redress  —  tardy  but  glorious. 


CHAPTER    XI 

DESCRIPTIVE     AND     COMPARATIVE     ANATOMY     IN     THE 
EIGHTEENTH     CENTURY 

THE  ANATOMICAL  SCIENCE  of  the  eighteenth  century  appears  to  be  a 
direct  continuation  of  that  of  the  previous  century;  no  important 
discoveries  of  a  pioneer  character  were  made,  but  those  fields  of 
research  that  had  been  won  were  well  investigated  in  detail,  and  this  field 
of  inquiry  can  show  names  that  testify  to  praiseworthy  endeavour,  if  not 
so  much  to  brilliant  genius.  Of  these  names  some  of  the  more  representative 
will  be  mentioned  in  the  present  chapter. 

Bernhard  Siegfried  Albinus  was  the  son  of  a  German  physician  of 
repute  who,  after  having  studied  at  Leyden,  held  various  posts  in  his  native 
country,  but  eventually  returned  to  Leyden  as  a  professor.  Young  Bernhard, 
who  was  born  at  Frankfurt  an  der  Oder  in  1697,  was  consequently  brought 
up  at  Leyden  and  spent  his  life  there.  At  the  early  age  of  twenty-four  he  was 
made  professor  of  anatomy  and  surgery,  and  lectured  on  these  subjects  and 
on  physiology  until  his  death,  in  1770.  He  was  highly  esteemed  by  his  con- 
temporaries and  honours  of  many  kinds  were  bestowed  upon  him.  He  was, 
in  fact,  a  thoroughly  educated  scientist  and  was  gifted  in  many  ways.  He 
was  interested  in  the  history  of  science  and  published  critical  editions  of 
the  works  of  the  leading  anatomists  —  those  of  Vesalius,  Eustacchi,  and 
Harvey  were  reprinted  by  him.  His  own  works  were  extensive  and  profound. 
He  studied  with  great  care  the  bone-structure  of  the  human  embryo  and  its 
development,  and  even  in  the  full-grown  man  it  was  mostly  the  bone- 
structure  and  the  musculature  that  interested  him.  He  compiled  a  fine  set 
of  engravings  illustrating  these  two  organic  systems  —  Tabula  sceleti  et  mus- 
culorum corporis  humani  —  a  gigantic  work  in  contents  and  weight,  in  which 
in  a  series  of  splendid  copperplates,  drawn  and  engraved  under  his  instruc- 
tions by  the  famous  artist  Vandelaar,  he  reproduces  the  human  bone-structure 
and  musculature  in  every  detail.  This  work,  which  cost  him  a  whole  fortune, 
is  of  its  kind  still  unsurpassed.  Besides  doing  research  work  Albinus  also 
practised  as  a  doctor,  and,  thanks  to  him,  Leyden  still  continued  during 
the  eighteenth  century  to  be  a  centre  for  anatomical  studies. 

One  of  Albinus's  most  brilliant  pupils  was  Johann  Nathanael  Lie- 
berkuhn.  Born  in  Berlin  in  1711,  he  was  destined  by  his  father  for  the 
priesthood,  and  for  several  years  had  to  study  theology  against  his  will. 

^58 


SEVENTEENTH  AND  EIGHTEENTH  CENTURIES  159 
After  his  father's  death  he  took  up  medicine,  studying  first  in  Germany  and 
then  under  Albinus  at  Leyden,  where  he  took  his  degree  with  a  treatise 
entitled  De  valvula  colt.  After  paying  visits  to  England  and  France,  he  settled 
down  in  Berlin  as  a  practitioner.  He  died  in  1756.  His  short  life  and  his 
extensive  practice  prevented  him  from  benefiting  science  as  much  as  he  other- 
wise would  certainly  have  been  able  to  do,  yet  what  he  did  achieve  ensures 
to  him  a  place  in  the  history  of  biology.  He  was  above  all  an  excellent 
technician.  He  himself  made  microscopes  of  splendid  workmanship  and  was 
able  to  prepare  under  the  microscope  the  most  minute  organic  details. 
Equally  remarkable  were  his  injections;  preparations  made  by  his  own  hand 
are  still  preserved  in  the  anatomical  museum  in  Berlin.  In  fact,  he  used  the 
microscope  for  the  purpose  of  studying  injection-preparations,  a  thing  which 
had  never  been  done  before.  His  only  really  important  work  is  his  exposition 
of  the  structure  of  the  small  intestine,  in  which  he  describes  the  Lieberkiihn- 
ian  crypts  (called  after  him),  as  also  those  cells  existing  at  the  bottom 
thereof,  now  called  the  Panethian  cells,  whose  glandular  nature,  however, 
he  failed  to  discover.  The  whole  work  bears  witness  to  his  technical  skill 
both  in  injections  and  in  microscopy,  and  forms  a  valuable  contribution  to 
the  development  of  microscopical  anatomy. 

Another  pupil  of  Albinus's,  who  won  a  far  greater  reputation  in  his  own 
age,  was  Petrus  Camper.  He  was  born  at  Leyden  in  17x2.,  studied  there,  and 
took  degrees  in  both  philosophy  and  medicine.  Having  spent  a  couple  of 
years  travelling,  he  was  appointed  professor  at  the  academy  at  Franeker, 
a  small  provincial  university  which,  when  he  first  went  there,  had  only 
four  medical  students,  a  number  which  he  succeeded  in  increasing  many 
times  over  in  a  very  short  time.  After  five  years,  however,  he  obtained  a 
professorship  in  Amsterdam,  and  some  time  later  one  in  Groningen,  but  he 
finally  gave  up  teaching  and  settled  at  The  Hague,  where  he  became  a  member 
of  the  state  council  and  took  part  in  its  political  life.  He  died  in  1789. 

Camper  is  described  as  a  man  of  an  extremely  superior  personality, 
brilliantly  gifted,  but  quick-tempered  and  despotic.  In  his  own  time  he  was 
regarded  as  one  of  the  leading  scholars  in  Europe  and  attained  a  splendid 
position,  both  socially  and  financially.  His  many-sidedness  was  extraordi- 
nary, almost  reminiscent  of  Olof  Rudbeck's.  Besides  carrying  out  anatomical 
research  in  a  number  of  different  fields,  he  was  a  surgeon  and  gynaecologist, 
hygienist,  and  expert  in  medical  law  and  veterinary  surgery,  and  in  all  these 
spheres  he  made  valuable  contributions.  He  was,  besides,  an  excellent  draughts- 
man and  a  leading  connoisseur  of  art.  He  took  measurements  of  the  facial 
angle  in  human  beings  of  different  ages  and  different  races,  and  in  comparison 
therewith  in  higher  vertebrates,  with  results  of  interest  both  to  the  history 
of  art  and  to  natural  science.  This  facial  angle,  which  still  bears  Camper's 
name,  is  formed  by  two  lines,  the  one  extending  through  the  opening  of 


z6o  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

the  ear  and  the  bottom  of  the  nostril,  the  other  at  a  tangent  to  the  most 
protuberant  part  of  the  forehead  and  the  chin.  When  Camper  expounded 
this  idea  before  the  Amsterdam  Academy  of  Painting,  with  a  view  to  giving 
the  artists  a  more  accurate  conception  of  the  human  form,  he  little  thought 
that  in  doing  so  he  was  laying  the  foundations  of  an  entirely  new  branch 
of  science  —  modern  craniology.  In  close  connexion  with  this  interest  in 
the  structure  of  the  human  body  are  his  special  investigations  of  the  apes, 
particularly  of  those  resembling  man.  He  had  procured  as  many  specimens 
as  he  could  possibly  get  of  the  orang-utan,  at  that  time  extremely  rare  in 
Europe,  and  he  not  only  dissected  a  number  of  them,  but  closely  studied  a 
live  specimen.  As  a  result  of  especially  careful  investigations  into  the  mus- 
culature of  the  extremities  and  the  structure  of  the  larynx,  he  proved  con- 
clusively that  the  animal  is  unable  to  walk  upright,  as  La  Mettrie  and  other 
"philosophers"  at  that  time  imagined;  nor  can  it  in  any  form  pronounce 
an  articulate  language.  The  philosophers,  however,  were  certainly  far  too 
firm  in  their  belief  to  allow  themselves  to  be  convinced  by  anatomical  proofs, 
all  the  more  so  as  it  could  be  urged  against  Camper  that  he  was  in  all  respects, 
both  religious  and  political,  a  conservative  man. 

Camper  s  anthropological  and  comparative-anatomical  investigations 
Camper  was  particularly  interested  in  the  anatomical  investigation  of  un- 
common and  rare  animals.  He  published  monographs  on  the  elephant,  the 
rhinoceros,  and  the  reindeer,  anatomically  useful  specimens  of  which  he 
succeeded  in  procuring  owing  to  Holland's  extensive  shipping-communi- 
cations. Of  more  general  interest  than  these  special  researches  is  his  study 
of  the  bone-structure  of  birds,  in  which  he  describes  for  the  first  time  how 
the  bones  are  filled  with  air  to  facilitate  flight,  and,  in  connexion  therewith, 
the  air-sacs  in  the  body  which  serve  the  same  purpose.  Of  immense  general 
interest  also  are  his  comparative  investigations  into  the  auditory  organs  of 
fish,  whales,  and  reptiles,  wherein  he  discusses  the  reproduction  of  sound 
in  various  media  and  the  ear's  adaptability  thereto,  at  the  same  time  making 
a  close  study  of  the  different  parts  of  the  auditory  apparatus.  Finally,  Camper 
carried  out  an  anatomical  investigation  of  a  highly  original  kind  in  his 
essay  "On  the  Best  Form  of  Shoe,"  in  which,  after  a  detailed  description 
of  the  bone-structure  of  the  foot,  he  sharply  condemns  the  unnatural  foot- 
wear of  his  time  and  describes  what  he  considers  to  be  the  most  rational 
shape  of  shoe. 

If,  then,  we  find  in  Camper  efforts  at  comparative  anatomy,  this  is  only 
evidence  of  his  foresight,  for  as  a  general  rule  his  contemporary  zoologists 
were  content  with  purely  superficial  descriptions  of  types  in  the  Linn^an 
style.  There  were  a  few  praiseworthy  exceptions,  however,  among  whom 
John  Hunter  and  Pallas  deserve  special  mention. 

John  Hunter  (172.8-93)  was  born  in  a  country  place  in  Scotland,  the  son 


SEVENTEENTH     AND     EIGHTEENTH     CENTURIES       z6l 
of  a  poor  farmer.  Being  orphaned  at  an  early  age,  he  received  a  very  indiffer- 
ent education,  a  fact  which  influenced  his  whole  life.  He  never  even  learnt 
to  spell  his  native  language  properly,  nor  at  the  beginning  did  he  learn  any 
proper  profession.  At  last,  at  the  age  of  twenty,  he  went  to  his  elder  brother, 
William,  who  had  become  a  highly  esteemed  doctor  in  London  and  had  been 
commissioned  to  examine  prospective  army-surgeons.  John  began  by  assisting 
at  the  dissection  classes  in  connexion  with  this  course,  but  during  them  he 
taught  himself  anatomy,  with  such  success  that  he  was  soon  able  to  take 
over  the  direction  of  the  entire  course.  He  continued  to  educate  himself, 
partly  under  his  brother's  and  partly  under  other  doctors'  guidance,  finally 
receiving  an  appointment  as  surgeon,  attached  to  the  English  fleet  which 
sailed  to  the  Spanish  main  during  the  Seven  Years'  War.  At  the  end  of  the 
war  he  settled  down  as  a  physician  in  London,  won  a  reputation  as  a  clever 
operator,  and  quickly  obtained  a  remunerative  post.  He  spent  all  his  spare 
time  in  anatomical  and  physiological  studies,  and  as  soon  as  his  salary  per- 
mitted, he  bought  a  house,  in  which  he  established  a  large  anatomical  mu- 
seum. On  this  museum  he  sacrificed  all  that  he  could  spare  in  the  way  of 
time  and  money,  so  that  at  the  time  of  his  death  it  was  undoubtedly  the 
finest  of  its  kind  in  existence.  He  also  gave  private  lectures  in  anatomy,  but 
he  was  not  a  particularly  good  lecturer.  As  a  practitioner,  on  the  other  hand, 
he  was  regarded  as  the  best  in  London  in  his  time.  He  was  universally  known 
as  an  honest,  benevolent,  and  charitable  man,  but  his  personal  manners 
showed  his  poor  education,  while  his  lack  of  self-control  in  particular  gained 
him  many  enemies.  In  a  violent  altercation  with  some  of  his  colleagues  he 
got  a  stroke  of  apoplexy,  which  caused  instant  death.  His  museum  was  taken 
over  by  the  State  and  is  to  this  day  one  of  the  sights  of  London  in  the  sphere 
of  natural  science.  His  manuscripts,  however,  were  taken  by  a  brother-in- 
law,  who  first  plagiarized  them  for  his  own  benefit  and  then  burnt  them  in 
order  to  destroy  all  evidence  of  his  plagiarism. 

Hunter  s  work  in  comparative  anatomy 
Hunter's  scientific  work  falls  essentially  within  the  sphere  of  practical 
medicine;  his  theoretical  researches  were  always  intended  as  foundations  on 
which  to  base  practical  medical  work.  His  famous  museum  was  intended 
for  a  similar  purpose,  but  on  the  broadest  lines;  he  collected  all  kinds  of 
animals,  both  higher  and  lower,  dissected  them,  and  experimented  with 
them,  setting  up  the  preparations  that  he  made  on  anatomical  principles. 
Thus  he  applied  for  the  first  time  in  practice  principles  of  comparative  anat- 
omy as  a  whole,  thereby  creating  a  precedent  for  future  research  of  very 
great  value.  Of  his  writings  a  treatise  on  the  natural  history  and  diseases 
of  the  teeth  has  been  of  the  utmost  value  to  biology;  in  it  he  gives  an  account 
of  a  systematic  investigation  into  the  origin  and  grov\th  of  the  teeth  that 
is  far  in  advance  of  any  previous  work  of  its  kind.  In  a  treatise  on  inflamma- 


2.62.  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

tion  of  the  blood  and  bullet-wounds  he  propounds  a  curious  theory  of  the 
blood  as  a  vital  principle,  which  he  further  developed  in  a  number  of  lectures 
on  the  musculature.  He  considers  the  blood  to  be  a  kind  of  primary  matter 
in  the  body,  whence  every  other  bodily  substance  is  derived;  all  living  matter 
is  of  a  similar  nature,  so  that  even  the  blood  of  one  animal  can  be  transferred 
into  another  of  a  different  genus  (modern  investigations  show  this  to  be  an 
error),  and  life  is  a  kind  of  independent  principle  in  the  body  which  prevents 
it  from  dissolving  —  a  theory  reminiscent  of  Stahl.  Though  Hunter  pro- 
duced a  few  solitary  brilliant  ideas,  yet  from  a  theoretical  point  of  view  he 
did  not  contribute  very  much  to  the  development  of  biology;  his  genius  for 
comparative  anatomy  was,  however,  probably  greater  than  anyone  else's  in 
his  time,  and  in  many  respects  it  has  borne  fruit  in  more  recent  times. 

Peter  Simon  Pallas  was  born  in  Berlin  in  the  year  1741,  the  son  of  a 
doctor,  and  studied  medicine  in  his  native  country,  at  Gottingen,  and  at 
Leyden.  At  the  latter  university  he  got  his  degree  with  an  essay  on  intestinal 
worms.  He  afterwards  spent  some  years  in  Holland,  working  at  zoological 
collections  from  the  tropics,  which  he  described  in  a  series  of  papers.  In 
1768  he  was  summoned  by  the  Russian  Government  to  take  part  in  an  im- 
portant expedition  which  was  being  sent  to  Siberia  to  explore  that  country 
from  the  point  of  view  of  natural  history  and  economics.  Pallas  spent  six 
years  travelling  in  Siberia,  reaching  as  far  as  Amur,  and  he  brought  home  an 
immense  quantity  of  scientific  material,  which  he  worked  at  in  St.  Peters- 
burg for  a  number  of  years.  In  1793  he  was  sent  to  explore  the  Crimean 
district,  which  had  just  then  become  part  of  Russia,  and  he  stayed  there  for 
a  long  time,  living  on  an  estate  which  the  Empress  Catherine  II  gave  him. 
Finally,  however,  he  moved  back  to  Berlin  in  order  to  be  in  closer  touch 
with  the  scientific  world,  and  there  he  died  in  1811. 

Pallas' s  ivork  on  intestinal  worms  and  on  mammals 
Pallas's  contribution  to  the  development  of  biology  is  particularly  many- 
sided.  In  his  doctor's  dissertation  he  incorporated  all  the  observations  he 
was  able  to  obtain  dealing  with  intestinal  worms  and  he  sought  to  prove 
that  they  enter  the  human  body  from  outside  —  in  his  time  it  was  univer- 
sally assumed  that  they  arose  out  of  "tainted  fluids"  in  the  body.  In  a  work 
on  the  zoophytes  he  tries  to  find  out  the  classification  of  these  animals, 
their  conditions  of  life,  and  their  relation  to  animals  and  plants.  He  endeav- 
ours to  prove  that  the  zoophytes  form  a  true  transition  between  animals  and 
plants,  following  the  ancient  saying  that  nature  never  makes  any  jumps. 
He  also  made  a  number  of  interesting  observations,  both  anatomical  and 
biological,  on  worms  and  expressly  points  out  how  utterly  heterogeneous 
the  Linnasan  class  bearing  this  name  is.  Primarily,  however,  Pallas  is  a 
student  of  vertebrates.  In  his  Spicilegia  zpologica  in  particular  —  a  collection 
of  monographs,  issued  in  separate  numbers  —  he  describes  in  detail  a  number 


SEVENTEENTH  AND  EIGHTEENTH  CENTURIES  x6} 
of  hitherto  unknown  higher  animals,  dealing  with  their  anatomy,  mor- 
phology, and  habits.  Among  his  biological  works,  however,  the  place  of 
honour  is  held  by  his  work  on  New  Mammal  Species  from  the  Kodentia.  In 
this  work  he  gives  an  account,  with  a  thoroughness  that  was  quite  unprec- 
edented, of  the  new  rodents  discovered  by  him  in  Russia  and  Siberia;  in 
it  he  endeavours  to  present  not  merely  diagnoses  as  resulting  from  his  ex- 
aminations, such  as  his  age  was  usually  content  with,  but  a  true  general 
knowledge  of  the  animals  described,  based  on  a  close  study  of  their  exterior, 
with  careful  measurements  of  every  part  of  their  body,  thorough  anatomical 
investigations  and  illustrations,  and  detailed  descriptions  of  the  conditions 
under  which  the  animals  lived.  The  anatomical  section  is  particularly  useful 
and  constitutes  the  best  work  so  far  carried  out  in  the  investigation  of  the 
inner  structure  of  the  members  of  an  entire  order  of  animals.  Though  direct 
points  of  comparison  do  not  occur  very  often  in  the  work,  nevertheless  the 
descriptions  are  so  detailed  and  at  the  same  time  so  comprehensive  that  the 
whole  must  be  regarded  as  one  of  the  really  sound  pieces  of  work  that  have 
paved  the  way  for  modern  comparative  anatomy. 

At  this  point  we  may  close  our  account  of  the  biology  of  the  eighteenth 
century.  Before,  however,  proceeding  to  the  cultural  phenomena  —  already 
hinted  at  above  —  that  represent  the  basis  of  the  natural  science  of  the 
nineteenth  century,  we  must  take  a  glance  at  a  radical  reform  in  another 
sphere  of  natural  science,  which  contributed  towards  the  creation  of  modern 
biology. 


CHAPTER    XII 

THE     FIRST     BEGINNINGS     OF     MODERN     CHEMISTRY     AND     ITS 
INFLUENCE     UPON     THE     DEVELOPMENT     OF     BIOLOGY 

The  phlogiston  theory 

So  LONG  AS  chemical  processes  had  their  explanation  in  the  phlogiston 
theory,  it  was  certainly  possible  to  offer  a  provisional  explanation  of 
a  number  of  phenomena  in  the  sphere  of  combustion  and  oxidization, 
but  any  deeper  insight  into  the  material  changes  which  both  animate  and 
inanimate  nature  daily  undergo  was  of  course  out  of  the  question.  In  par- 
ticular the  qualitative  side  of  the  chemical  process  was,  as  far  as  this  theory 
went,  inexplicable.  In  spite  of  this,  the  theory  was  stubbornly  maintained 
during  the  greater  part  of  the  eighteenth  century,  doubtless  because  so  many 
discoveries  had  been  made  under  the  assumption  of  its  correctness,  which 
the  chemists  hesitated  to  interpret  anew.  For  the  rest  a  more  accurate  knowl- 
edge of  the  process  of  combustion  presupposed  a  knowledge  of  the  types 
of  gas  that  play  a  part  therein,  and  this  knowledge  was  not  acquired  until 
the  latter  half  of  the  eighteenth  century.  The  progress  made  in  this  field  of 
inquiry  is  primarily  bound  up  with  three  names:  the  Englishmen  Priestley 
and  Cavendish,  and  the  Swede  Scheele.  Priestley  deserves  still  further  mention 
as  a  discoverer  in  the  biological  sphere;  Cavendish  (173 1-1810)  is  best  known 
as  the  discoverer  of  hydrogen,  and  Scheele  (i74z-86),  one  of  the  most  bril- 
liant experimental  scientists  of  all  time,  succeeded  in  making,  in  spite  of  his 
short  life,  a  large  number  of  chemical  discoveries,  his  treatise  On  Air  and  Fire 
becoming  especially  famous. 

Joseph  Priestley  was  born  in  1733  of  a  Free  Church  family  of  the  artisan 
class  living  in  the  north  of  England.  After  studying  in  his  sect's  theological 
training-college  he  was  eventually  ordained  a  minister  and  served  in  several 
parishes,  partly  in  Birmingham.  An  extreme  radical,  both  in  religion  and 
politics,  he  was  a  supporter  of  the  French  Revolution,  which  resulted  in  his 
being  subjected  to  personal  persecution;  the  mob  attacked  him  in  his  home, 
which  they  pillaged,  and  he  himself  escaped  with  his  life  and  fled  to  London. 
As  he  found  no  peace  there  either,  he  emigrated  to  America  and  died  there 
in  1804.  Priestley  had  begun  to  carry  out  chemical  experiments  independ- 
ently; throughout  his  life  he  worked  quite  unsystematically,  heating  up 
and  treating  with  reagents  everything  that  fell  into  his  hands,  but  as  he 
possessed  a  great  gift  for  arranging  and  observing  his  experiments,  he  did 

x64 


SEVENTEENTH  AND  EIGHTEENTH  CENTURIES  165 
some  wonderful  pioneering  work.  One  of  the  chief  results  of  his  observations 
was  his  discovery  of  oxygen,  which  he  found  by  heating  mercury  monoxide; 
further,  he  experimented  successfully  with  carbonic  acid,  which  brought 
him  into  the  sphere  of  vegetable  and  animal  chemistry.  He  found  that  rats 
kept  in  a  volume  of  air  that  was  confined  by  water  died  as  a  result  of  the 
pollution  of  the  air,  but  by  letting  green  plants  stand  for  a  time  in  that 
same  air,  it  was  so  improved  that  fresh  rats  were  again  able  to  live  in  it 
for  some  time.  He  found  by  a  series  of  experiments  that  the  air  polluted  by 
the  animals'  breathing  contains  carbonic  acid,  or  "fixed  air,"  as  he  called 
it.  As  a  theorist  Priestley  was  not  particularly  original;  up  to  his  death  he 
stubbornly  maintained  the  phlogiston  theory,  which  had  already  been  aban- 
doned by  most  chemists  of  his  age. 

The  scientist  who  put  the  chemistry  of  combustion  on  the  right  road 
was  Antoine  Laurent  Lavoisier.  He  was  born  in  Paris  in  1743,  the  son 
of  a  lawyer,  and  was  given  an  excellent  education,  special  attention  being 
paid  to  mathematics  and  natural  science.  He  went  in  for  an  official  career, 
however,  and  in  time  became  a  "farmer-general"  —  that  is,  a  titular  mem- 
ber of  a  body  to  which  the  French  Government  had  leased  the  collection 
of  revenue.  This  system  naturally  gave  rise  to  a  good  deal  of  abuse,  and  its 
officials  were  not  much  better  tolerated  than  the  publicans  of  the  Jews  of 
old.  Lavoisier  had  never  been  guilty  of  fraud,  but  when  the  Revolutionary 
tribunal  condemned  his  colleagues,  he  was  likewise  involved  in  their  fall. 
Condemned  for  no  reason  at  all,  he  was  guillotined  by  the  Terrorists  in 
1794.  When  his  services  to  science  were  cited  as  grounds  for  mercy,  the  peti- 
tion was  met  with  the  reply:  "La  Republique  n  a  pas  besoin  de  savants." 

Lavoisier  founds  quantitative  chemistry 
It  has  been  said  of  Lavoisier  that  he  never  discovered  a  new  substance  or 
a  new  phenomenon,  but  that  he  introduced  a  new  spirit  into  his  science. 
Even  the  system  of  weights  and  measures  on  which  he  based  his  reform  had 
been  used  before  him  by  Hales  and  others,  but  Lavoisier  was  the  first  who, 
in  the  study  of  chemical  phenomena,  consistently  paid  attention  to  the 
weight  conditions  and  in  each  chemical  process  determined  their  immuta- 
bility, thereby  making  of  chemistry  an  exact  science  in  the  same  way  as 
physics.  Thanks  to  Priestley's  discovery  of  oxygen,  he  was  able  to  account 
for  combustion  and  he  gave  the  name  of  "oxgyen"  to  the  gas  which  had 
formerly  been  called  " dephlogisticated  air."  Likewise,  he  established  the 
fact  of  water's  being  composed  of  oxygen  and  hydrogen,  the  latter  discovered 
by  Cavendish.  Moreover,  he  found  out  that  heat  is  unweighable  —  a  fact 
which  still  further  explained  the  process  of  combustion.  He  also  applied  his 
weighing  method  to  life-phenomena;  he  shut  up  animals  in  a  confined  volume 
of  air  and  by  means  of  weighing  determined  the  change  brought  about  by 
their  breathing  therein.  He  established  the  fact  that  oxygen  is  the  component 


■l66  the    history    of    biology 

of  the  air  which  is  consumed  by  respiration  and  that  it  is  substituted  in  the 
lungs  for  carbonic  acid.  He  saw  chemical  processes  both  in  respiration  and 
in  animal  heat,  as  also  in  fermentation.  His  influence  on  the  development  of 
science  can  scarcely  be  too  highly  estimated;  through  him  chemistry  was 
led  into  entirely  new  channels;  through  the  discovery  that  oxygen  was  a 
constituent  common  to  a  mass  of  chemical  elements,  the  latter  could  be 
viewed  from  a  common  standpoint  and  could  be  given  a  nomenclature 
which  in  part  is  still  in  use  today.  Moreover,  to  natural  science  in  general 
these  discoveries  meant  a  complete  revolution,  as  they  paved  the  way  for 
the  knowledge  of  the  indestructibility  of  matter.  Lavoisier's  association 
with  biology  lies,  of  course,  mostly  in  his  knowledge  of  the  respiratory 
process.  It  was  vegetable  physiology  in  particular  that  felt  the  immediate 
influence  of  the  new  advance  in  chemistry.  Two  examples  of  this  are  given 
in  the  following. 

Jan  Ingenhousz  was  born  at  Breda,  in  Holland,  in  1730,  and  studied 
medicine  at  Leyden  under  Albinus.  As  a  medical  practitioner  he  was  espe- 
cially known  for  his  skill  in  smallpox  inoculation  —  an  operation  which  in 
those  days  was  not  unaccompanied  by  danger.  Persons  of  high  rank  came  to 
him  to  be  inoculated,  and  he  was  the  recipient  of  distinguished  and  high 
marks  of  appreciation.  He  died  during  a  journey  lo  England  in  the  year 
1799.  In  the  course  of  a  previous  visit  to  England  Ingenhousz  had  learnt  of 
Priestley's  above-mentioned  attempts  to  "improve  polluted  air"  by  the  in- 
troduction of  live  plants,  and  he  resolved  to  proceed  with  them  in  a  more 
extensive  and  systematic  form.  And  in  spite  of  the  fact  that  his  experimental 
apparatus  lacked  variety  and  originality  —  he  immersed  different  parts  of 
plants  in  water  and  collected  the  gas  thus  given  off  by  them  —  he  succeeded 
in  establishing  a  number  of  facts  of  fundamental  importance  for  the  knowl- 
edge of  plant  life.  He  found  that  the  production  of  "  dephlogisticated  air," 
which  constitutes  the  plant's  role  as  an  air-purifier,  is  a  prerogative  of  the 
leaves,  and  particularly  of  their  under  side,  and  that  it  is  brought  about 
exclusively  by  the  influence  of  sunlight  on  the  plant,  whereas  during  the 
night,  and  even  in  the  shadow  by  day,  a  kind  of  air  is  produced  that  is 
fatal  to  animal  life,  and  that  this  air  is  produced  by  roots,  flowers,  and  fruit, 
while  these  latter,  if  enclosed  in  a  confined  air-space,  render  it  impossible 
for  a  light  to  burn  in  it.  Ingenhousz  also  carried  out  quantitative  investi- 
gations, though  of  a  somewhat  primitive  nature.  In  this  field  both  he  and 
every  one  of  his  contemporaries  were  far  outrivalled  by  a  younger  scientist, 
who,  it  is  true,  had  the  inestimable  advantage  of  being  able  to  avail  himself 
of  Lavoisier's  new  methods. 

Nicolas  Theodore  de  Saussure  was  born  at  Geneva  in  1767.  His  father 
was  3  scientist  of  repute  and  was  interested  in  botany,  but  his  real  mefier 
was  geology.  The  son  also  eventually  became  professor  of  geology,  after- 


SEVENTEENTH  AND  EIGHTEENTH  CENTURIES  %^-J 
wards  entering  the  Genevan  representative  council  and  making  a  great  rep- 
utation both  as  a  scientist  and  as  a  public  citizen.  He  died  in  1845.  He  was 
both  a  chemist  and  a  physicist,  but  he  is  chiefly  known  for  his  work  on 
vegetable  physiology,  spending  years  in  the  investigation  of  the  subject  and 
finally  publishing  his  results  in  1804.  The  greatest  service  performed  by  this 
work  lies  in  the  fact  that  here  for  the  first  time  the  quantitative  method  of 
chemical  research,  as  founded  by  Lavoisier,  together  with  its  results,  were 
systematically  applied  to  living  subjects  of  investigation.  This  opened  up 
for  Saussure  entirely  new  possibilities  for  methodically  organizing  his  experi- 
ments that  his  predecessors  never  possessed.  He  enclosed  plants  and  parts  of 
plants  in  a  quantity  of  air  which  had  been  previously  weighed  and  carefully 
analysed,  and  after  having  let  them  live  there  under  different  conditions, 
in  light  and  in  darkness,  he  investigated  the  changes  in  the  composition  of 
the  air  which  their  manifestations  of  life  had  brought  about.  He  thus  estab- 
lished the  quantitative  relation  between  the  amount  of  carbonic  acid  ab- 
sorbed by  the  plant  in  light  and  the  quantity  of  oxygen  simultaneously 
given  off  by  it.  In  the  same  way  he  found  out  the  quantity  of  oxygen  absorbed 
by  a  plant  at  night,  and  also  the  quantity  of  water  consumed  in  association 
with  the  absorption  of  carbonic  acid  that  is  required  for  the  growth  of  the 
plant.  While  the  plant  was  thus  found  to  derive  the  quantitatively  most 
considerable  portion  of  its  nourishment  from  the  air,  Saussure  on  the  other 
hand  established  the  indispensability  of  the  mineral  constituents  which  it 
drew  from  the  earth,  and  which  he  determined  by  careful  analyses  of  the 
ashes  of  the  plants  investigated.  Finally,  he  also  found  out  that  the  per- 
centage of  nitrogen  that  the  plants  possess  is  primarily  absorbed  in  the  form 
of  ammoniac  associations.  On  the  other  hand,  Saussure  was  wrong  in  think- 
ing, in  contrast  to  Ingenhousz,  that  the  green  colour  of  the  leaves  is  not 
essential  to  their  vitality  —  a  misconception  (based  on  the  existence  of  red 
leaves  in  certain  varieties)  that,  owing  to  his  authority,  was  long  associated 
with  that  line  of  research. 

But  while  Lavoisier's  new  method  was  thus  immediately  applied  to 
biology  with  a  large  measure  of  success,  the  more  speculatively  inclined 
scientists  were  led  by  it  to  make  bold  guesses  —  as  is  usually  so  with  new 
discoveries.  In  the  romantic  natural  philosophy  we  shall  find  ideas  which 
were  awakened  to  life  by  the  great  revolution  in  chemistry. 


CHAPTER    XIII 

CRITICAL     PHILOSOPHY     AND     ROMANTIC     CONCEPTIONS 

OF     NATURE 

I.  Kant  and  his  Immediate  Successors 

Mafer/alism  and  spiritualism  i)i  the  eighteenth  century 

THE  TRANSITION  PERIOD  between  the  eighteenth  century  and  the  suc- 
ceeding era  is  characterized  by  the  violent  political  and  social 
convulsions  beginning  with  the  French  Revolution  in  1789  and 
ending  with  the  fall  of  Napoleon  in  181 5.  During  this  period  came  into  being 
the  modern  social  system,  which,  based  on  the  claim  of  the  private  citizen 
to  be  allowed  both  to  determine  his  own  actions  and  to  take  part  in  the 
administration  of  the  State,  is  sharply  contrasted  with  that  of  the  preceding 
age,  with  the  State  possessing  unlimited  authority  in  all  matters,  both  secu- 
lar and  spiritual.  But  even  from  a  purely  scientific  point  of  view  the  begin- 
ning of  the  nineteenth  century  involved  a  radical  revolution,  which  had 
been  long  preparing,  like  the  political  revolution,  throughout  the  centuries. 
In  the  eighteenth  century's  conceptions  of  nature  and  life,  the  two  tendencies 
described  in  the  foregoing  —  the  mechanical  and  the  mystical-spiritualis- 
tic —  appear  in  deep  contrast  to  one  another.  Out  of  the  former,  which  has 
its  origin  in  the  natural  philosophy  and  natural-scientific  research  of  the 
seventeenth  century,  and  which,  like  its  predecessors,  seeks  to  explain 
natural  phenomena  on  purely  mechanical  lines,  there  develops  towards  the 
close  of  the  eighteenth  century  —  during  the  so-called  "Era  of  Enlighten- 
ment" —  a  general  materialism  of  the  kind  that  we  have  seen  in  La  Mettrie: 
a  conception  of  life  expressing  itself  partly  in  a  dogmatically  formulated 
theory  of  existence  as  a  play  of  exclusively  material  forces,  and  partly,  in 
the  ethical  sphere,  in  a  doctrine  of  a  state  of  blessedness  common  to  all 
mankind,  based  ultimately  on  the  liberty  to  enjoy  life  independent  of  tradi- 
tional rules  of  conduct.  This  doctrine,  which  assumed  its  best-known  and 
most  popular  form  in  Holbach's  work  Systeme  de  la  nature,  is  remarkable  for 
its  readiness  to  answer  every  conceivable  question  in  accordance  with  the 
formula,  laid  down  once  and  for  all,  that,  provided  the  mechanical  explana- 
tion of  nature  is  maintained,  the  most  daring  constructions  of  thought  and 
the  weakest  verbal  subtleties  may  pass  as  complete  scientific  evidence. 
Intellectual  superficiality  and  banal  hedonistic  morality  thus  became  marks 

i68 


ID 

2 


"§iB 


H 
W 

O 
pq 

CO 

W 

Pi 
< 


SEVENTEENTH     AND     EIGHTEENTH     CENTURIES       T.G<^ 

of  the  enlightened  philosophy  and  contributed  in  succeeding  generations 
towards  concealing  its  services  in  the  political  and  the  social  sphere;  the 
philosophers  of  enlightenment  have  striven  unceasingly  for  humanity  and 
tolerance  in  the  life  of  the  State,  and  in  that  respect  their  activities  have 
left  a  deep  impression  on  the  social  life  of  our  own  day.  Parallel  with  the 
philosophy  of  enlightenment,  however,  there  developed  another,  entirely 
contrasted,  conception  of  nature,  the  precursors  of  which  had  been  Paracel- 
sus and  van  Helmont,  and  which,  possessing  in  Stahl,  Swedenborg,  and 
Caspar  Friedrich  Wolff  its  scientifically  most  important  representatives, 
appears  throughout  the  eighteenth  century  under  various  forms;  a  view  of 
life  which  sees  in  natural  phenomena  an  expression  for  the  operations  of 
spiritual  powers,  whereas,  according  to  its  tenets,  the  mechanical  explana- 
tion of  nature  admits  of  only  a  superficial  observation  of  what  takes  place, 
without  any  insight  into  that  inherent  connexion  in  existence  which  the 
spiritual  powers  imply.  This  attempt  to  regard  nature  as  a  living  entity,  to 
look  for  connexions  in  phenomena  where,  when  viewed  superficially,  none 
are  apparent,  has  constituted  this  tendency's  greatest  service,  besides  which 
the  freedom  of  mechanical  principles,  in  many  cases,  admitted  of  greater 
liberty  in  the  interpretation  of  special  phenomena,  as  Wolff's  embryological 
and  Sprengel's  botanical  investigations  proved.  The  weakness  of  this  spirit- 
ualistic view  of  nature  has  lain  in  the  frequent  desire  to  solve  by  mystical 
formulas  problems  the  solution  of  which  would  have  required  observation 
and  deep  thought,  and,  generally  speaking,  in  its  tendency  to  degenerate 
into  meaningless  phrases.  As,  moreover,  this  natural  mysticism  was  asso- 
ciated with  moral  and  religious  speculations  and  was  upheld  by  specially 
founded  mystic  communities,  there  was  thereby  created  that  extremely  un- 
sound "secret  wisdom"  that  under  various  names  and  forms  spread  with 
incredible  rapidity  at  the  close  of  the  eighteenth  century,  in  spite  of  protests 
and  ridicule  on  the  part  of  the  adherents  of  enlightenment. 

Kant  and  his  -philosophy 
Besides  these  two  directions  of  thought,  which  offered,  at  least  in  their 
more  extreme  forms,  but  slender  possibilities  for  the  further  advancement 
of  science,  there  appears  towards  the  close  of  the  eighteenth  century  a  new 
system  of  thought  which  really  gave  the  scientific  activities  of  the  next 
century  their  peculiar  character  —  namely,  critical  philosophy.  Its  founder 
was  Emmanuel  Kant  (1714-1804),  whose  life's  work  has  undoubtedly  rep- 
resented the  greatest  contribution  to  the  history  of  human  thought  since 
Socrates  and  Plato,  and  for  this  reason  his  work  merits  attention  even  as 
concerning  the  history  of  biology.  Kant  was  born,  lived,  and  died  at  Konigs- 
berg,  in  Prussia,  where  he  was  professor  of  philosophy  and  applied  himself 
entirely  to  his  work  as  a  thinker  and  teacher.  In  his  youth  he  had  studied, 
besides  philosophy,  certain  exact  sciences,  chiefly  physics  and  mathematics, 


■L-JO  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

and  throughout  his  life  he  retained  his  interest  in  natural  research,  not 
least  in  biology.  His  first  papers,  in  fact,  dealt  with  mechanical  and  cos- 
mological  problems;  the  best  known  of  these  is  his  Allgememe  Naturge- 
schkhte  und  Theorie  des  Himmels,  in  which  he  tried  to  set  up  a  mechanical 
theory  concerning  the  origin  of  the  universe.  On  this  subject  Swedenborg 
and  BufFon  had  been  his  precursors;  BufFon,  an  account  of  whose  cosmological 
theory  has  been  given  above,  seems  to  have  been  his  chief  source  of  inspira- 
tion. In  contrast  to  the  latter,  Kant  believes  that  the  planetary  system  has 
evolved  from  a  collection  of  dust  particles  which  moved  in  space  and  even- 
tually became  concentrated.  This  theory,  the  details  of  which  need  not  be 
recounted  here,  all  the  more  so  as  it  has  often  been  referred  to,  testifies  to 
Kant's  efforts  to  find  a  mechanical  explanation  of  existence.  Towards  the 
end  of  the  work,  however,  he  becomes  involved,  doubtless  under  the  in- 
fluence of  Swedenborg,  in  fantastic  speculations  about  life  on  other  heavenly 
bodies;  he  believes  that  on  the  more  distant  planets,  Jupiter  and  Saturn, 
there  are  beings  of  a  higher  order  of  intelligence  than  that  of  man  —  this 
because  the  inhabitants  of  the  more  distant  planets  must  be  made  of  lighter 
material  in  order  that  the  less  intense  solar  heat  there  may  set  them  in  mo- 
tion; but  the  lighter  the  corporeal  matter  the  greater  the  intelligence,  while 
heavy  bodily  fibres  and  dense,  "sluggishly  cooking"  fluids  result  in  in- 
ferior abilities.  Strangest  of  all,  he  cites  Newton's  calculations  in  support 
of  this  theory,  which  might  more  naturally  have  originated  from  the  earliest 
Greek  philosophers.  Kant,  however,  soon  rose  above  these  fantasies;  in  a 
paper  published  ten  years  later  entitled  Trdume  eines  Geistersehers  he  settles 
with  Swedenborg,  as  indeed  with  all  metaphysical  speculations  upon  the 
relation  between  spirit  and  matter.  He  ironically  examines  all  the  old  theories 
about  the  location  of  the  soul  —  now  existing  everywhere  in  the  body,  now 
located  in  a  small  section  of  the  brain  —  and  finally  proves  the  impossibility 
of  determining  how  the  soul  influences  the  body  or  whether  spiritual  beings 
can  exist  without  material  space;  reason  is  as  little  able  to  decide  this  ques- 
tion as  it  is  to  determine  how  anything  can  be  a  cause  or  can  possess  a  force  — 
which  are  all  matters  that  can  only  be  determined  by  experience;  and  alleged 
experiences  of  single  individuals,  such  as  Swedenborg's  visions,  cannot  form 
the  basis  of  a  law  of  experience  for  the  very  reason  that  they  are  isolated 
cases.  He  ends  by  pointing  out  that  there  certainly  are  many  things  that  we 
do  not  understand,  but  there  is  also  a  very  great  deal  that  we  do  not  need 
to  understand.  We  must  be  quite  clear  as  to  what  is  necessary  for  us  to  know 
and  what  in  that  respect  can  and  must  be  dispensed  with. 

Kant,  having  thus  exposed  the  futility  of  the  old  metaphysical  specula- 
tions, spent  more  than  ten  years  in  trying  to  find  out  the  limitations  and 
conditions  of  the  human  capacity  for  knowledge  in  general.  The  result  of 
these  researches  he  recorded  in  his  Kritik  der  reinen  Vernunjt,  published  in 


SEVENTEENTH  AND  EIGHTEENTH  CENTURIES  zyi 
1781  —  one  of  the  most  epoch-making  works  in  the  whole  history  of  human 
development.  Kant's  purpose  —  which,  in  fact,  he  at  least  partly  achieved 
^  —  is  to  lay  the  foundations  of  a  new  philosophy,  to  meet  not  only  all  the 
needs  of  human  life  in  the  way  of  knowledge,  but  also  its  moral  and  religious 
aims.  The  many  different  points  of  view  from  which  he  examines  the  work- 
ings of  the  human  mind,  as  well  as  the  laws  he  lays  down  therefor,  cannot 
of  course  be  recounted  here.  Chief  in  importance  for  the  future  advancement 
of  natural  science  is  his  attempt  to  determine  what  justification  natural 
science  has  for  assuming  the  truth  of  the  knowledge  of  nature  which  it 
expounds.  Kant  first  of  all  discusses  the  ideas  of  space  and  time  and  finds 
that  they  are  not  grounded  in  experience,  but  in  human  nature  itself;  all 
experience,  on  the  contrary,  is  based  on  our  having  the  ideas  of  space  and 
time  that  we  have.  And  the  same  part  that  time  and  space  play  in  our  views, 
the  idea  of  causes  plays  in  our  understanding.  The  knowledge  we  gain  by 
experience  is  a  knowledge  of  the  phenomena  that  appear  to  us  owing  to 
our  organization's  being  what  it  is.  What  those  things  that  cause  the  phe- 
nomena are  like  in  themselves  we  can  never  know  for  certain.  Natural 
science  is  thus  a  knowledge  of  reality  such  as  we  observe  it,  not  a  knowledge 
of  reality  as  it  actually  is.  Natural  laws  are  based  on  our  own  capacity  for 
knowledge  and  are  binding  on  us  because  this  capacity  has  certain  funda- 
mental qualities  that  are  the  same  for  all  men.  Natural  science  is  thus  fully 
justified  in  drawing  its  conclusions  in  the  world  of  experience;  on  the  other 
hand,  it  can  never  give  any  enlightenment  as  to  the  intrinsic  meaning  of 
things  —  that  is,  what  is  not  phenomenon  —  nor  indeed  does  it  need  to  do 
so  for  the  purpose  of  its  physical  explanations;  but  even  if,  say,  some  influ- 
ences from  the  immaterial  world  were  to  arise,  it  should  pass  them  over 
and  base  its  explanations  upon  what  the  senses  are  able  to  reveal  and  what 
is  reconcilable  in  accordance  with  the  laws  of  experience,  with  our  actual 
observations.  On  the  other  hand,  all  things  on  which  the  experience  of  the 
senses  can  give  us  no  knowledge,  such  as  what  the  soul,  the  world,  God, 
actually  are  in  themselves,  fall  outside  any  rational  knowledge.  Of  these 
things,  then,  we  can  know  nothing  —  we  can  maintain  neither  their  exist- 
ence nor  their  non-existence.  But  for  that  very  reason  we  are  able,  if  our 
feelings  require  it,  to  take  them  for  granted;  we  are  justified  in  believing  in 
God,  in  the  immortality  of  the  soul,  and  in  the  free  will,  and  reason  has 
no  right  to  reject  any  such  belief  as  irrational.  These  things  are,  in  fact,  a 
part  of  practical  reason  —  that  sense  of  duty  and  right  which  Kant  is  firmly 
convinced  is  inherent  in  everyone;  that  which  says,  not  ivhy  we  act  in  this 
or  in  that  way,  but  hotv  we  should  act  in  order  to  obey  the  dictates  of  con- 
science within  us.  —  Kant  himself,  in  spite  of  his  keen  criticism  of  the 
life  of  the  human  soul,  was  an  ideally  minded  personality  throughout  — 
an  enthusiast  over  such  questions  as  human  justice  and  social  equality,  who 


xyz  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

hoped  for  universal  peace  in  the  future.  The  highest  feeling  he  knew  he  used 
to  express  in  the  following  words:  "The  starry  heavens  above  me,  the  sense 
of  duty  within  me."  These  words  are  actually  carved  on  his  gravestone. 

His  influence 
Through  his  critical  philosophy  Kant  has  played  an  important  part  in 
human  cultural  development  in  general,  and  not  least  in  scientific  develop- 
ment. Thanks  to  his  criticism,  biology  was  freed  from  the  question,  which 
had  so  often  arisen  and  yet  had  never  been  solved,  of  the  relation  between 
soul  and  body;  biological  research  had,  as  its  exclusive  mission,  to  explain 
the  material  course  of  the  phenomena  of  life,  while  the  investigation  of  the 
spiritual  side  of  the  soul-life  became  the  function  of  the  science  of  psy- 
chology, employing  entirely  different  methods.  But  in  other  respects,  too, 
Kant's  critical  philosophy  exercised  an  influence  upon  the  development  of 
biology  in  the  century  that  followed;  many  of  its  leading  biologists  have 
been  keen  supporters  of  Kant;  for  instance,  Johannes  Miiller,  to  mention  only 
one  of  the  most  eminent.  But  Kant's  practical  criticism  of  reason  has  also 
indirectly  affected  the  development  of  natural  science.  He  thereby  established 
that  reason  can  neither  prove  nor  disprove  man's  personal  ideas  of  faith  and 
conscience,  so  that  any  attempt  to  influence  what  the  individual  holds  in 
high  esteem  and  deep  reverence  is  both  unjustifiable  and  irrational,  whether 
it  is  done  in  the  name  of  the  Church  or  in  that  of  science.  His  principle, 
just  and  reasonable  though  it  is,  has  nevertheless  found  it  difficult  to  gain 
a  hearing;  ever  since  then,  and  indeed  up  to  the  present  day,  there  have  been 
disputes  between  "faith  and  knowledge,"  brought  about  not  least  by  the 
fact  that  the  ecclesiastical  authorities  claim  that  their  doctrines  shall  be 
accepted  in  their  entirety  as  objectively  true.  The  Roman  Catholic  Church 
in  particular  has  banned  Kant  and  his  philosophy.  But  even  his  contem- 
poraries found  it  difficult  to  reconcile  themselves  to  the  strict  self-control 
that  Kant  enjoins  upon  human  thought;  that  nothing  was  to  be  known  of 
"things  in  themselves"  annoyed  both  the  old  philosophers  of  enlighten- 
ment, who  found  Kant's  thoughts  difficult  to  grasp  and  oversubtle,  and  also 
the  champions  of  the  mystical-romantic  class,  which  strove  after  a  uniform, 
comprehensive  view  of  existence.  In  particular,  thinkers  in  the  latter  di- 
rection, while  adopting  certain  of  Kant's  principles,  thought  to  bring  human 
knowledge  beyond  the  contrast  between  personal  consciousness  and  the 
''Ding  an  sich" ;  as  a  matter  of  fact,  the  whole  of  the  beginning  of  the  nine- 
teenth century  was  full  of  efforts  of  this  kind,  which  have  left  their  mark 
on  every  science,  and  indeed  on  the  whole  of  human  culture  during  this 
period  of  history.  And  so  far  as  they  influenced  the  development  of  biology, 
they  will  be  briefly  touched  upon  in  the  following  pages. 

JoHANN  Gottfried  Herder  (1744-1803)  was  a  fellow-countryman  and 
disciple  of  Kant's.  He  was  ordained  a  minister  and  held  a  living  for  a  time 


SEVENTEENTH  AND  EIGHTEENTH  CENTURIES  173 
in  Riga,  afterwards  spending  some  years  travelling  in  Europe,  and  finally, 
on  Goethe's  recommendation,  becoming  court  chaplain  at  Weimar.  At  the 
same  time  enthusiastic  and  irascible,  he  had  great  difficulty  in  getting  on 
with  people;  at  times  even  he  and  Goethe  would  be  on  bad  terms,  but  they 
would  soon  become  reconciled  again.  As  a  poet  and  student  of  folk-lore 
Herder  has  contributed  much  to  literary  history.  Pronounced  romanticist 
as  he  was,  he  sought  earnestly  for  a  uniform  conception  of  existence;  in  these 
efforts  Spinoza  was  his  principal  master  —  he  rescued  the  latter's  writings 
from  oblivion  and  was  an  ardent  supporter  of  the  more  mystical  views  con- 
tained therein,  whereas  Kant's  criticism  attracted  him  but  little.  In  his  prin- 
cipal work,  Ideen  xur  Fhilosophie  der  Geschkhte  der  Menschheit,  Herder  tries  to 
prove  how  one  and  the  same  spirit  dominates  the  whole  of  nature;  all  living 
beings  have  been  created  -according  to  one  common  plan;  their  various  char- 
acteristics correspond  to  their  peculiar  functions  in  life,  which  finally  reaches 
full  perfection  in  man.  In  the  whole  of  this  conception  of  the  course  of  life 
Herder  is  a  precursor  of  the  romantic  philosophy,  which  left  such  a  deep 
impression  even  on  biological  history. 

JoHANN  Gottlieb  Fichte  (1761-18 14)  is  generally  regarded  as  the  first 
of  the  purely  romantic  philosophers.  The  son  of  poor  parents,  he  suffered 
many  hardships  before  becoming  a  professor,  first  at  Jena,  where,  on  account 
of  his  strictly  moral  principles,  he  came  into  conflict  with  both  professors 
and  students  and  was  finally  dismissed  for  "atheism";  and  then  in  Berlin, 
where  he  worked  hard  for  the  elevation  of  morals  and  of  the  national  spirit 
under  the  oppression  of  Napoleon's  rule.  His  philosophy,  too,  is  mostly 
concerned  with  ethics;  he  is  of  only  indirect  importance  in  biological  history, 
as  having  been  the  teacher  of  Scheiling,  the  founder  of  natural  philosophy. 
Fichte  bases  his  philosophical  speculation  on  Kant,  but  he  also  felt  the  in- 
fluence of  Spinoza.  Kant  thought  that  our  consciousness  gives  us  the  idea 
that  we  have  of  a  thing,  whereas  the  thing  itself  is  unknown  to  us.  Fichte 
also  starts  from  the  idea  of  consciousness,  but  denies  the  existence  of  the 
thing  in  itself:  he  believes  that  the  consciousness  or  the  ego,  ''das  Ich,"  as 
he  calls  it,  is  the  only  true  thing  existing;  through  its  operation  it  then  gives 
rise  to  existence  apart  from  itself —  "the  ego  places  the  non-ego,"  runs 
the  oft-quoted  phrase,  which  primarily  refers  to  the  creative  work  which 
the  moral  will  of  man  performs,  for  the  moral  will  is  man's  true  ego  and  the 
central  point  in  the  whole  of  Fichte's  extremely  abstract  and  involved  spec- 
ulations. But  besides  the  individual  ego,  Fichte  assumes  an  "absolute  ego" 
—  a  kind  of  world-soul,  which  can  be  attained  by  man  only  through  "in- 
tellectual intuition"  —  a  kind  of  mystical  impulse  on  the  model  of  Spinoza. 
It  was  Scheiling  who  further  developed  his  idea,  making  it  one  of  the  foun- 
dations of  his  natural  philosophy. 

Friedrich    Wilhelm    Joseph    Schelling   was    born    at   Leonberg   in 


2.74  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

Wiirttemberg  in  1775.  He  was  the  son  of  a  clergyman  and  from  childhood  was 
destined  for  the  same  calling.  He  developed  early;  after  a  brilliant  career  at 
school  he  matriculated  at  the  age  of  fifteen  and  in  his  twentieth  year  had  taken 
his  doctor's  degree  in  both  philosophy  and  theology.  His  first  philosophi- 
cal studies  had  dealt  with  Spinoza,  Kant,  and  Fichte.  He  afterwards  spent  a 
couple  of  years  as  a  private  tutor  at  Leipzig  and  there  studied  natural  science, 
chiefly  chemistry  and  physics.  At  the  age  of  twenty-two  he  published  a 
work  which  at  once  brought  him  fame  —  Ideen  zu  einer  Philosofhie  der  Natur. 
Thanks  to  this  work,  he  was  appointed  assistant  professor  at  Jena  —  Goethe, 
who  was  much  interested  in  the  book,  had  recommended  him  to  the  Saxe- 
Weimar  Government  for  the  post  —  and  there  he  came  in  contact  with  a 
circle  of  men  and  women  of  genius  with  pronounced  romantic  views  on 
science  and  art.  There  was  one  who  exercised  special  influence  on  him  — 
Caroline  Michaelis,  a  gifted  and  energetic  woman,  who,  although  she  was 
twelve  years  older  than  he  and  had  had  a  somewhat  adventurous  past, 
became  his  wife  and  highly  influenced  his  work  as  an  author.  After  her 
death,  in  1809,  Schelling's  influence  actually  came  to  an  end.  Six  years  be- 
fore, however,  he  had  already  left  Jena,  where,  through  his  extraordinary 
insolence,  he  had  acquired  many  enemies  —  with  one  or  two  of  these  he 
entered  into  a  dispute  that  ended  by  their  all  being  condemned  for  libel. 
After  this  he  was  for  a  time  professor  at  Wiirzburg.  He  then  spent  a  long 
time  in  Munich  as  secretary  to  the  Academy,  but  he  was  finally  summoned 
to  Berlin  (in  1841)  for  the  purpose  of  using  his  romantic  philosophy  to 
counteract  the  increasing  radicalism.  In  spite  of  the  support  of  the  Govern- 
ment, however,  he  was  utterly  defeated;  his  enemies  published  his  lectures 
with  insolent  comments,  with  the  result  that  he  withdrew  altogether  from 
public  life.  He  died  in  1854.  His  character  was  conspicuous  for  ostentatious 
egotism  and  uncurbed  violence  by  the  side  of  a  devoted  faith  in  the  doctrines 
he  expounded.  Early  successes  spoiled  him,  and  when  later  he  was  confronted 
by  opponents  who  did  not  allow  themselves  to  be  frightened  by  his  over- 
bearing manners  and  scornful  polemics,  his  creative  power  vanished  entirely. 
The  work  that  brought  him  fame  was  completed  before  his  thirtieth  year; 
the  half-century  that  he  lived  after  that  added  nothing  to  his  renown. 

As  a  thinker  Schelling  based  his  ideas  on  Spinoza  and  Fichte.  With  Kant, 
on  the  other  hand,  he  had  but  little  sympathy;  the  doctrine  of  the  strict 
limitation  of  the  capacity  of  human  reason  that  Kant  taught  was  really  the 
direct  opposite  of  what  Schelling  desired  and  thought  himself  able  to  pro- 
duce. His  relations  with  Fichte,  however,  were  at  first  those  of  a  loyal  pupil, 
though  he  later  broke  entirely  with  him.  It  was  from  this  master  of  his  that 
Schelling  borrowed  the  principle  of  the  ego  as  the  basis  of  everything,  both 
in  the  spiritual  and  in  the  material  world.  The  greatest  influence  on  Schelling, 
however,  was  exercised  by  Spinoza,  with  his  doctrine  of  spirit  and  matter 


SEVENTEENTH     AND     EIGHTEENTH     CENTURIES       175 

as  different  forms  of  one  and  the  same  "substance"  and  with  his  principle, 
derived  therefrom,  of  the  validity  of  the  laws  of  human  reason  even  in  nature. 
When  afterwards,  in  Leipzig,  Schelling  became  acquainted  with  natural  sci- 
ence, chiefly  with  chemistry,  which  was  then  making  great  strides,  there 
awakened  in  him  a  desire  to  create,  like  Spinoza,  one  common  system  of 
thought  embracing  the  whole  of  existence,  which  was  to  prove  the  connexion 
between  the  worlds  of  nature  and  of  the  spirit,  in  that  the  world  of  nature 
would  be  derived  from  that  of  the  spirit,  and,  vice  versa,  the  world  of  the 
spirit  from  that  of  nature.  The  latter  became  the  aim  of  Schelling's  natural 
philosophy  proper,  which  in  one  place  he  terms  "  Spinozismus  der  Physik." 

Schelling  s  natural  philosophy 
From  this  a  new  natural  science  was  to  arise,  which  was  not  only  to  observe 
individual  phenomena  and  from  them  derive  certain  universal  principles,  but 
which  would  actually  understand  the  fundamental  forces  that  cause  all  that 
happens  in  nature.  Thus  it  was  a  program  of  natural  research  directly  opposed 
to  that  developed  theoretically  by  Bacon  and  practically  by  Galileo,  which, 
indeed,  research  has  followed  since  then.  Nevertheless,  Schelling  expresses 
the  deepest  contempt  for  this  natural  research;  in  one  place  he  calls  Bacon, 
Newton,  and  Boyle  the  bane  of  natural  science,  and  Lavoisier's  chemistry 
is  treated  with  no  less  disdain.  It  is  natural  enough  that  the  so-called  Spinoz- 
ism  which  Schelling  would  put  in  its  place  should  become  a  mere  dogmatic 
system  of  thought;  moreover,  as  he  was  entirely  lacking  in  patience  and 
consistency  in  matters  of  detail,  his  theory  became  vague  and  fragmentary. 
In  view  of  the  great  influence  it  exercised  on  the  development  of  biology, 
however,  an  attempt  must  be  made  to  describe  it. 

In  a  paper  entitled  Darstellung  ineines  Systems,  which  Schelling,  after  the 
manner  of  Spinoza,  wrote  in  the  form  of  a  series  of  statements  and  proofs  — 
though  unfortunately  entirely  without  that  strictly  binding  logic  which 
characterizes  every  sentence  of  the  great  Jewish  thinker  —  he  describes  first 
of  all  the  ' '  absolute  reason "  as  "  eine  tot  ale  Indifferent,  des  Subjektiven  und 
Objektiven,"  which  is  to  be  attained  by  thinking  of  reason  while  being  fully 
abstracted  from  one's  thinking  self.  This  is  indeed  ultimately  the  same  as 
the  mystical  view  with  which  Spinoza  concludes  and  with  which  Schelling 
thus,  strikingly  enough,  begins.  Outside  this  reason  there  is  nothing,  and 
in  it  is  everything.  The  supreme  law  governing  the  existence  of  reason  is 
the  law  of  identity  —  that  is,  A  =  A.  "Die  absolute  Identitat  kann  nicht  un- 
endlich  sich  selbst  erkennen,  ohne  sich  als  Subjekt  und  Objekt  unendlich  xu  setzen. 
Dieser  Satz.  ist  durch  sich  selbst  klar."  Thus  arises  the  contrast  between  subject 
and  object,  by  which  Kant,  as  we  know,  meant  the  consciousness  that  con- 
ceives and  the  thing  which  is  conceived,  and  which  in  Schelling  means  about 
the  same.  Further  on,  the  absolute  identity  is  said  to  correspond  to  the  uni- 
verse, whereupon  the  subject  and  object  are  denoted  by  A  =  B;  finally 


2.76  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

+ 
matter  corresponds  to  A  =  B,  because  in  matter  the  objective  predominates. 

Then  the  absolute  indentity  is  identified  with  light,  the  opportunity  being 
here  taken  to  sneer  at  Newton  for  his  spectral  investigation  and  to  compli- 
ment Goethe  upon  his  optical  theories.  From  matter,  on  the  other  hand, 
are  derived  gravity,  cohesion,  and  magnetism:  "Die  Materte  im  ganxen  ist 
ah  ein  unendlkher  Nlagnet  an%usehen,"  and  "  Der  Magnetismus  ist  bedingend  der 
Gestaltung,''  with  the  result  that  " alle  Korper  sind  blosse  Metamorphosen  des 
Eisens."  Electricity  and  magnetism  are  indentified  according  to  a  deriva- 
tion that  reasons  of  space  compel  us  to  pass  over,  as  also  the  derivation  of 
heat  from  the  foregoing.  Finally,  organism  is  derived  from  the  absolute 
identity.  As  an  example  of  Schelling's  biological  speculation  may  be  cited 
one  of  the  paragraphs  in  the  work  in  extenso  (the  spacing  is  Schelling's): 

,,  Der  poten^ierteste  positive  Pol  der  Erde  ist  das  Gehirn  der 
Tiere,  und  unter  diesen  des  Nlenschen .  Denn  da  das  Gesetz  der  Meta- 
morphose nicht  nur  in  Ansehung  des  Gan^en  der  Organisation,  sondem  auch  in 
Ansehung  der  einxelnen  gilt,  das  Tier  aber  der  positive  (^Stickstoff^  Pol  der  allge- 
meinen  Metamofphose  ist,  so  wird  im  Tier  selbst  ivieder  das  hbchste  Produkt  der 
Metamorphose  der  vollkommenste ,  d.h.  potenzjerteste  Pol  sein.  Nun  ist  aber  (wie 
bekanni^  das  Gehirn  das  hochste  Produkt  u.s.tv.  Also  etc. 

, ,  Anmerkung  i.  Der  Beweis  dieses  Sat^es  ist  jreilich  nicht  aus  den  chemischen 
Analysen  %u  jiihren,  aus  Grunden,  ivelche  kunjtig  allgemein  werden  eingesehen 
werden.  .  ,  . 

,,  Anmerkung  2.  Das  Bestreben  der  Metamorphose  im  Tierreich  geht,  wie  aus 
dem  bisherigen  leicht  xu  schliessen  ist,  notxuendig  durchgangig  auf  die  reinste  und 
potenzierteste  Darstellung  des  Stickstojfs.  —  Dieses  geschieht  in  dem  gebildeten 
Tier  fortivdhrend  durch  den  Process  der  Assimilation,  der  Kespiration,  tuelche 
bloss  daxu  dient,  den  K.ohlenstojf  vom  Blut  losxureissen;  ruhiger  und  nicht  mehr 
in  einem  stetigen  tinunterbrochenen  Process,  gleichsam  als  ob  die  Natur  iiber  sich 
schon  zu  Kuhe  gekommen  ware,  durch  die  sogenannte  ivillkurliche  Beivegung.  — 
Das  erste  ruhende  Tier  stellt  die  bereits  ganz  aus  sich  selbst  herausgekommene 
Erde  dar;  mit  der  vollkommensten  Gehirn-  und  Nervenmasse  aber  ist  ihr  Imierstes 
entfaltet  und  das  Reinste,  das  die  Erde  der  Sontie  gleichsam  als  Opfer  darbringen 
kann. 

,,Zusatz  J.  Das  Geschlecht  ist  die  Wurzel  des  Tieres.  Die  Blute  das  Gehirn 
der  Pflanzen. 

,,  Zusatz  2..  Wie  die  Pflanze  in  der  Blute  sich  schliesst,  so  die  ganze  Erde  im 
Gehirn  des  Menschen,  welches  die  hochste  Blute  der  ganzen  organischen  Metamor- 
phose ist.^'^ 

This  quotation  may  suffice.  If  the  reader  desires  more  he  is  referred  to  the 
original,  the  159  paragraphs  of  which  are,  some  slightly  less,  others  some- 
what more,  absurd  than  the  one  quoted.  Quite  out  of  our  subject  is  Schel- 


SEVENTEENTH     AND     EIGHTEENTH     CENTURIES      xyj 

ling's  transcendental  philosophy,  which  resolves  itself  into  a  glorification 
of  art,  as  being  the  identity  of  the  conscious  and  the  unconscious,  and  in 
which  subject  he  certainly  felt  far  more  at  home  than  in  natural  science. 

The  influence  of  his  system 
But  even  in  regard  to  natural  philosophy  it  would  be  entirely  unhistorical 
to  dismiss  Schelling  as  simply  and  solely  a  half-witted  fool,  as  is  so  often 
done.  This  is  at  once  inadmissible,  owing  to  the  extraordinary  influence  he 
exercised  on  his  own  age.  And  it  must  be  admitted  that  among  all  the  identi- 
fications and  derivations  that  constitute  his  system,  there  are,  besides  much 
madness,  a  number  of  really  brilliant  ideas,  which,  although  expressed  as 
mere  fancies,  nevertheless  undoubtedly  exerted  an  influence  upon  the  future 
development  of  science.  Thus  we  may  at  least  suppose  that  Schelling's  com- 
parison of  electricity  and  magnetism  was  not  without  its  influence  upon 
Orsted,  who  along  experimental  lines  discovered  electromagnetism  and  who 
in  his  youth  was  a  great  admirer  of  Schelling.  It  should  also  be  noted  that 
Schelling  had  a  keen  eye  for  the  physiological  contrast  between  plants  and 
animals,   which  lies  in  the  former's  oxygen-production  and  the  latter's 
oxygen-resorption;  the  significance  of  this  contrast  for  the  general  economy 
of  nature  he  has  realized  and  expressed  quite  clearly,  though,  it  is  true,  he 
draws  the  odd  conclusion  that  the  plant  has  no  life,  for  its  arises  merely 
through  the  development  of  the  life  principle  and  possesses  only  the  sem- 
blance of  life  "im  l^ioment  dieses  negativen  Processes."  — The  whole  of  the 
extraordinary  thought-system  which  he  built  up  finds  its  explanation  partly 
in  the  vast  possibilities  which  the  new  gas-chemistry  had  just  then  opened 
up  for  research  and  speculation  —  even  in  our  own  time  hopes  of  the  solu- 
tion of  the  riddle  of  life  have  more  than  once  been  placed  upon  important 
discoveries  in  the  field  of  natural  science  —  partly  in  the  change  from  criti- 
cism to  dogmatic  philosophy  which  Fichte  had  brought  about  with  his 
theory  of  the  ego  as  the  origin  of  all  things  and  which  was  in  complete  har- 
mony with  the  romantic  tone  that  was  peculiar  to  this  epoch,  particularly  in 
Germany.  People  dreamt  of  a  uniform  conception  of  existence,  they  looked 
for  spiritual  forces  in  nature,  they  had  grown  accustomed  to  the  mystical 
dreams  that  were  propagated  by  a  number  of  secret  brotherhoods,  and  all 
these  vain  strivings  Schelling  met  with  his  explanation  of  existence  as  an 
"absolute  identity,"  an  explanation  that  was  no  more  dogmatic,  indeed,  but 
certainly  more  poetic,  than  La  Mettrie's  and  his  successors'  materialism, 
which   had  constituted  the   natural  philosophy  of  the  previous  genera- 
tion. What,  after  all,  makes  Schelling's  natural  philosophy  useless  from  the 
point  of  view  of  natural  science  is  its  absolute  lack  of  practical  value;  if  the 
object  of  natural  science  is  to  extend  and  consolidate  man's  dominion  over 
nature  —  and  that  has  indeed  been  its  aim  ever  since  the  days  of  Aristotle 
and  Hippocrates  —  then  certainly  most  of  Schelling's  efforts  have  been  in 


xyS  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

vain,  however  much  genius  he  put  into  his  work.  But  even  as  a  purely  specu- 
lative thought-system  it  suffers  from  serious  defects  —  inconsistency,  daring 
conclusion,  and  lack  of  cohesion.  All  this,  however,  Schelling  took  quite 
lightly;  he  was  indeed  a  genius  and  an  artist,  and  these  factors  work,  accord- 
ing to  his  theory,  half  unconsciously  and  without  being  worried  by  the 
pedantry  of  the  man  in  the  street.  It  was  these  very  faults,  however,  that  soon 
proved  his  undoing;  it  was  just  in  the  purely  theoretical  sphere  that  his 
philosophy  was  out-distanced  by  another  system,  the  Hegelian,  which  was 
equally  abstract  and  unreal,  but  far  more  consistently  thought  out,  and  be- 
sides, from  the  scientific  point  of  view,  it  had  the  undeniable  advantage  of 
not  involving  nature  in  its  speculations. 

Georg  WiLHELM  Friedrich  Hegel  (1770-1831)  was  a  fellow-country- 
man and  school-friend  of  Schelling's  and,  though  older,  was  at  first  under  the 
influence  of  his  precocious  friend.  However,  he  eventually  worked  out  for 
himself  a  theory  of  his  own  and  in  his  first  independent  work  published  a 
severe  criticism  of  Schelling's  theory  of  the  absolute,  which  is  described  as 
the  "simplicity  of  the  emptiness  of  knowledge;  a  night  in  which  all  the  cows 
are  black."  Hegel  eventually  became  professor  in  Berlin  and  founded  a  well- 
attended  school,  which  he  subjected  to  strong  discipline.  What  impressed 
his  pupils,  and  indeed  his  entire  age,  was,  besides  his  commanding  person- 
ality, the  splendid  consistency  that  he  developed  in  his  system  of  thought. 
His  dialectical  method,  however,  according  to  which  every  idea  has  its 
opposite,  both  of  which  are  afterwards  brought  together  and  combined  into 
one  larger  idea,  has  no  concern  with  our  subject,  especially  as  Hegel  and  his 
disciples  expressed  the  deepest  contempt  for  nature  and  its  study  —  which 
gradually  resulted  in  natural  scientists'  turning  the  tables  by  generally  re- 
garding all  that  is  meant  by  philosophy  as  empty  prattle  about  empty 
fancies.  On  the  other  hand,  Hegel  performed  a  great  service  to  the  study  of 
history  in  insisting  upon  the  necessity  of  ascertaining  not  only  the  events 
that  took  place,  but  also  the  spiritual  movements  that  brought  them  about. 
A  similar  position  to  that  of  Hegel  in  Germany  was  held  in  Upsala  by  Kris- 
TOFER  Jakob  Bostrom  (1797-1866),  who  for  half  a  century  governed  that 
university  and  made  of  Linnasus's  ancient  seat  of  learning  a  centre  of  abstract 
speculation. 

But  though  Schelling  was  thus  worsted  in  the  theoretical  sphere,  his 
natural  philosophy  survived  as  a  general  theory  of  life  with  the  support  of  a 
whole  generation  of  contemporary  scientists.  The  cause  of  this  strange  phe- 
nomenon must  partly  be  sought  in  the  fact  that  there  was  no  other  equally 
comprehensive  explanation  of  nature  available,  and  some  such  explanation 
was  an  absolute  essential  of  existence  at  that  time.  But  there  were  many  con- 
tributing causes  thereto,  including  the  fact  that  Schelling's  natural  philoso- 
phy was  embraced  by  a  man  who  was  regarded  by  his  age  as  an  authority  in 


SEVENTEENTH     AND     EIGHTEENTH     CENTURIES       179 

every  sphere  of  culture  —  namely,  Goethe,  the  poet  and  universal  genius. 
As  is  well  known,  he  has  been  an  influence  even  in  the  field  of  biology  and 
it  is  this  side  of  his  work  that  will  be  described  in  the  following  section. 


z.  Goethe 

JoHANN  Wolfgang  Goethe  was  born  in  1749  of  wealthy  middle-class  parents 
at  Frankfurt  am  Main.  He  studied  jurisprudence,  first  at  Leipzig,  then  at 
Strassburg,  and  after  passing  his  law  examinations  practised  for  a  time  as 
a  lawyer  and  at  the  same  time  acquired  a  reputation  as  a  poet.  In  1775  ^^ 
came  to  the  court  at  Weimar,  which  was  interested  in  literature,  and  there, 
thanks  to  his  brilliant  intellectual  and  personal  advantages,  obtained  an 
eminent  position  —  not  only  as  poet  and  organizer  of  the  pleasures  of  the 
court,  but  also  as  an  official  he  held  the  highest  appointment  in  the  little 
Saxon  capital.  For  a  long  time  he  held  the  reins  of  government  with  success 
as  Minister  of  State  to  the  principality  of  Saxe- Weimar.  In  1786  he  made  a 
journey  to  Italy,  which  lasted  two  years  and  which  proved  of  decisive  im- 
portance in  his  life,  especially  in  regard  to  his  scientific  work.  Having  re- 
turned home,  he  gradually  withdrew  from  public  life  and  devoted  himself 
whole-heartedly  to  poetry  and  science.  Active  and  possessing  his  full  in- 
tellectual powers  to  the  last,  he  attained  a  great  age,  dying  in  i8t,x. 

Even  as  a  child  Goethe  had  evinced  a  lively  interest  in  nature;  he  ex- 
amined flowers  and  carried  out  experiments  in  electricity  and  magnetism. 
In  his  poems,  too,  there  was  conspicuous  from  the  very  first  a  keen  interest 
in  nature  —  a  gift  of  observing  and  describing  its  life  in  its  different  phases, 
which  greatly  contributed  to  his  fame.  During  his  student  days  he  received 
varied  impressions  from  the  extremely  chequered  intellectual  life  prevailing 
in  Germany  at  that  time;  he  became  acquainted  with  French  materialism, 
which  seemed  to  him  dry  and  unanimated;  on  the  other  hand,  he  engrossed 
himself  in  mystical  literature,  studying  the  writings  of  Paracelsus,  van  Hel- 
mont,  and  Swedenborg,  which  made  a  somewhat  deep  impression  on  him 
and  influenced  his  poetry.  In  Strassburg  he  made  the  acquaintance  of  Herder 
and,  as  he  himself  declares,  his  association  with  him  increased  his  inter- 
est for  the  study  both  of  nature  and  of  human  development.  Like  Herder, 
Goethe  admired  Spinoza  and  sought  in  him  a  basis  for  the  unity  between 
spirit  and  nature  that  he  desired  to  find  in  life. 

Goethe' s  anatomical  researches 
At  Weimar  Goethe's  interest  in  the  natural  sciences  was  increased  through 
his  intercourse  with  scientists  at  the  University  of  Jena  and  through  periodi- 
cal collaboration  with  Herder.  While  the  latter  was  putting  the  finishing 
touches  to  his  above-mentioned  Idcen,  Goethe  was  studying  anatomy  ac 


z8o  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

Jena.  Herder,  it  will  be  remembered,  was  endeavouring  to  find  one  com- 
mon type  for  the  form  and  functions  of  human  beings  and  animals.  During 
the  latter  half  of  the  eighteenth  century,  moreover,  a  dispute  had  been 
going  on  with  regard  to  the  relation  of  man  to  the  apes,  about  which  we 
heard  through  La  Mettrie  and  Camper;  the  former,  indeed,  had  sought  to 
prove  that  the  orang-utan  was  a  kind  of  human  being,  which  it  should  be 
possible  to  civilize,  and  the  indignation  the  theory  aroused  in  the  Chris- 
tian-conservative people  had  found  expression  in  violent  polemics,  while 
Camper,  through  his  paper  on  the  anatomy  of  the  orang-utan,  referred  to 
above,  gave  support  to  those  who  maintained  the  dignity  of  man.  Goethe, 
who  as  a  young  man  was  somewhat  averse  to  religion,  to  which  his  fa- 
mous poem  Prometheus  in  particular  testifies,  entered  into  the  dispute  on  the 
side  of  the  materialists.  Camper  had  asserted  that  in  the  facial  skeleton  of 
the  orang-utan  there  is  a  suture  which,  starting  from  the  nasal  cavity,  ex- 
tends on  either  side  as  far  as  the  space  between  the  corner  tooth  and  the  fore- 
most front  tooth;  this  suture  does  not  exist  in  man,  in  contrast  to  the  apes 
and  other  mammals.  In  consequence  of  this  Goethe  wrote  a  short  treatise  in 
which  he  maintains  that  the  intermaxillary  bone,  which  terminates  in  the 
said  suture,  is  found  also  in  man  —  an  assertion  based  chiefly  on  the  exist- 
ence of  sutures  which  in  the  gum  and  above  it  separate  the  bone  in  question 
from  the  upper  jaw  and  adjoining  bones.  Goethe  also  described  it  as  existing 
in  certain  other  mammals  in  which  this  bone  had  not  previously  been  found. 
The  treatise  was  sent  in  1784  to  Camper,  who  expressed  courteous  thanks  for 
it  and  specially  complimented  Goethe  on  having  established  the  existence  of 
the  bone  in  the  walrus.  In  regard  to  the  discovery  in  man,  on  the  other  hand. 
Camper  had  no  remarks  to  offer,  and  that  for  sound  reasons;  as  a  matter  of 
fact,  the  bone  had  been  known  ever  since  Vesalius's  days  and  had  been  de- 
scribed in  man,  in  whom  in  the  embryonic  stage  it  is  clearly  separated,  while 
in  full-grown  individuals  its  outer  suture  disappears.  This  difference  between 
man  and  the  ape  existed  just  as  Camper  had  pointed  out,  and  for  obvious 
reasons  Goethe  had  not  been  able  to  disprove  it.  The  fact  that  he  imagined 
he  had  "discovered"  the  intermaxillary  bone  in  man  was  no  doubt  due  to 
the  accident  that  some  text-books  of  that  time  treated  the  incompletely 
separated  bone  in  the  full-grown  man  as  if  it  were  one  with  the  maxilla 
superior.  The  claim  to  this  discovery  has  on  Goethe's  authority  even  reap- 
peared in  literary  histories  and  is  believed  by  the  public,  unjustifiable  though 
it  is.  Goethe's  pamphlet  on  the  question  remained  for  the  time  unprinted, 
presumably  owing  to  lack  of  encouragement  on  the  part  of  the  specialists; 
at  any  rate,  there  were  no  financial  obstacles  standing  in  the  way  of  its 
publication. 

Goethe,   however,  continued  his  anatomical  experiments  and  finally 
published  the  theoretical  views  at  which  he  arrived,  in  a  paper  entitled 


SEVENTEENTH  AND  EIGHTEENTH  CENTURIES  x8l 
Erster  Enfwurf  einer  allgemeinen  Einleitung  in  die  vergleichende  Anatomic,  dated 
1795.  He  starts  with  the  principle  that  natural  science  is  on  the  whole  based 
on  comparison  —  a  principle  upon  which  Aristotle  had  already  laid  great 
emphasis.  As  the  standard  of  comparison  Goethe  sets  up  an  ideal  type,  with 
which  the  anatomical  details  in  each  animal  form  are  to  be  compared.  Thus 
one  should  at  once  be  able  to  interpret  an  anatomical  detail  in  an  individual 
by  comparison  with  the  ideal  type.  Goethe  offers  no  detailed  description  of 
what  he  imagines  this  type  to  be  like,  and  indeed  it  would  have  been  difficult 
to  conceive  one.  Herder's  above-mentioned  speculations  on  an  ideal  type  have 
obviously  influenced  Goethe  here  far  more  than  the  already  existing  com- 
parative anatomy  such  as  Buffon,  Daubenton,  and  Camper  practised.  Even 
in  this  theory  Goethe  indulges  in  wild  philosophical  fancies,  as  when  he 
states  that  the  tail  of  mammals  ''ah  eine  Andeutung  der  Unendlichkeit  organischer 
Existenzen  angesehen  iverden  kann,''  or  when  he  says  of  the  body  of  the  snake 
that  it  is  " gleichsam  unendlirh,"  because  it  does  not  need  to  expend  matter 
and  force  on  extremities.  This  paper  also  remained  in  manuscript  form  for 
the  time  being. 

His  metamorphosis  of  plants 
Before  this,  however,  Goethe  had  published  the  treatise  that  is  generally 
acknowledged  to  be  his  principal  contribution  in  the  field  of  natural  science 
—  namely,  his  Versuch,  die  Metamorphose  der  Pflan^en  xu  erklaren,  which  was 
printed  in  1790.  The  gist  of  it  is,  briefly,  that  the  leaves  of  plants  gradually 
develop  through  "metamorphosis,"  which  first  gives  rise  to  cotyledons, 
then  to  the  stem-leaves,  and  finally  to  the  flower-leaves:  food-leaves  and 
petals,  stamen  and  pistils.  This  metamorphosis  can  partly  be  "regular"  or 
'  'progressive, "  "  welche sich  von  den  ersten  Samenblattem  bis  zur  letzten  Ausbildung 
der  Frucht  immer  stufeniveise  wirksam  bemerken  Idsst,  und  durch  Umwandlung  einer 
Gestalt  in  die  andere,  gleichsam  auf  einer  geistigen  Leiter  xu  jenem  Gipjel  der  Natur, 
der  Fortpflanzimg  durch  z^vei  Geschlechter  hinaujsteigt.'"  Irregular  metamorphosis 
is  one  of  nature's  retrograde  steps:  "ivie  sie  dort  mit  unwiderstehlichem  Trieb 
und  krdjtiger  Anstrengung  die  Blumen  bildet  und  xu  den  Werken  der  Liebe  rustet,  so 
erschlafft  sie  bier  gleichsam,  und  Idsst  unentschlossen  ihr  Geschopf  in  einem  unent- 
schiedenen,  weichen,  unseren  Augen  oft  gefdlligen,  aber  innerlich  unkrdftigen  und 
univirksamen  Zustande.''  Here  he  refers  to  double  flowers,  whose  stamens  are 
converted  into  petals.  Thenhe  goes  through  the  different  leaf-forms:  the  seed- 
lobes  are  thick  because  they  are  filled  with  raw  material,  while  the  leaves  of 
the  stem,  and  still  more  of  the  flower,  become  finer  and  finer  on  account  of 
the  fact  that  only  finer  saps  penetrate  into  them.  Another  idea  that,  besides 
the  saps  of  various  degrees  of  tenuity,  plays  a  conspicuous  part  in  Goethe's 
vegetable  physiology  is  ''Anastomosis,''  by  which  he  apparently  means  the 
intercommunication  between  various  parts  of  plants;  the  idea,  however, 
remains   obscure  and  is  certainly  not  made   any  clearer  by    the    fact    of 


x8l  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

fertilization's  being  called  "eine  geistige  /4«^j-/-o;;z(?j-e."  Even  florescence  is  caused 
by  "geistige  Krafte,"  since  the  operation  of  these  forces  preponderates  over 
the  raw  saps  that  form  the  leaves.  And,  finally,  Goethe  develops  a  theory  of 
germination,  according  to  which  the  seeds  and  the  leaf-buds  are  compared. 
Goethe  himself  admits  that  his  metamorphosis  work  does  not  contain  any 
really  original  observations;  the  metamorphosis  theory  itself  occurs  in 
Linnasus's  Philosopbia  botanica,  in  which,  under  the  heading  " Metamofphosis 
vegetabilis,"  the  bud,  the  leaf,  and  the  flower  are  analysed  and  the  leaves  in 
their  various  transformations  identified.  Goethe,  who  admits  that  he  had 
read  that  work,  nevertheless  claims  to  have  "discovered  metamorphosis"; 
by  this  he  cannot  reasonably  mean  anything  else  than  its  philosophical 
side  —  the  theory  of  the  ideal  type,  according  to  which  the  leaves  are  trans- 
formed. The  "Geistige"  that  so  frequently  recurs  in  the  treatise  on  metamor- 
phosis is  explained  by  the  fact  that  it  was  this  that  Goethe  considered  to  be 
the  essential,  as  also  did  Herder,  of  whose  theory  the  plant-metamorphosis 
doctrine  is  most  reminiscent.  For  it  is  romantic  philosophy  from  beginning 
to  end;  it  bears  no  resemblance  whatever  to  modern  natural  research. 

His  theory  of  colours 
It  was  in  the  course  of  his  journey  to  Italy,  as  a  result  of  the  impression  made 
upon  him  by  the  southern  vegetation,  that  Goethe  first  had  the  idea  of  his 
metamorphosis  theory.  During  the  same  journey  he  had  also  studied,  in 
company  with  some  artists  in  Rome,  the  laws  of  colour-combination  and  its 
effect  upon  the  sight.  Not  content  with  the  results  obtained  in  this  respect, 
he  resolved  upon  his  return  home  to  devote  himself  to  the  study  of  colours 
from  the  physical  point  of  view  as  well.  He  procured  a  prism  and  with  its 
aid  studied  a  number  of  light  and  colour  phenomena.  These  he  described 
with  great  lucidity  and  accuracy  in  a  work  entitled  Beitrdge  %ur  Optik,  pub- 
lished in  1791.  He  had,  however,  made  one  or  two  observations  —  that  the 
centre  of  a  large  white  surface  viewed  through  a  prism  remains  white  and 
that  a  black  line  on  a  white  ground  is  resolved  by  the  prism  into  colours  — 
which  he  considered  it  impossible  to  explain  by  the  Newtonian  laws  of 
optics.  It  is  true,  some  physicists  in  the  piofession  who  read  his  book  ex- 
plained the  phenomena  to  him  in  the  light  of  Newton's  theory,  but  Goethe 
does  not  appear  to  have  been  much  edified  by  it.  Then  Schelling  took  up  the 
question.  As  mentioned  above,  to  him  light  represented  the  "absolute 
identity,"  and  he  enthusiastically  hailed  Goethe  as  a  liberator  from  New- 
ton's detestable  spectral  theory.  The  poet,  who  was  extremely  sensitive  to 
applause  as  well  as  to  criticism,  was  thereby  entirely  won  over  to  the  new 
natural  philosophy  and  felt  encouraged  to  go  on  with  his  optical  investiga- 
tions in  the  hope  of  creating  a  new  "colour  theory"  in  place  of  Newton's. 
After  years  of  preparation  he  finally  (in  1808)  published  his  Farbenlehre  — 
the  greatest  of  his  scientific  works  and  the  one  that  he  himself  valued  most 


SEVENTEENTH  AND  EIGHTEENTH  CENTURIES  iS} 
highly.  The  theory  of  colour  that  he  develops  in  this  work  agrees  entirely 
with  Schelling's  polarity  theory.  All  colour-effect  is  derived  from  a  "primal 
phenomenon"  —  namely,  the  contrast  between  light  and  darkness;  between 
these  two  stands  as  a  connecting  link  '  'das  Trube. ' '  When  pure  light  is  broken 
up  by  a  prism,  it  is  disturbed  by  the  action  of  the  glass,  and  from  this  arise 
the  spectral  colours.  That  these  colours  arise  through  the  disturbance  of  the 
light  Goethe  tries  to  prove,  infer  alia,  by  the  fact  that  the  sun,  when  viewed 
through  a  darkened  glass,  appears  red.  Newton's  view  that  the  pure  white 
light  actually  arises  as  a  result  of  the  combination  of  the  various  colours  in 
the  spectrum  puts  Goethe  into  a  furious  passion;  he  goes  through  Newton's 
optics  point  by  point  and  provides  them  with  marginal  notes  which  are  as 
irrational  in  content  as  they  are  scurrilous  in  tone.  The  coarsest  expressions 
in  the  vocabulary  denoting  stupidity  and  dishonesty  are  lavished  on  page 
after  page  of  the  work.  Goethe  has  here  —  to  his  own  discredit  —  adopted 
his  admirer  Schelling's  polemical  vocabulary,  while  his  general  attitude 
towards  Newton  displays  in  a  deplorable  manner  the  narrow  limitations  of 
even  a  universal  genius.  Goethe  deserves  no  place  in  the  history  of  optics. 

Nevertheless,  Goethe  was  not  entirely  wrong  when  he  considered  the 
colour  theory  to  be  his  best  natural-scientific  work.  In  fact,  it  contains  a 
section  in  which  Goethe's  finest  gifts  as  an  observer  of  nature  are  given  full 
play  as  nowhere  else  —  namely,  the  chapter  on  "physiological  colours." 
In  this  chapter,  as  well  as  here  and  there  in  other  parts  of  the  work,  are  a 
large  number  of  observations  of  subjective  colour-perceptions,  recorded  with 
all  the  exactness  of  a  scientist  and  with  the  keen  insight  of  an  artist.  These 
detailed  observations  concerning  colour  harmony,  colour  contrasts,  com- 
plementary colours,  and  other  optico-physiological  phenomena,  attracted 
great  attention  even  among  his  contemporaries;  they  resulted  in  continued 
research  by  scientists  possessing  professional  knowledge  of  quite  a  different 
type  from  that  of  their  model,  and  even  in  our  own  day,  when  mental  phys- 
iology has  become  a  specialized  science,  they  have  won  justifiable  recog- 
nition. In  no  field  has  Goethe  so  nearly  approached  the  spirit  of  exact 
natural  research  as  he  has  here,  and  that,  too,  in  spite  of  the  false  theory 
for  the  sake  of  which  this  subsequent  research  work  was  carried  out. 

During  the  remaining  years  of  Goethe's  life  the  colour  theory  absorbed 
most  of  his  scientific  interest;  in  fact,  in  his  old  age  he  ended  by  valuing  it 
above  all  his  poetic  works.  This  was  manifestly  due  to  the  fact  that  as  a 
poet  he  considered  himself  neglected;  his  neo-romantic  proteges,  Schelling's 
friends,  had  come  to  dominate  public  opinion,  and  though  they  always 
treated  him  with  courtesy,  they  wounded  his  feelings  by  placing  their  own 
quite  mediocre  leaders  on  a  level  with  him.  On  the  other  hand,  they  loudly 
praised  his  scientific  speculations;  there  grew  up  quite  a  school  of  scientific 
students  of  natural  philosophy  who  looked  up  to  Goethe  as  a  prophet  — 


i84  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

all  these  being  factors  conducive  to  continued  scientific  production.  The 
colour  theory  was  reprinted  and  amplified;  the  anatomical  writings  of  his 
youth  were  published  and  largely  added  to,  the  ideal  primal  type  and  Schel- 
ling's  polarity  theory  reappearing  in  several  variations.  In  these  works  he 
tries  to  find  a  primal  form  for  the  anatomical  details,  just  as  he  did  a  primal 
phenomenon  in  optics;  he  invented  the  word  "miorphology,"  knowledge  of 
form,  and  it  still  survives  in  modern  science,  although,  it  is  true,  in  an  en- 
tirely different  meaning  from  that  which  Goethe  originally  gave  it.  Of  these 
works  may  be  mentioned  an  article  on  the  six  vertebra;  composing  the 
cranium.  Ten  years  before,  Oken  had  expounded  a  similar  theory,  which  will 
be  referred  to  later  on;  he  has  thus  the  prior  right  to  the  idea  and  declared, 
moreover,  that  he  mentioned  it  to  Goethe  in  the  course  of  conversation, 
which,  however,  the  latter  emphatically  denied.  It  is  scarcely  possible  now  to 
find  out  exactly  what  happened;  besides,  it  is  of  not  very  great  interest 
nowadays,  as  the  whole  theory  is  out  of  date. 

Spiral  theory 
The  article  "tjber  die  Spiralfenden^'  der  Vegetation  belongs  to  Goethe's  last 
years.  Both  in  its  idea  and  in  its  method  this  article  is  one  of  the  most  ec- 
centric imaginative  creations  of  the  romantic  philosophy,  but  for  this  very 
reason  it  aroused  great  enthusiasm  amongst  the  supporters  of  that  tendency, 
whilst  those  who  hoped  to  see  in  Goethe  a  modern  natural  scientist  passed 
it  over  in  complete  silence.  According  to  this  article,^  the  plant  is  composed 
of  two  indissolubly  connected  "tendencies":  the  vertical,  which  represents 
the  eternal  essence,  and  the  spiral,  which  represents  the  nourishing,  the  culti- 
vating, the  reproductive.  The  latter  tendency,  naturally  represented  by  the 
spiral  vessels,  is  given  a  number  of  utterly  incomprehensible  definitions:  "das 
Spiralsystem  ist  abschliessend,  den  Abschluss  befordernd.  Und  Z}(-'ar  auf  gesetxjiche, 
vollendete  Weise.  Sodann  aber  auch  auf  ungesefzliche,  voreilende  und  vernichtende 
IVeise."  The  aquatic  plant  Vallisneria,  in  particular,  the  male  flower  of  which 
grows  straight,  while  the  stalk  of  the  female  flower  after  fertilization  con- 
tracts into  a  spiral,  is  analysed  in  connexion  therewith,  the  result  being  that 
as  a  general  rule  the  vertical  represents  the  male  in  the  plant,  and  the  spiral 
the  female,  which  is  confirmed  by  the  ancient  metaphor  of  the  tree  and  the 
vine-tendril  which  winds  itself  round  it,  as  a  symbol  for  the  masculine  and 
the  feminine  in  life.  With  this  glimpse  into  the  innermost  soul  of  existence 
Goethe  concludes  the  "spiral"  article,  which  was  written  six  months  before 
he  died,  so  that  after  all  it  is  the  poet  in  the  old  philosopher  Goethe  that  has 
the  last  word,  which  is  only  right,  as  the  need  for  a  deeper  and  wider  poetic 
view  of  nature  was  undoubtedly  the  true  reason  for  his  coming  to  grips  with 
the  study  of  nature. 

1  Here,  too,  Oken  had  previously  dealt  with  the  question;  in  his  natural  philosophy 
there  is  a  fantastic  exposition  of  the  spiral  vessels  in  plants. 


SEVENTEENTH     AND     EIGHTEENTH     CENTURIES       2.85 

His  influence 
Goethe's  posthumous  reputation  as  a  natural  scientist  has  varied  generation 
after  generation.  From  the  exact  scientists  of  his  own  age  he  met  with  but 
little  encouragement  —  optical  science  in  particular,  which  was  just  in  his 
time  making  brilliant  progress  in  the  hands  of  Fresnel,  Wollaston,  Brewster, 
and  others,  naturally  left  him  far  behind  —  while,  on  the  other  hand,  the 
entire  school  of  natural  philosophy  saw  in  him  an  inimitable  master.  And 
with  good  reason,  for  as  a  matter  of  fact  he  did  more  than  any  other  to  pre- 
serve the  reputation  of  natural  philosophy.  When,  however,  this  tendency 
w-as  finally  abandoned  and  mercilessly  given  up  to  ridicule,  Goethe  was  ac- 
corded far  more  indulgent  treatment;  his  great  authority  as  a  poet  and  man 
of  culture  exempted  him  from  harsh  treatment  at  the  hands  of  scientific 
critics.  Goethe's  morphological  speculation  received  a  new  lease  of  life 
through  the  coming  of  Haeckel;  for  reasons  that  will  be  explained  later  on, 
Haeckel  expressed  a  boundless  admiration  for  Goethe  and  regarded  him  as 
one  of  the  foremost  precursors  of  Darwinism.  On  his  authority  both  the 
general  public  and  literary  history  have  since  willingly  accorded  Goethe, 
who  in  other  respects  has  left  so  many  marks  on  the  cultural  development 
of  our  time,  the  further  honour  of  being  a  natural  scientist  in  the  modern 
sense  of  the  term.  Nevertheless,  his  biological  writings  have  certainly  been 
more  admired  at  a  distance  than  read  in  the  original,  a  fact  that  has  no  doubt 
contributed  in  the  long  run  towards  concealing  their  true  quality.^  Goethe 
was  no  exact  scientist,  but  a  romantic  natural  philosopher;  in  that  capacity, 
however,  he  has  also  exercised  an  influence,  which  must  not  be  underesti- 
mated; his  psycho-physiological  observations  and  speculations  have  formed 
the  basis  on  which  men  like  Johannes  Miiller  and  Purkinje  have  built  up 
their  work,  and  although  Goethe  may  have  had  no  eye  for  comparative 
morphology  in  the  modern  sense,  yet  many  an  eminent  anatomist  of  later 
date  has  been  induced  by  Goethe's  ideas  to  devote  himself  to  a  comparative 
study  of  form  that  has  proved  of  benefit  to  science.  Goethe  takes  his  place  in 
the  history  of  biology  as  a  stimulating  force;  his  influence  was,  it  is  true, 
both  good  and  bad,  but  by  no  means  inconsiderable. 

-  So  far  as  is  known,  no  separate  edition  of  Goethe's  scientific  writings  has  existed  until 
recent  times;  those  desirous  of  studying  them  have  had  to  have  recourse  to  the  somewhat  ex- 
pensive editions  of  his  Sdmtlkhe  IVerkt.  An  edition  of  these  writings  was  published  some  years 
ago  by  R.  Steiner,  who,  as  is  well  known,  made  Goethe's  conception  of  nature  the  basis  of 
his  "  anthroposophical "  theory  of  existence,  which  does  not  in  the  least  accord  with  modern 
natural  science. 


CHAPTER    XIV 


NATURAL-PHILOSOPHICAL    BIOLOGY 


I.  Germany  and  Scandinavia 

Character  of  the  natural  philosophy  of  the  time 

THE  DIRECTION  taken  by  natural-philosophical  thought  that  has  been 
described  in  the  foregoing  has  played  a  very  important  part  in  the 
cultural  development  of  the  world  and  not  least  in  the  science  of 
biology.  There  were,  of  course,  during  the  natural-philosophical  period  a 
large  number  of  scientists  who  were  not  at  all,  or  only  very  slightly,  affected 
by  the  speculative  tendencies  of  natural  philosophy,  while  others,  it  is  true, 
embraced  its  tenets  either  temporarily  or  permanently,  but  at  the  same  time 
carried  out  research  work  in  exact  natural  science  with  lasting  results.  The 
work  of  these  scientists  will  be  recorded  later  on;  in  the  present  chapter  we 
shall  devote  our  attention  to  a  group  of  scientists  who  applied  themselves 
entirely  to  a  speculative  explanation  of  nature  and  sought  to  incorporate  in 
it  all  the  known  facts  about  nature  that  they  considered  necessary  and  attain- 
able, or  who,  at  any  rate,  in  a  more  or  less  pronounced  way  gave  themselves 
out  as  champions  of  such  views.  It  was  in  Germany  and  Scandinavia  in 
particular  that  these  faithful  disciples  of  Schelling  and  the  other  idealist 
philosophers  won  for  a  time  extraordinary  success  and  managed  to  present 
to  the  public,  and  particularly  to  the  universities,  their  master's  theory,  with 
amendments  of  their  own,  as  the  only  true  natural  science.  The  causes  of  this 
phenomenon,  which  must  seem  strange  to  us,  as  it  was  to  earlier  generations, 
were  manifold.  The  universal  cultural  tendencies  that  favoured  romanticism 
in  general  —  disappointment  at  the  failure  of  the  efforts  to  win  liberty  under 
the  revolution  and  weariness  after  the  great  wars  of  independence  —  natu- 
rally also  played  an  important  part  in  the  development  now  under  discussion; 
again,  the  interest  in  mysticism  that  spread  far  and  wide  at  the  close  of  the 
eighteenth  century  and  was  cultivated  by  the  numerous  brotherhoods,  un- 
doubtedly had  a  great  influence.  The  possession  of  some  form  of  knowledge 
that  is  unattainable  for  the  majority  has  always  been  an  attractive  prospect 
for  human  egotism  —  now  it  was  possible  for  the  professor  of  philosophy  or 
natural  science  at  the  university  to  present  to  his  hearers  a  theory  which  at 
any  rate  had  the  advantage  of  being  incomprehensible  to  the  uninitiated; 

i86 


o 

N 

% 

Pi 

o 


u 
< 

< 
1-1 


SEVENTEENTH     AND     EIGHTEENTH     CENTURIES       iSy 

when,  moreover,  according  to  its  tenets,  the  elect  possessed  the  right  to  be 
hailed  as  geniuses,  it  is  easy  to  realize  the  enthusiasm  which  the  new  wis- 
dom evoked.  The  result  was  that  there  developed  at  the  universities  such 
student  insolence  as  had  never  existed  since  the  days  of  scholasticism;  and  it 
survived  for  a  long  time,  especially  at  the  academies  situated  in  the  provincial 
towns,  where  neither  masters  nor  pupils  had  much  contact  with  practical 
life.  This  very  academic  isolation  explains  to  a  certain  extent  how  it  was 
that  these  theories,  so  out  of  accord  with  reality,  could  survive  for  so  long, 
and  explains  the  fact  that  they  were  localized  in  Germany  and  Scandinavia, 
while  in  western  Europe,  with  its  more  lively  and  practical  activities, 
speculation  at  least  adopted  more  dispassionate  forms. 

One  of  the  most  notable  and  influential  personalities  in  German  natural 
philosophy  was  Lorenz  Oken  (1779-185  i).  He  was  of  south  German  peasant 
stock,  his  family  name  being  really  Ockenfuss,  and  was  brought  up  in  poverty, 
though  he  managed  to  obtain  a  school  education  and  afterwards  studied 
medicine,  eventually  becoming  a  doctor,  in  1804.  Medicine,  however,  was 
not  of  very  great  interest  to  him;  at  an  early  age  he  had  formulated  a  natural 
philosophy  of  his  own.  After  having  maintained  himself  under  severe  pri- 
vations at  several  universities,  he  was  in  1807  appointed  assistant  professor 
at  Jena,  where  he  published  as  his  inaugural  address  his  paper  on  the  subject 
of  the  cranium's  being  composed  of  several  vertebra;.  This  resulted  in  his 
falling  into  disfavour  with  Goethe,  which  caused  him  considerable  un- 
pleasantness, all  the  more  so  as  he  was  of  a  passionate  nature  and  found  it 
difficult  to  exercise  discretion  in  his  behaviour.  Being  an  ardent  German 
patriot,  moreover,  he  was  enthusiastic  for  his  country's  unity  and  was  con- 
sequently suspected  by  the  authorities  in  the  reaction  after  the  War  of  In- 
dependence, for  which  he  zealously  agitated.  At  last,  in  1819,  he  was  forced 
to  resign,  although  he  had  the  support  of  the  entire  University;  he  was  for  a 
time  without  an  appointment,  but  afterwards  became  a  professor  at  Munich; 
there  too,  however,  he  was  unable  to  get  on  with  the  authorities,  so  that  he 
was  glad  to  accept  a  post  in  Zurich  in  1831.  He  carried  on  his  work  there, 
respected  and  esteemed,  for  the  rest  of  his  life. 

Oken's  activities  were  many-sided  and  his  influence  upon  the  develop- 
ment of  culture  considerable.  For  many  years  he  published  the  journal 
his  —  the  name  is  characteristic  of  his  half-mystical  philosophy  —  which 
became  a  focus  for  the  scientific  life  of  Germany;  with  great  impartiality  it 
accepted  papers  by  scientists  of  different  camps;  the  discussion  of  problems 
was  encouraged,  and  prizes  offered  for  solutions,  with  the  object  of  promoting 
scientific  research.  Oken  took  the  initiative  in  another  idea  which  has  proved 
of  value  to  the  future  of  science;  he  organized  meetings  of  scientists  for  the 
purpose  of  exchanging  views  and  encouraging  sociability.  Thus  it  was  he 
who  originated  those  gatherings  that  are  so  much  appreciated  in  our  own 


l88  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

day  and  which  he  himself  stimulated  and  developed  by  his  lively  personality 
and  his  keen  interest  in  the  whole  domain  of  thought.  Finally,  by  his  writings 
he  promoted  also  an  interest  in  the  study  of  nature;  his  Allgemeine  Naturge- 
schichte  fur  alle  Stdnde  is  a  compilation  of  a  very  high  standard  of  excellence, 
based  on  comprehensive  material,  which  has  widely  increased  the  knowledge 
of  and  interest  in  the  study  of  nature. 

Oken's  natural  philosophy 
Oken's  own  contributions  to  exact  natural  science  are,  on  the  other  hand,  of 
but  little  importance.  In  his  youth,  before  going  to  Jena,  he  carried  out  an 
investigation  into  the  development  of  the  intestine  in  the  embryo,  which 
contains  a  number  of  sound  observations,  though  his  conclusions  were  partly 
drawn  from  principles  that  were  not  very  successfully  thought  out.  Oken,  in 
fact,  considered  himself  above  all  a  natural  philosopher  and  set  great  store 
by  his  best  work,  Lehrbuch  der  Naturphilosophie,  which  he  rewrote  twice.  He 
was,  however,  not  very  learned  as  a  philosopher;  his  conclusions  were  as 
fantastic  as  Schelling's,  but  had  not  even  the  latter's  small  degree  of  formal 
consistency  and  logic.  Nor  did  he  possess  Goethe's  poetical  imagination, 
and  his  speculations  were  therefore  as  grotesque  as  they  were  irrational.  In 
particular,  the  first  part  of  his  work,  which,  strikingly  enough,  is  called 
"Theosophie,"  is  simply  extraordinary;  its  first  sentence  runs:  "Die  hdchste 
mathematische  Idee  oder  das  Grundprincip  aller  M.athematik  ist  das  Zero  =  0." 

Then  we  learn  that  God  and  the  world  =  O  H ,  while  God  alone  or 

the  primal  idea  =  O,  and  space  is  O  =  +  O  -.  When  we  come  to  the  living 
creatures,  the  whole  is  certainly  somewhat  closer  to  facts;  organic  life  is 
derived  from  a  primal  slime,  which  is  described  as  "oxydierter,  gewdsserter 
Kohlensfojf,"  and  which  had  its  origin  in  the  sea,  whence  all  life  comes.  Life 
is  formed  of  three  "entelechia;" :  magnetism,  chemism,  and  respiration.  In 
regard  to  plants,  Oken,  like  Goethe  later  on,  speculates  upon  the  spiral 
ducts;  to  Oken  they  are  '  'das  Lichtsystem  in  der  PJJanze. ' '  The  parts  of  the  plant 
correspond  to  the  four  elements,  the  root  being  the  earth-organ,  the  stem 
the  water-organ,  the  leaf  the  air-organ,  and  the  flower  the  fire-organ.  With 
regard  to  the  animal  kingdom,  all  animal  life  is  derived  from  a  follicle;  there 
are  four  consecutive  formations  thereof  —  the  point-,  the  ball-,  the  fibre-, 
and  the  cell-formation.  The  organs  of  animals  constitute  special  systems, 
first  "pfianzliche"  (namely,  intestine,  gills,  veins);  then  "thierige"  (bony, 
muscular,  and  nervous  systems).  Moreover,  the  animal  is  composed  of 
"Hirnfier"  and  "Geschlechtstier,"  both  of  which  possess  organs  that  corre- 
spond to  one  another,  as,  for  instance,  lung  and  bladder,  mouth  and  rectum, 
thorax  and  pelvis.  The  animal  kingdom  in  its  entirety  is  regarded  as  one 
mighty  animal,  the  various  parts  of  which  correspond  to  different  animal 
forms;  the  lowest  animals  have  only  intestine,  as  the  polypi;  then  come  such 
as  have  intestine  and  skin  —  snails  and  insects;  finally,  those  having  in- 


SEVENTEENTH  AND  EIGHTEENTH  CENTURIES  189 
testines,  skin,  and  flesh  —  the  mammals.  Further  quotations  vvould  be  super 
fluous.  We  find  in  the  above  a  great  deal  of  ancient  mysticism,  such  as  the 
mysticism  of  numbers  —  recurring  groups  of  three  and  four  —  the  comparing 
of  the  animal  kingdom  to  a  great  body,  reminiscent  of  Swedenborg's  specula- 
tions, and,  finally,  the  strange  idea  of  figures  at  the  beginning  of  his  work.  At 
the  same  time  we  find  here  some  occasional  idea  that  recalls  biological  theo- 
ries of  our  own  day,  as,  for  instance,  the  follicle-shaped  primal  animal,  the 
idea  of  the  sea  as  the  origin  of  animal  life.  Oken  was  undoubtedly  a  man  of 
ideas,  many  of  which  might  be  of  value  to  the  future;  his  unbridled  imagi- 
nation, however,  made  him  a  warning  to  the  succeeding  generation  and  an  ill- 
directed  example  of  what  the  results  of  natural -philosophical  speculation 
may  be. 

Christian  Gottfried  Daniel  Nees  von  Esenbeck  (1776-185 8)  forms  a 
parallel  to  Oken  in  the  sphere  of  botany.  From  the  south  of  Germany,  like 
Oken,  he  was  the  son  of  a  public  official;  he  studied  medicine  at  Jena,  where 
he  was  won  over  to  Schelling's  philosophy  and  came  into  contact  with 
Goethe.  Having  completed  his  studies,  he  settled  down  on  an  estate  that  he 
had  inherited  and  there  worked  as  a  private  scholar  until  the  year  1818,  when 
he  was  appointed  professor  of  botany  at  the  newly-founded  University  of 
Bonn.  He  established  the  botanical  institute  and  gardens  there  and  wrote  a 
number  of  books  on  both  botany  and  natural  philosophy.  Later,  having 
been  appointed  professor  at  Breslau,  he  began  by  doing  some  successful  work. 
In  old  age,  however,  the  romantic  natural  philosopher  became  ultra-radical; 
he  took  part  in  the  labour  movement,  zealously  supported  ideas  for  the  re- 
form of  Christianity,  and  worked  hard  in  theory  and  practice  for  free  mar- 
riage without  State  co-operation;  the  end  of  which  was  chicanery,  dismissal, 
and  death  in  poverty.  The  Labour  Union  at  Breslau,  whose  chairman  he  was, 
followed  him  to  the  grave. 

As  a  classifier  of  plants,  Nees  von  Esenbeck  has  acquired  a  distinguished 
name;  he  has  won  special  fame  for  his  tropical  floras,  dealing  with  the  phan- 
erogamous plants  of  the  Cape  and  of  Brazil;  his  works  on  the  cryptogams, 
on  lichens  and  hepaticas,  alga;  and  fungi  were  also  at  one  time  highly  thought 
of.  He  himself,  however,  set  greater  store  by  his  natural-philosophical  spec- 
ulations. In  his  Lehrbuch  der  Bofanik,  which  he  dedicated  to  Goethe,  he  carried 
the  latter's  metamorphosis  theory  to  the  uttermost  extreme.  To  him  the 
leaf  is  a  kind  of  symbol  for  the  plant  as  a  whole;  the  entire  vegetable  world 
is  to  him  one  mighty  leaf,  just  as  the  animal  world  was  to  Oken  one  mighty 
animal.  Even  in  the  vegetable  world  the  number  three  plays  an  important 
and  mystical  role  and  is  the  basis  for  a  good  deal  of  play  upon  words.  Polarity 
in  the  style  of  Schelling  recurs  once  more;  the  fungi  represent  the  north  and 
the  plants  the  south,  the  animals  midnight  and  man  noon,  while  the  chemi- 
cal components  of  plants  are  dealt  with  just  as  arbitrarily.  The  colours  in 


Z90  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

the  vegetable  kingdom  are  of  course  treated  in  accordance  with  Goethe's 
theory  of  colour.  Even  the  spiral  vessels  give  rise  to  a  number  of  speculations, 
although  Goethe's  theory  had  not  yet  been  published.  The  spiral  theory  was, 
in  fact,  developed  later  by  a  large  number  of  botanists  who,  like  Nees  von 
Esenbeck,  could  be  quite  rational  collectors  and  systematists,  but  who  at 
the  same  time  gave  play  to  a  wild  and  reckless  imagination  on  the  subjects 
of  the  spiral  and  polarity,  till  at  last,  in  this  sphere  also,  exact  research 
claimed  its  due. 

One  of  the  last  survivors  of  Germany's  natural  philosophers  is  worthy 
of  mention  —  Carl  Gustav  Carus  (1789-1869).  Born  in  Leipzig,  he  became 
professor  of  comparative  anatomy  there  in  181 1  and  afterwards  professor  of 
gynaecology  and  court  physician  at  Dresden.  As  a  doctor  he  was  an  eminent 
specialist  and,  besides,  a  man  of  unusually  varied  interests;  a  personal  friend 
of  Goethe's,  he  had  a  truly  artistic  nature  and  was  himself  a  good  painter 
and  writer  on  art,  as  well  as  a  comparative  anatomist  and  natural  philoso- 
pher. He  experimented  in  comparative  osteology,  insect  anatomy,  and  zo- 
otomy. His  comparative  anatomy  (of  182.8)  stands  to  a  certain  extent  on  the 
border-line  between  the  contemporary  and  a  more  modern  conception  of  that 
science.  Carus,  for  instance,  no  longer  goes  in  for  the  plus  and  minus  signs 
with  which  his  predecessors  wasted  their  time  without  in  the  least  solving 
their  problems;  to  him,  indeed,  nature  is  an  expression  of  an  idea,  and  life  is  a 
flux,  and  the  three-grouping  recurs  here  and  there;  but  he  is  at  any  rate  able 
to  describe  an  organ  or  a  system  of  organs  without  at  once  becoming  in- 
volved in  sheer  incomprehensibilities.  He  sets  up  an  animal  system  arranged 
in  circles,  one  inside  the  other,  with  the  protozoa  outermost  and  man  inner- 
most, and  with  not  very  successful  descriptions,  but,  on  the  other  hand,  he 
gives  a  comparative  account  of  the  nervous  system  throughout  the  animal 
kingdom  that  is  arranged  clearly  and  in  an  exact  form  throughout.  In  1861,  as 
an  old  man,  Carus  summarized  his  ideas  in  a  work  entitled  Nafur  und  Idee, 
which  certainly  strikes  a  curious  note,  considering  the  advances  that  natural 
science  had  already  made  by  that  time.  Here  we  find  ether  regarded  as  the 
primal  substance  and  the  essence  of  all  chemical  elements;  after  which  we  are 
told  that  ''die  Urbandlung  des  Athers  ist  Leben."  The  nervous  system  is  the 
central  force  in  the  animal  kingdom,  like  the  primal  fire  and  the  electrical 
principle  in  the  earth;  the  universe  is  an  infinite  sphere  whose  centre  point  is 
everywhere  and  whose  periphery  is  purely  ideal.  Again,  animals  arise  out  of 
a  sphere,  the  ovum,  and  develop  through  new  spheres*  being  added  to  the 
original;  the  senses  are  drawn  in  the  corners  of  a  pentagram  inscribed  in  a 
circle.  When  this  work  was  published,  Darwin's  theory  of  selection  had  been 
known  for  two  years.  Thus  the  last  representative  of  natural  philosophy  in  its 
most  extreme  form  survived  up  to  modern  times. 

The  neo-romanticist  natural  philosophy  was  brought  to  Scandinavia 


SEVENTEENTH     AND     EIGHTEENTH     CENTURIES      191 

by  Henrik  Steffens,  who,  although  he  has  played  little  part  in  the  develop- 
ment of  biology,  nevertheless  deserves  mention  here  owing  to  his  importance 
in  cultural  history.  Born  at  Stavanger,  in  Norway,  he  studied  in  Copen- 
hagen and  Kiel  and  after  a  period  of  wandering  came  to  Jena,  where  he  be- 
came an  enthusiastic  admirer  of  Schelling,  a  friend  of  Oken,  and  a  natural 
philosopher  heart  and  soul.  He  returned  to  Copenhagen  in  1802.  and  for  a  year 
or  two  lectured  at  the  University,  but  as  he  obtained  no  permanent  post 
there,  he  accepted  an  appointment  in  Germany,  where  he  remained  for  the 
rest  of  his  life.  During  the  years  he  spent  in  Denmark  he  exercised  great  in- 
fluence by  his  enthusiastic  promulgation  of  natural  philosophy,  although  his 
exaggerations  aroused  doubts  in  the  minds  of  the  Danes,  which  were  not 
perceived  by  his  less  critical  friends  in  Germany.  His  principal  work  on 
natural  philosophy  dealt  with  the  internal  natural  history  of  the  earth;  in  it 
he  seeks  to  prove,  inter  alia,  that  the  various  strata  of  the  earth  are  sections 
of  a  galvanic  element.  Of  importance  to  the  history  of  biology  was  his  theory 
of  the  origin  of  the  circular  coral  islands;  he  believed  that  they  grew  up  on 
the  edge  of  volcanic  craters  in  the  ocean,  and  this  theory  was  accepted  as  true 
by  many,  until  Darwin  disproved  it  by  his  well-known  investigations  into 
the  subject. 

In  Sweden  natural  philosophy  was  embraced  by  the  famous  Carl  Adolf 
Agardh  (1785-1859),  known  as  one  of  Sweden's  most  many-sided  geniuses. 
He  was  a  native  of  Scania,  matriculated  at  Lund,  and  eventually  became 
lecturer  in  mathematics  and  professor  of  botany  and  economics  at  that 
University.  He  ended  by  being  Bishop  of  Karlstad,  after  having  won  renown 
as  a  botanist,  mathematician,  national  economist,  priest,  and  politician. 
Only  his  sphere  of  activity  as  the  first  belongs  to  this  narrative.  At  Lund 
Agardh  became  acquainted  with  the  Linn^an  system  of  plant  classification, 
and  in  the  course  of  journeys  in  Germany  he  came  to  know  Schelling  and 
natural  philosophy.  His  most  lasting  fame  he  has  won  as  one  of  the  founders 
of  alga;  classification;  much  of  the  system  that  he  created  still  exists  today. 
He  has  also  made  valuable  contributions  in  connexion  with  plant  classifica- 
tion as  a  whole;  in  particular  he  was  one  of  the  first  to  pronounce  against  the 
sharp  difference  that  had  hitherto  been  held  to  exist  between  phanerogams 
and  cryptogams.  His  general  views  with  regard  to  animate  nature  he  has  col- 
lected in  a  handbook  of  botany  published  in  the  years  1818-32.,  the  first  part 
of  which  he  dedicated  to  Schelling.  This  first  part,  entitled  "Organography," 
contains  also  traces  of  the  influence  of  natural  philosophy;  nevertheless 
Agardh  displays  a  degree  of  caution  in  speculation  that  is  in  favourable 
contrast  to  the  rashness  of  his  German  master.  Thus  he  at  once  declares  on 
the  first  page  that  natural  objects  cannot  be  exactly  defined  on  a  logical  basis; 
he  believes  that  we  have  to  content  ourselves  with  establishing  in  each  what 
is  the  most  common  phenomenon  or  the  most  usual  form,  without  venturing 


X9X  THE     HISTORY      OF     BIOLOGY 

to  lay  down  rules  having  no  exceptions.  And  when  he  quotes  Nees  von 
Esenbeck's  above-mentioned  comparison  between  natural  objects  and  the 
points  of  the  compass,  he  does  so  with  the  —  certainly  mild  —  reservation 
that  "this  method  of  philosophizing  is  beautiful  but  obscure."  On  the  other 
hand,  he  can  hit  upon  such  eccentric  ideas  as  that  the  human  hands  may 
represent  leaves  between  which  the  head  sits  like  a  bud;  and  the  metamor- 
phosis theory  likewise  leads  to  a  number  of  extremely  bold  comparisons 
between  the  stages  of  development  in  plants  and  animals.  But  there  is  observ- 
able throughout  a  keenness  of  observation  in  points  of  detail  which  proves 
that  the  teachings  and  example  of  Linnsus  had  not  lost  their  influence  in 
his  own  country.  The  second  section,  on  vegetable  biology,  treats  of  the 
manifestations  of  life  in  plants  and  is  on  the  whole  more  exact  than  the 
former  section. 

Another  important  representative  of  natural  philosophy  in  Scandinavia 
was  Israel  Hwasser  (1790-1860).  He  was  the  son  of  a  priest  at  Alvkarleby, 
and  after  being  educated  at  home  he  matriculated  at  Upsala,  where  in  1812. 
he  took  the  degree  of  doctor  of  medicine.  Five  years  later  he  became  pro- 
fessor of  medicine  at  the  academy  of  Abo,  where  he  exercised  considerable 
influence.  The  medical  education  there,  which  had  fallen  into  decline,  was 
improved  by  him  in  regard  to  both  the  number  of  students  and  the  standard 
of  the  knowledge  imparted,  while  he  himself  succeeded  in  gathering  about 
him  friends  and  pupils  who  took  part  in  his  idealistic  labours.  In  1830  he 
applied  for  and  obtained  a  professorship  in  Upsala,  where  he  afterwards 
worked  until  his  death.  The  reason  for  his  transfer  was  that  he  wished  to 
counteract  the  scheme  just  then  being  proposed  for  removing  the  medical 
school  to  the  Carolinian  Institute  in  Stockholm,  which,  he  argued,  was  at 
variance  with  the  principle  of  the  connexion  of  ideas  in  scientific  education. 
But  he  maintained  his  interest  in  Finland  throughout  his  life.  He  was  in 
everything  an  ideally  minded  personality  who  in  speech  and  writing  as  well 
as  in  private  company  was  a  zealous  supporter  of  patriotism,  loyalty,  and 
clean  morals  and  in  this  respect  exerted  great  influence  on  the  young  people 
in  the  University.  His  scientific  activities  he  desired  also  to  place  entirely 
at  the  service  of  moral  ideals.  He  was,  it  is  true,  a  natural  philosopher,  but 
he  did  not  approve  Schelling's  speculations,  especially  the  attempt  to  con- 
struct nature  out  of  an  idea;  on  this  attempt  he  passes  the  weighty,  and  on 
the  whole  correct,  judgment:  "It  was  a  scientific  extravagance  pushed  to 
extremes,  which  in  the  minds  of  some  of  those  who  took  part  in  it  seemed 
to  have  been  fostered  and  supported  by  a  pride  nearly  akin  to  madness." 
On  the  other  hand,  he  was  a  great  admirer  of  Sydenham  and  still  more  so 
of  the  French  anatomist  Bichat,  who  will  be  described  later  on.  His  whole 
conception  of  life  in  nature  is  characterized  by  his  deeply  ethical  aims.  He 
is  dissatisfied  with  those  who,  starting  from  the  lower,  would  try  to  under- 


SEVENTEENTH     AND     EIGHTEENTH     CENTURIES      193 

Stand  the  higher,  whether  they  do  so  by  means  of  theoretical  construction 
or  practical  investigation.  In  general  he  despises  any  dealings  with  matter 
as  such  and  denies  its  indestructibility.  To  him  life  is  a  magnificent  process 
of  ethical  refining;  to  his  mind  the  development  of  the  individual  represents 
the  selfish  element,  while  reproduction,  which  entails  self-sacrifice  for  the 
welfare  of  the  race,  is  the  highest  element  in  the  organism.  He  is  zealous 
also  for  an  ideal  conception  of  love  and  marriage  and  for  that  reason  dis- 
approves of  Goethe's  sensual  love-poetry  and  therewith  of  all  that  Goethe 
did.  His  theory  of  disease  as  self-destruction  in  the  individual  is  in  accord- 
ance with  this,  his  conception  of  life.  Nevertheless,  he  by  no  means  dis- 
approved of  practical  medical  education,  though  he  himself  had  little  to 
do  with  it,  owing  to  bodily  clumsiness,  and,  as  he  himself  declared,  conse- 
quent laziness.  As  will  have  been  seen  from  the  above,  his  biological  theory 
was  no  less  inconsistent  with  true  nature  than  Schelling's,  but  at  any  rate 
it  had  the  advantage  of  assuming  as  its  chief  mission  the  improvement  of 
morals,  which  Schelling's  certainly  did  not.  It  was  in  any  case  Hwasser's 
personality  that  exercised  the  best  influence;  it  is  mostly  for  this  that  he  is 
remembered  today. 

In  Finland  Hwasser's  natural  philosophy  was  maintained  after  his  death 
by  his  faithful  friend  and  pupil  Immanuel  Ilmoni  (1797-185 6),  who  shared 
his  ideas  and  warmly  defended  them.  With  the  passing  of  these  two  men 
natural  philosophy  disappears  from  the  universities  of  the  North,  where,  as 
a  matter  of  fact,  it  had  never  made  the  same  progress  that  it  had  done  in  Ger- 
many; biology  was  mostly  carried  on  throughout  the  natural-philosophical 
period  on  Linnasn  principles;  moreover,  men  like  Berzelius  and  Anders 
Retzius  were  working  for  exact  natural  research,  and  natural  philosophy 
had  no  rivals  in  Scandinavia  to  compete  with  them. 


2..     England  and  France 

Cultural  development  in  ivestern  Europe 
Natural  philosophy  has  by  no  means  played  the  same  part  in  the  two  lands 
of  culture  in  western  Europe  as  it  did  in  Germany.  The  reason  for  this  may 
be  sought  ultimately  in  the  national  character  of  their  peoples,  Englishmen 
and  Frenchmen  always  showing  themselves  less  speculative  and  more  in- 
clined to  direct  their  energies  towards  practical  aims  than  the  Germans. 
And  indeed  practical  functions  were  far  more  attainable  in  those  uniformly 
governed  and  well-organized  western-European  kingdoms  than  in  the  di- 
vided and  politically  disillusioned  country  of  Germany.  The  reaction  against 
the  opinions  of  the  eighteenth  century  sought  and  found  its  expression,  both  in 
England  and  France,  in  politics,  both  of  Church  and  State,  and  in  literature. 


194  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

while  science  was  abk  to  continue  its  work  undisturbed  by  any  serious 
revaluations  of  the  old  standards.  Speculative  tendencies  had  indeed  existed 
in  these  countries  at  an  earlier  period  —  Buffon  is,  of  course,  the  most  bril- 
liant example  —  and  the  theories  of  the  true  natural-philosophical  age  often 
appear  as  continuations  of  those  tendencies,  while,  on  the  other  hand,  they 
serve  as  the  transition  between  the  past  and  exact  science  in  the  nineteenth 
century.  Nevertheless,  even  during  this  period  there  arose  scientists  whose 
speculations  had  more  in  common  with  the  natural  philosophy  so  far  de- 
scribed, and  who  to  a  certain  extent  actually  had  direct  points  of  contact 
with  it.  It  is  now  proposed  to  give  one  or  two  examples  of  speculations  of 
this  kind,  while  such  scientists  as  seem  to  stand  in  a  more  direct  relation 
to  modern  biology  will  be  discussed  at  the  beginning  of  the  next  section  of 
this  work. 

In  England  natural-philosophical  speculation  has  been  a  familiar  prac- 
tice from  early  times.  Many  of  its  pioneers  have  combined  a  wealth  of  origi- 
nal ideas  and  theories  for  explaining  natural  phenomena  with  somewhat 
unsystematic  methods  of  thought  and  experiment.  More  or  less  gifted  authors 
of  this  type  there  were  in  abundance,  especially  in  the  numerous  circles  of 
private  scholars  in  England.  In  this  category  may  be  included  Erasmus  Dar- 
win (i73i-i8ox),  whose  speculations  caused  a  sensation  in  his  day,  not  only 
in  England,  but  also  on  the  Continent.  Born  at  Nottingham  of  an  old  stock, 
he  devoted  himself  to  medicine,  studied  in  Cambridge  and  Edinburgh,  and 
finally  practised  as  a  doctor  at  Lichfield.  He  is  described  as  very  original, 
vigorous  and  somewhat  coarse-grained,  honest  and  straightforward;  besides, 
he  was  a  keen  worker  and  well  thought  of  in  his  profession,  kind  towards 
the  poor,  and  an  ardent  supporter  of  temperance.  He  had  many  children; 
one  of  his  sons  was  the  father  of  Charles  Darwin,  and  a  daughter  became 
the  mother  of  Francis  Galton,  the  student  of  heredity.  Apart  from  his  own 
profession,  Erasmus  Darwin  was  an  indefatigable  author  and  wrote  a  great 
number  of  papers  for  the  Royal  Society  and  also  published  one  or  two  col- 
lections of  poems,  with  which  he  himself  was  highly  satisfied,  but  which 
fell  a  victim  to  the  ridicule  of  his  contemporaries  and  the  neglect  of  posterity. 
The  work,  however,  which  alone  has  made  his  name  memorable  is  his 
Zoonomia,  an  attempt  to  find  out  the  laws  of  organic  life,  which  was  pub- 
lished in  1794  and  was  translated  into  several  European  languages. '  It 
excited  a  good  deal  of  attention  at  the  time;  the  German  natural  philoso- 
phers in  particular  have  quoted  it  with  appreciation.  In  modern  times,  how- 
ever, it  would  certainly  have  caused  but  little  notice  had  not  the  author 
been  the  grandfather  of  Charles  Darwin.  At  first  sight  it  gives  the  impression 
of  being  a  most  extraordinary  conglomeration  of  diverse  notes  on  scientific 

^  The  author  has  not  succeeded  in  coming  across  the  original  of  this  work,  but  has  been 
compelled  to  have  recourse  to  Brandis's  German  translation. 


SEVENTEENTH     AND     EIGHTEENTH     CENTURIES       2.95 
and  medical  subjects;  but  on  closer  inspection  we  find  that  it  deals  with  a 
number  of  problems  that  engaged  the  minds  of  the  author's  contemporaries, 
although  from  a  curious  point  of  view. 

Erasmus  Darwin's  natural  philosophy 
The  work  begins  with  the  assertion  that  spirit  and  matter  are  the  foundations 
of  nature;  then  life  is  defined  as  being  due  to  a  special  force,  which,  after 
Haller,  is  called  irritability  and  by  aid  of  which  all  life-phenomena  are  ex- 
plained in  a  somewhat  peculiar  manner.  All  manifestations  of  life,  both  phys- 
ical and  psychical,  are  due  to  the  contraction  of  fibres,  which  is  induced  by 
irritation;  by  "idea"  the  author  understands  a  contraction  of  the  fibres  that 
form  the  direct  sensory  organs.  La  Mettrie  himself  could  hardly  have  ex- 
pressed himself  more  materialistically,  but  Erasmus  Darwin  is  by  no  means 
a  materialist  as  the  term  was  understood  by  his  own  age;  true,  he  refers  to 
the  sceptic  Hume's  inquiries  into  cause  and  effect,  but  at  the  same  time  cer- 
tifies his  invincible  faith  in  the  Bible,  quoting  verses  of  the  Psalms  on  the 
wisdom  of  the  Creator  and  citing  the  words  of  Moses  in  the  Book  of  Genesis 
touching  the  creation  of  Eve  from  Adam's  rib  as  a  proof  of  his  own  theory 
of  reproduction.  This  latter  theory,  more  than  anything  else  that  Erasmus 
Darwin  wrote,  attracted  great  attention,  which  indeed  it  undoubtedly  de- 
served. To  a  certain  extent  it  is  reminiscent  of  Caspar  Friedrich  Wolff's  theory 
of  evolution  —  that  is  to  say,  in  so  far  as  it  is  markedly  epigenetic.  Whether 
the  author  had  recourse  to  Wolff  is  not  clear  from  his  work  —  possibly  he 
had  on  second-hand  information.  But,  above  all,  his  theory  is  pronouncedly 
animalculistic;  just  as  the  whole  basis  of  his  theory  of  life  rests  on  the  as- 
sumption of  "irritable"  fibres  being  the  basic  substance  of  all  living  things, 
so  the  origin  of  the  embryo  is  a  "  filament, ' '  which  is  derived  from  the  father 
and  to  which  the  mother  only  gives  nourishment.  As  a  result  of  this  latter 
the  embryo  grows,  by  no  means,  however,  as  a  result  of  the  development 
of  ready-formed  rudiments,  but  through  the  addition  of  fresh  matter.  The 
author  seeks  to  disprove  the  preformation  theory  by  arguments  both  serious 
and  facetious;  Bonnet's  incapsulation  theory  in  particular  seems  to  him  ex- 
ceedingly ludicrous;  the  dimensions  of  the  infinite  number  of  embryos  con- 
tained one  inside  the  other  remind  him  of  how  St.  Anthony  was  tempted 
by  twenty  thousand  devils,  all  dancing  on  a  pin-point.  In  further  confirma- 
tion of  his  epigenesis  theory  he  declares  that  the  male  "filament"  which 
gives  rise  to  the  new  individual  is  manifestly  influenced  by  the  nourishment 
which  the  mother  provides;  any  resemblance  between  mother  and  child  is 
due  thereto,  as  is  particularly  shown  in  bastards.  And  still  further:  the  con- 
ditions under  which  the  parents  live  clearly  influence  the  character  of  their 
offspring,  as  is  proved  by  the  new  varieties  obtained  from  domestic  animals; 
organs  which  the  animals  need  are  produced  by  irritation  in  the  parts  of  the 
body  which  form  them,  and  they  are  afterwards  inherited  by  their  progeny. 


196  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

Thus  stags  have  got  horns,  and  cocks  spurs,  while  fighting  for  their 
mates.  In  fact,  one  is  justified  in  assuming  that  all  living  creatures,  different 
from  one  another  as  they  now  are,  nevertheless  originate  from  one  and  the 
same  "primal  filament,"  whose  offspring  have  become  changed  as  a  result 
of  different  conditions  of  life,  this  being  confirmed  by  the  existence  of  tran- 
sition between  all  animal  and  vegetable  forms,  both  higher  and  lower.  This 
theory  undoubtedly  sounds  to  a  certain  extent  "Darwinian,"  but  what  dif- 
ferentiates the  grandfather's  doctrine  from  the  grandson's  is  the  problem 
each  set  out  to  solve:  Erasmus  Darwin  really  had  no  interest  in  the  origin 
of  species;  with  him  it  was  a  question  of  obtaining  as  strong  evidence  as 
possible  for  the  epigenesis  theory,  which  was  a  marked  feature  of  his  specu- 
lations. Nor  indeed  was  it  this  side  of  his  work  that  evoked  contemporary 
interest;  it  was  rather  his  speculations  on  the  subject  of  the  life-force  and, 
further,  his  theory  of  irritability  and  his  observations  of  sense-impressions, 
which  he  made  with  a  view  to  confirming  the  latter  theory  and  which  in 
a  certain  degree  foreshadow  Goethe's.  All  this  afforded  special  interest  to 
the  German  natural  philosophers,  who  not  infrequently  refer  to  his  writings. 
He  was  entirely  forgotten  by  the  succeeding  generation;  in  fact,  it  was  not 
until  after  Charles  Darwin  had  become  world-famous  that  interest  in  Eras- 
mus revived,  when  an  attempt  was  made  to  see  resemblances  between  his 
speculations  and  those  of  his  grandson.  Some  resemblance  there  certainly  is, 
but  it  is  undeniable  that  the  originator  of  the  theory  of  selection  had  worked 
with  entirely  different  qualifications  from  his  grandfather's  in  order  to  pro- 
duce a  universal  theory  of  the  evolution  of  life. 

In  France  biological  speculation  during  the  latter  half  of  the  eighteenth 
century  was  essentially  governed  by  Buffon's  ideas.  He  and  his  friend  Dau- 
benton  had,  it  will  be  remembered,  carried  out  comparative  investigations 
into  the  anatomy  of  various  animals,  especially  the  bone-structure  of  mam- 
mals. During  the  following  epoch  also  French  scientists  were  keenly  occupied 
in  investigations  of  this  kind,  and  natural  philosophy,  to  which  such  investi- 
gations were  at  that  time  referred,  thereby  assumed  a  more  defined  and  prac- 
tical character  than  in  Germany.  Moreover,  its  exponents  stand  out  far 
more  clearly  as  the  precursors  of  modern  biology  and  deserve  to  be  discussed 
in  connexion  therewith.  In  particular,  he  who  is  regarded  as  the  foremost 
natural  philosopher  that  France  has  produced  —  Lamarck  —  seems,  in  view 
of  the  great  influence  he  has  exercised  on  modern  research,  to  be  most  worthy 
of  record  amongst  its  pioneers.  A  natural  philosopher  who,  on  the  other 
hand,  is  far  more  closely  associated  with  the  German  speculation,  and  who 
was  actually  connected  with  it,  was  Geoffroy  Saint-Hilaire.  He  may  there- 
fore suitably  be  described  in  this  context. 

Etienne  Geoffroy  Saint-Hilaire  was  born  at  Etampes,  near  Paris,  in 
the  year  177^,  the  son  of  a  public  official.  His  father  had  him  educated  for 


SEVENTEENTH  AND  EIGHTEENTH  CENTURIES  197 
the  priesthood  and  actually  procured  him  a  benefice,  but  at  the  same  time 
allowed  him  to  follow  his  bent  for  natural  studies.  Highly  gifted,  impulsive, 
and  passionate,  young  Geoffrey  became  deeply  engrossed  in  the  study  of 
chemistry,  crystallography,  and  anatomy.  During  the  Revolution  he  dis- 
tinguished himself  by  rescuing  a  number  of  priests  from  death  during  the 
massacres  in  September  1791  at  the  risk  of  his  own  life.  In  spite  of  this  he 
was  appointed  in  the  following  year  by  the  Revolutionary  Government  pro- 
fessor of  zoology  at  a  newly-founded  educational  establishment  and  at  once 
became  known  for  his  brilliant  energies  and  success.  Cuvier,  who  was  at 
that  time  still  quite  unknown,  was  promoted  to  another  professorship  under 
his  recommendation.  Eventually  Cuvier  was  to  rise  above  the  head  of  his 
patron,  but  for  the  time  they  collaborated  with  success  in  the  sphere  of  com- 
parative anatomy.  When  Bonaparte  made  his  famous  expedition  to  Egypt, 
Geoffroy  accompanied  him  as  zoologist  and  succeeded  in  making  there  a 
number  of  splendid  collections,  which  he  later,  thanks  to  his  resolute  action, 
prevented  from  falling  into  the  hands  of  the  English.  The  result  was  that, 
upon  returning  to  Paris,  he  won  still  further  honours.  He  won  less  glory 
in  an  expedition  that  he  m.ade  to  Portugal,  in  whose  museums  he  brought 
together  ' '  collections ' '  at  the  command  of  Napoleon  on  behalf  of  the  French 
State.  His  later  years  are  mainly  characterized  by  an  increasing  rivalry  and 
enmity  with  Cuvier;  they  were  very  largely  contrasts  to  one  another.  In  his 
old  age  he  became  blind  and  finally  also  paralytic.  He  died  in  1844. 

Geoffroy' s  comparative  anatomy 
The  comparative  anatomy  introduced  by  Buffon  and  Daubenton  was  enthusi- 
astically embraced  by  Geoffroy  and  Cuvier.  The  development  to  which  this 
science  attained,  chiefly  thanks  to  Cuvier,  who  made  it  one  of  the  most 
important  foundations  of  modern  biology,  will  be  described  in  the  following 
section.  Nor,  indeed,  was  GeofFroy's  contribution  towards  the  progress  of 
this  science  without  its  significance,  but  at  quite  an  early  age  there  developed 
in  him  a  fancy  for  imaginative  speculation,  which  justifies  his  being  placed 
in  the  category  of  theorizing  natural  philosophers.  It  has  been  thought  pos- 
sible to  trace  the  influence  of  German  natural  philosophy,  especially  Schel- 
ling's,-  in  this  tendency  of  his,  but  as  it  was  not  until  later  that  Schelling's 
writings  were  translated  into  French,  one  can  hardly  suppose  that  there  was 
any  direct  influence  from  that  quarter.  These  fantastic  speculations  were  cer- 
tainly characteristic  of  the  age;  he  had  predecessors  in  this  respect  even  in 
French  literature;  one  need  only  recall  the  name  of  Bonnet.  The  main  idea 
in  Geoffroy's  philosophy  is  the  existence  of  a  common  fundamental  type, 
beginning  with  the  organization  of  all  the  vertebrate  animals,  and  then  for 
the  entire  animal  kingdom  in  general.  He  worked  principally  at  the  anatomy, 

^  According  to  Kohlbrugge  in  his  essay  on  Goeche;  see  the  Bibliography  at  the  end  of 
the   book. 


X^S  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

particularly  the  bone-structure,  of  the  vertebrates,  and  here  he  has  really 
worked  out  a  number  of  ideas  which  foreshadow  results  that  have  been 
gained  by  modern  comparative  anatomy.  He  thus  derives  the  auditory  bone 
of  mammals  from  the  cranial  bone  in  fishes  —  doubtless  from  the  opercula 
and  not  from  the  bones  now  regarded  as  the  starting-point.  He  derives  the 
cartilage  of  the  larynx  from  the  fishes'  branchial  arches  —  as  has  indeed 
been,  at  least  partially,  done  in  present-day  comparative  anatomy.  But  here 
at  once  his  unbridled  imagination  manifests  itself  in  the  utter  lack  of  detailed 
criticism  and  ability  to  limit  his  speculative  field;  thus,  for  instance,  he  finds 
a  sternum  in  fishes,  and  he  derives  the  annular  cartilages  of  the  trachea  from 
the  gill-arches,  just  as  he  delights  in  making  direct  comparisons  between 
fishes  and  mammals  in  general.  (In  passing,  he  makes  the  truly  natural- 
philosophical  assertion  that  the  auditory  apparatus  of  birds  is  the  finest 
there  is,  which  is  proved  by  the  fact  that  they  are  so  musical.)  He  indulges 
in  his  wildest  flights  of  fancy,  however,  when  he  compares  vertebrates  and 
invertebrates.  To  his  mind,  insects  and  crustaceans  are  composed  of  verte- 
bras, in  which  both  apophyses  and  ribs  can  be  distinguished  —  the  joints 
are  vertebrae,  and  the  extremities  ribs.  The  shells  of  the  tortoise  and  the  snail 
are  compared,  and  the  ink-fish  is  a  vertebrate  animal  with  a  duplication  of 
the  back.  One  realizes  that  this  application  of  the  theory  of  a  common  fun- 
damental type  for  the  animal  kingdom  must  have  impressed  Goethe.  In  the 
dispute  that  eventually  broke  out  between  Geoffroy  and  Cuvier  —  which 
will  be  described  later  —  Goethe  loyally  supported  Geoffroy.  When  Cuvier 
died,  Geoffroy  was  left  free  to  promulgate  his  own  theories,  which  were 
also  adopted,  in  part  at  least,  by  his  son,  Isidore,  who  was  likewise  an  emi- 
nent biologist.  The  more  critical  comparative  anatomy,  besides  eradicating 
the  worst  exaggerations,  eventually  acknowledged  the  wealth  of  ideas  and 
the,  in  many  respects,  productive  thoughts  that  were  to  be  found  in  Geof- 
froy Saint-Hilaire. 

The  natural-philosophical  school  of  thought  which  we  have  endeav- 
oured to  describe  above  has  had  a  deep  influence  on  the  development  of  bi- 
ology. Its  extravagances  cannot,  of  course,  be  regarded  as  other  than  features 
tending  to  retard  the  sound  progress  of  science;  time  has  also  helped  to  put 
them  out  of  mind,  or  at  worst  they  have  been  recalled  only  for  the  purpose 
of  ridiculing  the  weaknesses  of  an  older  generation.  The  service  it  has  ren- 
dered to  humanity  lies  in  the  lively  interest  for  the  study  of  nature  which 
it  evoked  in  the  scientists  of  its  era  —  an  interest  in  striving  to  find  law- 
bound  phenomena  in  existence.  Otherwise  its  age  certainly  specialized  in 
speculation  upon  abstract  ideas,  as  Hegel  and  his  school  would  have  it;  but 
the  fact  that  during  this  period  the  study  of  nature  did  not  disappear  alto- 
gether nor  degenerate  into  a  mere  handicraft  is  at  any  rate  due  in  no  small 
measure  to  natural  philosophy.  Many  of  its  ideas,  indeed,  recur,  in  a  more 
or  less  revised  form,  in  the  biology  of  the  nineteenth  century,  an  account 
of  which  will  be  given  in  the  next  section  of  this  work. 


PART     THREE 


MODERN    BIOLOGY 


BIOLOGY     DURING     THE     FIRST     HALF 
OF    THE     NINETEENTH     CENTURY 

CHAPTER    I 

FROM     NATURAL    PHILOSOPHY     TO     MODERN     BIOLOGY 

I.    The  Predecessors  of  Comparative  Anatomy 

IN  THE  HISTORY  of  biology  the  nineteenth  century  will  undoubtedly  be  al- 
ways regarded  as  one  of  the  most  important  epochs.  With  regard  to  the 
value  of  the  discoveries  that  were  then  made,  that  period  can  certainly 
vie  with  the  most  brilliant  of  the  periods  that  preceded  it,  and  if  we  con- 
sider the  reputation  which  biology  enjoyed  in  the  world  of  culture  of  the 
time,  it  was  an  unrivalled  epoch.  It  is  primarily  the  latter  half  of  this  cen- 
tury, after  the  appearance  of  Darwin,  that  witnessed  the  greatest  advance 
that  biology  has  ever  been  able  to  record,  particularly  in  regard  to  the  volume 
of  its  discoveries.  But  this  advance  was  being  prepared  for  during  the  im- 
mediately preceding  decades  in  the  splendid  development  that  took  place 
in  most  branches  of  research  —  a  development  which  in  its  turn  was  evolved 
during  the  preceding  eras  out  of  events  that  have  previously  been  recorded 
in  this  work.  Thus,  in  the  biological  science  of  the  nineteenth  century  we 
find  elements  derived  from  the  exact  scientific  research  that  during  the  two 
preceding  centuries  had  sought  for  a  mechanical  explanation  of  the  phenom- 
ena in  animate  nature,  but  there  were  also  features  from  the  speculative 
natural  philosophy  that  endeavoured,  by  means  of  purely  theoretical  systems 
of  thought,  to  solve  those  problems  of  existence  which  exact  scientific  re- 
search had  found  itself  compelled  to  leave  unexplained.  As  has  already  been 
described  in  the  last  few  chapters  of  the  previous  section,  this  natural  phi- 
losophy chiefly  flourished  in  Germany  and  Scandinavia,  but  also  existed  in 
England  and  France;  it  exercised  a  decisive  influence  upon  the  cultural  de- 
velopment of  that  period,  and,  as  we  shall  see  later  on,  far  beyond  it.  During 
the  age  when  natural  philosophy  flourished,  however,  exact  scientific  re- 
search was  by  no  means  dead;  it  only  worked  the  better  in  peace,  and,  more- 
over, there  were  of  course  scientists  who,  though  convinced  supporters  of 

301 


30L  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

natural  philosophy,  nevertheless  carried  out  exact  investigations  on  special 
subjects.  A  fev^^  examples  of  this  exact  natural  research  during  the  age  of 
natural  philosophy  deserve  to  be  quoted  here  as  representing  a  transition  to 
modern  biology,  which  developed  during  the  succeeding  epoch. 

In  France,  as  we  have  already  found,  comparative  anatomy  had  been 
considerably  developed  through  the  work  of  BufFon  and  Daubenton.  But  de- 
scriptive anatomy  had  also  had  a  brilliant  representative  during  that  same 
century  in  the  Dane  Jacob  Benignus  Winslow,  a  relative  of  Steno,  who,  like 
the  latter,  became  a  Catholic  and  was  fully  naturalized  abroad,  but  who,  in 
contrast  to  his  predecessor,  enjoyed  an  unusually  long  life  of  activity.  He 
died  in  1760  at  the  age  of  ninety-one.  His  description  of  the  human  anatomy 
was  especially  complete,  particularly  as  regards  the  topographical  section,  and 
he  made  the  medical  faculty  in  Paris,  where  he  was  professor,  an  important 
centre  of  anatomical  study.  He  and  his  immediate  pupils  were,  however, 
outshone  by  a  man  who  was  able  to  develop  even  the  human  anatomy  along 
comparative  lines  on  the  model  of  Daubenton  and  Camper. 

Felix  Vicq  d'Azyr  was  born  in  1748  at  Valogne,  in  Normandy.  He  was 
the  son  of  a  physician,  and  after  being  educated  at  school,  he  chose  his 
father's  career  and  studied  in  Paris  with  such  success  that  only  eight  years 
after  entering  the  profession  he  was  able  to  give  lectures  there.  He  had  no 
academical  career,  however.  He  was  passed  over  when  a  vacancy  was  filled 
in  the  professorship  of  anatomy  at  the  Jardin  des  Plantes  in  1774,  and  again 
upon  the  appointment  of  a  successor  to  Buffon.  Instead,  he  was  sent  by  the 
Board  to  study  and  stamp  out  serious  epidemics  in  certain  provincial  parts 
of  France,  and  he  wrote  some  valuable  accounts  of  them.  In  the  field  of 
veterinary  science  also  he  made  some  important  contributions.  Besides  this 
work,  he  held  private  courses  in  anatomy,  which  were  very  popular,  and 
he  also  collaborated  in  the  founding  of  the  Royal  Society  of  Medicine  in 
Paris,  of  which  he  became  permanent  secretary;  in  that  capacity  he  composed 
a  number  of  brilliant  epitaphs  upon  past  distinguished  physicians,  on  ac- 
count of  which  he  was  appointed  Buffon's  successor  in  the  French  Academy. 
At  last  he  was  made  personal  physician  to  the  King,  but  when  the  Revolu- 
tion broke  out,  shortly  afterwards,  this  post  of  honour  was  a  cause  of  much 
trouble  and  danger.  His  health,  which  had  already  given  way  under  stress 
of  work,  now  broke  down;  finally,  as  a  result  of  attending  the  famous  feast 
of  the  Supreme  Being,  under  compulsion,  he  contracted  a  chill  and  died  a 
few  days  later. 

Vicq  d'Azyr's  career  was  thus  a  short  one,  and,  moreover,  his  energies 
were  divided  as  a  result  of  the  practical  work  he  had  to  carry  out  in  order 
to  make  a  living.  On  these  practical  activities,  indeed,  he  expended  much 
labour,  and  his  works  on  epidemics,  veterinary  surgery,  and  organizational 
problems  in  practical  medicine  are  fairly  numerous.  But  in  spite  of  all  this 


MODERNBIOLOGY  303 

he  found  time  for  carrying  out  serious  theoretical  research  in  the  sphere  of 
anatomy  and  physiology,  and  though  the  results  to  a  large  extent  exist  only 
in  the  form  of  brief  accounts  published  in  academical  proceedings,  neverthe- 
less he  has  thereby  contributed  largely  to  the  development  of  biology.  Of 
one  important  work  that  he  started  on  anatomy  he  managed  to  publish 
only  the  first  part,  wherein  he  lays  down  the  principles  on  which  he  con- 
siders that  the  study  of  anatomy  should  be  pursued. 

Vkq  d'Axyr's  classification  of  the  functions  of  the  organism 
For  this  purpose  he  takes  as  his  starting-point,  firstly  comparative  anatomy, 
as  created  by  Daubenton,  and  secondly  Haller's  physiological  theories  and 
experiments.  He  begins  by  discussing  the  ancient  division  of  natural  objects 
into  three  kingdoms  and  finds  that  the  essential  difference  lies  between  ani- 
mate beings  and  inanimate  things;  plants  and  animals  possess  common  prop- 
erties that  stones  and  minerals  lack.  In  connexion  therewith  he  strongly 
rejects  the  old  comparison  —  which  is  sometimes  repeated  even  in  modern 
times  —  between  the  growth  of  the  organism  and  that  of  the  crystal;  he 
points  out  the  mathematically  regular  shape  and  homogeneous  structure  of 
the  crystal  as  contrasted  with  the  rounded  forms  and  variously  constituted 
systems  of  organisms,  but  above  all  he  emphasizes  the  organisms'  definitely 
characterized  functions  as  a  peculiarity  of  life.  These  functions  he  divides 
into  the  following  categories:  (i)  digestion,  (x)  nutrition,  (3)  circulation, 
(4)  respiration,  (5)  secretion,  (6)  ossification,  (7)  generation,  (8)  irritability, 
(9)  sensibility.  The  existence  of  the  various  functions,  together  with  their 
respective  organs,  is  then  examined  in  the  different  life-forms;  regarding  di- 
gestion, it  is  stated  that  man,  the  quadrupeds,  whales,  birds,  and  crustaceans 
possess  one  or  more  stomachal  cavities  clearly  distinct  from  the  oesophagus 
and  the  intestine;  oviparous  quadrupeds,  snakes,  selachians,  and  osseans  have 
a  stomach  in  the  form  of  a  single  extension;  insects,  worms,  and  zoophytes 
have  only  one  intestinal  tube,  and  plants  no  digestive  canal  —  the  classifi- 
cation is  noticeable  as  being  more  reminiscent  of  Aristotle  than  of  Linnasus. 
With  regard  to  generation,  a  distinction  is  made  between  viviparous,  ovip- 
arous, and  gemmate  reproduction.  In  regard  to  irritability,  he  differentiates 
between  insect  larvae,  worms,  and  polypi,  which  have  an  entirely  contractile 
or  muscular  body;  vertebrate  animals,  whose  muscles  cover  the  skeleton; 
insects  and  crustaceans,  in  which  the  skeleton  covers  the  muscles;  and  plants, 
which  possess  no  free  movements.  It  would  be  possible,  of  course,  to  adduce 
weighty  detailed  objections  to  this  system  and  its  various  categories;  it 
gives  evidence,  however,  of  a  careful  study  and  a  penetrating  analysis  of 
the  phenomena  of  life.  And  Vicq  d'Azyr  undeniably  possesses  a  keen  eye 
for  certain  manifestations  and  functions  of  life  —  far  keener  indeed  than  any 
of  his  predecessors  and  many  of  his  successors. 

In  particular  he  keenly  criticizes  the  current  theories  of  the  essence  of 


304  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

life;  on  the  subject  of  vitalism,  as  maintained  by  Stahl's  successors,  he  holds 
that,  while  it  is  true  that  a  number  of  phenomena  exist  only  in  living  crea- 
tures, nothing  is  gained  by  referring  to  the  soul  as  their  cause;  they  should 
rather  be  regarded  as  physical  phenomena  and  studied  through  observation 
and  experiment,  but  not  ascribed  to  a  principle  "whereby  thought  retires 
in  the  belief  that  everything  is  done,  when  in  reality  everything  remains 
to  be  done."  This  criticism  he  extends  to  several  current  hypotheses;  thus, 
he  rejects  the  assumption  of  a  fluid  controlling  the  impulses  in  the  nervous 
system,  for  by  this  particularization  of  a  little-known  function  a  number  of 
illusions  have  been  created,  while  such  an  expression  as  "nervous  force" 
would  be  far  more  applicable  to  the  actual  knowledge  we  possess  of  the 
phenomenon.  Similarly  he  criticizes  the  theory  current  at  the  time,  which 
originated  in  Buffon,  that  the  different  parts  of  the  embryo  are  derived  from 
corresponding  parts  in  the  parents  —  a  theory  that  even  Darwin  afterwards 
entertained.  In  disproof  of  it  Vicq  d'Azyr  adduces  the  fact  that  two  parents 
who  have  lost  one  and  the  same  part  of  the  body  nevertheless  produce  normal 
offspring.  In  this  point  he  has  thus  foreshadowed  views  that  are  expressed 
by  modern  students  of  heredity. 

As  his  teacher  in  scientific  criticism  Vicq  d'Azyr  mentions  the  philoso- 
pher of  enlightenment  Condillac  (1715-80),  who  enjoyed  a  great  reputation 
in  his  time  and  who  made  a  special  study  of  the  relation  of  sense-perception 
to  the  consciousness  —  he  asserts  that  the  consciousness  is  composed  of  what 
the  sense-impressions  communicate  from  the  outside  world  —  and  in  con- 
nexion therewith  he  maintained  that  in  science  words  should  exactly  convey 
the  ideas  they  are  intended  to  denote.  By  a  careful  study  of  his  writings 
Vicq  d'Azyr  undoubtedly  learnt  to  realize  the  necessity  for  clear  ideas  and 
unambiguous  terms  in  natural  science  as  much  as  in  anything  else. 

Vicq  d' Ax,yr  s  comparative  anatomy 
VicQ  d'Azyr's  influence  has  been  felt  not  only  on  account  of  this  criticism, 
valuable  as  it  is,  but  in  a  still  greater  degree  as  a  result  of  his  studies  in 
comparative  anatomy,  which  were  unfortunately  fragmentary;  the  prin- 
ciples on  which  he  worked,  however,  he  summarized  in  the  form  of  a  pro- 
gram for  a  course  of  lectures  in  anatomy  and  physiology.  The  subject  is  first 
of  all  divided  up  according  to  the  nine  life -functions  referred  to  above.  Under 
the  heading  "ossification"  he  first  deals  in  descriptive  form  with  the  bone- 
structure  and  its  articulation  and  forms  of  connexion,  then  by  way  of  com- 
parison the  individual  bones  in  different  animal  forms,  and  further  a  number 
of  physiological  experiments  in  connexion  with  the  growth  and  regeneration 
of  bones,  and  finally  he  gives  an  account  of  the  chemical  composition  of 
osseous  tissue.  Under  the  heading  "irritability"  is  discussed  the  muscular 
system,  first  descriptively,  then  comparatively,  as  regards  both  conformation 
and  finer  structure,  the  vascular  and  nervous  ramifications,  and,  finally,  ex- 


Pi 

m 

1— I 

> 

p 
u 


< 

u 

I— t 

eq 

Pi 
w 

I— I 

> 

< 

X 


c 

2 

< 

w 

1—1 


MODERNBIOLOGY  305 

perimentally.  In  the  last-mentioned  respect  are  observed  both  the  contraction 
of  individual  muscles  when  the  nerves  that  are  connected  with  them  are 
irritated,  and  the  different  forms  of  movement  in  man  and  animals  —  a  sub- 
ject in  which  Borelli  and  Perrault  are  cited  as  precursors.  Similarly,  under 
the  heading  "sensibility"  the  nervous  system  is  dealt  with,  followed  by 
the  other  functions  of  the  body.  The  most  remarkable  point  of  this  exposi- 
tion is  the  detailed  comparison  made  between  the  same  organs  in  different 
animals  —  a  study  in  which  Vicq  d'Azyr  certainly  finds  support  in  the  pre- 
liminary works  of  Daubenton;  but  the  former  without  the  least  doubt  carries 
through  the  comparative  program  far  more  thoroughly  than  the  latter. 

Its  valuable  contributions  to  science 
In  points  of  detail  Vicq  d'Azyr's  investigations  contain  many  contributions 
of  immense  value,  and  also  a  wealth  of  ideas  of  great  significance  for  the 
future.  He  paid  special  attention  to  the  comparative  anatomy  of  the  mam- 
mals. He  continued  and  widened  the  comparison  of  the  bodily  structure  of 
man  and  the  apes  which  Camper  had  initiated,  arriving,  too,  at  the  same 
results  as  the  latter  (see  Part  II,  p.  x6o);  on  this  subject  he  made  a  special 
study  of  the  musculature  of  the  extremities,  and  in  general  closely  compared 
the  extremities  throughout  the  mammalian  class.  Further,  he  made  investi- 
gations into  the  teeth  of  the  entire  vertebrate  class;  he  points  out  the  differ- 
ence between  teeth  fixed  in  dental  sacs  and  provided  with  vascular  and 
nervous  systems,  and  those  that  are  fixed  on  the  jaw-bone;  he  observes  the 
dissimilarity  in  the  number  and  structure  of  teeth  in  mammals  of  different 
structure  and  habits;  he  draws  attention  to  the  pointed  teeth  of  the  beast  of 
prey,  the  knobby  teeth  of  omnivorous  animals,  and  the  enamel-coated  teeth 
of  herbivorous  animals;  he  notes  the  presence  and  absence  of  various  kinds 
of  teeth  in  different  animals.  He  points  out  the  correlation  existing  between 
different  organs  in  animals;  a  certain  shape  of  tooth  presupposes  a  certain 
type  of  structure  in  the  extremities  and  the  digestive  canal,  because  all  its 
bodily  parts  are  adapted  to  the  animal's  way  of  living.  He  also  shows  how 
these  different  characteristics  give  every  animal  a  special  role  to  play  in  the 
great  struggle  that  is  constantly  going  on  in  nature  between  the  various 
life -forms.  The  weakest  point  of  his  comparative  investigations  is  the  com- 
parison between  vertebrates  and  invertebrates;  although  he  is  far  more  cau- 
tious than  Geoffroy  Saint-Hilaire  was  later,  he  nevertheless  has  no  true  eye 
for  the  difference  between  the  organs  in  the  important  main  groups  in  the 
animal  kingdom,  and,  on  the  whole,  it  was  certainly  fortunate  for  him  that 
he  did  not  find  time  to  extend  his  studies  to  the  invertebrate  animals.  He 
even  includes  the  vegetable  world  in  his  comparative  studies,  sometimes 
without  much  success,  as  when  he  compares  the  symmetry  in  pinnate  plants 
with  that  of  animals,  and  sometimes  with  an  insight  that  looks  far  ahead 
into  the  future,  as  when  he  crosses  white  and  red  tulips  and  finds  that  the 


3o6  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

descendants  are  white,  red,  and  intermediate.  Finally,  it  is  worth  mentioning 
that  as  a  descriptive  anatomist  he  produced  a  copiously  illustrated  work  on 
the  brain  and  its  nervous  system  —  a  splendid  work  for  his  period  and  in  its 
extent  the  most  considerable  of  all  his  productions.  Thus,  in  more  than  one 
respect  Vicq  d'Azyr  has  left  his  mark  on  the  history  of  biology;  he  will  be 
especially  remembered  as  a  pioneer  in  the  sphere  of  comparative  anatomy. 

In  Germany  at  the  beginning  of  the  nineteenth  century,  biology  was 
dominated  by  the  romantic  natural  philosophy  that  was  described  at  the 
close  of  Part  II,  in  which  it  was  also  pointed  out  that  during  that  period 
there  were  working  by  the  side  of  the  natural  philosophers  a  number  of 
scientists  who  pursued  their  inquiries  by  exact  methods,  thereby  upholding 
the  traditions  of  the  preceding  era  and  at  the  same  time  paving  the  way  for 
the  succeeding  age's  magnificent  progress  in  the  field  of  biology.  Of  these 
exact  scientists  working  during  a  period  given  over  to  fantastic  dreams  some 
of  the  most  prominent  merit  description  here. 

JoHANN  Friedrich  Blumenbach  was  born  at  Gotha  in  1751;  his  father 
was  a  schoolmaster,  and  his  mother,  to  whose  memory  he  dedicated  a  special 
work,  was  a  good  and  gifted  woman.  Even  as  a  child  he  was  interested  in 
natural  science;  one  of  his  keenest  delights  was  putting  together  skeletons 
out  of  bones  that  he  collected.  He  studied  first  at  Jena,  and  then  at  Got- 
tingen,  where  he  took  his  degree  with  a  dissertation  on  the  human  races, 
which  brought  him  immediate  fame  and  procured  for  him,  as  early  as  in 
the  year  1776,  the  professorship  in  anatomy  at  that  university.  He  carried 
on  his  work  as  a  teacher  for  nearly  sixty  years,  during  which  he  led  a  quiet 
life,  interrupted  only  by  a  few  collecting-expeditions.  At  last,  in  1835,  ^^ 
resigned,  and  died  in  1840.  In  his  old  age  he  was  a  very  original  character; 
he  was  regarded  as  one  of  the  sights  of  Gottingen,  and  he  was  always  quite 
willing  to  show  himself,  especially  to  distinguished  visitors.  As  an  author, 
too,  Blumenbach  is  peculiar;  his  style  is  heavy  and  full  of  long  periods,  oc- 
casionally lightened  by  dry  humour,  which  is  always  inoffensive,  though 
now  and  then  not  in  the  best  of  taste  according  to  modern  standards.  It  is 
also  said  that  his  lectures  were  interspersed  with  witty  remarks,  which  re- 
curred year  after  year  in  a  given  context  to  the  delight  of  generations  of 
undergraduates.  And  Blumenbach  had  innumerable  pupils;  he  had  the  ability 
both  to  gather  round  him  and  to  train  scientific  experts,  and  not  a  few  scien- 
tists of  European  reputation  derived  their  knowledge  from  him.  As  an  author 
of  text-books  and  manuals  he  was  very  fine  for  the  age  in  which  he  lived, 
and,  generally  speaking,  he  has  contributed  very  largely  towards  stimulating 
his  countrymen's  interest  in  the  study  of  nature,  which,  indeed,  was  to  at- 
tain, during  the  generation  that  immediately  followed  his  own,  unexpected 
heights  in  his  country;  so  that  he  has  honourably  deserved  the  title  of 
'*  Mapsfer  Gerfnania,"  which  he  enjoyed  even  in  his  lifetime. 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  307 

Blwnenhach' s  comparative  anthropology 
As  the  chief  service  that  Blumenbach  has  rendered  to  science  is  generally 
quoted  the  fact  that  he  introduced  into  Germany  the  study  of  comparative 
anatomy  —  and  this  at  an  earlier  date  than  Cuvier  introduced  it  into  France. 
There  can  be  no  doubt  that  the  two  collaborators  in  research  BufFon  and 
Daubentonhave  the  prior  claim  to  the  introduction  of  comparative  anatomy, 
but  it  is  certain  also  that  Blumenbach  was  essentially  a  comparative  anato- 
mist and  that  he  brought  that  science  up  to  a  high  state  of  development. 
There  is  especially  one  branch  of  it  in  which  he  is  a  pioneer  —  namely,  an- 
thropology. Here,  it  is  true,  Buffon,  with  his  descriptive  and  statistical 
method,  and  Camper,  with  his  studies  of  the  facial  angle,  had  paved  the 
way,  but  Blumenbach  was  the  first  who  systematically  worked  at  the  sub- 
ject, thereby  laying  the  foundations  on  which  all  subsequent  research  has 
carried  on  its  constructive  work.  He  instituted  a  collection  of  skulls,  skele- 
tons, and  illustrations  of  human  beings  of  as  many  different  races  as  he  could 
procure,  and  he  methodically  studied  the  peculiar  characteristics  of  the  ma- 
terial he  thus  got  together  or  was  able  to  borrow  from  other  museums.  The 
result  was  a  close  comparison  of  the  characteristics,  both  external  and  in- 
ternal, of  different  human  types,  and  on  that  basis  a  division  of  mankind 
into  races.  A  similar  attempt  had  indeed  been  made  before,  such  as  Buffon's, 
for  instance,  but  Blumenbach's  was  the  first  that  really  proved  successful, 
and  his  five  races  —  Caucasian,  Mongolian,  Ethiopian,  American,  and  Ma- 
layan —  have  been  the  foundation  on  which  all  subsequent  racial  divisions 
have  been  based,  just  as  his  postulate  that  the  races  are  varieties  of  one  and 
the  same  species  is  also  regarded  as  true,  in  spite  of  isolated  attempts  to 
create  several  species.  His  characteristic  descriptions  of  the  cranium,  with 
accompanying  illustrations,  have  certainly  been  more  recently  improved 
upon  by  Anders  Retzius,  Virchow,  Broca,  and  others,  but  Blumenbach's 
nevertheless  form  the  groundwork  on  which  his  successors  have  built. 

Besides  the  study  of  races,  Blumenbach  paid  special  attention  to  the 
question  of  determining  the  characteristics  wherein  man  differs  from  the 
other  mammals,  and  particularly  from  the  manlike  apes,  whose  anatomy  he 
closely  studied.  Like  Camper,  he  strongly  maintained  that  man  is  funda- 
mentally unlike  the  apes;  it  was  he  who  divided  the  Linnasan  order  Primates 
into  two  —  Bimana  for  the  human  and  Quadrumana  for  the  apes.  And  he 
collected  as  much  anatomical,  morphological,  and  psychological  evidence  as 
he  could  in  proof  of  this.  Many  of  these  detailed  anatomical  characteristics 
are  without  doubt  correctly  observed,  whereas  others  are  the  result  of  ana- 
tomical misconceptions,  such  as  the  statement  that  the  apes  have  four  hands, 
while  man  has  two.  This  point  of  view  was  accepted,  however,  by  the  biol- 
ogists of  the  succeeding  age,  and  in  actual  fact  Blumenbach  was  the  origi- 
nator of  most  of  the  reasons  which  eventually  were  to  be  adduced  against 


3o8  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

Darwinism  by  its  conservative  opponents.  In  other  points,  too,  these  cham- 
pions of  man's  high  dignity  could  be  satisfied  with  Blumenbach's  views; 
he  believes,  for  instance,  in  species'  having  been  created  as  one  pair  of  each  — 
at  least  as  far  as  man  is  concerned  —  and  he  holds  the  view  that  the  Cau- 
casian race  was  the  original  out  of  which  the  others  were  created  later  by 
"degeneration,"  due  to  climatic  and  economic  conditions.  During  the  fight- 
ing days  of  Darwinism,  therefore,  old  Blumenbach  received  but  little 
gratitude  at  the  hands  of  the  champions  of  progress,  but  a  later  age  must 
indubitably  do  him  the  justice  of  acknowledging  him  as  the  founder  of 
comparative  anthropology. 

Blumenbach,  however,  extended  his  research  and  educational  work  to 
other  spheres;  actually,  like  Linnasus,  he  has  dealt  with  all  the  three  king- 
doms of  nature.  His  botanical  knowledge  is  based  entirely  on  Linnasus,  whose 
system  he  uses  in  its  entirety;  in  mineralogy,  too,  his  activities  were  not 
very  remarkable.  As  a  zoologist  he  is  likewise  limited;  he  deals  with  the 
invertebrates  in  a  summary  fashion  and  has  but  little  new  to  tell  of  them. 
The  vertebrates,  on  the  other  hand,  he  studied  carefully  from  the  comparative 
point  of  view,  with  special  reference  to  the  mammals;  he  discusses  the  lat- 
ter's  anatomy  in  detail,  principally  their  bone-structure,  and  his  work  on 
this  subject  is  worthy  to  be  compared  with  Daubenton's  and  Vicq  d'Azyr's. 
In  contrast  to  the  last-named  he  divides  his  comparative  anatomy  according 
to  organs  and  not  according  to  physiological  functions,  which  gives  to  the 
entire  work  a  far  more  modern  character. 

His  vitalism 
He  was  also,  however,  keenly  interested  in  physiological  problems  and  be- 
lieved that  he  had  created  something  essentially  new  in  this  field;  in  a  treatise 
entitled  tjber  den  Bildungstrieb  he  expounds  a  theory  of  reproduction  and  em- 
bryonic development,  which  he  afterwards  advances  repeatedly  in  various 
connexions.  In  this  work  he  first  of  all  gives  an  account  of  earlier  theories 
of  evolution;  the  preformation  theory  is  criticized  and  rejected,  with  a  cer- 
tain degree  of  satire,  his  principal  target  being,  as  usual.  Bonnet's  incap- 
sulating  theory;  the  spermatozoa  are  declared  to  be  parasites,  and  finally 
the  epigenesis  theory  is  advanced  as  the  true  explanation  of  the  phenomenon 
of  evolution.  With  C.  F.  Wolff,  he  holds  that  the  prospective  individual 
is  evolved  out  of  a  completely  indifferentiated  mass.  Blumenbach,  however, 
rejects  his  predecessor's  theory  of  "  vis  essenfialis"  (see  Part  II,  p.  2.49),  hold- 
ing instead  that  the  development  is  caused  by  a  special  "formative  force," 
which  is  displayed  not  only  in  the  development  of  the  embryo,  but  also 
in  all  kinds  of  growth,  regeneration,  and  reproduction  in  animate  beings. 
This  formative  force  —  nisus  jormativus  —  must  not,  however,  be  confused 
with  other  "life-forces,"  such  as  irritability  and  sensibility,  but  it  operates 
with  those  forces  in  order  to  maintain  life.  Blumenbach  specially  points  out 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  309 

that  these  "forces"  are  merely  expressions  by  which  to  denote  phenomena, 
the  cause  of  which  we  do  not  know,  but  the  effects  of  which  we  can  observe. 
By  the  side  of  this,  however,  he  speaks  also  of  the  body-mechanism.  Thus 
we  find  that  Blumenbach  did  not  create,  like  Stahl,  any  elaborated  vitalistic 
thought-system,  and  his  speculation  in  general  is  not  particularly  logical. 
His  service  lies  rather  in  the  field  of  comparative  observation  than  in  that 
of  speculation. 

Blumenbach's  contemporary  and  equal  in  scientific  reputation  was  Sam- 
uel Thomas  Sommerring  (175  5-1830).  He  was  born  in  the  Polish  town  of 
Thorn,  though  of  a  German  family;  his  father  was  town  physician,  and  the 
son  was  destined  early  for  the  medical  profession.  He  carried  out  his  elemen- 
tary studies  at  Gottingen,  where  Blumenbach  was  one  of  his  younger  teachers; 
he  afterwards  studied  anatomy,  in  Holland  under  Camper  and  in  England 
under  Hunter.  His  youth  recalls  that  of  Swammerdam,  in  so  far  as  his  father 
desired  to  see  him  early  established  in  practice  and  stubbornly  opposed  his 
going  in  for  expensive  scientific  studies;  but  the  young  man  refused  to  give 
in;  through  his  personal  ability  and  the  mediation  of  friends  he  managed  to 
secure  extended  help  towards  his  studies  away  from  home  and  thus  continued 
his  scientific  work  in  difficult  economic  circumstances,  until  he  was  able  to 
earn  not  only  a  good  reputation,  but  also  his  daily  bread.  He  held  profes- 
sorships, first  at  Kassel,  then  at  Mainz  and  Munich;  but  during  that  period 
spent  some  years  as  a  practitioner  at  Frankfurt  am  Main,  where  he  married 
and  found  his  true  home.  There,  too,  he  spent  the  last  ten  years  of  his  life 
in  peace  and  happiness,  surrounded  by  friends  and  continuing  his  scientific 
work  until  the  end. 

In  his  general  conception  of  nature  Sommerring  was  to  a  certain  extent 
influenced  by  the  speculations  in  mystical  natural  philosophy  in  which  his 
age  indulged.  At  Kassel  he  entered  the  Rosicrucian  Brotherhood  and  in  it 
carried  on  both  alchemy  and  spiritualism,  although  he  afterwards  realized 
his  delusion  in  both  respects.  At  Mainz,  where  his  activities  were  most  pro- 
ductive, he  applied  himself  exclusively  to  anatomy  and  carried  out  in  this  field 
a  number  of  valuable  investigations  on  special  subjects.  Like  Albinus,  whom 
he  chose  as  his  model,  he  employed  a  clever  draughtsman  and  with  his  assis- 
tance published  several  excellent  compilations,  one  on  the  human  body  in  its 
entirety  —  which  was  never  completed,  but  the  published  sections  of  which 
are  remarkable  for  their  clear  method  of  presentation  and  their  sound  de- 
scriptions —  as  well  as  a  number  of  special  investigations,  such  as  a  treatise 
on  monstrosities  of  various  kinds,  which  he  spent  some  years  in  collecting, 
and,  further,  a  comparative  study  of  the  visual  and  auditory  organs  in  differ- 
ent races  of  mankind,  and  finally  some  investigations  on  various  subjects 
and  of  varying  value. 


3IO  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

Sommerring  s  work  on  the  brain 
His  curious  work  fiber  das  Organ  der  Seele,  which  he  dedicated  to  Kant,  is  a 
combination  of  anatomical  inquiry  and  philosophical  speculation.  In  it  he 
gives  a  detailed  description  of  the  brain  and  its  nerves,  illustrated  with 
splendid  engravings.  His  account  of  the  origin  of  the  nerve-stems  in  particu- 
lar is  admirable,  considering  the  age  in  which  it  was  written,  and  he  has 
rendered  a  still  greater  service  to  science  by  treating,  for  the  first  time,  the 
sympathetic  nervous  system  as  a  pair  of  nerves  independent  of  the  central 
nerve  system,  "which  pair  is  in  indirect,  but  not  direct,  connexion  with  the 
brain  and  spinal  cord."  The  whole  of  this  study  of  the  brain,  however,  forms 
the  basis  of  a  highly  fantastic  speculation  upon  the  brain  as  the  organ  of  the 
soul,  or,  to  be  more  exact,  upon  the  location  of  the  "sensorium  commune," 
which  in  the  German  is  translated  as  "das  gemeinschajtliche  Emffindungsort." 
By  this  is  meant  that  part  of  the  brain  in  which  the  sense-impressions  con- 
verge and  co-operate.  Ideas  of  this  kind  in  regard  to  the  localization  of  the 
soul  in  the  brain  had  indeed  long  been  current;  Descartes  adopted  for  this 
purpose  the  glandula  pinealis,  Perrault  the  ??2edulla  oblongata;  Swedenborg 
alone  was  guided  on  the  right  path  by  his  brilliant  intuition  when  he  drew 
attention  to  the  pyramid-cells  of  the  cerebrum.  Sommerring  tries  to  prove 
that  all  the  cerebral  nerves  open  into  the  central  cavity  of  the  brain  and  that 
in  connexion  therewith  the  cerebral  fluid  is  the  organ  of  consciousness;  the 
only  point  that  worries  him  is:  "Kann  eine  Fltissigkeit  animirt  sein?"  which, 
however,  he  answers  in  the  affirmative  on  arguments  derived  from  the  Bible, 
Aristotle,  and  modern  writings.  This  assertion,  which  in  our  own  day,  when 
protoplasm  and  its  derivatives  have  so  often  had  to  serve  as  wholly  or  at 
least  partially  fluid,  should  not  be  regarded  as  utterly  absurd,  nevertheless 
aroused  grave  doubts  in  the  minds  of  Sommerring's  contemporaries,  just  as 
his  philosophical  argumentation  in  general  shocked  the  students  of  natural 
science;  his  good  friend  Goethe  wrote  him  a  letter  in  which,  with  reflective 
and  observant  criticism,  which  he  unhappily  did  not  always  employ  in  his 
own  writings,  he  warns  him  against  letting  philosophical  speculations  inter- 
fere in  scientific  investigations.  And  Sommerring  in  actual  fact  learnt  wis- 
dom from  the  opposition  he  met  with;  his  later  works  are  in  the  main  based 
on  exact  natural  science;  his  reputation  as  one  of  the  leading  anatomists  of 
his  age  was  greatly  enhanced  by  them  and  has  been  confirmed  by  posterity. 
There  was  one  scientist,  a  contemporary  of  Sommerring's,  who  ap- 
proached far  more  nearly  to  the  modern  conception  of  the  structure  of  the 
brain  and  nervous  system,  but  through  his  own  fault  he  managed  to  acquire 
a  somewhat  doubtful  reputation;  this  was  the  "phrenologist,"  Franz  Joseph 
Gall  (1758-1818).  Born  at  Baden,  he  went  as  a  medical  student  to  Vienna, 
became  a  doctor,  and  carried  on  a  medical  practice  there.  At  the  same  time 
he  began  to  interest  himself  in  the  study  of  the  brain's  structure  and  its 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  31I 

manifestations  of  life.  He  promulgated  his  ideas  on  the  subject  both  in 
writings  and  in  public  lectures;  when  these  were  prohibited  as  being  "ma- 
terialistic," he  left  Vienna  (in  1805)  and  wandered  about  Germany  for  a 
couple  of  years,  accompanied  by  his  friend  and  pupil  Spurzheim,  everywhere 
demonstrating  his  ideas  and  wherever  he  went  attracting  the  attention  of  the 
public,  which  was  occasionally  flattering,  but  often  quite  the  opposite. 
Eventually  he  settled  down  in  Paris,  became  naturalized,  and  lived  on  a 
practice  which  had  its  peculiar  features  —  for  instance,  he  kept  strictly 
secret  the  composition  of  the  medicines  he  prescribed  —  and  which  brought 
him  into  strained  relations  with  other  doctors.  He  was  also  on  bad  terms 
with  scientific  specialists;  universities  and  academies  closed  their  doors  to 
him.  The  public  became  all  the  more  interested  in  his  doctrines,  which  were 
promulgated  after  his  death  by  many,  mostly  dilettanti,  who  brought  his 
theories  into  utter  discredit,  so  that  ultimately  they  were  entirely  forgotten. 

Gall's  theory  of  brain  and  nerves 
Nevertheless,  Gail  has  exercised  an  undeniable  influence  even  upon  serious 
science.  For  he  was  without  doubt  one  of  the  most  brilliant  brain-anatomists 
of  his  age,  and  the  ideas  he  produced  on  the  subject  have  proved  of  great 
significance  for  the  development  of  that  branch  of  science.  In  his  exposition 
of  the  nervous  system  he  does  not  start  from  the  brain,  as  his  contemporaries 
did,  but  from  the  simple  nerve-fibre,  which  he  considers  to  be  the  simplest 
type  of  nerve;  it  is  found  even  in  worms,  and  out  of  it  "nature  has  evolved" 
all  the  higher  nerve-forms:  the  ganglia  as  the  junctions  of  several  nerve-fibres, 
and  the  spinal  cord,  which  consists  of  a  series  of  ganglia  drawn  through  by 
a  mass  of  nerve-fibres  and  connected  by  means  of  cross-fibres.  Through  the 
spinal  cord  the  nerves  lead  up  to  the  brain,  where  they  end  in  the  cortex- 
substance  which  represents  the  brain's  "ganglion";  in  this  latter  are  com- 
bined the  functions  of  the  nervous  system,  particularly  in  the  folds  of  the 
cerebrum;  this,  indeed,  is  the  reason  why,  the  more  highly  the  great  brain  is 
developed,  the  greater  is  the  intelligence.  In  the  cortex  of  the  brain  are  situ- 
ated the  different  intellectual  qualities  of  man;  these  qualities  are  due  to  he- 
reditary tendencies  and  together  form  the  soul,  which  is  thus  not  confined  to 
any  particular  spot  in  the  brain,  as  earlier  anatomists  had  declared.  What  is 
new  and  of  value  to  the  future  in  this  nerve  theory  is,  first  of  all,  the  emphasis 
he  lays  on  the  significance  of  the  nerve-tracts;  further,  and  above  all,  the 
placing  of  the  soul-functions  in  the  cortex  of  the  great  brain;  and,  finally,  the 
assumption  of  hereditary  intellectual  tendencies.  In  particular,  the  idea  that 
the  cortex  of  the  great  brain  is  the  organ  of  intelligence  has  been  fully  veri- 
fied. It  is  not  easy  to  determine  how  far  Gall,  who  undoubtedly  possessed  a 
thorough  knowledge  of  the  details  of  cerebral  anatomy,  himself  established 
this  fact,  or  how  much  he  borrowed  from  his  predecessors.  It  is  at  any  rate 
peculiar  to  him  that  he  cites  among  authorities  on   this    subject    even 


312.  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

Swedenborg,  whom  he  must  thus  have  studied,  and  who  may  well  have  been 
able  to  inspire  him  with  ideas  pointing  in  that  direction;  at  all  events,  he 
has  not  adopted  his  predecessor's  theory  of  the  essential  part  played  by  the 
pyramid-cells  in  the  work  of  the  brain;  on  the  contrary,  he  overlooks  them 
and  believes  that  the  cerebral  cortex  is  composed  of  matted  nerve-fibres. 
Gall's  theory  nervertheless  represents  a  great  advance  towards  the  modern 
standpoint  and  has  undoubtedly  exercised  considerable  influence  on  the 
development  of  cerebral  research,  in  spite  of  contemporary  opposition.  This 
is  also  the  case  with  Gall's  assumption  of  hereditary  intellectual  tendencies, 
which  represented  a  definite  advance  in  face  of  the  naive  belief  of  the  philoso- 
phers of  enlightenment  that  all  men  possess  like  tendencies  to  virtue  and 
genius,  which  require  only  proper  education  in  order  to  be  able  to  develop. 
Unfortunately  Gall  went  to  the  most  ridiculous  extremes  in  developing  his 
theory;  he  sought  and  discovered  in  the  brain  organs  for  all  kinds  of  intellec- 
tual and  moral  qualities,  for  genius  and  beauty,  love  and  piety,  and  even  for 
stealing  and  murder.  And  he  went  so  far  as  to  imagine  that  he  could  discern 
these  very  qualities  in  the  irregularities  on  the  surface  of  the  skull,  since  he 
believed  the  skull  to  be  exactly  fashioned  after  the  brain.  This  study,  which 
he  called  "cranioscopy,"  rapidly  degenerated  into  sheer  humbug;  in  particu- 
lar, the  discovery  of  the  "bumps  of  genius,"  which  were  supposed  to  denote 
special  talent,  brought  much  profit  to  quacks  and  rogues.  This  expression 
has  survived  in  modern  phraseology  as  the  best-known  relic  of  Gall's  activi- 
ties, which  has  served  to  conceal  the  really  sound  work  that  he  accomplished 
in  biological  science. 

Another  scientist  who  was  closely  connected  with  natural  philosophy 
was  JoHANN  Christian  Reil  (1759-1813).  Son  of  a  clergyman  of  East  Fries- 
land,  he  studied  medicine  at  Gottingen  and  Halle,  practised  for  some  years 
in  his  home  district,  was  then  appointed  professor  of  internal  medicine  at 
Halle,  and  at  the  same  time  became  town  physician  there.  When  the  Uni- 
versity of  Berlin  was  founded,  he  was  elected  a  professor,  but  resigned  his 
post  upon  the  outbreak  of  the  War  of  Independence  against  Napoleon  and 
volunteered  as  an  army  surgeon.  When  acting  in  that  capacity  he  fell  a 
victim  to  the  typhus  epidemic  that  raged  during  the  war. 

Reil's  life-theory 
Reil's  influence  has  been  both  many-sided  and  important.  He  was  highly 
esteemed  by  his  contemporaries;  among  Scandinavian  doctors  Israel  Hwasser 
in  particular  studied  and  admired  him.  As  a  practitioner  he  enjoyed  a  wide 
field  of  activities;  he  recorded  in  a  compendious  work  all  the  knowledge  that 
his  age  possessed  of  fevers  and  their  treatment.  Still  more  influential,  how- 
ever, was  his  work  in  the  sphere  of  psychiatry,  which  he  radically  reformed; 
he  effected  improvements  in  the  appalling  conditions  prevailing  in  the  luna- 
tic asylums  and  insisted  upon  the  elevation  of  psychiatry  to  the  position  of 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  313 

an  independent  branch  of  study  at  the  universities.  All  his  practical  endeav- 
ours, how^ever,  he  preferred  to  base  upon  a  careful  study  of  the  functions  of 
the  body;  for  this  purpose  he  started  in  the  year  1796  the  journal  Archiv  fur 
Physiologic,  which  under  various  names  and  editorial  conditions  has  sun 
vived  up  to  the  present  day.  In  an  essay  in  this  journal  he  expounded  a 
general  biological  theory  that  exercised  great  influence  on  his  own  time  and 
is  therefore  worthy  of  reference.  This  essay,  "Von  der  Lebenskrajt ,"  contains, 
like  many  others  written  in  that  age  of  pioneers,  a  number  of  ideas  fruitful 
both  for  the  contemporary  world  and  for  posterity,  side  by  side  with  a  mass 
of  uncritical  and  fantastic  nonsense.  After  a  philosophical  introduction 
touching  the  terms  "matter,"  "phenomenon,"  and  "idea,"  Reil  criticizes 
the  vitalistic  speculation  of  preceding  ages  and  declares,  with  an  obvious 
reference  to  Stahl,  that  phenomena  in  the  animal  kingdom  cannot  emanate 
from  an  immaterial  soul,  because  assumptions  as  to  supernatural  influences 
explain  nothing.  Rather,  the  basis  of  all  phenomena  in  the  animal  body  that 
are  not  ideas  must  be  sought  only  in  corporeal  matter  and  in  "the  form  and 
composition"  in  its  various  constituent  parts;  to  matter's  different  "compo- 
sition" in  muscles,  nerves,  and  bones  are  due  the  different  properties  and 
functions  of  those  parts.  Reil  has  here  learnt  not  only  from  Stahl,  but  also 
from  the  animal  chemistry  that  started  in  connexion  with  Lavoisier  and  had 
been  developed  in  his  own  time.  Unfortunately,  however,  he  does  not  by 
any  means  come  up  to  the  standard  already  reached  by  his  contemporaries 
in  this  respect;  thus,  he  did  not  realize  the  relation  between  the  interchange 
of  gas  in  plants  and  animals,  a  fact  which  Schelling,  for  instance,  during  the 
same  period  realized  well  enough  to  be  able  to  ascribe  fundamental  impor- 
tance to  it  (Part  II,  p.  xyy),  and  he  shares  the  ancient  popular  belief  that 
the  grain  of  seed  in  the  earth  and  the  still  unbrooded  tgg  are  "dead"  and  ac- 
quire life  by  being  provided  with  warmth  and  other  fine  components  of  life. 
Herein  lies  the  weakness  of  Reil's  speculation,  and,  generally  speaking,  both 
chemistry  and  philosophy  lead  him  into  somewhat  strange  paths.  Having 
thus  started  by  defining  the  idea  of  force  in  nature  and  the  relation  between 
phenomena  and  the  properties  in  matter  which  produce  them,  he  goes  on  to 
explain  the  life-force  in  animate  creatures  as  being  the  relation  between 
more  individualized  phenomena  and  a  special  kind  of  matter,  wherein  a 
differentiation  is  made  between  vegetative  force  in  plants,  animal  force  in 
animals,  and  reason  in  man.  Growth  in  inanimate  and  animate  nature  is 
declared  to  be  of  an  identical  character,  so  that  animal  growth  is  at  once 
termed  ''tierische  Kristallisafion."  But  besides  these  fanciful  ideas  Reil  suc- 
ceeds in  producing  a  definition  of  the  term  "organ"  itself  that  undoubtedly 
represents  a  real  advance.  Starting  from  the  elder  Darwin's  theory  of  fibre 
as  a  basic  component  in  the  animal  organism  (Part  II,  p.  X95),  he  describes 
various  categories  of  fibres:  cell-tissue  fibres,  bone-,  muscle-,  and  nerve-fibres. 


314  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

Out  of  these  are  formed  more  complex  organs,  such  as  nerves,  bones,  liga- 
ments, cartilages,  muscular  mass;  and  finally  there  are  formed  of  these  com- 
ponents in  various  proportions  the  higher  organs  — ■  namely,  intestines, 
sensory  organs,  and  musculature.  Here  we  undoubtedly  catch  a  glimpse  of 
the  idea  of  tissue,  which  Bichat  afterwards  developed,  independently  of  Reil 
and  more  universally  and  radically  than  the  latter.  There  is  no  doubt,  how- 
ever, that  Reil  also  helped  the  succeeding  generation,  in  Germany  especially, 
to  define  the  terms  on  which  anatomical  science  has  since  developed. 


2..     Humboldt 

In  this  connexion  there  is  also  worthy  of  mention  a  scientist  who,  like 
those  described  in  the  foregoing,  belongs  both  to  the  history  of  natural  phi- 
losophy and  to  that  of  exact  natural  science,  but  whose  fame  far  outshone  the 
rest  and  who  is  universally  looked  upon  as  one  of  the  greatest  personalities 
in  the  whole  range  of  science:  Alexander  von  Humboldt.  He  was  born  at 
Berlin  in  1769  of  a  distinguished  and  wealthy  family;  his  father  was  chamber- 
lain at  the  court,  his  mother  came  from  a  French  family,  who  had  gone  into 
exile  for  their  Protestant  faith.  Having  studied  at  the  University  of  Gottingen 
and  at  the  mining  academy  at  Freiberg,  he  entered  the  service  of  the  Prussian 
Mining  Department  and  worked  there  for  some  years,  until  an  ample  in- 
heritance placed  him  in  a  position  of  being  able  to  devote  himself  to  natural 
science  without  having  to  earn  his  living.  After  preliminary  studies  and 
travelling  in  Europe,  he  equipped  at  his  own  expense  in  the  year  1799  a 
journey  of  exploration  to  South  America,  which  region  he  traversed  in 
various  directions  and  explored  so  thoroughly  that  he  was  called  the  second 
discoverer  of  America.  After  five  years  out  there  he  returned  home  with  rich 
collections,  which  it  took  many  years  to  work  up.  For  this  purpose  he  spent 
a  long  time  in  Paris  and  there  published  an  extensive  account  of  his  expedi- 
tion, which  made  him  world-famous.  He  spent  all  his  fortune  on  the  journey 
and  its  description,  but  the  King  of  Prussia  indemnified  him  by  presenting 
him  with  a  well-paid  post  as  chamberlain;  he  rejected  offers  of  university  ap- 
pointments. In  1817  he  settled  in  Berlin  and  there  spent  the  rest  of  his  days, 
except  for  a  short  expedition  to  Russia  and  Siberia.  In  close  contact  with  the 
royal  family,  yet  retaining  the  liberal  ideas  of  his  youth,  respected  as  one 
of  the  great  men  of  science  and  highly  esteemed  for  his  lovable  person- 
ality, he  lived  to  a  great  age,  working  incessantly  at  different  branches  of 
science,  though  certainly  towards  the  end  with  diminished  energies.  He  died 
in  1859. 

Humboldt  was  an  unusually  highly  gifted  personality,  artistically  as 
well  as  scientifically,  and  he  has  exercised  an  extraordinarily  varied  influence 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  315 

Upon  the  development  of  natural  science,  although  he  did  not  rise  to  the 
highest  levels  in  any  particular  sphere.  As  a  scientific  explorer  he  is  without 
a  rival  and  he  raised  geography  to  the  rank  of  a  science.  Climatology  es- 
pecially owes  its  fundamental  principles  to  him:  thus,  the  method  of  indicat- 
ing on  the  map  by  means  of  isothermal  lines  places  having  a  similar  annual 
temperature  was  invented  by  him.  He  devoted  many  years  of  methodical 
study  to  terrestrial  magnetism,  and  the  magnetic-meteorological  observa- 
tories which  are  now  established  throughout  the  globe  have  him  to  thank 
for  their  existence.  As  a  geologist  he  deserves  especially  well  of  science, 
owing  to  his  studies  of  the  problem  of  Vulcanism;  he  established  the  fact 
that  the  volcanoes  exist  grouped  in  ranges  along  cracks  in  the  earth's  crust. 
But  he  was  also  highly  interested  in  biological  problems. 

Humboldt' s  idea  of  life- force 
In  his  youth  he  expounded  a  theory  of  life  as  a  whole  in  the  form  —  charac- 
teristic of  the  man  himself  and  of  his  age  —  of  a  mythological  story  en- 
titled Die  Lebenskraft  oder  der  rhodische  Genius.  The  gist  of  it  is  that  life  is 
maintained  by  a  force  that  prevents  the  elements  of  which  the  body  is  com- 
posed from  obeying  the  laws  of  affinity  that  hold  good  in  inorganic  nature.' 
In  his  old  age,  however,  he  abandoned  this  fantastic  theory  and  in  his  later 
writings  utters  a  warning  against  any  kind  of  speculating  upon  the  life- 
force.  He  displayed  greater  exactitude,  however,  in  his  investigations, 
published  shortly  before  his  South  American  expedition,  into  the  influence  of 
electricity  upon  muscles  and  nerves,  which  he  carried  out  partly  with  himself 
as  subject,  and  which,  together  with  a  number  of  natural-philosophical 
illusions,  contain  ideas  that  have  been  utilized  in  research  work  of  a  later 
period  in  connexion  with  electrical  phenomena  in  the  animal  kingdom. 

His  vegetable  geography 
The  greatest  service  rendered  to  biology  by  Humboldt,  however,  was  his 
creation  of  vegetable  geography.  Even  as  early  as  in  Linnasus  we  found  a 
lively  interest  and  a  keen  eye  for  the  life-habits  of  plants.  Linnasus's  investi- 
gations into  the  question  of  the  habitat  and  distribution  of  plants  (Part  II, 
p.  115)  were,  however,  based  entirely  on  his  classification  system.  Humboldt's 
interest  in  plant  life,  on  the  other  hand,  is  at  the  very  outset  of  quite  a 
different  nature.  As  is  the  part  of  a  natural  philosopher,  he  takes  as  his 
starting-point  life  in  its  entirety,  examines  its  various  manifestations,  and 
finally  dwells  on  the  special  advantages  which  soil  and  climatic  conditions 
offer  to  the  vegetable  world  in  different  latitudes.  He  puts  the  question: 
How  is  the  shape  of  plants  affected  by  these  conditions  of  life?  And  he 
searches  for  the  connexion  between  the  impression  made  by  the  landscape 

^  The  idea  contained  in  this  story  is  without  doubt  directly  or  indirectly  influenced  by 
Stahl's  previously  mentioned  theory  of  the  soul  as  the  force  that  prevents  the  chemical  com- 
ponents of  the  body  from  disintegrating  (see  Part  II,  p.  181). 


3l6  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

on  the  observer  and  the  shape  of  the  plants  that  dominate  the  landscape. 
Thus  he  produces  semi-artistic,  semi-scientific  pictures  of  vegetation  in 
different  latitudes;  he  declares  that  each  latitude  possesses  its  own  charac- 
teristic natural  physiognomy,  and  he  finally  differentiates  between  certain 
vegetable  types,  not  according  to  systematic  characters,  but  according  to  the 
impression  the  observer  receives  of  their  form  as  a  whole.  He  distinguishes 
sixteen  of  these  landscape-forming  vegetable  types,  though  he  states  that 
their  number  could  certainly  be  increased.  Among  these  types  may  be  men- 
tioned: the  palm  type,  the  banana  shape,  the  heather  type,  the  cactus  type, 
the  orchid  type,  the  fir  type,  grasses,  ferns,  lilies.  The  whole  of  this  concep- 
tion of  plant  life  and  this  grouping  of  its  individual  components  according 
to  common  conditions  of  life,  instead  of  according  to  the  nomenclature 
of  species,  represent  a  new  idea;  it  is  true  that  here  Humboldt  has  learnt 
something,  as  he  himself  acknowledges,  from  BufFon,  as  well  as  from  a 
number  of  earlier  describers  of  landscapes,  but  out  of  these  ideas  and  as  the 
result  of  his  own  observations  he  created  a  new  field  for  research,  which  was 
cultivated  and  extended  at  a  later  period  with  great  success. 

His  cosmos 
During  the  last  decades  of  his  life  Humboldt  devoted  himself  to  formulating 
a  universal  cosmology,  which  was  intended  to  reproduce  every  imaginable 
conception  of  and  all  the  known  facts  about  the  universe :  the  purely  scientific, 
the  historical,  and  the  artistic.  This  gigantic  work,  the  execution  of  which 
was  far  beyond  the  powers  of  one  single  man,  he  called  Kosmos;  its  first  part 
was  published  in  his  seventy-fifth  year  and  a  final  part  of  the  unfinished  work 
came  out  after  his  death.  Never  has  any  natural  scientist  of  modern  times 
conceived  a  plan  on  a  grander  scale,  and  though  its  execution  is  naturally 
both  fragmentary  and  defective,  the  work  nevertheless  contains  a  vast 
amount  of  valuable  material  in  the  way  of  facts  and  is,  besides,  like  all 
Humboldt's  work,  unequalled  in  style.  Romantic  natural  philosophy's  idea 
of  a  uniform  conception  of  nature  has  received  in  Humboldt's  Kosmos  its 
most  glorious  memorial;  it  seems  almost  symbolical  that  its  creator  should 
have  died  in  the  same  year  as  that  in  which  Darwin  published  his  work  on 
the  origin  of  species;  the  modern  theory  of  evolution  stepped  in  where 
natural  philosophy  ended. 


3 .      Lamarck 

Jean  Baptiste  Pierre  Antoine  de  Monet,  usually  styled  Chevalier  de 
Lamarck,  was  born  in  Picardy ,  in  northern  France,  in  1744,  ^^^  ^^  ^^^  young- 
est of  a  large  and  poor  noble  family.  At  an  early  age  he  was  sent  to  a  Jesuit 
school  with  a  view  to  eventually  securing  a  comfortable  living  as  a  priest. 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  317 

From  the  outset  this  prospect  failed  to  have  the  least  attraction  for  him,  but 
as  long  as  his  father  lived,  he  had  to  obey  him.  When  he  was  seventeen, 
however,  his  father  died,  and  he  inherited  a  sum  just  sufficient  to  enable  him 
to  buy  a  nag;  on  this  he  rode  away  and  joined  the  French  Army,  which  at 
that  time  was  in  the  field  during  the  Seven  Years'  War.  On  the  day  after  he 
enlisted,  a  battle  took  place,  in  which  his  company  suffered  severely,  losing 
all  its  officers  and  non-commissioned  officers,  whereupon  Lamarck,  with  his 
one  day's  war-experience,  collected  the  survivors  and  held  out  at  his  post  until 
help  arrived.  This  deed  was  rewarded  with  a  lieutenant's  commission,  but 
his  promotion  went  no  further;  he  was  sent  to  Toulon  on  garrison  duty,  and 
on  the  conclusion  of  peace  he  resigned  his  commission  for  reasons  of  ill 
health  and  was  granted  a  small  pension.  He  now  had  to  look  about  him  for  a 
fresh  means  of  livelihood,  and  for  this  purpose  betook  himself  to  Paris; 
there  he  remained  for  the  next  fifteen  years  as  a  literary  hack,  living  in  a 
garret  in  the  Quartier  Latin  just  the  kind  of  Bohemian  life  that  has  so  often 
been  described  in  novels.  During  these  difficult  years,  however,  there  de- 
veloped in  Lamarck  an  ever-increasing  love  of  natural  science,  particularly 
botany;  even  during  his  garrison  life  on  the  shores  of  the  Mediterranean  the 
abundant  and  wonderful  flora  of  that  coast  had  deeply  interested  him,  and 
this  love  of  knowledge  grew  apace  in  Paris,  where  in  those  days  the  interest 
in  animate  nature  was  kept  alive  by  Buffon.  It  was  he,  too,  who  paved  the 
way  for  the  scientific  success  of  the  penniless  writer;  he  became  interested 
in  a  flora  of  France  that  Lamarck  had  written  and  procured  his  admittance 
to  the  Academy  of  Science.  Further,  Lamarck  was  commissioned  to  travel 
through  several  European  countries  as  companion  to  Buffon's  young  son, 
and  he  finally  became  an  assistant  in  the  botanical  department  of  the  natural- 
history  museum.  It  was  during  the  Revolution,  however,  that  Lamarck 
first  obtained  a  secure  position;  the  National  Convention,  which  wanted  to 
reform  everything,  instituted  a  number  of  professorships,  including  two  in 
zoology.  As  no  more  suitable  candidates  could  be  found,  the  one  chair  was 
offered  to  the  botanist  Lamarck,  and  the  other  to  Geoffroy  Saint-Hilaire, 
who  had  till  then  been  mostly  occupied  with  mineralogy.  These  two  im- 
provised zoologists  shared  between  them  the  duty  of  lecturing,  Geoffroy 
undertaking  the  vertebrates,  and  Lamarck  the  invertebrates.  Thus,  at  the 
age  of  fifty  Lamarck  started  research  work  in  the  field  in  which  he  was 
eventually  to  win  fame  as  a  pioneer.  The  rest  of  his  life  passed  in  assiduous 
work  in  the  career  he  entered  so  late;  retiring  and  modest  as  he  was,  he 
sought  no  outward  honours,  nor  did  he  win  any;  he  remained  throughout 
his  life  in  poor  circumstances,  especially  at  the  end,  having  lost  by  unsuccess- 
ful speculation  what  little  capital  he  had  saved.  He  suffered,  too,  from  domes- 
tic troubles  more  than  most  people;  he  was  married  four  times  and  lived  to 
see  all  his  unions  dissolved  by  death,  while  of  his  seven  children  the  majority 


3l8  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

also  died  prematurely.  Two  daughters,  who  devoted  themselves  entirely  to 
administering  to  him,  were  his  one  consolation  in  his  old  age;  with  their 
aid  he  was  able  to  carry  on  his  work  unremittingly  to  the  end,  although  he 
was  blind  during  the  last  years  of  his  life.  He  died  in  18x9,  and  a  year  later 
the  last  part  of  the  work  that  had  occupied  him  up  to  the  last  was  published. 
Just  as  the  strangeness  of  Lamarck's  fate  is  unique  in  the  annals  of  biol- 
ogy —  a  discharged  lieutenant  without  any  scientific  grounding,  who  from 
being  a  Bohemian  literary  hack  works  himself  up  to  lasting  fame  as  a  scien- 
tist and  who  at  the  age  of  fifty  becomes  professor  in  a  subject  that  he  had  never 
studied  before  —  so  his  posthumous  reputation  has  likewise  been  unique. 
By  his  contemporaries  he  w^as  mainly  looked  upon  as  a  systematist,  and,  as 
we  shall  find  later  on,  he  certainly  did  accomplish  valuable  and  sound  work 
as  one.  But  besides  that  he  published  a  number  of  works  on  evolutionary  his- 
tory based  upon  speculation;  these  attracted  little  attention,  however,  either 
in  his  own  day  or  in  the  immediately  succeeding  period.  They  were  neglected 
by  the  natural-philosophical  school  for  reasons  that  will  be  explained  later, 
and  were  regarded  by  the  subsequent  representatives  of  exact  research  as 
fantastic  speculations.  It  was  not  until  after  the  launching  of  the  modern 
theory  of  the  origin  of  species  that  Lamarck  came  into  his  own.  Haeckel  in 
particular,  who  searched  everywhere  for  precursors  of  that  theory,  the 
promulgation  of  which  he  made  his  mission  in  life,  referred  to  Lamarck  as 
a  pioneer  of  modern  natural  research,  and  there  followed  in  his  footsteps 
a  whole  group  of  scientists  who  saw  in  Lamarck's  theories  the  basis  for  a 
correct  view  of  evolution  in  nature.  During  the  last  few  decades  this  so-called 
neo-Lamarckian  school  has,  it  is  true,  fallen  off  considerably  in  both  num- 
bers and  influence,  but  Lamarck  himself  is  still  counted  one  of  the  pioneers 
of  modern  biology. 

Lamarck' s  multifarious  ivorks 
The  cause  of  these  varying  opinions  lies  essentially  in  the  very  character  of 
Lamarck's  scientific  productions.  As  will  be  seen  from  the  above  account  of 
his  life,  he  was  a  self-taught  man,  without  any  systematic  scientific  training, 
with  the  result  that  his  production  to  a  large  extent  bears  the  mark  of  dilet- 
tantism —  many-sided  interests,  vagueness  of  both  thought  and  expression, 
daringly  brilliant  ideas  side  by  side  with  foolish  fancies.  His  earlier  works 
especially  —  up  to  about  the  close  of  the  century  —  are  extremely  multi- 
farious as  to  contents,  as  well  as  of  unequal  value.  Besides  a  number  of  partly 
still  valuable  botanical  writings,  he  wrote  numerous  works  on  meteorology 
and  geology,  as  well  as  a  collection  of  essays  with  the  striking  title  of 
Memoires  de  physique  et  d' his f aire  nafurelle,  etablis  sur  des  bases  de  raisonnement 
independantes  de  toute  theorie.  Towards  the  close  of  his  life,  however,  he  con- 
centrated entirely  upon  zoology  and  in  that  field  produced  his  best  works.  His 
enthusiastic  admirers  have  as  a  rule  passed  over  his  earlier  speculations  in 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  319 

silence,  yet  without  a  knowledge  of  them  it  is  impossible  to  gain  any  idea  of 
Lamarck's  scientific  development,  all  the  more  so  as  throughout  his  life  he 
firmly  adhered  in  all  essentials  to  the  views  he  held  in  his  youth. 

In  the  above-mentioned  work,  Memoires  de  physique,  Lamarck  endeav- 
oured to  form  a  general  theory  of  existence,  a  combination  of  physics, 
chemistry,  and  physiology.  This  theory  represents  a  continuous  attack  upon 
what  he  calls  "pneumatic  chemistry"  —  that  is,  Lavoisier's  quantitative 
method  (Part  II,  ch.  xii).  For  Lavoisier  himself  Lamarck  has  nothing  but 
praise,  his  polemics  being  invariably  objective  and  honest,  but  on  the  com- 
position of  things  he  has  ideas  that  are  entirely  his  own.  Lavoisier  had  con- 
ceived combustion  as  a  process  of  oxidization;  Lamarck  finds  this  explanation 
absurd  —  the  idea  of  oxygen's  being  an  essential  component  of  both  water 
and  air  is  in  his  opinion  utterly  irrational;  no  chemist  has  ever  seen  it  and 
nobody  has  been  able  to  prove  its  actual  existence.  And  equally  irrational  is 
the  theory  of  chemical  affinity  as  a  cause  of  chemical  associations  between 
the  elements:  "It  is  not  compatible  with  reason  and  is  therefore  impossible." 
As  essential  components  of  nature  Lamarck  assumes  the  four  known  ele- 
ments — •  fire,  air,  water,  and  earth  —  and  adds  a  fifth,  light.  The  purest 
earth  is  —  rock-crystal.  The  chemical  associations  are  not  at  all  bound  to- 
gether by  any  affinity;  rather,  they  strive  to  disintegrate  into  their  simple 
components.  What  creates  chemical  associations  on  the  earth  is  exclusively 
life;  all  inorganic  associations  that  exist  —  rocks,  minerals,  metals  —  are 
disintegrated  remains  of  living  beings.  Lamarck  sets  up  an  evolutionary  series 
that  is  unique  of  its  kind,  beginning  with  blood,  bile,  urine,  bone-substance, 
snail-shell,  and  proceeding  to  increasingly  greater  "disintegrations"  through 
shell-lime,  marble,  gypsum,  to  precious  stones,  metals,  and  lastly  "simple" 
rock-crystal.  The  problem  of  what  life  really  is  is  of  course  a  question  that 
largely  occupies  the  mind  of  Lamarck  and  is  discussed  by  him  with  great 
particularity.  The  essential  factor  in  life  he  finds  to  be  motion;  an  animate 
being  is  composed  of  various  parts  which  affect  one  another  and  are  kept  in 
motion  partly  by  mutual  influence  and  partly  by  influence  from  without,  and 
it  undergoes  constant  change  in  consequence  of  this  motion.  Life  itself  is 
motion  and  nothing  else  —  that  is,  a  purely  mechanical  phenomenon.  The 
essential  components  in  the  living  body  are  partly  solid  (fibres  and  mem- 
branes), partly  liquid  (blood,  lymph,  and  other  special  "fluids,"  of  which 
more  later  on).  Of  the  functions  of  life,  secretion  within  the  organism  is  an 
expression  for  the  afore-mentioned  efl"orts  made  by  the  chemical  associations 
to  disintegrate;  nutrition  counteracts  these  eff'orts  by  providing  the  living 
being  with  fresh  substances,  a  difference  being  made  between  the  power  of  a 
plant  to  form  out  of  simple  alimental  substances  complex  bodies,  and  the 
dependence  of  animals  upon  these  same  complex  products  for  their  nourish- 
ment. —  In  these  and  other  phenomena,  in  both  animate  and  inanimate 


310  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

nature,  there  is,  according  to  Lamarck,  incorporated  as  an  essential  com- 
ponent fire,  which  penetrates  the  whole  of  existence;  it  is  a  "fluid,"  which 
appears  under  various  modifications,  as  heat,  as  electric  and  magnetic  fluid, 
and  in  living  beings  still  further  specialized.  It  produces  colour-perceptions, 
sound  —  Lamarck  denies  that  the  air  conveys  the  sound,  for  a  cannon-shot 
is  heard  at  a  distance  better  with  the  ear  to  the  ground  than  in  the  air  — ■ 
,  and,  further,  chemical  changes,  the  various  kinds  of  which  it  would  take  too 
long  to  enumerate  here.  The  serious  offences  against  contemporary  physical 
and  chemical  knowledge  of  which  Lamarck  is  guilty  in  this  work  will  have 
been  sufficiently  illustrated  by  the  above.  And  it  would  be  a  waste  of  time  to 
trace  the  sources  out  of  which  he  created  these  wild  fancies;  he  himself,  in- 
deed, asserts  that  they  are  "independent  of  any  theory"  and  they  are  charac- 
terized from  beginning  to  end  by  sheer  dilettantism.  Fortunately,  however, 
Lamarck  did  not  retain  this  standpoint  always;  although  more  than  fifty 
years  old  when  he  published  his  Memoires,  he  managed  to  escape  out  of  the 
helpless  maze  of  thought  that  they  involve  and  to  create  works  which  have 
kept  his  memory  alive  even  up  to  the  most  recent  times  —  a  spiritual  test  of 
strength  indeed,  which  is  almost  without  its  counterpart  in  the  history  of 
science.  That  this  was  so  is  not  due  to  his  having  acquired  any  essentially 
better  knowledge  of  physics  and  chemistry  than  others,^  but  to  his  having 
applied  himself  whole-heartedly  to  zoology.  In  this  field,  thanks  to  his  long 
experience  as  a  lecturer  and  a  museum-worker,  he  had  gained  a  many-sided 
knowledge  of  form,  whereon  he  was  able  to  base  a  system  of  thought  that 
was  not  only  original,  but  also  truly  scientific,  as  regards  both  form  and  sub- 
stance. 

The  result  of  Lamarck's  theoretical  speculations  in  the  sphere  of  bi- 
ology —  he  it  was,  in  fact,  who  created  the  word  "biology"  —  is  recorded 
in  three  separate  works:  Kecberches  sur  V organisation  des  corps  vivants,  of  i8ox; 
Philosophic  ^(^oologique,  of  1809;  and  the  introduction  to  his  great  work  His- 
toire  naturelle  des  animaux  sans  verfebres  (i8i5-xx).  The  first  of  these  presents 
in  short  and  concise  form  the  theory  of  the  development  of  life  that  made 
Lamarck  famous.  It  has  been  completely  overshadowed,  however,  in  the 
history  of  biology  by  Philosophie  Zfiologique,  which  is  the  one  work  of 
Lamarck  that  is  regarded  as  a  classic  and  which  has  in  more  recent  times  been 
frequently  reprinted  and  translated  into  many  languages.  It  is  really  an  ex- 
pansion of  the  previous  work,  full  of  repetitions  and  containing  a  number 
of  additions,  which  in  many  instances,  but  not  in  all,  are  improvements. 
In  the  third  of  these  works  the  author  once  more  recapitulates  the  theory  in 
summary  form,  as  he  entertained  it  towards  the  close  of  his  life. 

2  In  his  latest  works,  it  is  true,  he  acknowledges  the  existence  of  oxygen,  a  fact  of  which 
he  had  apparently  been  convinced  by  some  chemist,  but  on  the  whole  he  maintains  the  old  stand- 
point. 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  3x1 

His  life-theory:  life  is  motion 
Lamarck  begins  his  work  Kecherches  with  a  protest  against  that  dry  systema- 
tization  that  is  content  with  differentiating  as  many  species  as  possible  with- 
out troubling  to  make  a  comprehensive  survey  of  the  connexion  between  the 
life-forms  in  nature.  Rather,  he  would  start  by  regarding  life  in  its  entirety, 
and  he  thereupon  finds,  in  accordance  with  his  conception  referred  to  above, 
that  the  most  essential  quality  of  life  is  motion.  All  that  occurs  in  life  is 
motion;  through  it  the  organism  strives  to  develop  and  to  specialize  the 
organs;  motion  is  also  the  absorption  of  nutriment,  whereby  the  individual, 
during  its  days  of  physical  power,  compensates  for  the  losses  caused  by  excre- 
tion, whereas  during  the  later  period  of  life  excretion  becomes  superior  to  the 
power  of  absorbing  nutriment,  so  that  eventually  death  results;  it  is  through 
motion  that  development  proceeds  in  every  living  being,  the  fluids  of  the 
body  making  their  way  through  the  surrounding  solid  parts,  with  the  result 
that  in  these  latter  are  formed  organs  which  assume  various  functions,  and 
canals  which  convey  nourishment  to  them.^  Thus  is  gradually  formed  not 
only  the  individual,  but  also,  step  by  step,  all  living  beings  of  various  types, 
while  the  qualities  that  have  been  developed  in  the  individual  life-forms  are 
transferred  by  reproduction  to  the  descendants.  On  this  basis  it  is  possible  to 
place  all  living  beings  in  one  series,  beginning  with  the  lowest  and  ending 
with  the  highest.  It  is  more  instructive,  however,  to  examine  the  organiza- 
tion of  animals  in  the  opposite  direction,  in  that,  if  we  start  from  the  highest 
forms,  we  can  follow  the  "degradation"  that  appears  in  the  series,  one  organ 
after  another  becoming  changed,  simplified,  and  finally  disappearing.  The 
mammals  are  naturally  the  highest;  they  are  the  only  creatures  that  really 
produce  their  young  alive;  they  possess  milk-secretion,  independent  lungs, 
and  complete  diaphragm.  The  birds  come  lower  than  the  mammals,  for  they 
lay  eggs,  their  lungs  are  fixed,  and  they  have  no  diaphragm.  Below  these  two 
warm-blooded  animal  groups  come  the  reptiles,  owing  to  their  cold  blood  and 
incompletely  formed  heart  and  lungs,  which  latter  are  in  certain  forms  repre- 
sented during  earlier  stages  by  gills  (the  batrachians,  as  is  well  known,  were 
still  at  that  time  grouped  together  with  the  reptiles);  further,  the  two  pairs 
of  extremities  in  these  animals  gradually  disappear,  wherefore  the  snakes, 
which  possess  no  extremities,  are  the  lowest  of  the  order  of  reptiles.  Upwards, 
again,  the  transition  between  reptiles  and  birds  is  formed  by  the  Chelonia 
(tortoises),  while  the  then  newly-discovered  duck-billed  platypus  assumes 
the  same  role  between  birds  and  mammals.  The  fishes,  on  the  other  hand,  are 
lower  than  the  reptiles,  for  they  have  entirely  lost  lungs  and  extremities; 
that  is  to  say,  their  fins  are  not  real  extremities.  With  the  transition  from  the 
fishes  downwards  the  backbone  and  the  inner  skeleton  disappear  from  the 

^  This  theory  recalls  a  similar  one  of  Caspar  Friedrich  Wolff's  (Part  II,  p.  2.50),  but  it  is 
uncertain  whether  Lamarck  knew  his  works  —  at  any  rate,  he  never  quotes  them. 


3X1  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

animal  kingdom.  Of  the  invertebrates,  the  molluscs  stand  highest,  for  they 
have  gills  like  the  fishes  and  possess  brain,  nerves,  and  single-chambered 
heart.  Next  to  them  come  the  Annelida,  which  Lamarck,  after  Cuvier,  dis- 
tinguishes from  the  worms,  and  which  he  has  named;  they  likewise  breathe 
by  means  of  gills,  sometimes  visible,  sometimes  concealed  in  the  skin;  more- 
over, they  possess  a  nervous  system,  a  vascular  system  with  red  blood,  and  a 
pair  of  extensions  thereof  corresponding  to  the  heart.  These  are  followed  by 
the  crustaceans,  also  possessing  gills  and  heart,  but  after  them  these  latter 
organs  disappear  from  the  animal  kingdom.  The  spiders  come  next;  because 
they  have  a  concentrated  respiratory  system  and  emerge  from  the  egg  in  the 
same  form  as  they  retain  afterwards,  they  are  above  the  insects,  which  pos- 
sess scattered  tracheae  and  undergo  metamorphosis.  With  these  animals,  in 
Lamarck's  view,  sexual  reproduction  disappears  from  the  animal  kingdom. 
Thus,  the  worms,  which  follow  next  in  the  series,  are  reproduced  by  gemma- 
tion; as  a  matter  of  fact,  they  may  possess  a  nervous  system  and  tracheas. 
With  them  disappear  visual  organs  and  nervous  system  from  the  animal  king- 
dom. The  next  class  is  the  Radiata,  another  systematic  creation  of  Lamarck's; 
these  animals  lack  visual  organs,  but  possess  organs  of  generation  —  though 
sexless  — ■  and  are  thereby  distinguished  from  the  polypi,  which  possess  no 
organs  at  all. 

Lamarck  having  thus  classified  the  animals  in  a  series  on  a  basis  of  the 
absence  or  presence  of  certain  principal  organs,  he  goes  on  to  state  that  the 
sequence  thus  formed  does  not  refer  to  the  separate  animal  individuals,  but 
to  the  great  masses  of  animals  that  form  one  entire  class;  within  such  a  class 
it  is  possible  that,  owing  to  dissimilarities  in  less  essential  organs,  ramifica- 
tions may  take  place  in  various  directions,  but  the  above  arrangement,  which 
has  been  made  in  the  animal  classes  on  the  basis  of  the  structure  of  the  most 
vital  organs,  is  presented  with  such  certainty  that  "no  enlightened  natural 
scientist  will  be  able  to  produce  another."  It  shows  how,  the  higher  we  come 
in  the  series,  the  greater  becomes  the  specialization  in  the  organs,  while  the 
lower  we  go,  the  simpler  we  find  the  organs  becoming  and  the  wider  their 
functions.  On  this  ever-increasing  specialization  of  the  organs  Lamarck  now 
bases  his  theory  of  how  the  various  life-forms  have  arisen,  a  theory  which  at 
the  very  outset  he  formulates  as  follows:  "It  is  not  the  organs  —  that  is  to 
say,  the  form  and  character  of  the  animal's  bodily  parts  —  that  have  given 
rise  to  its  habits  and  peculiar  properties,  but,  on  the  contrary,  it  is  its  habits 
and  manner  of  life  and  the  conditions  in  which  its  ancestors  lived  that  has 
in  the  course  of  time  fashioned  its  bodily  form,  its  organs,  and  its  qualities." 
He  seeks  to  prove  this  basic  argument  by  innumerable  examples:  moles  and 
blind  mice  have  lost  their  sight  as  a  result  of  living  underground  for  several 
generations,  the  ant-bear  its  teeth  through  swallowing  its  food  whole; 
waders  have  acquired  long  legs  and  long  neck  through  stretching  those  parts 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  313 

of  the  body  in  their  search  for  food  on  the  shores,  swimming  birds  their 
webbed  feet  through  stretching  out  their  toes  during  their  movements  in  the 
water.  In  connexion  herewith  he  declares  that  if  a  number  of  children  were 
to  be  deprived  at  birth  of  their  left  eye  and  they  were  allowed  to  have  children 
by  one  another,  there  would  eventually  arise  after  a  few  generations  a  one- 
eyed  race  of  men.  But  it  is  not  merely  influences  of  this  detailed  kind  that 
re  create  the  life-forms;  but  also  the  effect  of  geographical  conditions  in 
general;  climate,  humidity,  abundance  or  scarcity  of  food,  have  in  the  long 
run  had  a  transforming  influence  upon  animals  as  a  whole  and  have  produced 
new  organs  or  caused  the  old  ones  to  disappear.  This  is  rendered  possible 
owing  to  the  fact  that  there  is  an  infinity  of  time  at  the  disposal  of  evolution; 
"Time  has  no  limits,"  says  Lamarck  explicitly.  Thus  life  becomes  purely 
and  simply  a  mechanical  process;  all  its  manifestations  are  motion  and  noth- 
ing else.  It  is  true,  existence  has  a  Supreme  Originator,  for  whose  name 
Lamarck  always  si^ows  respect,  but  His  greatness  lies  in  the  fact  that  He  has 
created  nature  in  such  a  way  that  it  has  developed  its  profuse  multiplicity 
without  interference  from  without.  This  development  out  of  given  qualifica- 
tions Lamarck  does  not  succeed  in  establishing,  however;  "nature"  appears 
constantly  as  a  creative  power  and  is  spoken  of  in  terms  suggestive  of  a 
personality;  this  is  especially  so  in  Philosophie  ■::oologique,  from  which  a  few 
examples  will  be  cited  further  on  in  this  chapter. 

His  theory  of  life- fluid 
In  the  continuation  of  Kecherches  Lamarck  further  develops  his  mechanical 
theory  of  life,  which  to  him  is  really  the  main  problem,  in  which  his  evolution 
theory  is  only  one  detail  among  many.  To  his  mind,  life  itself  is  the  condition 
in  all  the  parts  of  the  body  that  makes  their  organic  movements  possible. 
This  condition  consists  in  the  existence  of  " T or gasme  vital,"  a  state  of  tension, 
a  "tonus,"  which  maintains  the  molecules  in  the  soft  parts  of  the  body  in  a 
definite  position  and  which  by  increasing  and  diminishing  enables  the  organs 
to  contract  and  expand.  The  cause  of  this  tension  is  a  fluid  that  is  secreted 
by  the  blood  and  thence  absorbed  by  all  the  organs  of  the  body,  but  is  particu- 
larly concentrated  in  the  nervous  system.  This  fluid  is  really  a  peculiar  variety 
of  fire,  related  to  heat  and  electricity,  a  "feu  ethere."  It  is  transmitted  on 
fertilization  from  the  male  sexual  product  to  the  embryo,  which  derives 
life  from  it  —  immediately  in  mammals,  but  not  until  later  in  the  bird's  ^gg, 
which  only  receives  life  by  brooding.  But  this  same  fluid  exists  scattered 
everywhere  throughout  nature,  so  that  everywhere,  and  especially  in  hot 
countries,  with  their  humid  climate,  there  takes  place  a  spontaneous  produc- 
tion of  life.  Lamarck  asserts  that  this  spontaneous  generation  under  the  influ- 
ence of  heat,  light,  and  electricity  goes  on  incessantly,  the  lowest  animal 
forms  —  and  even  plant  forms  —  being  continually  reproduced  out  of 
inanimate  matter;  he  declares  it  to  be  probable  that  the  fresh-water  polypi 


32-4  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

freeze  to  death  every  winter  and  spontaneously  generate  again  every  spring. 
According  to  his  idea,  the  most  primitive  living  creatures  consist  of  a  mass  of 
gelatinous  substance,  which  absorbs  nourishment  through  pores  on  its  sur- 
face. Out  of  these  nature  gradually  evolves  a  special  organ  for  the  admission 
of  food;  first  there  arises  as  a  result  of  the  movements  of  the  animal  a  small 
depression  in  which  the  food  can  easily  collect;  through  the  pressure  ex- 
ercised by  the  food,  this  slight  hollow  expands  into  a  sack-like  cavity,  which 
similarly  becomes  in  process  of  time  still  further  extended;  thus  arose  the 
polypus's  digestive  canal.  The  next  important  life-property  which  nature 
developed  was  reproduction;  this  consists  in  reality  of  a  growth  over  and 
above  the  normal  dimensions;  a  division  must  therefore  take  place,  and 
actually  does  so  in  the  lowest  animals,  the  Infusoria,  which  never  die  of  old 
age,  but  divide  themselves  in  two  when  they  have  attained  a  certain  size. 
Through  the  division's  not  being  uniform,  gemmation  arises,  which  is  the 
manner  of  propagation  characteristic  of  the  polypi;  when  this  is  repeated,  one 
particular  area  becomes  specialized  for  the  purpose,  and  thus  originated  the 
internal  gemmation  by  means  of  which  the  Radiata  propagate.  Through 
further  evolution  in  this  direction  there  arose  the  eggs,  being  incomplete 
buds  which,  in  order  that  they  may  develop  further,  require  to  be  influenced 
by  the  male  sexual  product. 

The  evolution  of  man 
Here  Lamarck  interrupts  his  exposition  of  the  origin  of  the  most  vital  organs 
and  proceeds  direct  to  a  consideration  of  the  evolution  of  man.  Like  Camper, 
he  emphasizes  the  differences  between  the  anatomical  structure  of  man  and 
of  the  higher  apes,  but  all  the  same  he  maintains,  in  conformity  with  his 
view  that  all  properties  are  evolved  by  exercise,  that  both  the  physical  and 
the  intellectual  superiority  of  man  has  been  achieved  through  his  having  in 
the  course  of  ages  exercised  his  faculties  to  an  ever-increasing  perfection, 
while,  on  the  other  hand,  the  higher  apes  can  also  be  trained  to  attain  a  high 
standard  of  intelligence  and  a  finer  character.  But  there  is  still  a  vast  difference 
between  Lamarck's  ideas  of  human  development  and  La  Mettrie's  and  his 
contemporaries'  enthusiasm  over  the  intellectual  similarity  between  primi- 
tive man  and  the  higher  animals,  Lamarck  maintaining  that  it  has  been  given 
to  but  few  men  in  the  whole  course  of  the  ages  to  achieve  real  intelligence, 
whereas  the  majority  have  remained  in  a  state  of  bestial  ignorance;  they 
have  prayed  to  beasts  and  perpetrated  acts  of  the  wildest  folly;  even  where 
a  nation  has  attained  the  highest  culture,  this  has  been  due  to  the  work  of  a 
few  highly  gifted  persons,  while  the  majority  of  their  countrymen  have  in- 
dulged in  the  maddest  aberrations.  Lamarck  is  without  doubt  thinking  here 
of  the  Reign  of  Terror  during  the  Revolution,  which  he  had  witnessed  at  close 
quarters.  It  was  probably  these  memories  of  human  degradation  that  deprived 
him  of  his  taste  for  inquiry  into  the  characteristics  of  primitive  man  and  the 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  315 

man-apes.  Possibly,  too,  fears  of  censure  on  the  part  of  the  Napoleonic 
Government  had  their  influence  in  this  respect. 

After  a  brief  discussion  of  the  term  "species"  in  the  vegetable  and  animal 
kingdoms  in  relation  to  the  mineral  kingdom,  wherein  he  states  that  the 
mineral  differs  from  plants  and  animals  in  not  possessing  individuality,  and 
further  emphasizes  the  influence  of  environment  upon  the  development  of 
species,  adducing  such  examples  as  the  deep-water  and  shore  form  of  Ranun- 
culus aquaticus,  Lamarck  proceeds  to  record  his  views  on  the  nervous  system 
and  its  functions.  As  he  deals  with  the  same  subject  more  fully  in  his  sub- 
sequent works,  we  may  postpone  our  account  of  his  views  on  these  questions 
and  here  close  our  resume  of  his  Kechercbes  —  the  work  that  displays  his  genius 
and  his  limitations  more  clearly,  perhaps,  than  any  other. 

In  his  Philosophic  xpologique  Lamarck  discusses  once  more  his  theory  of 
the  development  of  life  in  nature.  By  way  of  introduction  he  examines  the 
question  of  how  much  is  human  invention  and  how  much  is  nature's  own 
law  in  natural  science,  and  he  comes  to  the  conclusion,  with  Buffon,  that  all 
systematic  classifications  are  arbitrary  products  of  human  thought;  in  nature 
there  are  only  individuals,  which  can  certainly  be  placed  in  groups  in  respect 
of  certain  characteristics,  but  the  lines  between  which  are  always  arbitrarily 
drawn.  As  regards  the  problem  of  evolution  itself,  he  adopts  the  same  plan 
as  in  Kechercbes;  he  first  describes  the  "degradation"  throughout  the  animal 
kingdom,  and  then  expounds  the  theory  as  to  how  the  organs,  and  therewith 
the  animal  forms  themselves,  have  developed  by  habit  and  way  of  living. 
He  further  insists  upon  the  importance  of  the  essential  organs  for  purposes 
of  development  in  contrast  to  the  non-essential,  citing  the  old  instances  of 
how  organs  develop,  to  which  reference  has  been  made  above,  and  a  number 
of  new  ones  besides  —  sometimes  quite  absurd  ideas,  such  as  that  the  males 
of  the  Ruminantia  have  acquired  horns  through  the  blood  having  gone  to 
their  heads  in  the  mating-season.  In  regard  to  the  general  conditions  under 
which  life  has  developed,  he  holds  that  the  earth  has  evolved  continuously 
and  not  as  a  result  of  catastrophes,  as  Buffon,  and  after  him  Cuvier,  main- 
tained, and  also  that  no  animal  species  have  died  out,  except  those  that  man 
himself  has  eradicated,  but  that  the  fossil  species  that  are  not  found  at  the 
present  time  have  been  transformed  into  now  existing  forms.  With  increased 
emphasis  and  with  his  criticism  directed  especially  against  Cuvier,  he  seeks 
to  prove  that  all  animal  classes  are  derived  from  one  another  and  should 
therefore  be  arranged  in  a  line  and  not  parallel  or  "reticularly";  nevertheless, 
it  is  permitted  for  the  genera  in  each  class  to  form  ramifications  from  a 
common  primal  form.  Further,  in  a  supplement  to  the  work  he  extends  this 
ramification  theory  to  the  classes  in  the  Vertebrata,  in  that  the  birds  are 
derived  from  the  tortoises  and  the  mammals  from  the  crocodiles. 


32.6  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

Reform  of  the  animal  system 
Then  follows  a  review  of  the  animal  system,  which  is  one  of  the  most 
brilliant  features  in  the  whole  of  Lamarck's  work.  Here  he  draws  up  the 
invertebrate  system  that,  except  for  one  or  two  alterations,  has  held  good 
ever  since.  He  distinguishes  the  Infusoria  from  the  Polypi,  and  the  Cirri- 
pedia  from  the  MoUusca,  and  thus  gets  ten  invertebrate  classes:  Infusoria, 
Polypi,  Radiata,  Vermes,  Insecta,  Arachnida,  Crustacea,  Annelida,  Cirri- 
pedia,  Mollusca.  Of  these  classes  the  Radiata  are  now  divided  into  two: 
Ccelenterata  and  Echinodermata;  the  Polypi  have  been  grouped  with  the 
Coelenterata  and  the  Cirripedia  with  the  crayfish.  A  number  of  fresh  divisions 
have  certainly  been  made  in  modern  times,  but  at  any  rate  Lamarck  created 
a  system  that,  in  comparison  with  Linnasus's  invertebrate  grouping,  repre- 
sents an  extraordinary  advance;  and  it  is  all  the  more  to  Lamarck's  honour 
that  he  so  generously  acknowledges  his  predecessor,  whom  he  calls  one  of 
the  greatest  scientists  that  have  ever  existed.  But  Lamarck  was  not  only  a 
natural  philosopher,  he  was  also  an  expert  on  form,  and  as  such  he  was  bound 
to  realize  the  value  of  the  preliminary  work  carried  out  by  Linnaeus,  although 
he  did  not  accept  his  hard  and  fast  rules  governing  species.  In  this  connexion 
Lamarck  describes  the  difficulties  with  which  the  systematist  is  overwhelmed 
as  a  result  of  the  aggravated  chaos  in  scientific  nomenclature;  to  cure  this 
evil  he  recommends  that  the  nomenclature  be  fixed  by  international  agree- 
ment, and  this  has  actually  been  done,  though  not  until  quite  recently. 

After  reviewing  the  system  of  the  vertebrate  animals,  which  he  has  bor- 
rowed from  another  zoologist,  Dumeril,  and  is  therefore  not  to  be  compared 
in  point  of  interest  with  the  invertebrate  system,  Lamarck  once  more  takes 
up  the  question  of  the  origin  of  man.  He  says  that  the  centre  of  gravity  in  a 
man  standing  erect  is  situated  far  in  advance  of  the  vertebras,  so  that  muscu- 
lar effort  is  required  to  hold  himself  upright,  which  indicates  an  origin  from 
quadruped  animals.  He  drafts  a  theory  as  to  man's  descent  from  the  anthro- 
poid apes,  but  adds  that  this  might  have  been  so  if  man  had  not  a  different 
origin  from  the  animals.  He  has  evidently  not  dared  to  draw  the  obvious 
conclusion  from  his  theory,  but  has  taken  refuge  behind  a  reservation,  simi- 
lar to  that  made  by  Descartes  in  his  hypothetical  views  on  the  creation. 
Lamarck  apparently  feared  that  Napoleon  would  not  have  felt  flattered  by  a 
genealogy  based  on  the  orang-utan. 

Theoretical  speculation  on  life 
More  than  half  the  Philosophie  loologique,  however,  is  taken  up  with  purely 
theoretical  speculations  on  life  and  its  manifestations,  and  in  this  sphere 
Lamarck  again  shows  his  weaker  side  almost  as  much  as  he  does  in  physics 
and  chemistry.  Although  in  the  foregoing  he  constantly  makes  nature  ap- 
pear as  a  creative  power,  he  defines  it,  in  his  introduction  to  the  speculative 
section  of  the  work,  in  the  following  manner:  "Nature  —  that  word  that 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  317 

is  so  often  pronounced  as  if  it  referred  to  a  particular  being  — -  should  not 
appear  to  us  as  anything  else  than  the  comprehension  of  things,  embracing: 
(i)  all  physical  bodies  that  exist,  (x)  the  general  and  particular  laws  which 
direct  the  changes  in  the  condition  and  position  of  these  bodies,  and  (3)  the 
motion  that  is  current  in  different  forms  among  them,  eternally  maintained 
and  renewed,  infinitely  varying  in  the  products  it  creates  .  .  .  .  "  But  he 
is  so  little  capable  of  adhering  to  this  view  that  only  a  few  pages  further 
on  he  is  able  to  say:  "Every  step  which  Nature  takes  when  making  her 
direct  creations  consists  in  organizing  into  cellular  tissue  the  minute  masses 
of  viscous  or  mucous  substances  that  she  finds  at  her  disposal  under  favour- 
able circumstances."^  A  personal  god  could  not  have  acted  more  personally. 
And  Lamarck's  belief  in  creative  nature  is  as  dogmatic  as  was  Linn^eus's 
belief  in  God.  He  develops  afresh  his  old  statement  that  life  is  nothing  but 
motion,  and  that  motion  is  produced  by  this  wonderful  and  ubiquitous 
ethereal  fire,  which  is  to  Lamarck  what  the  soul  was  to  Stahl;  we  can  apply 
to  the  one  as  to  the  other  the  saying  of  Bonnet,  that  it  performs  anything 
that  one  requires  of  it  and  its  non-existence  can  never  be  proved.  On  this 
basis  Lamarck  creates  an  extremely  curious  psychological  theory.  To  his 
mind  the  soul-life  is  a  purely  mechanical  process,  which  is  dependent  for 
its  nature  upon  those  organs  that  the  animal  in  question  possesses;  animals 
that  lack  muscles  and  nerves  have  practically  no  sense-impressions;  they  are 
"apathetic, "  they  move  only  as  a  result  of  influences  from  outside,  through 
the  ethereal  fire's  penetrating  them  and  stimulating  them.  Animals  having 
a  nervous  system  certainly  receive  sensible  impressions,  but  they  react  to 
them  purely  schematically  and  are  incapable  of  combining  the  impressions 
as  a  guide  for  their  actions;  animals  that  possess  a  brain  can  retain  the  sense- 
impressions  they  receive  and  combine  them  to  form  ideas  as  a  guide  for  their 
actions.  Lamarck's  way  of  explaining  all  the  manifestations  of  the  human 
soul-life  —  sense-impressions,  ideas,  and  moral  conceptions  —  with  the  aid 
of  the  ubiquitous  and  universally  applicable  ethereal-electrical  fluid,  is  in 
itself  of  but  little  interest;  in  this  he  associates  himself  with  thinkers  of 
the  eighteenth  century:  Locke,  Condillac,  and  in  particular  the  physician 
Cabanis  (1757-1808),  all  of  whom  taught  that  ideas  are  exclusively  based  on 
sense-impressions;  the  last-named,  the  most  pronounced  materialist  of  them 
all,  was,  however,  a  far  more  trained,  and  therefore  also  a  more  cautious, 
thinker  than  Lamarck,  who  blindly  relied  on  his  fluid,  by  means  of  which 
he  explained  everything,  while  his  predecessors  were  content  to  analyse  cer- 
tain definite  phenomena  in  the  soul-life. 

Lamarck  managed  to  complete  one  or  two  further  important  works  in 
his  old  age :  the  above-mentioned  lengthy  systematic  survey  of  the  Invertebrata 

*  Philosophic  zoologiqu(,  cd.  cit.,  Part  I,  pp.  349,  362.. 


3X8  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

and  a  work  on  fossil  Mollusca,  which  is  worthy  to  be  associated  with 
Cuvier's  contemporary  works  on  extinct  vertebrate  animals.  In  the  intro- 
duction to  his  former  work  he  deals  for  the  last  time  with  his  theory  of 
evolution.  Nature  is  here  represented  with  greater  emphasis  than  in  his  ear- 
lier works  as  a  creative  force.  "Nature  is  .  .  .  an  intermediary  between  God 
and  the  various  parts  of  the  physical  universe  for  the  fulfilling  of  the  divine 
will."  And  "Nature  has  given  to  animal  life  the  power  of  progressively  con- 
summating the  organization  and  of  developing  and  gradually  perfecting  it." 
It  is  thus  an  inner  striving  after  perfection  that,  besides  the  influence  of  en- 
vironment, has  here  been  the  cause  of  evolution.  This  striving  after  evolu- 
tion, which  is  also  hinted  at  in  his  earlier  writings,  became,  as  we  shall  see, 
a  stumbling-block  for  Darwin,  which  evoked  his  opposition  to  Lamarck's 
theory.  It  now  remains  to  examine  the  hypotheses  on  which  this  wealth  of 
scientific  production  rests  and  the  influence  it  had. 

Influence  of  Buff  on  and  Bonnet  on  Lamarck 
The  scientist  by  whom  Lamarck  as  well  as  other  biologists  in  France  at 
that  period  was  undoubtedly  most  influenced  was  Bufi"on.  We  recognize  this 
influence  in  Lamarck's  emphatic  assertion  that  only  individuals  exist  in 
reality,  while  the  categories  of  the  classification  system  are  products  of  the 
mind,  as  also  in  the  whole  of  his  general  conception  of  life  as  one  vast  evo- 
lutionary process  of  a  purely  physical  character;^  even  the  very  idea  of 
evolution  as  a  result  of  habits  of  life  and  environment  we  find  developed 
in  Buffon,  who  cites  in  proof  thereof  the  featherless  face  of  the  rook  and  the 
padded  feet  of  the  camel.  If  we  compare  these  two  scientists,  we  find  that 
BufFon  is  without  doubt  superior  as  a  thinker;  he  realizes  the  difference  be- 
tween hypothesis  and  fact,  as  he  is  aware  of  the  limitations  of  natural  science 
—  things  for  which  Lamarck  has  absolutely  no  mind.  On  the  other  hand, 
Lamarck  is  decidedly  superior  in  his  knowledge  of  form  and  has  a  far  keener 
eye  for  classification,  which  is  certainly  not  exclusively  due  to  the  fact  that 
he  was  acquainted  with  a  greater  number  of  forms  than  his  predecessor. 

But  Lamarck  also  learnt  a  good  deal  from  Bonnet,  as  indeed  he  ex- 
pressly acknowledges.  The  classification  of  the  animal  kingdom  in  one  single 
series  was  adopted  by  him  from  this  source,  as  also  the  actual  French  expres- 
sion for  it  —  "  khelle ' '  (scale).  The  idea  of  animals'  ' '  degeneration ' '  through 
the  loss  of  certain  organs  is,  however,  reminiscent  of  Vicq  d'Azyr.  And, 

^  Among  Lamarck's  precursors  it  is  also  customary  to  mention  BENoix  de  Maillet  (1656- 
1738),  for  a  long  time  French  consul  in  Egypt  and  the  author  of  a  work  on  natural  philosophy 
published  under  the  name  of  Telliamed  (the  anagram  of  his  surname),  wherein  is  described  in 
an  extremely  fantastic  manner  how  the  entire  earth  was  once  covered  by  the  sea,  and  the  ances- 
tors of  all  existent  land-animals  were  aquatic  animals,  which  gradually  became  accustomed  to 
living  on  land.  It  is,  however,  difficult  to  determine  what  influence  this  work,  which  was  treated 
with  contempt  by  Voltaire  and  was  speedily  forgotten,  may  have  had  upon  Lamarck. 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  32.9 

finally,  Cuvier,  with  whom  he  was  so  often  in  controversy,  has  undoubtedly 
exercised  great  influence  upon  him  through  his  earlier  writings;  we  have 
already  seen  how  Lamarck  gained  from  them  important  ideas  in  regard  to 
classification,  but  in  connexion  also  with  problems  of  evolutionary  history 
he  has  undoubtedly  felt  the  influence  of  his  younger  rival  —  a  point  that 
will  be  more  closely  dealt  with  in  connexion  with  the  latter's  own  work. 
But  though  we  can  thus  trace  outside  influences  in  Lamarck's  speculations, 
it  is  nevertheless  to  his  lasting  credit  that  he  formulated  and  elaborated  as 
he  did  the  idea  of  origin.  In  that  respect  he  is  truly  a  pioneer  of  modern 
biology.  It  is  true  that  the  theory  of  the  heredity  of  qualities  acquired 
through  the  influence  of  environment  has  not  stood  its  ground  in  face  of 
modern  exact  research  in  this  field,  and  also  that  the  actual  method  of  work- 
ing out  the  idea  leaves  very  much  to  be  desired.  Thus,  for  instance,  one  would 
have  expected  that  when  he  so  definitely  differentiates  between  essential 
and  non-essential  organs  and  qualities,  he  would  have  tried,  following  his 
own  method,  to  trace  the  development  of  the  essential  organs  (heart,  lungs, 
backbone),  instead  of  dilating  upon  such  details  as  the  legs  and  feet  of  waders 
and  swimming  birds.  But  the  idea  itself  is  nevertheless  conceived  and  elab- 
orated not  only  with  splendid  consistency,  but  also  with  a  keen  eye  for  pe- 
culiarities in  the  interrelation  of  living  forms,  which  left  all  his  predecessors 
far  behind.  And  indeed  details  can  be  instanced  which  are  highly  original, 
as,  for  example,  the  theory  of  the  origin  of  the  digestive  canal  through  in- 
vagination. It  is  in  all  probability  here  that  Haeckel,  the  originator  of  the 
"gastr^a"  theory  and  an  enthusiastic  admirer  of  Lamarck,  obtained  the 
idea  for  his  hypothesis,  which  has  proved  so  valuable  to  modern  embryology. 
The  superficiality  of  Lamarck's  psychological  speculation  has  already  been 
pointed  out,  but  this  quality  he  shared  with  many  of  his  predecessors  and 
contemporaries;  he  is  here  a  child  of  the  era  of  enlightenment;  the  Supreme 
Originator  who  was  at  one  time  creative,  but  afterwards  inactive,  and 
also  the  subsequently  omnipotent  nature,  are  ideas  that,  since  the  days  of 
Voltaire,  often  recurred  in  the  works  of  scientists  of  that  epoch,  while  even 
the  mechanical  soul-theory  constantly  occurs,  better  or  worse  expounded  in 
the  writings  of  that  period.  In  the  purely  systematical  sphere,  on  the  other 
hand,  Lamarck  is,  as  previously  pointed  out,  one  of  the  foremost  of  all  time, 
and  perhaps  he  has  made  in  this  sphere  his  most  lasting,  although  not  his 
most  brilliant,  contribution  to  the  development  of  biology. 

Importance  of  Lamarck's  life-work 
We  have  already  suggested  that  Lamarck's  reputation  in  his  own  age  was 
based  entirely  on  his  work  as  a  systematist.  That  he  did  not  receive  recogni- 
tion as  a  natural  philosopher  was  essentially  due  to  the  fact  that  his  materi- 
alistic conception  of  nature,  which  originated  during  the  previous  century, 
was  already  out  of  date  when  he  came  on  the  scene;  the  two  scientists  who 


330  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

entirely  controlled  the  development  of  biology  at  that  time,  and  who  will 
be  discussed  in  the  next  chapters  —  namely,  Cuvier  and  Bichat  —  both  em- 
braced an  entirely  different  theory  from  Lamarck's  as  to  the  intrinsic  nature 
of  life,  nor,  indeed,  did  the  latter's  speculation  really  possess  that  force  and 
consistency  which  would  have  enabled  it  to  hold  its  own  against  more  mod- 
ern directions  of  thought.  Neither,  on  the  other  hand,  did  contemporary 
natural  philosophers  pay  any  attention  to  this  thought-system,  which,  even 
from  its  own  point  of  view,  became  rapidly  out  of  date  and,  besides,  was 
not  particularly  complete  in  form;  to  one  such  as  Schelling  and  his  school 
it  must  indeed  have  been  an  abomination,  if  only  on  account  of  its  connexion 
with  the  hated  seventeenth-century  materialism,  and  even  Goethe  had  much 
the  same  motive  for  leaving  it  at  its  worth.  The  day  arrived,  however,  when 
the  mechanical  conception  of  life  again  came  into  its  own  and  when  La- 
marck's Philosophic  :^oologique  underwent  a  brilliant  revival.  The  account  of 
this  revival  is  reserved  for  a  future  chapter;  but  this  much  may  be  pointed 
out  here,  that  Lamarck's  greatest  admirer  in  modern  times,  Haeckel,not  only 
adopted  his  theory  of  evolution,  but  also  a  considerable  amount  of  both 
good  and  bad  out  of  his  materialistic  psychology  —  this,  too,  having  thus 
exercised  some  influence  up  to  our  own  day. 

But  though  Lamarck's  ideas  were  thus  to  have  a  future,  the  biological 
research  of  his  own  age  was  being  directed  by  a  man  with  an  entirely  differ- 
ent conception  of  nature  and  its  phenomena,  a  man  who  possessed  to  a  rare 
degree  a  conception  of  those  problems  which  at  that  time  most  urgently 
required  solution,  and  who  was,  moreover,  capable  of  dealing  with  these 
problems  in  a  manner  that  redounded  to  the  lasting  benefit  of  science.  This 
scientist  was  Cuvier,  one  of  the  foremost  of  those  who  laid  the  foundations 
of  biology  in  the  modern  sense  of  the  word. 


CHAPTER    II 


CU VIER 


GEORGES  Leopold  Chretien  Frederic  Dagobert  Cuvier  was  born  in 
1769  at  Montbeliard,  a  small  town  not  far  from  Basel,  which,  al- 
«•  though  entirely  French,  belonged  at  that  time  to  the  Duchy  of 
Wiirttemberg.  He  came  from  a  French  Huguenot  family,  which  had  at  one 
time  sought  refuge  from  religious  persecution  at  home;  his  father,  however, 
had  been  an  officer  in  French  service,  but  in  his  old  age  had  returned  to  his 
native  town,  where  he  married  and  lived  on  a  small  pension  given  him  by 
the  French  Government.  At  an  early  age  young  Georges  displayed  brilliant 
intellectual  gifts;  he  passed  through  the  local  school  with  honours  and  dur- 
ing his  time  there  became  acquainted  with  BufFon's  writings,  which  he 
diligently  studied.  The  poverty  of  his  family,  however,  threatened  to  pre- 
vent him  from  continuing  his  education,  when  a  chance  opportunity  procured 
him  free  entry  into  the  Karlsschule  at  Stuttgart.  This  one-time  famous  edu- 
cational establishment  was  originally  a  military  academy,  but  had  been  ex- 
tended by  the  reigning  Duke  Karl  into  a  college  providing  for  the  training 
of  Civil  Service  officials  as  well.  The  school  was  renowned  for  its  excellent 
staff  of  teachers  and  at  the  same  time  feared  for  the  severe  military  discipline 
exercised  there  under  the  personal  supervision  of  the  despotic  Prince.  Schil- 
ler, the  German  poet  of  liberty,  had  been  one  of  its  first  pupils,  but  had 
escaped  from  the  insufferable  constraint  by  flight,  and  others  had  followed 
his  example.  Cuvier,  on  the  other  hand,  who  was  not  only  naturally  gifted, 
but  also  possessed  a  sense  of  discipline,  got  on  well  there;  although  upon 
first  entering  the  academy  he  had  no  knowledge  of  German,  he  soon  became 
one  of  the  best  pupils  in  the  class  for  the  science  of  State  finances,  which 
he  entered  because  natural  science  was  most  widely  taught  there  for  the  bene- 
fit of  aspiring  argicultural  and  forestry  employees.  The  teacher  of  biology 
here  was  Karl  Friedrich  Kielmayer  (1765-1844),  one  of  the  most  extraor- 
dinary of  German  biologists,  afterwards  professor  at  Tubingen,  a  man  who 
allowed  none  of  the  courses  of  lectures  that  he  gave  during  a  long  life  to 
be  printed,  though  they  were  highly  thought  of,  copies  of  them  being  made 
and  eagerly  studied.  He  appears  to  have  been  a  speculative  natural  scientist, 
who  had  been  influenced  by  Herder's  ideas  of  a  common  primal  type  for  all 
living  creatures  and  their  several  organs,  and  who  consequently  strongly 
recommended  the  study  of  comparative  anatomy.  Cuvier  received  a  thorough 

331 


332.  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

grounding  at  his  hands  and  gained  from  him  many  valuable  ideas, 
which  indeed  he  gratefully  acknowledged  throughout  his  life.  Having  suc- 
cessfully passed  out  of  the  school  at  the  age  of  eighteen  he  returned  home; 
he  could  not  afford  to  work  his  way  up  as  an  unsalaried  official  in  the  Civil 
Service,  so  he  had  to  accept  the  post  of  tutor  in  a  Protestant  family  in  Nor- 
mandy. Here  on  the  Channel  coast  he  found  an  entirely  new  animal  world, 
which  he  at  once  began  to  study  with  keen  interest;  in  his  spare  time  he 
dissected  all  the  fishes  he  came  across  and  compared  their  structure,  and  with 
even  greater  enthusiasm  took  up  the  study  of  the  innumerable  lower  animal 
forms  that  the  ebb  tide  left  stranded  on  the  shore  —  molluscs,  worms,  and 
starfish.  In  Linnasus's  Systema  Nature,  which  was  the  examination  text-book 
of  the  time,  these  creatures  were  not  thoroughly  dealt  with;  even  Aristotle 
had  at  one  time  displayed  greater  interest  in  marine  animals,  and  in  his  writ- 
ings Cuvier  found  not  only  records  of  their  life,  but  also  ideas  suggesting 
ways  of  comparing  their  different  structure.  He  drew  everything  that  he 
studied,  for  he  had  learnt  to  be  a  clever  draughtsman.  Some  of  these  pictures, 
which  were  submitted  through  an  aquaintance  to  Geoffrey  Saint-Hilaire, 
then  newly-elected  professor  in  Paris,  proved  of  momentous  importance  for 
Cuvier's  future.  He  was  summoned  to  Paris  and  within  a  short  time  was 
appointed  professor  of  comparative  anatomy,  although  he  had  never  dis- 
sected a  human  body  —  an  appointment  similar  to  that  of  GeofFroy  and  La- 
marck the  year  before.  Thus  his  fortune  was  made  and  new  promotions  and 
honours  followed  in  rapid  succession,  more  than  space  allows  us  to  enumer- 
ate. Cuvier  stood  especially  high  in  Napoleon's  favour;  contemporary  with 
the  Emperor  in  regard  both  to  the  year  of  his  birth  and  to  the  period  when 
he  first  became  eminent,  he  possessed  something  of  the  latter's  genius  for 
organization;  his  energy  was  inexhaustible,  he  could  discharge  many  duties 
at  the  same  time  without  neglecting  a  single  detail,  he  was  full  of  ideas 
touching  problems  of  organization,  and  he  also  possessed  a  theoretical 
knowledge  of  statecraft  which  he  had  acquired  during  his  school  period 
at  Stuttgart.  Thus  he  became  "  insfecteur  generaV  in  the  department  of  edu- 
cation and  carried  out  his  duties  in  that  post,  at  the  same  time  attending  to 
his  professorship  and  his  science,  so  successfully  that  under  his  leadership 
the  educational  system  in  France  was  thoroughly  reformed  and  a  number 
of  new  universities  founded,  both  in  France  and  in  its  extensive  subject 
countries,  Italy  and  Holland.  When  Napoleon  fell,  Cuvier  became  an  indis- 
pensable authority  in  the  spheres  of  science  and  education;  in  spite  of  the 
Catholic  reaction  that  succeeded  the  Bourbon's  regime,  he,  a  Protestant,  was 
allowed  to  retain  his  appointments  and  received  still  further  promotions, 
becoming  a  baron  and  minister  for  Protestant  ecclesiastical  affairs.  Through- 
out this  period  he  was  wise  enough  to  maintain  his  political  independence, 
and  after  the  July  revolution  he  rose  still  higher,  becoming  a  peer  of  France. 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  333 

By  that  time,  however,  his  days  were  numbered;  he  died  of  cholera  during 
the  first  epidemic  that  ravaged  Europe,  in  i83z.  His  wife  survived  him,  but 
all  his  children  had  died  before  him. 

As  a  personality  Cuvier  has  been  very  differently  judged,  both  by  his 
contemporaries  and  by  subsequent  generations.  It  may  be  taken  for  granted 
that  one  who  served  Napoleon  with  such  great  success  was  himself  some- 
thing of  a  despot,  and  he  certainly  did  not  escape  the  personal  hatred  that 
is  always  the  lot  of  such  men.  Bitter  accusations  have  been  made  against 
him  even  in  modern  times,  but  their  truth  is  contradicted  by  the  reputation 
he  enjoyed  amongst  his  contemporaries.  Better  evidence  of  his  true  character 
is  provided  by  the  unfailing  dignity  with  which  he  carried  on  his  contro- 
versy against  Geoffroy  Saint-Hilaire,  as  well  as  by  his  widely  attested  kind- 
liness and  helpfulness  towards  younger  scientists.  In  his  political  views  he 
was  conservative,  though  not  one  of  the  servile  type;  since  the  appearance 
of  the  origin-of-species  theory  he  has  been  accused  even  of  scientific  conserv- 
atism on  account  of  his  having  maintained  the  immutability  of  species; 
in  this  respect  he  must  naturally  be  judged  according  to  the  standards  of 
his  time  and,  viewed  from  this  standpoint,  his  opposition  to  Lamarck's 
theories  is  easily  explained.  As  to  his  vital  importance  for  the  development 
of  biology,  however,  there  can  be  no  two  opinions;  a  survey  of  his  most 
important  work  will  confirm  this. 

Cuvier  s  co:nparative  anatojny 
When  Cuvier  set  out  to  deal  with  comparative  anatomy  on  scientific  and 
educational  lines,  he  started  from  a  point  directly  opposed  to  his  predeces- 
sors' line  of  advance.  All  of  these  had  been  medical  men:  Daubenton  and 
Vicq  d'Azyr  as  well  as  Camper  and  Blumenbach;  to  them  man  was  the  pri- 
mary object,  with  which  all  other  living  creatures  were  compared.  Cuvier, 
however,  had  begun  by  studying  marine  animals:  fishes,  molluscs,  and 
worms.  Upon  coming  to  Paris  he  carried  out  a  num.ber  of  valuable  investi- 
gations, in  the  style  of  Camper,  on  special  subjects,  such  as  the  orang-utan, 
the  rhinoceros,  and  the  lemur,  and  later  on,  the  Vertebrata  became  his  chief 
object  of  investigation.  He  believed  his  mission  in  life  to  be  the  creation  of 
a  general  comparative  anatomy;  he  worked  for  it  throughout  his  life  and 
in  his  other  writings  often  referred  to  the  forthcoming  work,  but  it  was 
never  completed.  In  preparation  for  it  he  published  his  lectures  on  compara- 
tive anatomy,  written  down  by  his  pupil  Dumeril.  The  system  of  thought 
that  he  elaborated  in  these  lectures  was  adopted  in  several  treatises  on  spe- 
cial subjects:  fishes,  molluscs,  and  fossil  vertebrates.  Finally  he  published  a 
systematic  work,  Kegm  animal^  based  on  the  same  principle.  As  a  result  of 
these  works  he  became,  as  W.  Leche  says,  "the  founder  of  modern  compara- 
tive zoology.  He  became  so  not  through  bringing  to  light  a  large  number 
of  fresh  facts,  but  rather  through  having  introduced  a  new  method."  Much 


334  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

the  same  judgment  has  been  expressed  concerning  another  of  the  great  pio- 
neers whom  France  has  given  to  scientific  research  —  Lavoisier.^  This  abil- 
ity to  create  new  scientific  values  by  way  of  method  seems  to  be  inherent 
in  the  French  nation,  with  its  keen  and  critical  faculty. 

The  new  method  that  Cuvier  thus  introduced  was  comparative  anatomy 
in  the  modern  sense  of  the  term.  True,  as  he  himself  admits,  he  was  not  with- 
out precursors  —  the  two  collaborators  BufFon  and  Daubenton,  and  also 
Camper,  Vicq  d'Azyr,  and  Blumenbach,  had  made  weighty  contributions 
to  the  branch  of  science  in  question.  But  Cuvier's  great  contribution  is  his 
consistent  and  far-reaching  application  of  the  comparative  method,  whereby 
he  actually  created  an  entirely  new  view  of  the  connexion  of  causes  in  nature, 
in  respect  of  both  the  construction  of  the  separate  individual  and  the  mutual 
relation  of  the  various  animal  forms.  In  this  sphere  he  has  perhaps  learnt 
most  from  Aristotle,  whom  he  resembled  in  his  power  of  discovering  and 
comparing  formal  qualities  of  fundamental  importance  for  the  conception 
of  life  in  nature. 

In  his  first  more  important  work,  the  above-mentioned  Lecons  sur  V anato- 
mic corn-park,  which  came  out  in  the  years  1 799-1 805,  Cuvier  still  to  a  certain 
extent  holds  to  the  old  point  of  view,  the  influence  of  his  predecessors,  chiefly 
Daubenton  and  Vicq  d'Azyr,  being  clearly  apparent.  But  what  at  once  strikes 
one  on  reading  this  work  of  Cuvier's  youth  is  the  clarity  and  soberness  of 
thought  that  dominate  his  whole  conception,  particularly  in  the  purely  theo- 
retical problems.  All  speculation  upon  the  innermost  essence  of  existence 
is  carefully  avoided;  he  frankly  acknowledges  the  powerlessness  of  the  human 
capacity  for  thought  in  this  sphere  and  the  worthlessness  of  those  systems 
of  thought  that  earlier  and  contemporary  natural  philosophy  had  created 
in  order  to  fill  the  gaps  in  our  knowledge  of  nature.  In  this  Cuvier  stands 
out  in  sharp  contrast  to  such  scientists  as  Buffon,  Bonnet,  and  Lamarck,  to 
say  nothing  of  the  German  natural  philosophers  of  his  age.  This  tendency 
to  criticism  was  undoubtedly  innate  in  Cuvier;  it  was  certainly  stimulated 
by  the  study  of  Kant,  whom  he  quotes  in  one  place,  just  as,  on  the  whole, 
his  acquaintance,  initiated  in  Stuttgart,  with  the  German  world  of  thought 
contributed  towards  broadening  his  field  of  vision  beyond  what  was  cus- 
tomary in  his  countrymen  at  that  time.  The  consideration  of  the  problem 
of  life  with  which  the  work  referred  to  starts  is  thus  introduced  by  the  em- 
phatic  declaration  that  life  in  its  innermost  essence  is  and  must  remain  a 
riddle:  "a  word  that  the  untrained  mind  is  ready  to  regard  as  an  expression 
for  a  special  principle,  although  actually  it  can  never  denote  anything  but 
the  summary  of  the  phenomena  that  have  given  rise  to  its  formation."  Then 
follows  a  description  of  these  phenomena,  which  recalls  that  which  Hum- 

^  See  Part  II,  p.  2.65. 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  335 

boldt  gives  in  his  early  work  mentioned  above:  we  observe  a  state  that  hin- 
ders the  ordinary  physical  and  chemical  forces  in  their  efforts  to  dissolve 
the  body  into  its  simple  components:  this  is  called  life,  and  its  maintenance 
requires  a  constant  renewal  of  chemical  components;  fresh  components  are 
absorbed  by  the  body  at  the  same  time  as  others  already  existing  in  it  are 
given  off.  Finally  this  process  ceases,  whereupon  death  ensues,  accompanied 
by  that  dissolution  of  the  components  of  the  body  which  life  had  prevented. 
And  this  life  can  be  produced  only  by  previous  life,  but  the  problem  of  the 
production  of  life  is  as  much  beyond  our  grasp  as  is  that  of  life  itself.  Cuvier 
therefore  does  not  accept  the  principle  of  spontaneous  generation.  Next,  he 
gives  an  account  of  the  various  components  of  the  body  —  their  composi- 
tion and  function.  His  account  shows  that  he  had  mastered  contemporary 
chemistry,  as  developed  by  Lavoisier  and  his  successors;  he  emphasizes  the 
part  played  by  oxygen  in  respiration,  which  is  expressly  compared  with  a 
process  of  combustion;  he  enumerates  the  simple  components  of  the  body  — 
carbon,  hydrogen,  oxygen,  and  nitrogen  —  pointing  out  the  importance  of 
the  last-named  element  in  the  animal  organism  as  opposed  to  the  vegetable 
organism.  It  is  hardly  necessary  to  lay  stress  on  the  vast  difference  between 
this  substantiated  and  critical  exposition  of  life-phenomena  and  their  basic 
structure,  and  Lamarck's  fantastic  speculations  upon  life.  The  one  predeces- 
sor whom  Cuvier  most  recalls  in  this  early  work  of  his  is  without  doubt 
Vicq  d'Azyr.  But  in  contrast  to  him  there  stands  out  at  once  Cuvier's  origi- 
nality, chiefly  in  his  conception  of  the  object  of  anatomy  and  the  consequent 
arrangement  of  the  details  of  his  exposition;  whereas  in  Vicq  d'Azyr  the 
function  of  the  organs  is  the  essential,  and  the  basis  on  which  the  work 
rests  is  therefore  physiological,  Cuvier  thrusts  the  form  of  the  organs  into 
the  foreground.  He  holds  that  respiration,  whose  role  in  the  renewal  of  sub- 
stance is  the  same  throughout  the  entire  animal  kingdom,  is  performed 
within  the  separate  animal  classes  by  means  of  organs  which  are  so  unlike 
one  another  that  no  comparison  is  possible  between  them.  And  this  is  also 
the  case  with  the  organs  of  motion. 

His  correlation  theory 
On  the  other  hand,  in  similar  animals  there  takes  place  a  co-operation  be- 
tween the  organs  that  makes  them,  as  far  as  regards  their  form,  entirely 
dependent  upon  one  another;  the  correlation  between  the  separate  organs 
in  the  same  body,  which  Vicq  d'Azyr  had  already  described  in  its  main  fea- 
tures, is  studied  in  detail  by  Cuvier  and  to  him  represents  the  very  basis  of 
his  conception  both  of  animals'  habits  of  life  in  nature  and  of  their  system- 
atic classification.  He  points  out  that  a  carnivorous  animal,  while  having  a 
digestive  canal  intended  to  absorb  this  kind  of  food,  must  also  possess  sharp 
teeth  for  tearing  the  meat,  jaws  adapted  to  these  teeth,  claws  for  clutching 
its  prey,  power  of  rapid  motion,  and  good  visual  organs;  a  beast  of  prey 


336  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

thus  never  has  hoofs  or  flat  molars,  for  they  suit  only  herbivorous  animals. 
A  practised  naturalist  should  thus  be  able  to  determine  from  the  shape  of 
one  single,  suitably  selected  part  of  the  body  the  whole  of  the  animal's 
structure,  habits,  and  place  in  the  system.  And  in  this  system,  therefore, 
only  such  animals  should  be  grouped  together  as  fully  conform  to  one 
another,  at  least  in  the  organs  that  are  most  essential  to  life.  The  creation 
of  a  system  based  entirely  upon  such  conformity  in  the  organs  henceforth 
became  one  of  the  missions  in  life  that  Cuvier  never  let  out  of  sight.  For 
the  time  being,  however,  he  contented  himself  with  a  system  of  grouping 
that  differs  from  the  old  only  in  that  the  vertebrates  and  the  invertebrates 
are  distinguished  from  one  another,  and  also  that  the  lowest  animals  are 
grouped  together  under  the  name  of  Zoophyta  —  a  name  of  which  Lamarck 
strongly  disapproved.  Otherwise  Cuvier  retained  the  variously  composed 
class  Vermes,  and  he  also  made  his  anatomical  comparisons  cover  the  entire 
animal  kingdom  all  at  once.  In  doing  so,  however,  he  is  at  the  very  outset 
careful  not  to  extend  the  comparisons  in  detail  beyond  what  he  can  vouch 
for  —  in  sharp  contrast  to  the  audacity  of  both  Vicq  d'Azyr  and  Lamarck, 
not  to  speak  of  Geoffroy  Saint-Hilaire. 

His  studies  of  fossils 
During  the  succeeding  period  Cuvier  applied  his  method  to  the  special  in- 
vestigations into  fishes  and  molluscs  that  have  been  previously  mentioned, 
but  principally  to  mammals.  Within  this  class  he  soon  found  himself  engaged 
in  a  special  field  of  research,  the  study  of  fossil  forms.  As  is  well  known, 
Paris  is  situated  in  the  centre  of  a  calcareous  district,  in  which  the  stone 
used  for  building-material  is  particularly  rich  in  fossils.  These  had  already 
attracted  Buffon,  for  purposes  of  both  observation  and  speculation;  it  was 
on  the  basis  of  material  gathered  from  this  and  other  districts  that  he  formed 
his  theory  of  the  evolution  of  the  earth  and  of  the  creatures  living  on  it 
(Part  II,  p.  ii4).  Cuvier,  however,  was  the  first  to  apply  himself  to  a  system- 
atic exploration  of  the  richly  fossiliferous  Paris  area;  with  the  assistance 
of  his  friend  Brogniart,  he  organized  systematic  excavations,  in  the  course 
of  which  the  location  of  the  fossils  was  closely  observed  and  the  animal 
remains  scattered  about  in  each  place  were  noted  as  carefully  as  possible. 
After  this  Cuvier  began  to  apply  his  correlation  theory  to  fossils;  for  every 
single  bone  that  was  discovered  he  searched  in  the  neighbourhood  for  such 
bones  as  appeared  from  their  structure  to  belong  to  the  first  one  found,  if 
the  resultant  skeleton  nevertheless  remained  incomplete,  he  drew  his  con- 
clusions from  the  structure  of  the  available  bones  as  to  the  habits  of  the 
animal,  and  from  them  again  as  to  the  structure  of  the  bones  that  were  miss- 
ing; from  the  bone-structure  it  was  afterwards  possible  to  determine  the  con- 
struction of  the  soft  parts.  The  accuracy  of  the  method  was  still  further 
ensured  by  the  extinct  animal's  skeleton  being  regularly  compared  in  detail 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  337 

with  the  corresponding  bones  of  closely  related  existing  animals.  Through 
this  method  of  reconstruction,  which  he  expounded  in  his  famous  work 
Recbercbes  sur  les  ossemens  jossiles  (i8ii),  Cuvier  created  the  science  of  palae- 
ontology in  the  modern  sense.  And  at  the  same  time  he  largely  reformed 
the  system  of  zoological  classification  by  introducing  fossil  animals  into  it; 
by  account's  being  taken  of  the  extinct  animal  forms  the  investigations  into 
the  problem  of  affinity  in  the  modern  animal  world  have  been  far  more  firmly 
substantiated  and  placed  on  a  sounder  basis  than  had  been  possible  before, 
and,  moreover,  they  have  led  to  results  that  to  the  systematists  of  earlier 
times  would  have  been  utterly  inconceivable.  Of  Cuvier's  own  investigations 
in  this  field  his  comparative  study  of  the  order  of  elephant  in  particular  has 
won  high  commendation;  he  has  here  shown  in  the  most  convincing  way 
what  results  his  new  method  is  capable  of  giving.  He  begins  by  examining 
the  difference  between  the  Indian  and  the  African  elephant,  which  were  for- 
merly grouped  as  a  single  species,  but  which,  as  he  proves  by  comparison  of 
their  teeth  and  bone-structure,  are  two  widely  different  species;  moreover, 
he  has  established  the  fact  that  the  extinct  mammoth,  of  which  he  secured 
as  many  remains  as  he  possibly  could,  is  in  reality  more  closely  related  to 
the  Indian  elephant  than  the  latter  is  to  the  African.  And,  finally,  he  com- 
pares with  existing  elephants  a  number  of  other  extinct  types,  which  had 
either  been  known  before  and  described  by  Buffon,  or  else  were  in  the  form 
of  newly-discovered  remains;  among  these  fossils  there  are  some  from  Amer- 
ica that  possess  knobby  molars,  which  warrants  their  being  formed  into  a 
new  genus,  Mastodon;  the  members  of  this  genus  must,  however,  be  re- 
garded as  true  elephants,  for  their  heavy  head  postulates  a  short  neck,  and 
this  again,  as  well  as  the  long  legs,  show  that  the  animal  must  have  pos- 
sessed a  trunk,  while  from  the  knobby  molars  it  may  be  concluded  that  its 
food  was  similar  to  that  of  the  hippopotamus.  Generally  speaking,  the  Pach- 
ydermata  especially  interested  Cuvier;  he  studied  their  existing  forms: 
rhinoceros,  hippopotamus,  and  tapir,  in  comparison  with  their  extinct  an- 
cestors; of  these  he  described  a  number  of  new  genera,  Pal^eotherium,  Dino- 
therium,  etc.  Even  the  small  Hyrax  he  removed,  for  anatomical  reasons, 
from  the  rodents,  with  which  it  had  previously  been  associated,  to  the  prox- 
imity of  the  elephants  —  one  of  the  most  daring  applications  of  his  com- 
parative-anatomical method.  The  first  detailed  descriptions  of  the  American 
giant  sloth  likewise  originate  from  him.  He  also  carried  out  some  rather 
sporadic  studies  of  extinct  birds  and  reptiles,  which  are  of  considerable  value. 

Cuvier  as  a  geologist 
These  investigations  into  the  existence  and  relationship  of  extinct  animal 
forms,  however,  brought  Cuvier,  as  they  had  formerly  brought  Buffon,  face 
to  face  with  the  question:  What  changes  have  taken  place  in  the  character 
of  the  earth's  surface  that  have  caused  the  dissimilarity  between  the  animal 


338  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

world  of  the  past  and  that  of  the  present?  He  has  tried  to  give  the  answer 
in  a  survey  of  the  process  of  the  earth's  development  through  the  ages,  which 
forms  the  introduction  to  his  Kecherches  and  which  became  his  best-known 
and  his  most  discussed  work.  Herein,  basing  his  argument  on  material  de- 
rived from  the  finest  observations  of  earlier  times,  supplemented  by  his  own, 
he  seeks  to  prove  that  the  changes  in  the  character  of  the  animal  world  have 
been  caused  by  great  catastrophes  undergone  by  the  earth's  surface  in  pre- 
historic times.  He  at  once  takes  it  for  granted  that  these  changes  had  the 
character  of  violent  catastrophes;  that  they  were  violent  he  considers  to  be 
established  by  the  fact  that  stratifications  which,  judging  from  the  nature 
of  the  fossils,  have  demonstrably  taken  place  in  the  sea,  are  now  found  on 
the  one  hand  elevated  to  enormous  heights  and  on  the  other  hand  over- 
thrown and  inverted.  That  all  this  took  place  with  great  rapidity  is  obvious 
to  his  mind,  not  only  from  the  sharp  lines  of  demarcation  shown  by  the 
various  strata,  but  also  from  the  fact  that  many  of  them  contain  such  extraor- 
dinarily numerous  animal  remains  that  it  can  only  be  assumed  that  they 
died  a  sudden  death  as  the  result  of  upheavals  which  obliterated  all  life  for 
the  time  being.  The  assumption  of  such  catastrophic  changes  on  the  earth's 
surface  also  affords,  in  Cuvier's  opinion,  the  best  explanation  as  to  why  the 
animal  species  of  ancient  times  have  disappeared  and  been  succeeded  by  new 
and  entirely  different  forms.  And  as  a  further  confirmation  of  this  assump- 
tion he  adduces  the  fact  that  most  nations  possess  legends  which  tell  of  a 
mighty  catastrophe,  a  flood  that  drowned  all  living  creatures,  and  in  which 
undoubtedly  the  mammoth  and  the  other  great  land-animals  living  in 
Europe  in  earlier  times  perished. 

His  catastrophe  theory 
It  is  this  universally  known  "catastrophe  theory"  that  without  doubt 
brings  out  both  Cuvier's  strength  and  his  weakness  as  a  natural-scientific 
thinker.  He  does  not,  however,  deserve  any  very  severe  censure  for  the  ac- 
tual theory  of  these  vast  volcanic  upheavals,  with  their  resultant  inunda- 
tions; the  geological  material  available  for  observation  was  still  somewhat 
scanty  and  was,  moreover,  as  far  as  French  research  was  concerned,  largely 
gathered  from  the  Alps,  with  their  greatly  subverted  formations,  which 
even  to  this  day  are  difficult  to  interpret,  and  which  are  peculiarly  likely 
to  induce  a  belief  in  violent  upheavals.  But  there  undoubtedly  existed  in 
Cuvier  a  very  pronounced  tendency  to  pursue  the  theories  he  had  once  set 
up  to  their  uttermost  conclusions  —  a  tendency  which  may  well  be  at- 
tributed to  his  marked  aptitude  for  the  formal  side  of  science.  Thus,  he  ex- 
pressly declares  that  each  stratum  has  its  definite  fossil  species,  which  are 
characteristic  of  it  and  do  not  exist  elsewhere;  the  catastrophes  that  took 
place  entirely  eradicated  all  then  existent  species;  never  has  a  species  sur- 
vived from  one  period  to  the  next,  so  that  species  found  in  the  form  of 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  339 

fossils  cannot  be  the  same  as  those  living  now;  the  fossil  remains  of  lions, 
bears,  elephants,  belong  to  species  other  than  those  at  present  existing; 
fossilized  human  remains  do  not  exist,  the  human  bones  that  have  been 
declared  to  be  such  have  become  mixed  up  with  fossil  finds  by  accident. 
In  this  connexion  he  maintains,  in  opposition  to  Lamarck,  that  the  pe- 
riods of  geological  development  have  not  by  any  means  been  going  on  for 
an  indefinite  time,  but,  on  the  contrary,  during  a  fairly  limited  space  of 
time,  and  that  therefore  the  assumption  that  species  change  through  hab- 
its and  environment  is  unwarranted.  If  change  of  species  were  conceivable, 
it  would  be  possible,  he  thinks,  to  come  across  transitions  between  extinct 
and  now  existing  animal  forms,  but  there  are  none.  The  immutability  of 
species  is  to  Cuvier's  mind  an  absolute  fact;  he  has  not  a  trace  of  Linnasus's 
hesitation,  which  he  expressed  in  his  old  age,  in  face  of  the  difficulty  of 
drawing  a  line  of  demarcation  between  the  species;  according  to  Cuvier's 
definition,  species  consist  of  "those  individuals  that  originate  from  one  an- 
other or  from  common  parents  and  those  which  resemble  them  as  much  as 
one  another."  In  this  definition  no  mention  is  made  of  the  creation  of  the 
species,  which,  it  will  be  remembered,  Linnasus  took  as  his  starting-point, 
but  which,  on  the  whole,  Cuvier  does  not  discuss  at  all.  The  assertion  that 
so  often  occurs  in  literature  that,  in  his  view,  life  has  been  created  anew 
after  each  catastrophe  is  utterly  incorrect;  on  the  contrary,  he  points  out 
that  isolated  parts  of  the  earth  may  have  been  spared  on  each  occasion  when 
it  was  laid  waste,  and  that  living  creatures  have  propagated  their  species 
anew  from  these  oases,  which  indeed  he  expressly  applies  to  the  human  race. 
But  as  a  rule  Cuvier  is  not  particularly  interested  in  what  might  conceivably 
have  happened;  he  adheres  to  what  he  considers  to  be  definitely  proved, 
leaving  hypotheses  to  the  "metaphysician."  Nor  is  it  true,  as  has  also  been 
stated  of  him,  that  he  allowed  religious  beliefs  to  invade  the  realm  of  sci- 
ence; he  certainly  embraced  with  conviction  the  tenets  of  the  Protestant 
Church,  whose  guardian  he  eventually  became,  but  in  his  scientific  argu- 
ments these  doctrines  play  no  part  whatever;  as  a  matter  of  fact  Lamarck 
refers  to  the  Creator  far  more  often  than  Cuvier.  It  is  true  that  the  latter 
cites  the  First  Book  of  Moses  in  support  of  his  flood  theory,  but  Chaldean 
and  Egyptian  documents  are  quoted  at  the  same  time  and  with  exactly  the 
same  authority;  and  to  ascribe  historical  authenticity  to  popular  legends 
was  an  illusion  shared  at  that  time  by  most  professional  historians. 

His  Regne  animal 
In  his  work  Le  Regne  animal,  distribue  apres  son  organisation,  which  was  pub- 
lished in  1817,  Cuvier  develops  his  ideas  further.  In  the  foreword  he  enters 
a  strong  protest  against  those  who  would  arrange  all  living  creatures  in  one 
series  and  declares  that  such  a  method  is  unforgivable.  He  emphatically  de- 
nies that  mammals,  which  come  last  in  the  system,  are  the  lowest,  or  that 


340  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

the  last  mammal  in  the  series  is  more  perfect  than  the  first  bird.  Here  Cuvier 
has  certainly  laid  his  finger  on  one  of  the  weakest  points  of  the  whole  series- 
theory,  as  expounded  by  Bonnet  and  Lamarck,  and  has  undeniably  fore- 
stalled the  conception  of  the  relativity  of  the  degree  of  evolution  as  held  in 
modern  times.  And  as  an  application  of  this  doctrine  of  his  he  presents  his 
famous  type-grouping  system.  According  to  this,  the  animal  kingdom  is  di- 
vided into  four  main  groups,  Vertebrata,  Mollusca,  Articulata,  and  Radiata. 
Within  each  of  these  groups  there  is  a  special  "ground-plan"  for  the  con- 
struction of  the  life-forms  —  a  plan  that  appears  modified  in  various  ways 
in  the  different  systematic  categories  within  the  type.  Thus,  the  animals 
within  the  same  type  may  be  compared  with  one  another,  but  there  is  no 
comparison  between  the  ground-plans  of  the  different  types.  This  type  theory 
is  Cuvier's  greatest  contribution  in  the  sphere  of  systematization  and  repre- 
sents the  farthest  advance  in  animal  classification  since  Linnasus;  in  fact, 
it  represents,  although  in  a  somewhat  modified  form,  the  basis  of  all  sub- 
sequent animal  classification,  and  it  is  thanks  to  it  that  modern  biology  has 
been  able  to  lay  firmer  foundations  for  the  theory  of  descent  than  Lamarck 
succeeded  in  doing  with  his  uniform  evolutional  series.  But  this  is  certainly 
due  to  the  fact  that  in  modern  times  it  has  been  possible  to  compare  ground- 
plan  and  organic  structure  even  in  animals  belonging  to  different  types.  Here 
Cuvier  was  far  too  reluctant,  as  indeed  he  was  in  the  application  of  his  geo- 
logical theory,  to  draw  his  conclusions  from  the  observations  on  which  he 
based  his  system. 

Besides  the  account  of  the  type  theory,  the  work  in  question  also  con- 
tains a  number  of  observations  on  general  scientific  problems,  and  here,  as 
everywhere,  Cuvier  maintains  the  strictly  critical  attitude  which  to  him 
was  one  of  the  essentials  of  life.  He  is  a  master  in  not  giving  utterance  to 
more  than  he  can  stand  for,  and  sometimes  it  is  only  in  a  roundabout  way 
that  one  can  guess  his  train  of  thought.  Thus,  he  repeats  his  above-mentioned 
principle  regarding  life's  quality  of  counteracting  the  manifestations  of  chem- 
ical affinity  in  the  elements  that  form  the  body,  and  he  adds  that  it  would 
be  irrational  to  assume  that  the  force  which  acts  in  that  way  has  a  chemical 
nature.  But  he  enunciates  no  definite  vitalistic  theory.  With  equal  caution 
he  expresses  himself  in  regard  to  fertilization;  how  the  embryo  arises  we 
cannot  tell,  we  can  only  study  its  subsequent  development.  Similarly,  the 
essence  of  the  soul-life  is  a  mystery;  materialism  is  an  arbitrary  hypothesis, 
"so  much  the  more  so  as  philosophy  cannot  offer  any  direct  proof  of  the 
true  existence  of  matter."  Here  Cuvier  has  undoubtedly  learnt  from  Kant; 
on  the  other  hand,  his  analysis  of  the  influence  of  sense-impressions  upon 
the  brain  seems  rather  to  have  been  influenced  by  Condillac  and  his  school. 
However,  the  knowledge  with  which  Cuvier  applies  the  theories  of  the  new 
chemistry    to   zoology  represents  a  remarkable   advance;  in  this  respect 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  34I 

he   has  laid   the  foundations  upon  which  subsequent  research  has  built 
further. 

His  controversy  with  Geoffroy  Saint-Hilaire 
In  the  writings  which  Cuvier  produced  during  the  last  years  of  his  life  there 
stands  out  with  increasing  distinctness  his  clear,  though  narrow,  concep- 
tion of  the  interrelation  of  animal  types.  This  is  especially  conspicuous  in 
his  controversy  with  Geoffroy  Saint-Hilaire,  which  attracted  much  atten- 
tion in  his  own  time  and  has  been  keenly  debated  by  later  generations,  up 
to  the  present  day.  These  two  had  indeed  been  friends  from  youth  and  had 
for  a  long  time  loyally  collaborated.  Gradually,  however,  their  ways  parted. 
Cuvier  insisted  more  and  more  upon  the  truth  of  his  principles  regarding 
the  immutability  of  species  and  the  incomparability  of  types,  while  Geoffroy 
became  more  and  more  deeply  engrossed  in  the  study  of  the  comparison  of 
organs  in  different  animal  forms  and  speculations  inferred  therefrom  upon 
the  question  of  one  uniform  type  of  life.  Cuvier  did  not  like  personal  con- 
troversy; his  objections  to  views  of  which  he  did  not  approve  he  invariably 
made  without  personal  remarks  and  clothed  in  a  sometimes  rather  haughty, 
but  always  courteous,  style.  While,  then,  Geoffroy  for  years  propounded 
his  fantastic  comparisons  between  the  segments  of  the  Articulata  and  the 
vertebra;,  tortoise-shell,  and  mussel-shell,  which  have  been  referred  to  in 
the  foregoing,  Cuvier  never  directly  opposed  these,  to  him,  absurd  ideas, 
but,  on  the  other  hand,  formulated  with  increasing  distinctness  his  own 
theories  and  his  arguments  against  all  that  contradicted  them.  At  last,  how- 
ever, came  the  inevitable  clash,  in  the  year  1830.  Geoffroy  had  submitted 
to  the  Academy  of  Science  a  paper  written  by  two  younger  scientists,  con- 
taining a  detailed  comparison  between  ink-fish  and  vertebrates:  the  ink-fish 
was  regarded  as  a  vertebrate  animal  reflexed  in  the  middle,  with  the  anal 
opening  pressed  on  to  the  head,  possessing  a  diaphragm,  cartilages  corre- 
sponding to  the  cranial  bones,  and  in  general  most  of  the  organs  peculiar 
to  a  vertebrate  animal.  The  essay  contained  a  direct  attack  on  Cuvier, 
though  this  passage  was  struck  out  when  sent  to  the  press;  but  it  was  read 
before  the  Academy,  and  therefore  called  for  a  reply.  This  produced  from 
Cuvier  a  courteous  but  sharp  criticism  dealing  with  the  whole  of  Geoffroy's 
natural-scientific  speculation;  by  illustrating  side  by  side  the  organs  of  an 
ink-fish  and  of  a  vertebrate  animal  in  the  reflexed  position,  which  it  had  been 
claimed  constituted  the  likeness  between  them,  he  demonstrated  the  funda- 
mental difference  between  the  organs  common  to  both,  both  in  structural 
detail  and  position,  showing,  moreover,  that  many  organs  existing  in  the 
one  form  do  not  occur  at  all  in  the  other.  But,  besides  this,  Cuvier  rejected 
the  entire  fundamental  principle  on  which  Geoffroy  based  his  research,  at  the 
same  time  emphasizing  the  latter's  brilliant  services  as  an  exponent  of 
the  comparative  anatomy  of  vertebrates.  He  made  special  reference  to  the 


342-  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

similarities  between  bones  of  different  vertebrates  during  the  embryonic  stage 
that  GeofFroy  had  established,  maintaining  that  the  method  employed  in 
Geoffrey's  investigations  was  by  no  means  new,  but  originated  in  Aristotle, 
and  that  Geoffroy's  talk  of  a  uniform  plan  for  the  structure  of  the  entire 
animal  kingdom  was  mere  empty  words  without  any  real  meaning  and  with- 
out any  equivalent  in  nature.  This  reply  greatly  offended  Geoffroy,  where- 
upon there  started  one  of  those  long-drawn-out  controversies  so  common 
in  scientific  history,  when  two  persons  of  utterly  different  temperament  fall 
foul  of  one  another,  and  when  the  longer  it  lasts,  the  more  unprofitable  it 
becomes.  Strikingly  enough,  Geoffroy  at  once  desisted  from  maintaining  the 
comparison  between  ink-fish  and  vertebrates;  instead,  he  transferred  the 
whole  discussion  to  the  sphere  of  the  vertebrates.  Similarly,  he  replaced 
the  expression  '' unite  de  plan,"  to  which  Cuvier  had  objected,  by  the  phrase 
" tbeorie  des  analogues,"  but  at  the  same  time  emphatically  declared  that  this 
theory  was  entirely  new;  for  while  the  old  comparative  anatomy  concerned 
itself  merely  with  the  form  and  function  of  an  organ,  the  new  theory  took 
for  comparison  all  the  parts  of  which  an  organ  was  composed.  As  an  in- 
stance of  this  he  cited  the  hyoid  bone  in  mammals,  which  he  found  to  be 
composed  of  different  parts  in  different  animals,  and  also  the  opercular  bones 
in  fishes.  Here  Geoffroy  was  clearly  referring  to  what  we  nowadays  call 
homology  —  the  likeness  that  exists  in  the  evolutional  history  of  certain 
organs,  which  warrants  comparison  in  a  manner  different  from  what  the 
mere  functions  of  these  organs  would  justify.  But  unfortunately  he  was  too 
vague  in  his  speculations  to  be  able  to  give  them  plausible  form;  in  the  sub- 
sequent discussions  before  the  Academy,  Cuvier  pointed  out  a  great  number 
of  errors  of  detail  even  in  Geoffroy's  comparisons  of  the  hyoid  bones  in  the 
vertebrates,  not  to  mention  his  idea  that  this  bone  occurred  in  crayfish.  Fur- 
ther Geoffroy  had  a  weakness  for  general  philosophical  speculation  that  must 
have  seemed  utterly  absurd  to  his  sober-minded  opponent.  In  the  introduc- 
tion to  a  book  in  which  he  collected  his  contributions  to  the  discussion, 
there  occurs  the  following  passage,  which,  like  Schelling's,  must  be  quoted 
in  the  original:  Pour  cet  ordre  des  considerations  il  n  est  plus  d' animaux  divers. 
Un  seul  fait  les  domine,  c  est  comme  un  seul  etre  qui  apparait.  11  est,  il  reside 
dans  V Animalite;  etre  ahstrait,  qui  est  tangible  par  nos  sens  sous  des  figures 
diver ses."  Such  an  expression  of  views  was  quite  in  Goethe's  style  —  he, 
too,  as  is  well  known,  took  part  in  the  dispute  as  a  warm  supporter  of 
Geoffroy;  he  considered  that  the  latter's  cause  was  the  cause  of  natural  phi- 
losophy itself,  and  in  this  he  was  certainly  right.  For  if  there  existed  in 
Geoffroy's  speculations  advanced  ideas  of  the  greatest  value  even  for  modern 
comparative  anatomy,  they  were  nevertheless  an  expression  for  that  same 
romantic  natural  philosophy,  that  same  striving  after  an  ideal  unity  in  exist- 
ence, which  was  then  prevalent  in  Germany  and  which,  in  fact,  GeofFroy 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  343 

persistently  claimed  in  his  favour.  Cuvier,  on  the  other  hand,  displaying 
his  somewhat  narrow  range  of  vision,  claimed  the  object  of  science  to  be 
an  exact  knowledge  of  natural  phenomena.  It  is  not  worth  while  following 
the  discussion  between  these  two  any  further;  it  developed  into  a  repetition 
of  old  arguments  and  a  more  and  more  stubborn  adherence  to  statements 
once  uttered. 

The  results  of  the  dispute 
Nevertheless,  one  more  point  in  connexion  with  this  dispute  must  be  noted. 
Among  the  assertions  that  Cuvier  made  and  that  Geoffroy  at  the  very  out- 
set quotes  with  disapprobation,  there  is  one  which  deserves  attention,  not 
only  because  it  shows  up  Cuvier's  limitations,  but  mainly  because  it  em- 
phasizes the  contrast  between  the  origin-of-species  theories  of  earlier  times 
and  that  of  our  own  day.  Cuvier  says  of  the  ink-fish:  "They  have  not  resulted 
from  the  development  of  other  animals,  nor  has  their  own  development 
produced  any  animal  higher  than  themselves."  In  face  of  the  modern  theory 
of  evolution  the  former  of  these  statements  is  undoubtedly  untrue,  whereas 
the  latter  is  correct.  To  Lamarck  and  Geoffroy  both  statements  were  equally 
untrue  and  they  became  even  more  excited  over  the  latter  than  over  the  for- 
mer. For  what  they  were  particularly  in  search  of  was  just  that  connecting 
link  between  the  highest  form  in  each  class  and  the  lowest  type  in  the  next 
one  —  ink-fish  and  fishes,  tortoises  and  birds,  to  name  two  examples.  On  this 
rock  the  earlier  theories  of  origin  regularly  suffered  shipwreck.  The  fact  that 
the  modern  historian  of  evolution  has  learnt  instead  to  search  backwards  in 
the  evolutional  series,  in  order  to  find  among  more  primitive  forms  primary 
types  for  the  separate,  highly  specialized  groups,  has  been  rendered  possible 
owing  to  modern  zoology's  having  accepted  Cuvier's  type  theory,  which 
avoids  direct  comparison  between  highly  developed  life-forms  of  different 
types  —  but  thanks  also  to  embryology,  which  Geoffroy  endeavoured,  though 
without  success,  to  make  the  basis  of  his  theory  of  comparison  between 
organs  of  the  same  kind  in  different  animal  forms.  It  happens  then,  that  both 
the  parties  to  the  dispute  of  1830  have  contributed  to  the  creation  of  the 
modern  view  of  natural  evolution. 


CHAPTER    III 

BICHAT     AND     HIS     TISSUE     THEORY 

IN  THE  IMMEDIATELY  PRECEDING  SECTION  of  this  worlc  One  chapter  (chap- 
ter v)  was  devoted  to  giving  an  account  of  the  two  mutually  opposed 
ideas  as  to  the  nature  of  life  that  were  prevalent  during  the  early  part  of 
the  eighteenth  century:  the  mechanistic,  which  conceived  the  phenomena  of 
life  from  the  purely  mechanical  point  of  view,  and  the  vitalistic,  which,  rep- 
resented by  Stahl  and  his  pupils,  saw  in  the  soul  the  real  entity  of  life  and 
regarded  the  body  as  existing  for  and  through  the  soul.  Curiously  enough, 
Stahl's  doctrine,  the  most  markedly  vitalistic  of  them  all,  won  support 
particularly  in  France,  where  it  was  preserved  and  further  developed  by  the 
medical  faculty  at  Montpellier.  It  was  especially  Stahl's  idea  of  the  complex 
chemical  composition  of  the  body  and  the  easy  decomposability  of  its  constit- 
uent parts,  and  the  peculiar  structure  of  them  characteristic  of  different 
beings,  that  was  developed  by  the  Montpellier  school.  On  the  other  hand, 
these  scientists  paid  less  attention  to  Stahl's  speculations  on  the  soul  itself; 
rather,  it  was  life,  the  life-force,  that  was  believed  to  be  the  binding  force 
that  prevents  the  chemical  components  of  the  body  from  disintegrating.  We 
have  seen  Stahl's  theory  recur  in  this  form  both  in  Humboldt  and  in  Cuvier. 
In  actual  fact  the  sharp  distinction  between  mechanism  and  vitalism  was  to 
a  certain  extent  removed  towards  the  close  of  the  eighteenth  century;  the 
progress  of  chemistry  made  it  necessary  to  consider  other  functions  in  the 
body  besides  the  purely  motive  phenomena  — ■  a  fact  that  even  the  most  con- 
vinced mechanists  eventually  had  to  realize;  while,  on  the  other  hand,  a 
number  of  active  natural  forces  were  discovered  —  primarily  the  electric  and 
the  magnetic  —  of  which  earlier  ages  knew  nothing  and  in  face  of  which  bi- 
ology —  whether  vitalistic  or  mechanistic  —  was  bound  to  adopt  a  definite 
attitude.  As  examples  of  the  influence  of  these  new  discoveries  may  be  men- 
tioned, on  one  hand,  Galvani's  experiments  with  electrical  phenomena  in 
the  organism,  which  were  continued  by  Humboldt  and  others,  and  on  the 
other  Mesmer's  investigations  into  "animal  magnetism,"  or  what  we  should 
nowadays  call  hypnotic  phenomena.  As  a  result  of  all  these  complications, 
that  age's  conception  of  life-phenomena  became  a  mere  groping  in  the  dark;  it 
was  only  after  the  discovery  of  the  law  of  the  indestructibility  of  energy  that 
biology  also  gained  a  fresh  basis  on  which  to  build,  as  a  result  of  which  it 
became  possible  to  form  a  fresh  mechanical  conception  of  life-phenomena. 

344 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  345 

Among  the  scientists  of  the  MontpeJlier  school  who  disputed  the  pre- 
vailing mechanistic  theory  of  life,  which  was  maintained  chiefly  on  the 
authority  of  Boerhaave,  may  be  mentioned  Theopiiile  de  Bordeu  (1711-76). 
The  son  of  a  doctor  living  in  the  south  of  France,  he  settled  down  in  practice, 
after  taking  his  degree,  first  in  his  home  district  and  later  in  Paris.  He  wrote 
an  account  of  his  views  on  life-phenomena  in  a  work  entitled  On  the  Glands. 
Contemporary  physiologists  of  the  mechanistic  school  of  thought  believed 
that  glandular  secretion  was  due  simply  to  the  mechanical  pressure  of  adjacent 
muscles.  Through  a  series  of  careful  experiments  and  extensive  investigations 
based  thereon,  Bordeu  proves  that  mechanical  compression  cannot  produce 
glandular  secretion.  This  is  due  rather  to  the  direct  influence  of  the  nerves 
leading  to  the  glands.  Through  this  nervous  influence  the  supply  of  blood 
to  the  gland  is  increased  and  by  means  of  a  purely  mechanical  arrangement  — 
Bordeu  believes  that  he  found  openings  capable  of  expanding  or  closing 
through  the  influence  of  the  nerves  —  the  follicles  of  that  gland  absorb  out 
of  the  blood  such  fluids  as  are  characteristic  of  the  secretion.  This  individual 
power  of  the  gland  to  absorb  fluids  that  are  suitable  to  it  Bordeu  names 
"sensation"  and  he  ascribes  to  each  organ  in  the  body  a  special  power  of  self- 
operation,  a  "tact,"  as  he  calls  it;  the  stomach  absorbs  certain  substances, 
and  reacts  against  others  by  the  process  of  vomiting;  the  eye  has  its  special 
reaction  against  the  outside  world,  and  likewise  the  ear.  Life  proceeds  as 
the  result  of  co-operation  between  the  individual  action  of  all  the  organs. 
The  brain  and  the  nervous  system  control  this  co-operation;  their  action  is 
expressed  in  the  alternate  contraction  and  expansion  of  their  mass.  Although 
Bordeu  evinces  great  admiration  for  Stahl,  it  is  nevertheless  with  extreme 
caution  that  he  expresses  any  opinion  on  the  question  of  the  soul's  relation 
to  the  body,  just  as  in  general  he  avoids  entering  into  more  abstract  regions 
of  thought. 

We  find,  on  the  other  hand,  speculations  of  a  markedly  natural-philo- 
sophical character  in  a  somewhat  later  pupil  of  the  Montpellier  school,  Paul 
Joseph  Barthez  (1734-1806).  Hewas  first  of  all  a  practitioner,  then  professor 
at  Montpellier,  and  finally  chancellor  of  its  university.  Being  of  a  pugnacious 
and  irascible  nature,  he  became  involved  in  many  a  dispute,  especially  after 
he  had  taken  sides  with  the  aristocracy  during  the  Revolution.  Having  been 
deprived  of  his  post,  he  lived  for  a  time  as  a  private  individual.  He  published 
his  theoretical  opinions  in  a  work  bearing  the  striking  title  of  Science  de 
Vhomme.  By  way  of  introduction  hj  gives  an  analysis  of  causality,  which  he 
afterwards  examines  with  special  reference  to  the  cause  of  life.  Barthez  finds 
the  ultimate  cause  of  life  to  be  inexplicable  and  considers  that  neither 
Boerhaave' s  nor  Stahl 's  theories  are  satisfactory  hypotheses  or  of  any  use 
to  medical  science;  in  their  place  he  assumes  a  special  "life-principle"  as  the 
foundation  for  the  vital  manifestations  of  all  living  creatures.  In  man  this 


346  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

principle  does  not  coincide  with  the  conscious  psychical  life;  it  is  rather  a 
kind  of  general  force,  which  contains  within  itself  irritability,  sensibility,  and 
the  other  vital  phenomena  described  by  physiologists  of  that  period.  This 
speculative  tendency,  it  appears,  follows  a  line  of  thought  exactly  opposed  to 
that  which  Bordeu  pursued;  he  tried  to  regard  the  vital  manifestations  of  the 
different  organs  as  isolated  phenomena,  while  Barthez  sought  above  all  for 
one  common  principle  that  would  hold  good  for  all  manifestations  of  life. 

These  and  other  members  of  the  Montpellier  school  during  the  eighteenth 
century  would,  however,  scarcely  deserve  mention  beyond  the  borders  of 
France  had  not  their  work  formed  the  basis  on  which  Bichat  built  further. 
Marie  pRANgois  Xavier  Bichat  was  born  in  1771  at  Jura,  in  eastern  France. 
His  father  was  a  doctor  of  repute,  and  the  son  was  from  early  youth  destined 
for  the  same  profession;  after  finishing  school  he  studied  surgery  at  a  hospital 
at  Lyons,  but  when  that  city  was  destroyed  during  the  wars  of  the  Revolu- 
tion, he  betook  himself  to  Paris.  There  he  found  a  patron  in  the  surgeon 
Desault,  with  whom  he  worked  both  as  a  surgeon  and  as  an  anatomist.  After 
the  death  of  his  benefactor,  in  1795,  he  spent  a  couple  of  years  editing  his 
writings;  in  return  he  found  in  Desault 's  widow  a  maternal  friend  and  a 
practical  adviser.  Bichat  displayed  throughout  his  short  life  an  enthusiasm 
for  science  that  has  hardly  ever  been  equalled;  although  he  lived  through  the 
most  exciting  events  of  the  French  Revolution  that  occurred  in  his  immediate 
neighbourhood,  he  was  nevertheless  able  to  devote  himself  entirely  to  his 
anatomical  works.  He  spent  his  days  and  quite  often  his  nights  in  the  ana- 
tomical theatre,  in  order  not  to  waste  time.  Nor  did  he  care  much  about 
promotion;  in  1797,  however,  he  began  to  give  lectures  and  four  years  later 
was  appointed  to  a  professorial  chair,  without  having  applied  for  it.  More- 
over, he  carried  on  very  intensive  work  as  an  author  and  took  part  whole- 
heartedly in  the  life  of  the  medical  faculty.  In  the  spring  of  i8oi,  however, 
he  was  attacked  by  a  malignant  fever  —  whether  as  a  result  of  septic  poison- 
ing or  whether  owing  to  some  other  infection  is  apparently  not  known  — 
and  he  died  in  spite  of  the  utmost  care  of  his  friends  and  colleagues;  at  the 
time  of  his  death  he  had  not  yet  reached  his  thirty-first  year. 

Bichat' s  character  is  described  by  his  contemporaries  as  mild,  modest, 
and  unselfish.  His  writings  testify  to  a  general  knowledge  that  was  surpris- 
ingly extensive  for  such  a  young  and  extremely  busy  man,  and  yet  his  is  the 
work  by  no  means  of  an  unpractical  bookworm,  but  of  one  who  took  a  deep 
interest  in  life  and  also  observed  a  great  deal  in  his  fellow  men.  His  works 
were  written  during  the  last  four  years  of  his  life;  in  the  early  maturity  of 
his  creative  powers  he  resembled  Linnreus,  as  also  in  the  fact  that  his  genius 
was  primarily  formal  and  systematic.  Bichat  has  introduced  a  new  system 
into  the  science  of  anatomy  and  it  is  in  this  fact  that  his  chief  greatness  lies. 

In  his  writings  Bichat  shows  himself  above  all  a  medical  man;  the  func- 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  347 

tions  of  the  body  are  invariably  described  in  close  relation  to  its  morbid 
changes  and  to  the  manner  in  which  they  should  be  treated.  Pathological 
anatomy  engages  his  interest  quite  as  much  as  normal  anatomy,  and  post- 
mortem examinations  formed  a  considerable  part  of  his  practical  work.  He 
studied  the  various  parts  of  the  body  in  both  its  healthy  and  its  diseased 
state,  employing  a  number  of  different  methods  for  the  purpose;  besides 
dissection  he  mentions  drying,  cooking,  and  maceration,  as  well  as  treat- 
ment with  acids,  alkalis,  and  alcohol.  On  the  other  hand,  he  did  not  use  a 
microscope,  for  he  thought  that  this  only  gave  rise  to  fallacies  and  delusions. 
And  yet  it  is  as  the  founder  of  a  science  of  microscopy  that  he  won  his  highest 
fame.  Another  peculiar  fact  about  him  was  that  he  despised  the  illustration 
as  a  means  of  reproducing  the  results  of  research;  in  his  view,  all  represen- 
tations, even  plastic,  illustrate  only  in  an  imperfect  and  misleading  manner 
the  facts  which  the  research-worker  wishes  to  convey.  His  writings  do  not 
contain  a  single  illustration. 

Bichat' s  conception  of  life 
Bichat's  conception  of  life  has  always  been  regarded  as  vitalistic.  Indeed,  his 
theoretical  fundamental  view  is  unquestionably  reminiscent  of  Stahl;  life, 
says  he,  is  "the  sum  of  the  functions  that  resist  death."  It  is  a  far  cry,  how- 
ever, between  Bichat's  so-called  vitalism  and  Stahl's;  the  latter's  theory  of 
the  soul  as  the  ultimate  end  and  conservator  of  the  body  Bichat  strongly 
denies.  Stahl,  he  declares,  had  realized  the  incompatibility  between  physical 
laws  and  animal  functions,  but  because  the  soul  was  everything  to  him  in 
explaining  the  functions  of  life,  he  failed  to  discover  the  laws  of  life.  With 
equal  emphasis,  however,  Bichat  rejects  Boerhaave's  theory  that  life  should 
be  regarded  as  a  purely  mechanical  process.  "The  true  essence  of  life  is  un- 
known; it  can  only  be  studied  through  the  phenomena  it  manifests";  and 
among  these  phenomena  the  most  conspicuous  is  that  previously  men- 
tioned —  that  it  resists  the  influence  of  those  forces  which  strive  to  disinte- 
grate the  body  and  which  achieve  their  object  as  soon  as  life  has  departed.^ 
As  is  well  known,  Stahl  laid  special  stress  upon  the  complexity  of  the  body's 
chemical  composition  and  its  consequent  easydecomposability  as  being  some- 
thing essential  to  life;  this  truth  was  appreciated  by  Bichat  more  than  by 
any  of  his  predecessors  and  was  further  developed  on  the  basis  of  the  epoch- 
making  discoveries  in  chemistry  in  his  own  age.  The  primary  lesson  he  learnt 
from  Stahl,  however,  is  the  importance  that  different  structural  conditions 
have  for  the  functions  of  the  organism;  in  fact,  the  theory  of  structure  repre- 
sents Bichat's  greatest  contribution  to  the  development  of  biology;  it  forms 
one  of  the  corner-stones  on  which  our  conception  of  life  and  its  manifes- 
tations rests. 

^  This  definition  recalls  Humboldc's  early  ideas  referred  co  above  and  may  certainly  be 
derived  from  the  same  source. 


348  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

His  classification  of  tissues 
According  to  Bichat's  classification,  the  body  is  built  up  of  tissues,  which 
may  be  grouped  in  systems  —  for  example,  the  bone  system,  the  cartilage 
system,  the  muscle  system.  An  organ  is  composed  of  several  systems  (e.g.,  the 
stomach,  the  lungs,  the  brain);  several  organs  form  an  apparatus  (e.g.,  the 
respiratory  apparatus,  the  digestive  apparatus).  The  knowledge  of  the  tissue 
systems  forms  what  Bichat  calls  "general  anatomy,"  which  he  discusses  in 
an  important  work;-  upon  this  knowledge  should  be  based  the  theory  of 
organs  or,  as  he  calls  it,  descriptive  anatomy.  Bichat  claims  that  this  method 
of  research  and  investigation  is  new,  for,  as  he  adds  with  justifiable  self- 
appreciation,  general  anatomy  hardly  existed  before  he  produced  his  works 
on  the  subject. 

The  tissues,  Bichat  declares,  are  the  true  conservators  of  the  life  of  the 
body.  He  distinguishes  between  twenty-one  diff^erent  kinds  of  tissues  — ■ 
namely,  (i)  cellular  (closely  corresponding  to  what  is  now  called  retiform 
connective  tissue);  (z)  the  nervous  tissue  of  animal  life;  (3)  the  nervous 
tissue  of  organic  life;  (4)  arterial;  (5)  venous;  (6)  the  tissue  of  exhalation; 
(7)  absorbent;  (8)  bone-tissue;  (9)  medullary  tissue  (in  the  bones);  (10) 
cartilaginous;  (11)  fibrous;  (li)  fibrocartilaginous;  (13)  animal  musculature; 
(14)  organic  musculature;  (15)  mucous  tissue;  (16)  serous;  (17)  synovial; 
(18)  glandular;  (19)  dermoid;  (xo)  epidermoid  (dermis  and  epidermis); 
(21)  capillary  tissue.  These  tissues,  however,  are  by  no  means  alike  every- 
where; rather,  they  invariably  possess  the  power  to  adapt  themselves  to  the 
organs  in  which  they  are  incorporated.  The  tissues  are  the  true  conservators 
of  life;  not  each  individual  organ,  as  Bordeu  asserted,  but  each  individual  tis- 
sue has  individual  life.  Therefore  diseases,  in  so  far  as  they  attack  individual 
organs,  are  localized  in  their  tissues;  in  abdominal  catarrh  it  is  the  mucous 
membrane  that  is  affected  and  not  the  m.uscles  in  the  abdominal  wall;  in 
inflammation  in  the  brain  it  is  in  most  cases  the  cerebral  membrane  that  is 
the  seat  of  the  disease.  "If  we  would  study  a  bodily  function,  we  must  con- 
sider the  organ  which  performs  that  function  from  a  general  point  of  view, 
but  if  we  would  become  acquainted  with  the  vital  qualities  of  the  organ,  we 
must  disintegrate  it"  —  that  is,  into  the  tissues  of  which  it  is  formed.  The 
tissues  are  thus  the  vehicles  of  life;  in  maintaining  this  view  Bichat  definitely 
dissociates  himself  from  a  number  of  earlier  and  contemporary  scientists, 
who  considered  the  fluids  to  be  the  true  vital  elements  of  the  body.^  But  the 
vital  qualities  are  not  identical  with  the  actual  structure,  for  this  still 
remains  after  life  has  departed;  not  even  the  fluids  of  the  body  are  the  same 
after  death,  and  if  we  analyse  them  chemically  we  find  only  an  equivalent 

^  The  Traiti  des  membranes,  cited  in  the  bibliography,  may  be  regarded  as  a  preliminary 
study  to  this  work. 

'  See,  for  instance,  Sommerring's  above-mentioned  theory  on  the  cerebral  fluids. 


MODERN      BIOLOGY  349 

to  the  anatomical  nature  of  the  dead  body.  Life  consists  rather  in  certain 
qualities,  which  the  living  tissues  possess  and  which  are  not  found  in  inani- 
mate nature.   Here  Bichat  takes  as  his  starting-point  Haller's  previously- 
mentioned  theories  of  irritability  and  sensibility  and  he  develops  them 
further,  expressing  great  appreciation  of  Haller,  who,  to  his  mind,  had  a 
far  more  correct  view  of  life  than  Stahl.  According  to  Bichat,  sensibility 
is  the  characteristic  quality  of  the  nervous  system;  the  muscular  system  dis- 
plays a  quality  that  he  calls  contractility;  this  has  different  characteristics 
in  different  organs  and  should  not  be  confused  with  the  tensibility  that  the 
tissues  possess  independently  of  life.  But  life  manifests  itself  not  only  in  these 
qualities,  but  in  still  another  phenomenon,  unknown  in  inanimate  nature; 
this  is  called  sympathy  and  expresses  itself  in  the  effect  that  the  vital  func- 
tions of  the  various  organs  have  upon  one  another  in  conditions  of  sickness 
and  health.  Bichat  made  serious  attempts  to  ascertain  the  nature  of  these 
vital  phenomena  by  experimenting  with  living  organs  under  various  con- 
ditions. Thus  he  tried  to  analyse  especially  muscular  contractility  and  dis- 
tinguishes several  categories  thereof  —  namely,  he  holds  that  the  muscle 
comes  into  action:  (i)  as  the  result  of  impulses  from  the  brain  received 
through  the  nerves  —  that  is,  normal  contractility;  it  ceases  if  the  nerve  is 
severed;  (i)  through  chemical  or  physical  influences  —  that  is,  organic  and 
sensible  contractility  or  irritability;  it  ceases  if  the  muscle  is  deadened  (e.g., 
by  opium);  (3)  through  the  fluids  which  the  vascular  systems  convey  to  the 
muscle  and  which  distend  its  minutest  parts  —  that  is,  passive  contractility 
or  tonicity;  it  ceases  as  a  result  of  death;  (4)  finally,  the  muscle  contracts  on 
being  severed  —  that  is,  the  contractility  of  tissue  itself,  which  only  ceases 
as  a  result  of  putrefaction.  Of  sensibility  he  distinguishes  two  categories  — 
namely,  "organic,"  which  consists  in  the  power  of  receiving  an  impression, 
and   "animal,"  which  not  only  receives  the  impression,   but  conveys  it 
farther  to  a  common  centre  and  is  thus  a  higher  category  of  the  previous  one. 

Organic  and  anbnal  life 
The  contrasted  ideas,  organic  and  animal,  frequently  referred  to  above,  play 
an  important  part  in  Bichat's  explanation  of  life.  "Organic"  are  vegetable  life 
and  the  unconscious  life  of  animals;  "animal"  are  the  functions  in  animals 
that  are  controlled  by  the  will  of  the  individual  and  are  consequently  the 
more  developed  the  higher  the  life  is.  Even  in  modern  times  one  sometimes 
differentiates  between  animal  organs,  among  which  are  included  especially 
the  nervous  system  and  the  motive  organs,  and  the  vegetative,  among  which 
are  included  the  digestive,  circulatory,  respiratory,  and  excretal  organs. 
Bichat,  however,  carries  this  differentiation  to  most  absurd  extremes  when 
he  consistently  speaks  of  "the  two  lives,"  the  animal  and  the  organic,  and 
assures  us  that  the  former's  organs  are  always  symmetrical  and  the  latter's 
unsymmetrical,  much  labour  being  spent  on  trying  to  prove  that  lungs  and 


350  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

kidneys  are  in  reality  unpaired.  Similarly,  he  endeavours  to  show  that  the 
animal  functions  are  always  "harmonious,"  while  the  organic  are  "dis- 
cordant," by  which  is  meant  that  it  makes  no  difference  if  one  lung  functions 
more  or  less  than  the  other,  whereas  dissimilarity  in  the  visual  or  auditory 
organs  causes  serious  disturbances;  the  lack  of  a  gift  for  music  Bichat  con- 
siders to  be  due  to  the  fact  that  the  ears  possess  different  powers  of  hearing. 
He  does  not  include  the  sexual  organs  in  either  category,  because  they  serve 
the  genus  and  not  the  individual.  Of  the  psychical  qualities,  the  intelligence 
belongs  to  animal  life,  while  the  passions  are  derived  from  organic  life,  from 
disturbances  in  the  digestion  and  the  blood-circulation.  The  community  is 
thus  only  a  development  of  animal  life,  while  the  passions  have  brought  about 
all  human  disasters  —  revolutions  and  reigns  of  terror.  In  all  this  Bichat 
shows  an  inclination  for  sophistry,  which  not  infrequently  accompanies  a 
highly  developed  genius  for  the  purely  formal.  Several  others  of  his  sys- 
tematic divisions  are  also  by  no  means  wholly  successful.  At  all  events,  if 
only  for  the  new  system  that  he  introduced  into  anatomical  science,  Bichat 
must  be  counted  as  one  of  the  greatest  pioneers  of  that  science  that  have  ever 
lived.  Considerations  of  space  forbid  a  more  detailed  account  of  his  thorough 
exposition  of  the  different  tissue  systems  which  he  gives  in  his  general  anat- 
omy, as  also  of  his  application  of  it  to  the  theory  of  organs  in  his  descrip- 
tive anatomy.  His  work  contains  no  histology  in  the  modern  sense,  but  this 
is  only  natural,  as  he  refuses  to  learn  from  microscopical  observation;  on 
the  contrary,  he  dismisses  with  some  compassion  Leeuwenhoek's  attempts  at 
determining  the  form  and  size  of  muscular  fibrillar;  the  true  nature  of  muscu- 
lar fibre  is  unknown,  and  that  is  all  there  is  to  be  said  about  it.  He  is  far 
more  interested  in  the  chemical  composition  of  the  tissues,  as  far  as  it  was 
possible  to  ascertain  it  in  those  days,  and  in  their  condition  under  processes 
of  drying  and  maceration.  It  is  at  any  rate  the  topography  of  the  tissues  that 
chiefly  engages  his  attention;  their  finer  quality  did  not  concern  him;  for 
instance,  Malpighi  certainly  knew  more  about  the  structure  of  the  brain 
than  he  did.  Bichat 's  greatness,  then,  lies  in  his  having  so  convincingly 
proved  the  quality  of  the  tissues  as  fundamental  constituents  of  the  body  and 
its  functions.  He  thereby  placed  the  study  of  the  phenomena  of  life  on  a  defi- 
nite basis,  the  value  of  which  is  best  realized  if  we  compare  his  tissue  theory 
with  the  fantastic  ideas  of  a  "nervous  fluid"  and  "microscopical  life-units," 
in  which  the  works  of  even  the  most  brilliant  biologists  of  the  imme- 
diately preceding  epoch  abound.  Even  the  terms  "sensibility"  and  "con- 
tractility," which  were  invented  by  him,  have  been  incorporated  in  modern 
terminology.  And  although  his  ideas  of  the  application  of  physics  and  chem- 
istry to  biology  must  appear  primitive  to  a  modern  reader,  still,  he  had  the 
eye  of  a  genius  for  essentials  in  the  contrast  between  animate  and  inanimate 
matter,  which  many  a  modern  biologist  has  lacked.  That  he  so  strongly 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  35I 

maintained  this  difference  was  certainly  well  justified  as  a  reaction  against 
those  clumsy  mechanical  theories  of  life  which  were  then  being  propounded 
by  Lamarck  and  others.  Nor  indeed  can  it  be  said  that  Bichat  prostituted  his 
contractility  idea  to  metaphysical  or  mystical  speculations.  His  mind  was, 
in  fact,  trained  through  studying  the  sceptical  philosophers  of  the  eighteenth 
century  —  he  quotes  both  Condillac  and  Cabanis  —  and  their  criticism 
formed  a  sound  counterbalance  to  the  bold  ideas  which  he  learnt  from  Stahl 
and  his  school.  Bichat  knew  to  a  fair  degree  how  to  retain  the  best  of  what 
he  learnt  from  his  predecessors  and  how  to  establish  on  the  basis  of  the 
knowledge  thus  gained  a  consummate  field  of  research  of  his  own. 


CHAPTER    IV 

cuvier's    younger    contemporaries 

THE  FIRST  HALF  of  the  eighteenth  century  shows  in  general  a  lively  de- 
velopment in  the  sphere  of  biology.  The  splendid  progress  made 
simultaneously  in  physics  and  chemistry  created  innumerable  fresh 
problems  also  in  the  biological  sciences;  voyages  of  geographical  explora- 
tion, which  were  made  to  hitherto  unknown  lands  on  the  precedent  of 
Humboldt,  resulted  in  new  material  for  investigation,  which  broadened 
existing  ideas  and  broke  down  old  systematical  barriers  — ■  we  need  only 
mention  such  animals  as  the  duck-billed  platypus  and  the  lung-fish  in  order 
to  show  clearly  the  importance  of  these  discoveries  — •  and,  finally,  the  vast 
technical  and  economic  progress  of  that  epoch  awakened  an  interest  in  the 
study  of  nature,  which  also  proved  of  benefit  to  biology.  Among  the  techni- 
cal inventions  that  belong  to  this  period  may  first  of  all  be  mentioned  the 
improvement  in  the  construction  of  the  microscope,  which  alone  has  given 
mankind  a  knowledge  of  a  whole  series  of  hitherto  unknown  life-forms;  the 
economic  progress,  again,  rendered  possible  the  instituting  of  collections 
such  as  earlier  times  had  never  dreamt  of,  as  well  as  the  carrying  out  of  costly 
experiments  on  a  large  scale.  As  a  result  of  all  these  circumstances,  of  which 
many  keen  scientists  took  full  advantage,  biology  achieved  more  and  more 
brilliant  results  as  the  years  went  by,  with  the  consequent  enhancement  of 
its  general  cultural  reputation  —  in  spite  of  the  indignant  protests  and  the 
scornful  rejection  of  the  idealistic  philosophers. 

Progress  of  comparative  anatomy 
One  branch  of  biological  research  which,  more  than  any  other,  made  rapid 
strides  during  the  period  under  discussion  was  that  of  descriptive  and  com- 
parative anatomy.  Cuvier,  its  most  brilliant  precursor,  had  many  pupils  in 
different  countries,  both  direct  and  indirect,  who  carried  on  the  numerous 
ideas  he  brought  out,  and  besides  these  there  were  many  others  whose  re- 
search work  resulted  in  valuable  contributions  towards  the  progress  of 
science.  A  number  of  the  most  representative  of  these  scientists  will  be  dealt 
with  in  the  present  chapter. 

Carl  Asmund  Rudolphi  was  born  in  1771  in  Stockholm,  of  German 
parents.  He  studied  medicine  at  Greifswald,  at  the  German  university  of 
Swedish  Pomerania,  becoming  professor  in  anatomy  first  there  and  afterwards 
in  Berlin,  where  he  worked  until  his  death,  in  1831.  He  founded  the  Berlin 

352- 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  353 

zoological  museum,  now  one  of  the  finest  in  the  world,  and  did  much  ex- 
tremely successful  educational  work;  he  was  highly  esteemed  by  pupils  and 
friends  on  account  of  his  zeal  for  science  and  his  noble,  almost  supersensitive 
temperament.  He  could  never  get  himself  to  perform  vivisections  and  once 
declared  that  even  the  prospect  of  world-wide  fame  would  not  induce  him  to 
possess  the  insensitiveness  of  a  Brunner.'  At  the  same  time  he  was  severely 
critical  towards  others  as  well  as  towards  himself  and  laboured  hard  for 
the  abolition  of  the  mysticism  that  natural  philosophy  had  introduced  into 
biology,  so  that  his  writings,  in  spite  of  a  number  of  inaccuracies,  give  on 
the  whole  an  impression  of  solid  reality  and  of  being  far  more  modern  than 
those  of  many  of  his  famous  contemporaries. 

Ktidolphf  s  work  on  -parasites 
It  is  in  three  particular  branches  of  biology  that  Rudolphi  has  made  valuable 
contributions:  parasitic  research,  comparative  anatomy,  and  physiology.  In 
the  first-named  he  is  a  pioneer;  his  work  Entozporum  historia  naturalis  has  so 
considerably  widened  the  knowledge  of  intestinal  worms  which  Pallas 
founded  that  all  subsequent  research  has  been  based  on  it;  this  work  is  the 
result  of  investigations  into  numerous  germ-carrying  animals  and  gives  de- 
tailed accounts  of  the  appearance  and  conditions  of  life  of  the  parasites 
existing  in  them.  Through  this  work  the  number  of  known  species  of  intesti- 
nal parasites  has  tripled.  But  while  Pallas  believed  that  the  parasites  or  their 
eggs  enter  the  host  from  outside,  Rudolphi  is  convinced  that  they  are  pro- 
duced by  diseased  processes  inside  the  hosts  —  a  false  idea,  which  is  all  the 
more  curious  because  otherwise  he  most  emphatically  denies  the  possibility 
of  spontaneous  generation.  In  these  circumstances  it  is  natural  that  his 
account  of  the  evolutional  history  of  the  intestinal  parasites  should  be  the 
weakest  part  of  his  work  and  far  inferior  to  the  masterly  description  that 
he  gives  of  the  different  forms. 

In  a  collection  of  short  essays  Rudolphi  has  recorded  a  number  of  valu- 
able investigations  in  comparative  anatomy.  Of  special  interest  are  his  com- 
parative microscopical  studies  of  the  intestinal  villi  in  different  vertebrates. 
He  gives  an  account  in  this  work  of  a  large  number  of  different  forms  of  these 
appendices,  thereby  increasing  not  only  the  knowledge  of  the  tissue  theory 
as  created  by  Bichat,  but  also  the  use  of  the  microscope.  This  investigation 
therefore  deserves  to  be  remembered  as  one  of  the  first  in  the  sphere  of  com- 
parative histology.  Another  useful  work  of  his  was  the  study  of  the  cerebral 
cavities,  wherein  he  attacked  Sommerring's  above-mentioned  theory  of  the 
cerebral  fluid's  being  the  intellectual  organ  and  his  belief  in  connexion  there- 
with that  the  nerve-fibres  end  in  these  cavities.  Rudolphi  considers  that  the 

'  JoHAN  Conrad  Brunner  (165 3-1737),  whose  name  is  preserved  in  the  glands  of  the 
duodenum  called  after  him,  made  some  well-known  experiments  with  the  extirpation  of  the 
pancreas  of  live  dogs. 


354  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

entire  brain  is  the  "intellectual  organ"  and  maintains,  in  contrast  to  the 
attempts  of  earlier  times  to  localize  the  soul,  that  such  a  complex  phenome- 
non may  very  well  require  a  complex  organ  as  its  foundation.  On  the  other 
hand,  Rudolphi's  attempt  at  a  new  systematic  grouping  of  the  animal  king- 
dom, into  nerveless,  single-nerved,  and  double-nerved,  was  not  very  success- 
ful and  was  forgotten  long  ago  —  a  scheme,  in  fact,  which  had  already  been 
rejected  by  his  contemporaries  and  which  had  to  give  way  to  Cuvier's  better 
and  more  natural  basis  of  classification. 

His  text-book  on  physiology 
Rudolphi's  most  important  work,  however,  was  his  Grundriss  der  Physiologic, 
which  occupied  his  old  age  and  was  still  unfinished  at  his  death.  This  work 
best  displays  his  great  knowledge,  founded  on  his  own  experiences  and  his 
wide  reading,  as  well  as  his  critical  faculty  and  elevated  mode  of  thought. 
Physiology,  he  says,  is  "the  doctrine  of  the  human  organism."  An  organism 
without  life  is  unthinkable;  when  the  one  is  created,  the  second  must  be 
present;  a  dead  body  is  not  an  organism,  but  only  the  remains  of  one.  The 
classifying  science  of  physiology  is  therefore  anthropology:  here  Rudolphi, 
like  Blumenbach,  strongly  insists  upon  man's  dissimilarity  from  the  apes, 
but  considers  in  opposition  to  the  latter  that  the  human  genus  should  be 
divided  into  species,  not  races.  In  this  connexion  he  declares  that  human 
beings  cannot  have  originated  from  one  single  pair  —  a  sentiment  which, 
during  that  reactionary  period,  it  certainly  required  some  courage  to  express. 
The  chapter  on  anatomy  that  follows  this  section  is  one  of  the  most  brilliant 
parts  of  the  work;  the  clear  and  concise  manner  in  which  he  expounds  the 
composition  of  the  human  body  was  unrivalled  at  the  time;  as  compared 
with  Bichat's  tissue  theory  it  represents  a  great  advance,  on  account  of  both 
its  simple  and  concise  grouping  of  the  tissues  and  its  sound  criticism;  here  we 
find  no  fantastic  theories  of  life,  no  absurd  speculations  on  symmetry,  but  a 
clear  and  sober  account  of  the  different  parts  of  the  body,  which  is  mostly 
consistent  with  modern  conceptions.  In  regard  to  the  essence  of  life,  Rudolphi 
associates  himself  most  closely  with  Reil's  theory  of  life  as  bound  up  with 
the  form  and  mixture  of  matter,  while  Oken's  and  Schelling's  extravagant 
ideas  are  utterly  repudiated.  Likewise,  he  rejects  Stahl's  theory  of  the  soul 
as  a  cause  of  bodily  phenomena:  "Das  Dasein  oder  das  Hinxutreten  eines  Geistes 
oder  einer  Seele  xum  Korper  erkldrt  uns  das  Leben  nicht  im  geringsten. ' '  On  the  other 
hand,  he  strongly  emphasizes  the  importance  of  the  chemical  processes  for 
the  vital  functions,  in  this  associating  himself  with  Berzelius's  animal 
chemistry,  which,  thanks  to  his  childhood's  having  been  spent  in  Sweden, 
Rudolphi  was  able  to  read  in  the  original.  His  account  of  the  functions  of 
the  nervous  system  and  the  sensory  organs  is  an  extremely  careful  piece  of 
work,  which  sharply  criticizes  all  the  mystical  nonsense  that  was  prevalent 
at  that  time:  animal  magnetism,  interpretation  of  dreams,  divining-rods, 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  355 

and  the  like.  Occasionally,  however,  his  criticism  goes  beyond  the  mark;  he 
expresses  doubt  not  only  of  Gall's  theory  of  the  nerves'  leading  to  the  grey 
matter  of  the  brain,  but  also  of  the  existence  of  sensory  and  motor  nerves. 
The  caution  with  which  he  treats  current  theories  is  at  any  rate  attractive. 
Space  forbids  a  more  detailed  account  of  his  exposition  of  the  digestive 
organs,  respiration,  and  the  musculature;  these  organs  and  their  functions  are 
described  with  the  same  thoroughness  and  care  that  marked  his  previous 
chapter.  The  whole  work  testifies,  even  in  its  incomplete  form,  to  the  strides 
that  exact  research  had  already  made  during  the  first  decades  of  the  nineteenth 
century,  as  regards  both  methods  and  results,  foreshadowing  the  immense 
successes  of  subsequent  periods. 

Contemporary  with  Rudolphi  there  was  working  in  Germany  a  scientist 
who  made  important  contributions  in  the  sphere  of  exact  biology,  although 
in  his  theoretical  conceptions  he  maintained  the  point  of  view  of  the  natural 
philosophy  of  the  time.  Johann  Friedrich  Meckel  was  born  at  Halle  in 
1781.  Both  his  father  and  his  grandfather  had  been  professors  in  anatomy 
there;  both  had  by  their  keenness  and  insight  improved  the  anatomical 
collection  existing  there  —  especially  the  father,  who  had  even  declared  in 
his  will  that  his  skeleton  was  to  be  mounted  and  set  up  in  the  museum. 
Young  Meckel  followed  in  their  footsteps;  having  matriculated  and  taken 
his  degree  at  Halle,  he  worked  for  a  year  or  two  with  Cuvier  and  afterwards 
made  a  tour  through  Europe.  At  the  age  of  twenty-five  he  was  appointed 
professor  in  his  native  town,  where  he  worked  until  his  death,  in  1833. 
During  his  lifetime  he  exercised  great  influence  both  as  a  teacher  and  as  a  re- 
search-worker, and  not  least  as  a  result  of  his  having  undertaken  the  publica- 
tion of  Reil's  above-mentioned  Archiv,  in  which  he  developed  his  own  ideas 
and  gave  accounts  of  a  number  of  special  investigations.  These  partly  fall 
within  the  sphere  of  descriptive  and  comparative  anatomy,  and  partly  they  arc 
purely  speculative  and  philosophical.  In  the  former  sphere  Meckel  proved  a 
worthy  pupil  of  Cuvier,  while  in  the  theoretical  sphere  he  was  undoubtedly 
influenced  by  GeofFroy  Saint-Hilaire.  The  name  of  "the  German  Cuvier," 
which  his  contemporaries  gave  him,  thus  only  partially  corresponds  to  his 
point  of  view;  what  made  him  most  worthy  of  the  title  was  the  work  he  did 
by  exhortation  and  example  to  introduce  into  Germany  the  study  of  com- 
parative anatomy,  which  in  course  of  time  was  to  reach  its  highest  develop- 
ment in  that  very  country.  Amongst  his  contemporaries,  at  any  rate,  there 
was  not  one,  with  the  exception  of  Cuvier,  who  had  mastered  the  anatomy  of 
all  animal  forms,  both  higher  and  lower,  so  thoroughly  as  he,  though  his  most 
important  investigations  he  carried  out  in  the  field  of  vertebrate  anatomy. 

Meckel's  system  of  comparative  anatomy 
Of  these  specialized  investigations  of  Meckel's  the  most  exhaustive  are  his 
anatomical  monographs  on  the   ornithorynchus   and   the  cassowary,   but 


356  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

besides  these  he  has  made  considerable  contributions  in  several  other  spheres  of 
anatomy:  investigations  into  the  development  of  the  nervous  system  and  the 
intestinal  tube  in  the  embryonic  stage,  into  the  structure  of  the  brain  of  birds, 
into  the  intestinal  villi,  which  reasons  of  space  make  it  impossible  to  discuss 
in  detail.  Finally,  in  his  later  years  he  collected  the  results  of  his  researches 
in  a  large  work  entitled  System  der  vergleichenden  Anatomie,  which,  like  Rudol- 
phi's  Physiology,  was  never  finished.  The  first  part  of  it  forms  a  summary  of 
Meckel's  theoretical  speculations;  the  following  sections  deal  with  the 
structure  of  the  individual  organs. 

If  we  turn  from  reading  Rudolphi's  Physiology  to  Meckel's  general 
anatomy,  the  first  impression  will  undoubtedly  be  that  we  have  taken  a 
long  step  backwards  in  time  —  from  a  critical  and  almost  modern  method 
of  presentation  back  to  romantic  natural  philosophy.  The  very  foreword 
contains  the  statement  that  the  "  Bildungsgesetze"  which  govern  the  animal 
kingdom  may  be  grouped  under  two  main  principles,  "multiplicity"  and 
"unity,"  the  latter  also  being  termed  "reduction."  And  the  exposition  of 
these  "formative  laws"  is  introduced  with  the  assertion  that  the  form  of  the 
animal  may  be  regarded  either  in  itself  and  with  reference  to  the  physical 
force  which  is  its  origin,  or  with  reference  to  the  purpose  intended  to  be 
served  thereby  and  the  creative  spiritual  force  that  forms  the  basis  thereof. 
This  at  once  is  far  more  reminiscent  of  Schelling  than  of  modern  natural 
science,  and  yet  we  constantly  come  across  proofs  of  the  author's  many-sided 
and  radical  knowledge  of  anatomy  and  of  his  genius  for  combining  acquired 
facts.  By  the  formative  law  of  multiplicity  is  meant  all  those  qualities  which 
distinguish  the  life-forms  from  one  another,  and  herein  are  included  not  only 
the  characters  that  differentiate  the  species,  genera,  and  higher  groups,  but 
also  the  qualities  of  the  individual  organs  in  the  same  and  in  different 
animals  and  the  changes  in  them,  such  as  are  brought  about  by  age,  habits  of 
life,  and  heredity.  Under  this  heading,  then,  comes  descriptive  anatomy,  while 
the  "reduction"  law  embraces  comparative  anatomy,  or,  as  Meckel  says,  the 
proofs  that  all  formations  in  the  animal  kingdom  are  variations  of  one  single 
type  —  that  is,  the  same  idea  that  Geoffroy  and  Goethe  tried  to  develop. 

Law  of  multiplicity 
Under  the  law  of  multiplicity  is  described,  to  start  with,  the  body's  for- 
mation of  tissues  —  a  chapter  in  which  Meckel  does  not  compare  well  with 
Rudolphi  in  clarity  and  conciseness.  As  the  fundamental  substance  for  all 
the  parts  of  the  body  he  gives  a  solid  matter,  shaped  like  minute  globes, 
which  lie  embedded  in  a  fluid;  these  are  clearly  visible  in  the  lower  animals 
and  in  the  embryos  of  higher  animals,  while  in  the  latter  themselves  the  fluid 
is  coagulated  and  in  conjunction  with  the  globes  forms  fibres,  membranes, 
and  tissues.  In  this  speculation  Meckel  is  without  doubt  influenced  by  Caspar 
Friedrich  Wolff,  whom  he  held  in  high  esteem  and  whose  writings  he  trans- 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  357 

lated  into  German.  As  regards  the  system,  Meckel  to  a  certain  extent  adopts 
an  attitude  of  indecision;  on  the  one  hand  he  has  to  accept  Cuvier's  types, 
but  on  the  other  the  whole  object  is  to  prove  the  possibility  of  one  single 
primal  type;  consequently  Meckel  rejects  the  definite  line  that  both  Cuvier 
and  Lamarck  draw  between  vetebrates  and  invertebrates,  and  as  an  inter- 
mediary form  between  them  he  places  the  ink-fish,  whose  carapace  is  declared 
to  be  the  rudiment  of  a  backbone.  Further,  Meckel,  like  Lamarck,  believes 
in  a  common  spontaneous  generation  whereby  a  number  of  lower  life-forms 
arise  in  various  parts  of  the  world  and  thus  increase  the  number  of  existing 
species.  In  this,  as  in  his  general  idea  of  the  origin  of  life-forms,  Meckel  in- 
clines towards  Lamarck,  his  indebtedness  to  whom  he  acknowledges  when 
quoting  him.  Each  of  them  sought  to  produce  a  "history  of  natural  creation," 
and  it  must  be  admitted  that  on  this  subject  Meckel  was  able  to  derive  ad- 
vantage both  from  the  work  of  his  predecessors  and  from  his  own  thorough 
knowledge  of  anatomy.  Meckel's  theory  of  origin  thus  contains  many  in- 
teresting and  suggestive  ideas  of  importance  for  the  future  of  science,  but 
it  certainly  contains  also  masses  of  weird  fancies  and  ridiculous  conclusions. 
What  distinguishes  Meckel's  theory  from  Lamarck's  —  and  even  from  Dar- 
win's —  is  the  fact  that  he  does  not  assume  one  single  cause  of  evolution,  but 
a  number  of  causes,  and  his  exposition  herein  lacks  the  easy  comprehensibil- 
ity  that  characterizes  both  his  predecessor's  and  his  successor's  work,  which, 
indeed,  explains  why  it  is  that  he  failed  to  win  the  same  degree  of  popu- 
larity that  they  did.  Among  the  causes  of  evolution,  it  is  true,  Meckel,  like 
Lamarck,  lays  great  stress  on  the  influence  of  habit  and  environment,  or,  as 
he  expresses  it,  the  formative  influence  of  mechanical  forces.  In  this  connexion 
he  quotes  stories  of  how  bobtailed  equine  and  canine  races  have  been  created 
as  a  result  of  the  tails  of  the  animals'  ancestors  having  been  docked,  and  in 
the  same  way  mechanical  pressure  in  the  course  of  ages  has  produced  the 
numerous  interlacings  and  various  divisions  of  the  digestive  canal,  as  also 
other  changes  in  the  internal  organs.  And  he  ascribes  similar  transforming 
force  to  light,  heat,  and  electricity;  in  particular,  the  electrolysis  of  fluids, 
which  was  then  newly  discovered,  leads  him  to  indulge  in  fantastic  specu- 
lations upon  the  effect  of  this  force  on  the  development  of  life-forms.  More- 
over, he  drags  into  his  theory  of  the  formation  of  species  the  entire  category 
of  mostly  unknown  phenomena  that  give  rise  to  malformations;  thus,  he 
cites  the  old  belief  that  mothers  can  give  birth  to  malformed  children  after 
"getting  a  fright,"  as  at  least  a  plausible  cause  of  the  appearance  of  new  life- 
forms,  and  he  finally  mentions  hybridization  as  an  important  cause  of  the 
arising  of  fresh  species.  To  this  factor  in  the  evolution  of  life,  however, 
which,  as  is  well  known,  has  excited  special  attention  in  modern  times,  he 
attributes  utterly  irrational  eff^ects:  he  believes  in  old  tales  of  a  cross  between 
a  cat  and  a  hare,  a  cock  and  a  duck.  There  is  indeed  far  better  justification 


358  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

for  his  expressly  ascribing  the  abundance  of  species  in  the  insect  class  to 
hybridization. 

Law  of  unity 
All  the  speculations  just  referred  to,  Meckel  includes  in  the  sphere  of  the 
law  of  multiplicity.  As  already  mentioned,  under  the  law  of  reduction  come 
the  proofs  of  the  unity  of  the  life-type.  Here  Meckel  displays  the  whole  of 
his  extensive  knowledge  of  anatomy,  both  good  and  bad;  here  he  presents 
his  most  brilliant  ideas  and  also  indulges  in  the  most  ridiculous  absurdities. 
The  latter  necessarily  result  from  the  false  preconception  of  one  single  life- 
type  and  evolutional  series,  the  same  fatal  constructions  of  thought,  in  fact, 
which  led  Lamarck  and  GeofFroy  to  such  wild  delusions.  And  it  may  be  said 
that  herein  Meckel  outrivals  them  to  the  same  extent  as  his  anatomical 
knowledge  is  more  extensive  than  theirs.  It  is  hardly  worth  while  going 
further  with  him  along  these  erratic  courses;  as  when  he  compares  the  shell 
of  the  tortoise  and  of  insects,  or  the  papillas  on  the  tongue  of  cats  and  of 
snails,  or  when  he  likens  the  double  malformations  occurring  in  man,  now 
generally  called  Siamese  twins,  to  a  colony  of  polypi.  It  would  be  better  to 
ponder  over  the  numerous  ideas  of  great  value  for  the  future  to  which  he  gives 
expression  in  this  connexion.  Among  these  ideas  that  have  been  generally 
adopted  in  modern  times  may  be  mentioned  his  view  that  the  lungs  of  the 
land  vertebrates  are  derived  from  the  air-bladders  of  fishes,  his  comparison 
between  the  male  and  the  female  sexual  organs  and  his  derivation  of  their 
several  parts  from  an  indifferent  embryonic  stage,  his  comparison  of  the 
segmentation  of  worms  and  articulates  with  metamerism  in  the  vertebrates, 
and,  above  all,  his  foreshadowing  of  Haeckel's  biogenetical  organic  law, 
when  he  declares  that  each  higher  animal  during  its  embryonic  development 
passes  through  the  same  forms  as  those  that  are  lower  in  the  evolutional 
series  possess  when  fully  formed.  This  theory  of  "the  development  of  the 
special  organism  in  accordance  with  the  same  laws  as  the  entire  animal 
series"  he  supports  by  a  number  of  very  ill-founded  arguments  —  for  in- 
stance, he  makes  the  human  liver  undergo  a  crayfish  and  a  mollusc  stage  — 
but  also  on  reasoning  which  has  been  accepted  by  modern  supporters  of  the 
theory.  This  doctrine,  which  had  already  been  sweepingly  rejected  by  Rudol- 
phi,  has  certainly  been  very  widely  debated  in  our  own  day,  but  at  all  events 
it  has  had  a  highly  stimulating  effect  upon  research;  its  subsequent  fate  will 
be  discussed  later  on.  The  theoretical  conception  that  Meckel  thus  formed 
he  applies  in  detail  in  the  special  part  of  his  work  wherein,  with  a  many- 
sided  and  at  the  same  time  thorough  knowledge  of  his  subject,  which  but 
few  had  so  far  emulated,  he  describes  the  structure  of  the  organic  systems 
throughout  the  animal  kingdom.  With  extreme  thoroughness  he  discusses 
and  compares  the  bone-structure  in  the  vertebrates,  describing  especially 
the  bones  of  fishes  in  great  detail  and  making  new  discoveries  in  this  latter 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  359 

field;  the  musculature  and  digestive  canal,  the  respiratory  and  circulatory- 
systems,  are  also  carefully  described.  This  radical  detailed  knowledge  of 
Meckel's  has  had  a  considerable  influence  on  the  development  of  biological 
science.  Moreover,  his  general  conception  of  the  phenomena  of  life  has  like- 
wise made  a  deep  impression.  His  theory  of  evolution  deserves  to  be  men- 
tioned by  the  side  of  Lamarck's;  he  is  at  all  events  worthy  to  be  named  by  the 
many  who  at  the  zenith  of  Darwinism  sought  for  "pre-Darwinists,"  instead 
of  Goethe,  who  never  discussed  the  problem  of  species.  He  undoubtedly  had  a 
great  influence  also  on  biological  research  in  Germany  during  the  succeeding 
era;  the  very  word  "BiUungsgeserz"  sounds  quite  familiar  to  anyone  who  has 
studied  Haeckel's  works  for  instance,  in  which  the  word  '"law"  occurs  so 
often  in  passages  where  "hypothesis"  or  "theory"  should  have  been  written 
instead.  Nor  can  there  be  any  doubt  that  his  penchant  for  bold  comparisons 
and  derivations  has  not  been  without  its  influence  on  the  modern  school, 
which  has  made  the  derivation  of  the  organs  of  the  higher  animals  from 
corresponding  less  developed  forms  the  chief  aim  of  biology.  This  morpho- 
genetical  school  has  largely  applied  Meckel's  ideas,  although  employing  an 
entirely  different  standard  of  criticism,  so  that  Meckel,  who  so  essentially 
belongs  to  romantic  natural  philosophy,  stands  as  an  intermediary  between 
this  school  of  research  and  that  which  included  a  man  like  Gegenbaur 
amongst  its  notable  members. 

Comparative  anatomy  in  France 
While  thus  the  exact  biological  method  in  Germany  only  gradually  suc- 
ceeded in  getting  rid  of  its  connexion  with  natural  philosophy,  the  same 
method  in  France  had  no  difficulty  in  triumphing  over  the  more  speculative 
method  of  natural  research  represented  by  Lamarck  and  Geoff'roy;  it  was 
Cuvier  and  Bichat  who  with  their  pioneer  work  determined  the  direction  in 
which  the  scientists  of  the  next  generation  were  to  follow  with  fair  una- 
nimity. Thanks,  then,  to  these  precursors,  France  acquired  before  other  Euro- 
pean countries  a  science  of  life-phenomena  free  from  the  romantic  infusions 
of  speculative  philosophy,  but,  on  the  other  hand,  this  science  eventually 
became  extremely  conservative,  and  when  the  theory  of  the  origin  of  species 
appeared,  French  research  repudiated  it  with  greater  vehemence  than  any 
other.  Of  these  French  biologists  from  the  beginning  of  the  century  some 
practised  a  purely  experimental  method;  these  will  be  dealt  with  below.  As 
a  direct  pupil  of  Cuvier  and  Bichat,  however,  Blainville  is  worthy  of  mention, 
for  he  furthered  the  cause  of  comparative  anatomy  long  and  successfully. 

Henri  Marie  Ducrotay  de  Blainville  was  born  in  1777  at  Arques,  in 
Normandy,  of  noble  family.  He  was  brought  up  at  a  monastic  school,  and 
when  it  was  closed  down  during  the  Revolution,  he  went  to  Paris,  where  he 
first  of  all  applied  himself  to  painting,  apparently  with  but  little  enthusiasm 
or  success.  A  mere  chance  —  a  lecture  by  Cuvier  that  he  happened  to  go  to 


360  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

hear  —  aroused  his  interest  in  biology;  at  about  the  age  of  thirty  he  became 
a  pupil  of  Cuvier's,  quickly  obtained,  through  his  recommendation,  a  post  as 
assistant,  and  eventually,  after  having  held  certain  other  appointments, 
became  his  master's  successor.  By  that  time,  however,  the  relations  between 
them  had  long  been  severed,  for  the  pupil's  quick-tempered  and  unreasonable 
disposition  could  not  reconcile  itself  to  the  calm  considerateness  of  the  mas- 
ter. Blainville  himself,  however,  was  a  splendid  teacher,  attracting  large 
audiences  and  devoting  himself  with  indefatigable  energy  to  his  teaching 
and  research  work  up  to  a  ripe  old  age.  He  died  in  1850. 

Blainville  was  a  biologist  with  many  and  varied  interests.  Amongst  his 
works  the  Manuel  d'actinologie  et  de  xpophytologie  is  worthy  of  mention,  in 
which  he  gives  the  results  of  his  thorough  investigations  into  the  lowest 
animal  forms,  and  further  an  Osfeograplne,  which  deserves  to  be  coupled  with 
Cuvier's  investigations  into  the  present-day  and  fossilized  vertebrate  ani- 
mals. His  theoretical  conception  of  biology  he  has  recorded  in  three  works: 
De  r organisation,  des  animaux,  Cours  de  physiologie,  and  Histoire  des  sciences 
de  I'organisme.  In  these  he  presents  a  view  of  life-phenomena  that  is  in  many 
respects  original  and  has  proved  of  value  for  the  future.  The  first  work  is 
introduced  with  a  survey  of  the  objects  and  methods  of  comparative  anat- 
omy. First  of  all  an  account  is  given  of  vegetable  and  animal  chemistry, 
wherein,  curiously  enough,  the  universally  accepted  contrasts  between  the 
alimental  process  of  plants  and  animals  are  considered  doubtful.  Then  the 
animal  is  characterized  as  a  "combination  of  certain  organs,  which  give  rise 
to  certain  forces  —  inter  alia,  a  digestive  and  a  motive  force  —  assuming  a 
definite  form  and  influencing  external  surroundings  in  a  definite  manner." 
As  methods  of  getting  to  know  the  structure  of  the  animal  are  adduced  ob- 
servation, experiment,  and  a  logical  mode  of  thought,  after  which  are  named 
certain  pioneers  in  this  sphere,  among  whom  one  seeks  in  vain  for  the  name 
of  Cuvier  —  a  characteristic  touch,  showing  the  pupil's  bitter  feelings 
towards  his  master. 

Blainville' s  theory  of  cellular  tissue 
Next,  an  account  is  given  of  the  structure  of  the  animal  body  —  this  forming 
one  of  the  most  brilliant  sections  of  the  work.  Here  Blainville  declares  with 
a  confidence  such  as  was  never  shown  previously  that  the  cellular  tissue  is 
the  fundamental  substance  of  the  animal  organism,  the  element  which  is 
formed  earliest  and  out  of  which  all  the  organs  are  evolved.  Of  this  tissue 
it  is  said  that  it  represents  the  finest  and  most  extensive  element  in  the  ani- 
mal body  and  that  it  is  formed  of  thin  membranes,  which  cross  one  another, 
so  that  cystic  interstices  arise.  As  modifications  of  this  tissue  are  mentioned 
the  skin,  the  mucous  membranes,  connective  tissue,  bone,  vascular  systems, 
and  finally  —  the  most  complex  of  all  —  muscle  and  nerves.  Regarded  from  the 
modern  point  of  view,  Blainville's  conception  of  the  cellular  tissue  as  the  basis 
of  the  animal  body  is  certainly  imperfect,  but  when  compared  with  the  cellu- 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  361 

lar-tissue  theories  of  his  predecessors,  Caspar  Friedrich  WolfF  and  Bichat,  it 
represents  an  undoubted  advance;  it  is  one  of  many  examples  of  how  knowl- 
edge in  a  given  sphere  progresses,  as  it  were,  fumblingly  from  generation  to 
generation  until,  finally,  the  decisive  word  has  been  spoken.  In  regard  to  the 
conception  of  tissues  and  the  part  they  play  in  the  formation  of  the  organs, 
Blainville  otherwise  associates  himself  closely  with  Bichat,  and  he  likewise 
adopts  the  latter's  theory  of  organic  and  animal  life,  which,  however,  he 
employs  with  considerably  greater  moderation  than  its  creator.  For  the  rest, 
he  believes  a  living  body  to  be  a  kind  of  chemical  workshop  wherein  fresh 
molecules  are  constantly  being  conveyed  and  old  ones  removed,  where  the 
combination  is  never  fixed,  but  always,  so  to  speak,  "in  nisu,"  resulting  in 
constant  motion  and  heat.  This  view  of  life  is  certainly  not  vitalistic,  but 
Blainville  nevertheless  emphasizes  in  what  follows  the  contrast  betwxen 
"general"  and  "vital"  forces,  both  unknown  as  to  their  real  nature,  but  the 
former  far  more  measurable  than  the  latter;  both  operate  in  the  living  body 
and  life's  intensity  is  dependent  upon  the  ascendancy  of  the  life-forces  over 
the  general  forces.  In  this  sphere,  then,  Blainville  wavers  somewhat  between 
divergent  principles,  and  on  the  whole  he  has  been  counted  amongst  the 
vitalists.  The  two  primary  qualities  of  life  are,  according  to  him,  "cowpo- 
sition"  and  " dkom-position" ;  in  the  former  is  included  the  absorption  of 
nourishment,  in  the  latter  not  only  excretion,  but  also  reproduction.  Among 
the  alimental  organs  are  also  counted  the  organs  of  motion  and,  in  general, 
everything  that  moves  the  external  bodily  form,  to  which  Blainville  as- 
cribes a  fundamental  importance  for  all  knowledge  of  animal  life.  His  sys- 
tem rests  entirely  on  this  basis  and  thereby  acquires  a  somewhat  artificial 
character;  nevertheless,  it  has  done  considerable  service,  chiefly  in  the  fact 
that  here  for  the  first  time  a  definite  line  of  demarcation  is  drawn  between 
amphibians  and  reptiles,  which  all  subsequent  research  has  confirmed.  For 
the  purposes  of  his  special  presentation  of  comparative  anatomy  Blainville 
prefers  to  go  from  the  higher  form  to  the  lower,  his  arguments  in  justifica- 
tion of  which  are  somewhat  reminiscent  of  Lamarck's  "degradation"  theory. 
In  other  respects,  too,  his  treatment  of  comparative  anatomy  is  based  on  a 
form  of  theoretical  speculation  that  renders  the  actual  method  of  presenting 
his  subject  highly  artificial;  it  would,  however,  take  too  long  to  go  more 
deeply  into  these  questions.  Undoubtedly  Blainville's  works  contain,  besides 
much  that  is  absurd,  a  number  of  ideas  of  immense  value,  both  in  detail  and 
as  a  whole.  Among  these  may  be  specially  mentioned  the  importance  he  at- 
taches to  the  stages  of  embryologic  development  as  a  basis  of  comparison 
between  the  animal  forms,  a  principle  that,  as  is  well  known,  has  since 
proved  of  fundamental  importance  to  comparative  anatomy.  For  this  fact 
science  has  to  thank  a  number  of  works  in  the  sphere  of  embryology  that 
were  brought  out  during  the  period  now  under  discussion.  To  this  sphere, 
therefore,  we  shall  now  proceed. 


CHAPTER    V 

THE   PROGRESS   OF   EMBRYOLOGY 

Ovists  and  animalculists 

THE  MOST  IMPORTANT  FEATURES  of  the  earlier  history  of  embryology 
have  already  been  referred  to  in  previous  sections  of  this  work  —  how 
even  Hippocrates  had  observed  the  development  of  the  hen's  Qgg,  how 
Aristotle  studied  the  embryology  of  various  animals,  how  Fabricius, 
Harvey,  Malpighi,  and  C.  F.  Wolff  each  in  turn  made  valuable  contributions 
to  the  knowledge  of  the  development  of  the  embryo,  especially  in  the  hen's 
egg,  which  had  remained  throughout  the  most  easily  available  object  of 
investigation,  but  also  in  a  number  of  other  animals,  chiefly,  of  course, 
mammals.  These  inquiries  were  naturally  much  influenced  by  the  speculations 
on  the  process  of  development  that  succeeded  one  another  during  different 
epochs;  in  this  respect,  the  "preformation"  theory,  which  prevailed  for  a 
time,  had  a  most  unfavourable  effect,  seeing  that  its  champions,  for  obvious 
reasons,  cared  but  little  for  practical  observations  of  the  embryonic  develop- 
ment —  everything  having  been  ready-formed  from  the  beginning,  there 
was,  of  course,  no  need  for  observation.  This  explains  why  the  eighteenth 
century,  during  which  the  preformation  theory  held  sway,  proved  so  barren 
in  embryological  observations;  instead  of  investigating,  scientists  wasted 
their  time  in  profitless  speculations  and  controversies  between  ovists  and 
animalculists.  Some  of  the  latter  certainly  reached  the  height  of  absurdity 
when  they  saw  in  the  spermatozoa  the  true  agents  of  reproduction,  with  the 
consequence  that  they  succeeded  in  distinguishing  under  the  microscope  in 
every  human  spermium,  with  the  aid  of  their  imaginations,  a  complete 
miniature  human  being  with  all  the  limbs  ready  formed.  It  was  not  until 
the  close  of  that  century  that  embryology  received  a  fresh  impetus;  C.  F. 
Wolff  made  a  beginning  with  his,  certainly  exaggerated,  epigenesis  theory 
and  his  embryological  observations  based  thereon;  Cuvier,  who  was  in- 
terested in  all  biological  problems,  also  made  weighty  contributions  to  this 
subject;  Blainville  has  just  been  mentioned  as  a  promoter  of  embryological 
research;  nevertheless,  science  has  mainly  to  thank  certain  German  scientists 
for  its  most  important  progress  in  this  direction,  progress  which,  in  fact, 
gave  rise  to  an  essentially  new  view  of  life-phenomena.  As  has  often  hap- 
pened with  pregnant  problems  in  the  history  of  science,  this,  too,  was  dealt 
with  simultaneously  by  several  observers,  each  of  whom  contributed  his 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  363 

portion  towards  its  solution.  In  the  following  we  shall  deal  with  Pander, 
who  investigated  the  germ  layers  in  the  embryo  of  the  hen;  Rathke,  who  dis- 
covered the  branchial  slits  in  the  embryo  and  the  circulation  in  conjunction 
therewith;  and,  in  another  connexion,  Purkinje,  who  discovered  the  germ- 
cell  in  the  hen's  egg.  The  first  place  among  the  creators  of  modern  embryol- 
ogy, however,  is  held  by  von  Baer,  one  of  the  great  personalities  in  the  field 
of  research  in  the  nineteenth  century. 

Karl  Ernst  von  Baer  was  born  in  1791  on  the  Piep  estate  in  Esthonia, 
the  son  of  a  landowner  belonging  to  the  German  nobility  of  that  country. 
Upon  leaving  school  at  Reval  he  matriculated  at  the  recently  founded  Uni- 
versity of  Dorpat,  where  he  applied  himself  to  medicine.  He  continued  his 
studies  in  branches  of  that  subject  in  Vienna,  but  from  there,  realizing  that 
he  was  not  made  for  a  doctor,  he  proceeded  to  Wurzburg  in  order  to  be  trained 
as  a  theoretical  scientist.  The  teacher  of  anatomy  in  that  university  at  the 
time  was  Ignaz  Dollinger  (1770-1841),  a  disciple  of  Schelling's,  who, 
combining  his  master's  passion  for  philosophical  speculation  with  a  radical 
knowledge  of  anatomy,  especially  interested  himself  and  his  pupils  in  prob- 
lems of  evolutional  history.  It  was  here  that  von  Baer's  research  took  the 
course  in  which  he  was  eventually  to  go  further  than  any  of  his  contempo- 
raries. After  completing  his  studies  he  was  appointed  professor  at  Konigs- 
berg  and  carried  out  his  principal  investigations  at  that  place.  In  1834  he 
accepted  an  invitation  to  become  an  academician  at  St.  Petersburg.  There  his 
activities  won  a  brilliant  success,  and  honours  were  lavished  upon  him  ac- 
cordingly. The  scientific  works  of  his  old  age,  however,  do  not  possess  the 
same  importance  as  those  of  his  early  years.  This  is  due  primarily  to  the  fact 
that  he  to  a  great  extent  divided  his  interests;  upon  official  request  he  under- 
took several  journeys  to  diff'erent  parts  of  the  Russian  Empire  and  as  a  result 
became  interested  in  a  number  of  different  problems  —  anthropology,  ethnog- 
raphy, archasology,  and  even  etymology.  Having  been  allowed  to  resign  his 
post,  he  settled  at  Dorpat  and  died  there  in  1876.  He  was  honoured  by  his 
countrymen  in  many  ways;  the  Esthonian  nobility  published  at  their  own  ex- 
pense a  splendid  edition  de  luxe  of  the  autobiography  that  he  had  written  in 
his  old  age,  and  after  his  death  a  bronze  statue  was  raised  to  him  at  Dorpat. 

Von  Baer  discovers  the  egg  of  mammals 
There  can  be  no  doubt  that  von  Baer  won  his  greatest  fame  through  the 
embryological  works  written  in  his  youth.  He  published  the  results  of  these 
in  a  brochure  entitled  De  ovi  mammalium  genesi,  which  came  out  in  18x7,  and 
a  larger  work,  IJber  Entivicklungsgeschicbte  der  Tiere,  of  the  years  1818  and  1837. 
In  the  first-mentioned  treatise  he  describes  the  most  important  of  the  dis- 
coveries he  made  in  this  field  —  namely,  the  egg  of  mammals  in  the  ovary. 
Apart  from  the  vague  ideas  of  earlier  scientists  on  this  subject,  de  Graaf 
(Part  II,  p.  lyz)  was  the  first  to  explain  at  all  the  conditions  obtaining  at  the 


364  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

earliest  stages  of  development  of  mammals.  He  described  the  follicles  named 
after  him  in  the  ovary  and  believed  these  to  be  eggs;  when  later  he  discovered 
eggs  in  the  uterus  of  a  rabbit  in  a  later  stage  of  growth,  he  supposed  that 
these  had  been  moved  thither  from  the  ovary  for  their  further  development; 
he  met  with  an  insoluble  difficulty,  however,  in  the  fact  that  the  further 
advanced  eggs  in  the  uterus  were  smaller  than  the  follicles,  and,  moreover, 
the  latter  proved  to  be  not  very  constant,  wherefore  Haller,  who  carefully 
investigated  the  matter,  assumed  that  the  egg  was  formed  out  of  the  follicu- 
lar fluid  through  coagulation.  By  carefully  following  the  development  of 
the  egg  in  dogs,  von  Baer  learnt  to  know  its  later  stages,  afterwards  trac- 
ing its  origin  back  by  investigating  a  series  of  animals  approaching  nearer 
and  nearer  to  the  fertilization  stage.  Here  he  found  the  egg  to  be  a  minute 
yellowish  cell  inside  the  follicle,  after  which  he  was  able  to  continue  the 
study  of  its  progressive  development. 

His  pioneer  work  on  evolution 
Besides  these  studies  in  mammal  embryology  von  Baer  devoted  himself  to 
that  ancient  classical  object  of  study  in  evolutional  history  —  the  hen's  egg. 
He  followed  its  evolution  with  the  utmost  care  and  published  the  results  in 
the  first  section  of  the  above-mentioned  work  tjber  Entivicklungsgeschichte, 
which,  besides,  summarizes  all  the  then  existing  knowledge  of  the  subject, 
thereby  becoming  a  pioneer  work  on  which  all  subsequent  research  has  had 
to  be  based.  The  latter  half  of  the  work  is  a  survey  of  the  embryonic  develop- 
ment of  all  the  vertebrates.  Through  this  book  von  Baer  has  created  modern 
embryology,  not  only  as  an  independent  field  of  research,  but  also  as  an  im- 
portant branch  of  comparative  anatomy  and  a  means  of  proving  the  affinity 
of  different  animal  forms.  In  the  embryo  of  the  chicken  von  Baer  discovered 
the  spinal  cord,  which  he  identified  by  comparison  with  the  cord  of  the 
selachians.  He  also  showed  in  its  proper  light  Rathke's  discovery  of  the  gill- 
slits  and  gill-arches  in  the  embryo.  Further,  he  has  explained  the  cause  of  the 
amnion  formation  —  a  discovery  comparable  with  the  foregoing  —  and  has 
also  given  concise  accounts  of  the  development  of  the  uro-genital  apparatus 
of  the  formation  of  the  lungs,  of  the  various  stages  of  development  of  the 
digestive  canal  and  the  nervous  system.  And  finally  he  makes  his  proved 
ideas  a  basis  for  a  general  evolutional  theory,  which,  it  is  true,  contains  a 
mass  of  natural-philosophical  notions,  but  on  the  other  hand  gives  a  clear 
survey  of  the  connexion  in  evolution  and  far  excels  all  previous  theoretical 
representations,  although,  since  it  is  ignorant  of  the  part  played  by  the  cells 
in  the  generative  process  of  the  organism,  it  cannot  be  called  modern.  For 
the  process  of  fertilization  is  thus  substituted  a  vague  hypothesis  in  which 
the  idea  of  a  growth  over  and  above  the  individual  plays  a  conspicuous  part: 
' '  Zuerst  wird  die  Moglichkeit  eines  neuen  Tieres  durch  unmittelhares  Wachsthum  des 
mutterlichen  Korpers  gegeben.  Es  bleibt  aber  nur  Teil.  Durch  die  Bejruchtung  wird  aus 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  365 

dem  Telle  ein  Ganges."  This  definition  of  fertilization  is  pure  metaphysics, 
here  closely  akin  to  Aristotle's.  In  opposition  to  Wolff's  one-sided  cpigenesis 
theory,  von  Baer  declares  that  in  reality  no  new  formation  takes  place  in  the 
egg,  but  only  transformation  in  the  direction  of  increasing  specialization. 
True,  this  theory  is  also  based  on  purely  speculative  grounds  —  that  the 
idea  of  the  producing  animal-form  controls  the  development  of  the  embryo  — 
but  it  at  any  rate  leads  to  a  result  that  has  been  accepted  even  in  modern 
times.  Further,  against  Meckel's  theory  that  during  the  embryonic  stage 
higher  animals  pass  through  the  form  of  lower  animals,  von  Baer  makes  one 
particularly  striking  criticism;  he  maintains  that  no  lower  animals  exist 
that  really  resemble  the  embryonic  stages  of  the  higher  animals,  but,  on 
the  other  hand,  the  embryo  of  a  higher  animal  and  that  of  a  lower  animal 
resemble  one  another  more  closely  than  do  the  fully  developed  animals.  The 
tissues  of  the  embryo  are  less  differentiated  than  those  of  the  animal  itself 
and  are  therefore  more  like  the  tissues  in  lower  animals;  but  a  fish  embryo  is 
from  the  very  outset,  and  always  remains,  a  fish,  just  as  every  vertebrate 
animal's  embryo  is  from  the  beginning  a  vertebrate  animal.  Since,  then, 
evolution  involves  a  differentiation,  the  principle  holds  good  that  "the 
more  dissimilar  two  animal  forms  are,  the  further  we  have  to  go  back  in 
evolutional  history  to  find  an  agreement."  The  common  primal  form  for  all 
animals  is  the  simple  cell-form,  the  form  of  the  egg  and  of  the  first  embryonic 
stage.  Starting  from  these  considerations,  von  Baer  emphatically  rejects  the 
Bonnet-Lamarckian  theory  of  a  uniform  chain  of  development  in  the  animal 
kingdom  and  instead  associates  himself  with  Cuvier's  type  theory,  which  he 
further  develops.  He  maintains  that  a  series  of  animals  can  in  respect  of  the 
development  of  one  organ  be  progressive,  while  another  organ  in  the  same 
animal  series  is  regressive,  and  that  one  animal  within  a  lower  type  may 
attain  to  a  very  high  development  in  comparison  with  another  form  which 
comes  low  down  within  a  higher  type  —  the  bee  and  the  fish  are  cited,  with 
the  intelligence  as  the  standard  of  comparison.  Each  organ,  therefore,  should 
be  judged  not  only  according  to  its  definitive  form,  but  also  with  reference 
to  its  evolutional  history;  the  different  animal  types  often  possess  organs 
having  the  same  function,  but  an  entirely  different  origin.  He  predicts  that  a 
comparative  investigation  of  the  different  organs  in  the  animal  kingdom  on 
this  basis  will  prove  of  great  importance  for  the  future,  and  this  prediction 
has  of  course  been  fulfilled. 

His  natural  philoso-phy 
Side  by  side  with  these  progressive  ideas,  and  often  curiously  interwoven 
with  them,  we  find  in  von  Baer  a  wealth  of  ideas  of  manifestly  natural- 
philosophical  origin  which  must  certainly  seem  highly  grotesque  to  the 
modern  mind,  but  which  nevertheless  have  undoubtedly  had  some  influence 
on  the  biological  speculation  that  was  to  come.  A  number  of  these  ideas  he 


3  66  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

had  adopted  from  contemporary  natural  philosophers,  as  for  instance  Oken's 
theory  of  the  head's  being  composed  of  vertebrae  and  of  the  jaws'  having  the 
qualities  of  ribs.  Others  again  he  has  certainly  invented  himself  —  for  ex- 
ample, the  theory  that  the  vertebrate  animals  are  composed  of  a  number  of 
tubes  lying  inside  one  another  in  the  shape  of  the  figure  8.  He  reaches  the 
extreme  heights  of  Schellingism  with  a  scheme  he  works  out,  according  to 
which  the  three  tubes  lying  within  one  another  are  each  divided  into  a 
positive  and  a  negative  half;  the  epidermis,  the  muscles,  and  the  nervous 
membrane  are  thus  given  a  plus  sign,  while  the  cutis,  the  bones,  and  the 
nerve-fibres  are  denoted  by  a  minus  sign.  Strangely  enough,  one  comes  across 
fancies  of  this  kind  in  many  of  the  eminent  biologists  of  that  period;  some 
have  already  been  mentioned,  others  will  be  discussed  later  on.  It  would  be 
quite  irrational,  however,  to  accept  these  confessions  of  the  weakness  of 
the  period  for  more  than  what  they  are;  they  are  certainly  striking  from  the 
point  of  view  of  cultural  history,  but  their  significance,  whether  for  the 
activities  of  the  scientists  named  or  for  their  contribution  to  the  general 
development  of  science,  should  at  any  rate  not  be  exaggerated. 

Martin  Heinrich  Rathke  may  claim  an  eminent  place  by  the  side  of 
von  Baer  among  the  pioneers  of  embryology.  He  was  born  in  1793  at  Danzig 
of  a  wealthy  burgher  family.  He  studied  at  Gottingen  under  Blumenbach, 
practised  for  a  time  as  a  doctor  in  his  native  town,  was  invited  to  Dorpat 
in  18x9  as  professor  in  physiology  and  thence,  as  von  Baer's  successor,  to 
Konigsberg,  where  he  worked  until  his  death,  in  i860.  Being  personally 
a  lovable  character,  keenly  active  on  behalf  of  his  science,  constantly  seeking 
to  increase  his  knowledge  by  research  work  at  home  and  abroad,  he  was 
universally  esteemed  by  his  colleagues  and  pupils. 

Rathke's  work  as  a  biologist  was  many-sided  and  important.  Among 
his  earliest  works  was  an  article  published  in  a  journal,  "On  the  Develop- 
ment of  the  Respiratory  Organs  in  Birds  and  Mammals,"  which  in  point  of 
value  may  be  compared  with  von  Baer's  above-mentioned  embryological 
treatises.  It  has  already  been  pointed  out  that  Rathke  discovered  the  gill- 
slits  in  the  embryo  of  birds  and  mammals,  as  well  as  the  ramification  of 
blood-vessels  connected  therewith.  He  further  compared  them  with  those  of 
the  fishes  and  followed  their  later  development  —  how  the  gill-slits  dis- 
appear and  how  the  blood-vessels  adapt  themselves  to  the  lungs,  which  are 
developed  from  an  expansion  of  the  front  part  of  the  digestive  canal.  He  has 
also  described  and  compared  the  development  of  the  air-sacs  of  birds  and  the 
larynx  of  birds  and  mammals.  In  another  work  he  gives  an  account  of  the  so- 
called  Wolffian  bodies  discovered  by  him,  which  he  characterizes  as  "head 
kidneys"  (pronephros),  and  which  for  a  time  performed  the  function  of  excre- 
tal  organs,  only  to  disappear  later  according  as  the  true  kidneys  developed, 
while  their  efferent  ducts  in  certain  animals  serve  as  part  of  the  sexual  organs. 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  367 

In  regard  to  his  theoretical  conception  of  these  conditions,  Rathke  accepts 
without  reservation  Meckel's  theory  of  the  lower  animal  forms  that  the 
higher  animals  pass  through  during  their  embryonic  life.  A  more  independent 
theory  is  developed  by  him  in  a  treatise  tjber  die  rucks chre it ende  Metamorphose 
der  Tiere,  in  which  he  records  the  results  arrived  at  during  his  research  work 
in  comparative  embryology.  Although  full  of  difficult  abstract  ideas,  this 
article  presents  a  view  —  original  for  the  time  at  which  it  was  written  — ■ 
of  a  hitherto  neglected  phenomenon  in  animal  life.  The  phrase  "ruckschrei- 
tende  Metamorphose"  is  characteristic  of  the  age.  Rathke  makes  a  cautious 
reservation  against  the  confusion  of  his  ideas  of  metamorphosis  with  those 
of  Goethe;  in  the  form  in  which  it  is  presented  here,  it  has  in  view  the  regres- 
sive development  which  certain  organs  undergo  during  their  embryonic  and 
early  life  and  which  concludes  with  their  total  disappearance  or  survival  as 
rudiments.  Rathke  cited  examples  of  phenomena  of  this  kind  from  the  entire 
animal  kingdom,  but  he  supports  his  argument  mainly  on  examples  taken 
from  the  vertebrates,  as  for  instance  the  gills  and  tail  of  the  tadpole,  the 
Wolffian  organs,  etc.  He  declares  that  such  organs  are  either  dissolved  or  are 
reabsorbed  by  the  rest  of  the  body,  or  else  are  knocked  off  and  disappear;  the 
latter  occurs  if  they  are  horny  and  lack  blood-vessels,  the  former  if  they 
possess  blood-vessels  by  which  their  substance  can  be  absorbed  and  made  use 
of  in  the  body.  And  it  always  happens,  he  declares,  that  such  a  disappearance 
of  one  organ  is  succeeded  by  the  development  of  another  which  takes  its 
place,  as  for  instance  the  lungs  of  the  frog,  which  develop  according  as  the 
gills  disappear,  or  the  kidneys  in  the  bird  and  mammal  embryo,  which  take 
the  place  of  the  Wolffian  bodies.  Only  an  entirely  altered  mode  of  living 
during  more  advanced  stages  of  development  can  bring  about  the  total  loss 
of  previously  existing  organs,  as  happens  in  the  parasitic  crustaceans.  It 
will  at  once  be  realized  that  here  Rathke  has  shed  light  on  one  of  the  most 
important  problems  of  modern  biology. 

Rathke' s  marine-zoological  studies 
But  Rathke's  activities  were  not  merely  confined  to  embryology;  he  is  also 
one  of  those  who  have  opened  up  for  biological  research  the  vast  field  that 
the  seas  have  to  offer.  Cuvier  was  the  first  in  modern  times  to  draw  the  atten- 
tion of  science  in  this  direction.  Rathke,  who  was  born  and  grew  up  in  a 
seaport  and  who  in  the  course  of  his  travels  —  in  Scandinavia  amongst  other 
countries  —  had  his  own  interest  in  this  field  of  research  stimulated  hereby, 
contributed  largely  towards  awakening  it  in  his  countrymen.  In  this  respect 
he  gained  much  from  the  acquaintance  he  made  in  Bergen  with  the  then 
priest  Michael  Sars  (1805-69),  another  of  the  pioneers  of  marine  research, 
who  presented  him  with  many  valuable  animal-forms  and  gave  him  much 
information.  Of  Rathke's  work  in  this  sphere  may  be  mentioned  his  careful 
description  of  the  lancet-fish  —  that  extremely  primitive  vertebrate  animal 


368  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

which  has  been  so  widely  studied  in  modern  times  and  which,  not  long  be- 
fore Rathke's  period,  had  been  thought  to  be  a  worm  of  a  mollusc.  Rathke's 
monograph  was  the  first  detailed  anatomical  description  of  the  animal  and 
was  written  with  the  same  thoroughness  that  characterized  his  embryologi- 
cal  investigations.  His  abundant  and  valuable  writings  further  contain  several 
monographs  on  crustaceans,  both  independent  and  parasitic,  molluscs  and 
worms,  as  also  a  number  of  monographs  on  the  vertebrates  —  for  example, 
on  the  lemming  —  which  are  worthy  of  mention  as  examples  of  Rathke's 
extensive  and  radical  research-work. 

The  third  in  order  of  the  above-mentioned  pioneers  of  embryology  was 
Heinrich  Christian  Pander  (1794-1865).  Born  at  Riga,  the  son  of  a  wealthy 
banker,  he  was  able  to  give  undivided  attention  to  scientific  work,  which 
had  attracted  him  from  an  early  age.  He  studied  at  Dorpat,  Berlin,  and  Got- 
tingen  and  afterwards,  having  made  the  acquaintance  of  von  Baer,  at  Wiirz- 
burg  in  the  latter's  company.  There  he  carried  out  his  pioneer  work  on  the 
development  of  the  embryo  of  the  chick,  the  results  of  which,  thanks  to 
his  great  wealth,  he  was  able  to  publish  in  a  very  fine  edition.  In  182.6  he 
became  an  academician  at  St.  Petersburg,  but  the  very  next  year  he  resigned 
and  lived  for  some  time  as  a  landowner  in  the  neighbourhood  of  Riga.  In 
1842.  he  entered  the  Russian  Mining  Board,  after  which  he  published  only 
works  on  geology. 

Discovery  of  the  germinal  layers  of  the  hen  s  embryo 
Pander's  above-mentioned  treatises  on  the  development  of  the  hen's  &gg, 
which  were  published  as  early  as  1817,  were  the  fruits  of  work  carried  out 
under  the  guidance  of  Dollinger  and  with  the  collaboration  of  von  Baer. 
They  thus  represent  to  a  certain  extent  the  basis  on  which  the  latter  scien- 
tist worked  further,  although  there  is  no  doubt  that  while  they  were  being 
written,  the  younger  of  the  two  friends  came  under  the  influence  of  the  elder. 
As  Pander's  greatest  service  should  be  recorded  the  fact  that,  taking  as  his 
starting-point  the  preliminary  work  of  Malpighi  and  C.  F.  Wolff,  he  dis- 
tinguishes the  different  layers  out  of  which  the  organs  of  the  chicken  embryo 
are  built  up.  These  layers,  which,  following  Wolff,  he  names  '^Blatter''  —  a 
relic  of  the  latter's  attempts  to  compare  plants  and  animals  anatomically  — 
were  afterwards  further  investigated  by  von  Baer  and  have  since  then  formed 
the  foundations  of  modern  embryology.  In  his  presentation  of  the  continued 
course  of  development  of  the  embryo,  however,  Pander  is  not  to  be  compared 
with  his  above-mentioned  contemporaries  and  he  was  unable  to  follow  up 
the  promising  ideas  that  he  had  produced  in  his  early  work.  A  work  Ver- 
gleichende  Osteologie,  which  he  published  as  an  edition  de  luxe  in  collaboration 
with  the  artist  d' Alton  during  his  visit  to  Germany,  and  which  attracted 
the  attention  of  Goethe,  has  not  the  same  interest  as  his  embryological 
works,  and  upon  his  return  home  he  divided  his  genius  between  a  number 


MODERNBIOLOGY  3  69 

of  small  tasks,  the  results  of  which  have  not  attracted  the  attention  of  pos- 
terity. There  was  created,  however,  by  the  scientists  described  above,  a  new 
branch  of  comparative  morphology,  which  proved  of  the  greatest  impor- 
tance for  the  development  of  biology  in  general,  in  that  it  made  possible 
a  far  more  universal  and  extensive  study  of  the  organ  in  living  creatures  than 
had  been  conceivable  before,  embracing  not  only  the  present  characteristics 
of  the  organs,  but  also  their  evolutional  history,  thus  proving  not  only  a 
morphological,  but  also  a  morphogenetical  subject  of  research.  From  this 
period  we  can  also  consider  that  the  advent  of  comparative  anatomy  in  the 
modern  sense  dates,  and  its  development  during  the  succeeding  decades,  es- 
pecially in  Germany,  was  splendid.  It  was  this  line  of  research  that  really 
dominated  biological  science  in  that  country  during  the  greater  part  of  the 
nineteenth  century.  But  it  was  certainly  not  merely  the  embryological  dis- 
coveries that  produced  this  fresh  impetus.  In  other  spheres,  too,  there  opened 
up  for  biological  research,  as  a  result  of  new  methods  and  new  facts,  vistas 
of  an  extent  hitherto  unknown.  In  particular,  there  were  two  methods,  al- 
ready previously  known,  it  is  true,  but  not  sufficiently  appreciated  by  the 
immediately  preceding  generation,  which  were  adopted  at  this  period  with 
renewed  interest  and  considerable  improvements,  and  which  produced  re- 
sults that  fundamentally  reformed  the  views  on  life-phenomena  —  namely, 
the  experimental  method  and  microscopy. 


CHAPTER    VI 

THE     DEVELOPMENT     OF     EXPERIMENTAL    RESEARCH     AND     ITS 
APPLICATION     TO     COMPARATIVE     BIOLOGY 

The  development  of  organic  chemistry 

IN  THE  PREVIOUS  SECTION  it  has  been  pointed  out  that  during  the  eighteenth 
century  the  experimental  method  was  applied  with  great  success  both  in 
animal  and  in  vegetable  biology;  names  such  as  Haller  and  Spallanzani, 
Hales  and  Ingenhousz  are  sufficient  proof  of  this.  During  the  reign  of  roman- 
tic natural  philosophy,  conditions  were  diff"erent;  the  representatives  of  that 
school,  who  imagined  that  they  could  solve  all  the  riddles  of  existence  by 
speculation,  deeply  scorned  experiment,  which  they  considered  led  to  noth- 
ing but  fruitless  artifice.  Indeed,  the  physiological  works  which  saw  the 
light  during  this  epoch  are  for  the  most  part  purely  speculative  or  else  de- 
voted to  morphological  problems.  Gradually,  however,  reason  came  into 
its  own  even  in  this  sphere;  the  immense  success  which  the  experimental 
method  brought  to  contemporary  physics  and  chemistry  induced  attempts 
at  applying  that  method  also  to  biology.  And  this  all  the  more  so  as  during 
the  immediately  preceding  period  eminent  scientists  had  begun  to  apply 
themselves  with  considerable  success  to  the  study  of  the  chemical  composi- 
tion of  living  organisms.  A  glance  at  the  development  that  had  taken  place 
in  that  branch  of  chemistry  may  therefore  not  be  out  of  place  in  this  con- 
nexion. 

Carl  Wilhelm  Scheele,  mentioned  in  the  previous  section  as  a  pioneer 
in  gas  chemistry,  is  worthy  to  be  called  the  founder  also  of  animal  and  vege- 
table chemistry.  German  in  origin  and  upbringing  —  he  was  born  at  Stral- 
sund  in  ij^i.  —  in  his  youth  he  adopted  the  profession  of  apothecary  in 
Sweden,  finally  settling  at  Koping,  a  small  town,  where  he  died  in  1786. 
During  a  brief  life  spent  in  very  poor  circumstances  he  managed  to  carry 
out  unusually  fruitful  research  work.  As  one  part  of  his  work  it  may  be 
mentioned  that  he  subjected  to  a  more  thorough  chemical  revision  than  any- 
one had  done  before  him  elements  from  the  animal  and  vegetable  kingdom; 
among  the  results  he  obtained  was  the  discovery  of  lactic  acid,  cyanuric  acid, 
hydrocyanic  acid,  and  uric  acid,  and,  further,  glycerine,  citric  acid,  and  malic 
acid,  not  to  mention  other  equally  important  elements.  Lavoisier,  it  will  be 
remembered,  also  studied  phenomena  in  the  animal  and  vegetable  kingdoms. 
A  successor   to  him  was   Antoine  pRANgois  de  Fourcroy  (175 5-1 809). 

370 


H 

P 
hJ 
O 
« 

O 

> 

w 
Q 

< 
X 

w 
1-1 

<5 


H 
O 

o 

o 
z 

0 
(J 

o 

o 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  371 

Brought  up  in  poverty,  he  received  financial  aid  for  his  medical  studies 
from  Vicq  d'Azyr  and  when  still  a  young  man  became  a  professor  of  chem- 
istry. He  was  a  zealous  supporter  of  the  Revolution,  was  a  member  of  the 
famous  committee  of  public  safety,  and  eventually  became  director-general 
of  instruction.  In  a  handbook  that  he  wrote  on  chemistry,  Philosophie  chi- 
mique,  as  well  as  in  a  number  of  other  writings,  he  deals  exhaustively  with 
animal  chemistry;  the  so-called  "chemical  philosophy"  excited  consider- 
able attention  and  was  translated  into  several  languages.  In  this  work  an 
account  is  given  of  the  chemical  composition  of  plants  and  animals.  The 
essential  difference  between  substances  derived  from  the  vegetable  and  the 
animal  kingdom  is  claimed  to  be  the  latter's  azotic  content.  Vegetable  ele- 
ments are  divided  into  sixteen  separate  substances,  including  gum,  sugar, 
fatty  and  fugitive  oils,  resin,  etc.  The  elements  derived  from  the  animal  king- 
dom form  three  groups:  albumen,  lime,  and  fibrin;  characteristic  of  both 
the  vegetable  and  animal  kingdoms  arc  fermentative  processes  of  various 
kinds,  whereof  is  described  the  fermenting  of  wine  and  vinegar,  and  putre- 
faction. Besides  this  grouping  of  the  components  of  living  creatures, 
Fourcroy  has  given  us  the  results  of  a  large  number  of  valuable  special 
investigations  into  animal  substances:  milk,  blood,  gall,  serum,  and  others. 
His  services  have  been  fully  acknowledged  by  Berzelius,  who  was  the  great 
discoverer  in  this  sphere  as  much  as  he  was  in  chemistry  in  general. 

Jons  Jakob  Berzelius  was  born  in  1779  at  Vaversunda  in  Ostergotland, 
Sweden,  the  son  of  a  poor  priest.  Being  left  an  orphan  at  an  early  age,  he 
had  to  carry  out  his  studies  under  severe  privations,  first  of  all  earning  his 
living  by  private  teaching  and  practising  as  an  apothecary,  and  later,  hav- 
ing taken  the  degree  of  bachelor  of  medicine,  in  medical  practice.  In  1809  he 
became  a  doctor  of  medicine  and  obtained  an  appointment  as  doctor  at  the 
College  of  Surgery  in  Stockholm  (out  of  which,  thanks  mainly  to  his  ac- 
tivities, the  Carolinian  Institute  was  eventually  founded).  Here  he  had  a 
laboratory  in  which  he  was  able  to  apply  himself  to  those  chemical  investi- 
gations which  in  a  few  years  were  to  bring  him  world-wide  fame.  An  un- 
rivalled capacity  for  work  made  it  possible  for  him,  apart  from  his  research 
and  literary  work,  to  devote  himself  to  a  large  number  of  public  duties  — 
thus,  he  became  permanent  secretary  to  the  Academy  of  Science,  whose  an- 
nual report  he  used  to  write  in  a  masterly  style  —  and  he  was  also  the  recipi- 
ent of  innumerable  honours  both  at  home  and  abroad.  Ill  health  weakened 
his  powers  during  the  last  years  of  his  life.  He  died  in  1848. 

Berzelius' s  animal  chemistry 
Berzelius's  work  as  the  creator  of  the  science  of  chemistry  in  general  is 
universally  known,  and  falls,  moreover,  outside  the  scope  of  this  history. 
In  actual  fact,  he  mastered  the  whole  of  chemistry  as  no  one  else  has  ever 
done  since  his  time,  and  he  created  something  new  in  all  the  spheres  in  which 


37i  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

he  worked.  One  of  his  most  important  contributions,  however,  is  his  inves- 
tigation of  the  substances  that  are  produced  by  life  on  the  earth.  In  his  Lec- 
tures on  Animal  Chemistry,  published  during  the  years  1806-8,  he  expounds 
his  conception  of  life-phenomena  in  general  and,  besides,  records  a  number 
of  fresh  facts  in  the  sphere  of  organic  analysis,  which  he  later  still  further 
augmented.  These  purely  chemical  investigations  into  the  composition  of 
blood,  gall,  milk,  bone,  fat,  and  many  other  elements,  really  belong  to  the 
science  of  chemistry  rather  than  to  biology;  although  they  exercised  a  fun- 
damental influence  on  the  knowledge  of  life  and  the  functions  of  the  living 
body  during  the  succeeding  period,  a  detailed  account  of  their  results  would 
hardly  be  in  place  here,  but  the  views  on  the  phenomena  of  life  which  Ber- 
zelius  formed  as  a  result  of  these  investigations  have  naturally  played  an 
important  part,  both  in  his  own  time  and  in  the  age  that  followed;  an  ac- 
count of  them  is  therefore  of  interest,  quite  apart  from  the  interest  always 
excited  by  ideas  expressed  by  one  of  the  great  pioneering  personalities  of 
the  world. 

As  sources  from  which  he  derived  his  view  of  the  phenomena  of  life 
Berzelius  mentions  first  of  all  the  works  of  Bichat  and  Fourcroy;  in  partic- 
ular, the  former's  explanation  of  the  tissues  of  the  body  and  their  functions 
formed  the  basis  of  his  entire  conception  of  life-phenomena.  Reil,  too,  con- 
tributed largely  thereto,  while  Fourcroy's  role  was  primarily  that  of  a  pre- 
cursor in  the  purely  chemical  sphere.  What  chiefly  distinguishes  Berzelius's 
general  conception  of  nature  from  the  conceptions  of  his  predecessors  is  his 
severe  criticism  of  and  opposition  to  any  kind  of  "hypothesis-mongering." 
While  contemporary  natural  philosophy  created  brilliant  thought-systems, 
Berzelius  introduces  his  "animal  chemistry"  with  the  words:  "I  have  every- 
where sought  to  avoid  hypothesis,  and  where  I  have  at  any  time  ventured 
to  make  insignificant  guesses,  they  are  all  of  such  a  nature  that  they  will 
soon  be  decided  by  experience.  I  prefer  to  say:  'This  is  entirely  unknown  to 
us,'  than  to  try  by  means  of  a  number  of  probabilities  to  gloze  over  a  gap 
in  our  knowledge." 

Berzelius  rejects  vitalism 
In  conformity  with  this  principle  he  rejects  the  vitalistic  theories  of  his 
age:  "Life  does  not  lie  in  any  extraneous  essence  deposited  in  an  organic 
or  living  body;  its  origin  must  be  sought  in  the  common  fundamental  forces 
of  primal  elements,  and  this  is  a  necessary  consequence  of  the  condition 
wherein  the  elements  of  the  living  body  are  combined."  And  further  on  he 
says:  "All,  therefore,  that  we  explain  with  the  words  ' oim  vitality^  is 
entirely  unexplained  and  it  is  an  illusion  if  they  are  given  any  other  meaning 
than  that  of  a  still  unknown  mechanico-chemical  process."  Even  the  func- 
tions of  the  soul  are  explained  in  the  same  way:  "Unreasonable  as  it  may 
seem  .  .  .  nevertheless,  our  judgment,  our  memory,  our  reflections,  as  well 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  373 

as  other  functions  of  the  brain,  are  organic  chemical  processes,  as  well  as, 
for  instance,  those  of  the  abdomen,  the  intestines,  the  lungs,  the  glands, 
etc.;  but  here  chemistry  rises  to  a  higher  plane,  where  our  spiritual  research 
can  never  reach  her."  Even  La  Mettrie  himself  has  never  expressed  himself 
more  clearly,  and  though  he  adds  in  a  note  on  materialism  that  "it  is  not 
in  accord  with  our  hope  and  our  practical  innate  feeling  regarding  the  im- 
mortality of  soul,"  yet,  in  view  of  what  has  been  said  above,  this  makes  but 
little  impression.  It  is  obvious  that  a  man  like  Israel  Hwasser  must  have  felt 
antipathy  for  the  man  and  the  university  whence  such  words  originated. 

When,  later,  it  becomes  a  question  of  applying  in  detail  the  mechani- 
cal theory  in  life,  Berzelius,  like  so  many  of  his  predecessors  and  successors, 
gives  way  to  the  temptation  to  simplify  too  much,  and  in  spite  of  his  honest 
endeavours  he  is  unable  to  free  himself  from  speculative  construction.  Under 
the  heading  "Principle  Components  of  the  Animal  Body"  he  declares  that 
"the  phenomena  of  animal  life  are  divided  into  two  systems,  the  nerves  and 
the  other  organs.  Life  is  really  placed  in  the  former,  and  through  them  the 
animal  lives  for  the  moment.  The  latter,  on  the  other  hand,  promote  those 
conditions  whereby  the  animal  is  to  live  in  the  immediate  future."  The  nerve 
system  thus  represents  the  essential  difference  between  organic  and  inorganic 
nature;  the  plants,  therefore,  must  also  possess  nerves,  although  they  are 
still  unknown.  This  contrast  between  the  nervous  system  as  the  real  con- 
servator of  life  and  the  other  organs,  which  are  called  instrumental  organs, 
is  just  as  unnatural  as  Bichat's  theory  of  the  two  lives,  which  Berzelius 
criticizes,  and  the  idea  that  life  cannot  exist  except  in  a  nervous  system  is 
still  more  unfortunate.  The  functions  of  the  nervous  system  are,  according 
to  Berzelius,  unknown,  and  he  utters  a  serious  warning  against  adducing 
electrical  and  other  forces  to  explain  what  one  does  not  understand.  He  has 
only  vague  ideas  of  the  structure  of  the  brain  and  the  nerves;  he  takes  no 
account  of  Malpighi's  microscopical  discoveries  and  Swedenborg's  appli- 
cation of  them.  Moreover,  he  makes  a  number  of  unfelicitous  assertions 
regarding  the  vascular  system;  he  believes  that  the  capillaries  open  out  be- 
tween the  organs  and  that  the  latter  grow  up  as  a  result  of  a  stratification 
of  solid  matter  around  the  opening  —  "a  kind  of  crystallization."  In  this 
connexion  it  may  be  mentioned  that  he  believes  in  the  spontaneous  genera- 
tion of  lower  animals.  On  the  other  hand,  his  description  of  fertilization  is 
clear  and  definite;  he  frankly  acknowledges  the  inability  of  science  at  that 
time  to  explain  the  process,  and  his  ideas  on  the  development  of  the  tgg 
are  extraordinarily  clear,  considering  they  were  arrived  at  twenty  years  be- 
fore von  Baer's  epoch-making  discovery. 

Berzelius,  therefore,  cannot  be  said  to  have  been  a  very  deep  thinker  in 
the  sphere  of  theoretical  natural  science,  as  was  Galileo,  for  example,  but 
his  honest  and  modest  acknowledgment  of  the  limitations  of  natural  science 


374  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

and  his  opposition  to  any  kind  of  hypotheses  doubtless  to  a  great  extent 
cleared  the  atmosphere  in  a  generation  that  had  been  befogged  by  the  fan- 
tastic ideas  of  natural-philosophical  speculation,  all  the  more  so  as  he  cer- 
tainly possessed  all  the  authority  to  which  a  discoverer  of  the  highest  rank 
in  the  world  of  natural  phenomena  can  lay  claim.  His  pupils  were  numerous 
and  brilliant;  the  most  gifted  chemists  of  the  following  generation  received 
their  training  from  him  and  undoubtedly  they  disseminated  the  master's  aim 
to  try  to  establish  the  actual  phenomena  in  nature  without  any  "explana- 
tions by  means  of  qualitates  fere  occulta  ^ 

Experiments  on  live  animals 
The  experimental  research  of  which  an  account  has  been  given  above  con- 
cerned the  chemical  composition  of  the  various  organs.  But  the  functions 
of  the  organs  as  well  —  their  vital  manifestations,  each  separately  and  in 
collaboration  — ■  were  during  this  period  the  subject  of  radical  experimental 
investigations.  In  this  field  of  research  Haller  was  a  pioneer;  in  his  foot- 
steps there  followed  an  increasing  number  of  scientists  who  sought  by  means 
of  experiment  on  live  animals  —  that  is,  vivisections  —  to  ascertain  the 
course  of  events  in  animal  life,  both  in  the  isolated  organs  and  in  groups 
thereof,  to  an  ever-increasing  extent.  These  experiments  led  to  the  discovery 
that  the  actual  phenomena  of  life  were  themselves  bound  by  laws  to  an  extent 
hitherto  undreamt  of;  it  was  found  that  they  could  be  made  the  subject 
of  exact  research  just  like  the  chemical  and  physical  processes  in  inanimate 
nature.  As  pioneers  in  this  sphere  French  and  English  scientists  were  con- 
spicuous; in  Germany,  where  formerly  natural  philosophy  and  afterwards 
comparative  morphology  predominated,  the  representatives  of  experimental 
research  were  also  comparative  morphologists,  at  least  those  of  the  older 
generation,  wherefore  it  is  often  hard  to  decide  to  which  category  this  or 
that  scientist  rightfully  belongs. 

Charles  Bell  was  born  in  1774  in  the  neighbourhood  of  Edinburgh, 
the  son  of  a  country  parson.  Having  studied  in  circumstances  of  great  poverty 
and  taken  his  degree  at  Edinburgh  University,  he  came  as  a  doctor  to  London, 
where  he  rapidly  gained  a  great  reputation,  becoming  professor  of  surgery 
and  curator  of  the  Hunter  Museum,  mentioned  in  a  previous  section  of  this 
book.  In  his  later  years  he  returned  to  his  native  country  as  professor  of  anat- 
omy and  died  there  in  i84z.  He  enjoyed  a  universal  reputation  as  a  clever 
doctor,  a  distinguished  university  tutor,  and  a  warmly  religious  personality; 
he  was  the  recipient  of  an  extraordinary  number  of  honours.  As  a  scientific 
author  he  was  very  productive;  he  published  a  text-book  on  general  anatomy 
that  gained  a  wide  reputation,  and  also  a  large  number  of  papers  on  special 
subjects.  In  several  of  these  latter  his  Christian  piety  is  a  marked  feature, 
particularly  in  an  essay  on  the  structure  and  function  of  the  hand,  which 
represents  from  beginning  to  end  a  hymn  of  praise  to  the  wisdom,  power. 


MODERNBIOLOGY  375 

and  love  of  the  Creator.  What  chiefly  made  his  name  famous  to  later  genera- 
tions, however,  was  his  original  investigations  in  the  sphere  of  nerve- 
physiology.  Even  Galen  had  been  aware  that  some  nerves  had  to  do  with 
motion,  while  others  received  sense-impressions,  and  since  then  the  nervous 
system  had  been  investigated  by  innumerable  scientists  with  increasing  ac- 
curacy in  the  matter  of  detail.  But  there  still  remained  the  question  of  how 
the  nerves  running  from  the  spinal  marrow  can  act  as  intermediaries  be- 
tween not  only  motive  impulses,  but  also  sense-impressions;  to  this  question 
no  answ^er  had  been  given  or  else  only  very  unsatisfactory  ones.  Bell  recorded 
his  experiment  on  this  subject  in  a  brief  paper  entitled  Idea  of  a  Neiv  Anat- 
omy of  the  Brain.  He  had  a  few  copies  of  this  printed  in  1811  and  presented 
them  to  his  friends.  In  this  work  he  describes  how  he  severed  the  posterior 
root  of  a  medullary  nerve  without  causing  any  muscular  contraction,  whereas 
the  act  of  touching  the  anterior  root  caused  convulsions  in  the  muscles.  From 
this  he  concludes  that  the  medullary  nerves  have  a  double  function,  due  to 
their  double  roots.  The  idea,  however,  is  hinted  at  rather  than  followed  up, 
and  indeed  this  small  brochure  contains  several  similar  suggestions  —  re- 
garding the  specific  mental  energies,  a  problem  which  J.  Miiller  afterwards 
examined  thoroughly,  as  well  as  ideas  on  the  localizations  in  the  great  brain 
and  the  connexion  between  them,  an  inquiry  which  at  the  time  held  wide 
possibilities.  During  the  next  decade,  however,  Bell  did  not  follow  the  line 
he  had  opened  up,  with  the  result  that  others  got  in  advance  of  him,  es- 
pecially Magendie  in  Paris.  Nevertheless,  Bell's  work  received  high  praise 
later  on,  which  it  deserves  without  a  doubt. 

Francois  Magendie  was  born  in  1785  at  Bordeaux,  where  his  father 
was  a  surgeon.  He  went  to  Paris  to  study  medicine,  and  after  studying  in 
great  poverty  and  anxiety  and  having  successfully  passed  his  examinations,  he 
became  prosector  at  the  anatomical  institute,  then  a  hospital  doctor,  and 
finally  a  professor  at  the  College  de  France,  where  he  worked  with  immense 
success  as  a  lecturer,  gathering  a  number  of  distinguished  pupils  around  him. 
He  systematically  originated  the  method  of  ascertaining  the  vital  phenomena 
by  operations  performed  on  live  animals,  thereby  exciting  both  admiration 
and  disgust  amongst  his  contemporaries;  the  sensitive  Rudolphi  mentions 
his  experiments  with  horror,  and  his  notorious  ruthlessness  has  even  gone 
down  to  posterity.  Perhaps  this  has  been  exaggerated  owing  to  his  manners 
towards  his  fellow  men;  his  manners  were  rough  and  his  self-esteem  and 
scorn  for  the  opinions  of  others  often  reached  outrageous  heights.  But  if 
he  was  hard  on  others,  he  did  not  spare  himself;  when  for  the  first  time 
cholera  raged  in  Paris,  he  voluntarily  undertook  the  task  of  ministering  to 
the  sick  among  the  poorest  of  the  population,  defying  both  the  risk  of  in- 
fection and  the  fanaticism  of  the  populace,  who  believed  that  the  doctors 
had  caused  the  disease  by  poisoning  the  drinking-water.   Magendie  was 


376  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

active  both  as  a  doctor  and  as  a  research-worker  until  the  time  of  his  death, 
which  took  place  in  1855. 

Magendie' s  criticism  of  contemporary  vitalism 
Even  in  his  earliest  writings  Magendie  appeared  as  a  keen  opponent  of 
Bichat's  vitalism,  and  the  whole  of  his  subsequent  work  turns  on  his  insist- 
ence on  the  possibility  and  the  necessity  of  applying  to  the  phenomena  of 
life  the  laws  that  hold  good  in  physics  and  chemistry,  and,  in  connexion 
therewith,  the  experimental  method  that  brought  these  sciences  such  suc- 
cess. But  he  also  possessed  from  the  very  outset  a  keen  eye  for  the  limitations 
of  that  method;  he  repeatedly  declares  that  it  is  not  possible  to  explain  all 
life-phenomena  merely  as  physical  and  chemical  processes.  The  life-mani- 
festations of  the  nervous  system  in  particular  are  called  by  him  "vital"  and 
are  excepted  from  the  mode  of  thought  that  he  applies  to  other  life-processes. 
These  vital  phenomena  are  to  his  mind  inexplicable  for  the  very  reason  that 
the  physical-chemical  principles  cannot  be  applied  to  them;  simply  to  invent 
on  their  account  a  number  of  theories  of  a  speculative  kind  he  considers  to 
be  harmful;  he  hopes  rather  that  in  future  the  exact  method  will  be  appli- 
cable also  to  as  much  as  possible  of  this  field  of  research,  for  that  method 
alone,  he  says,  can  produce  results  of  lasting  value.  He  would  take  as  the 
basis  of  his  research  the  method  that  was  created  by  Galileo  and  perfected 
by  Newton  — •  "  to  observe  and  to  question  nature  by  means  of  experiment." 
Among  his  predecessors  in  the  biological  sphere  he  names  first  of  all  Borelli, 
whose  previously  described  investigations  into  the  mechanism  of  animal 
movements  he  cites  with  admiration  and  pursued  still  further.  He  applies 
the  same  mechanical  idea  especially  to  the  respiration  and  the  circulation 
of  the  blood,  at  the  same  time  endeavouring  to  take  as  full  advantage  as 
possible  of  the  progress  made  by  chemistry  during  his  age.  In  doing  so  he 
came  into  constant  disagreement  with  Bichat,  whose  theory  of  the  independ- 
ent life-manifestations  of  the  various  organs  he  desired  to  replace  as  far  as 
possible  by  purely  mechanical  processes  such  as  could  be  confirmed  by  ex- 
periment or  observation.  He  considers  hypotheses  in  general  to  be  useless; 
facts  alone  have  any  scientific  value  and  what  cannot  be  explained  with  their 
aid  must  for  the  time  being  remain  unexplained.  This  scepticism,  which  he 
pursues  with  absolute  consistency,  undoubtedly  proved  a  useful  counter- 
balance to  the  unbridled  speculation  of  preceding  periods.  True,  even  his 
criticism  could  sometimes  lead  him  astray,  as  when  he  accepts  Spallanzani's 
assertion  that  the  spermatozoa  play  no  part  in  fertilization,  and  yet  doubts 
von  Baer's  discovery  of  the  egg  in  mammals;  but  on  the  whole  his  concep- 
tion of  nature  is  both  sound  and  keen-sighted.  It  rests,  too,  on  a  broad  basis; 
although  it  is  the  vital  manifestations  of  the  human  body  that  he  studied 
most  carefully,  nevertheless  he  makes  constant  reference  to  other  animal 
forms  and  he  supplements  his  text-book  on  physiology  with  a  systematic 
survey  of  the  entire  animal  kingdom. 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  377 

Magendie's  greatest  service  to  biology,  however,  is  not  on  the  theo- 
retical side,  useful  though  his  criticism  of  his  contemporaries'  hypotheti- 
cal ideas  v^as;  his  most  valuable  positive  contribution  was  without  doubt 
the  experimental  technique  that  he  created.  In  working  it  out  he  took 
advantage  of  experiences  gained  from  methods  of  physics  and  chemistry  as 
well  as  from  those  of  surgery  and  internal  medicine,  thereby  originating  an 
experimental  procedure  that  even  to  this  day  forms  the  basis  of  the  method 
of  research  in  physiology.  He  employs  it  in  a  number  of  important  processes 
in  the  higher  animal  life,  especially  in  connexion  with  the  phenomena  of 
circulation  and  resorption.  To  both  these  studies  he  successfully  applied  his 
mechanical  system  of  thought;  to  him  the  circulatory  apparatus,  as  also  the 
respiratory  system,  was  a  mechanism,  the  operation  of  which  should  be  cal- 
culable, and  indeed  was  partly  calculated  by  him.  With  regard  to  resorption, 
he  took  advantage  of  Dutrochet's  then  recent  discovery  of  the  osmotic 
processes.  Magendie's  investigations  into  the  nervous  processes,  however, 
brought  him  the  greatest  fame;  independently  of  Bell  he  took  up  the  prob- 
lem of  the  roots  of  the  medullary  nerve,  studying  it  both  experimentally  and 
theoretically,  with  far  greater  attention  to  detail  than  his  predecessor.  He 
actually  claimed  as  his  own  the  discovery  of  the  physiology  of  the  sensory 
and  motor  nerve-roots,  and  if  by  this  is  meant  thorough  investigation  into 
the  subject,  he  is  no  doubt  justified  in  his  claim.  Bell,  however,  appeared 
once  more  and  maintained  his  old  claims;  this  led,  as  usual,  to  a  not  very 
edifying  controversy  between  Magendie  and  his  predecessor.  As  a  matter 
of  fact,  the  contrast  between  them,  as  far  as  regards  their  general  concep- 
tions of  nature,  was  as  wide  as  it  could  possibly  be  — ■  Bell  looking  to  the 
glory  of  God  in  his  scientific  results,  and  Magendie  refusing  to  accept  any 
other  explanation  of  nature  than  the  purely  mechanical.  In  actual  fact,  both 
have  performed  considerable  services  in  the  sphere  mentioned  —  Bell  in  hav- 
ing been  the  first  to  determine  the  bearing  of  the  problem  and  to  establish 
the  different  functions  of  the  two  nerve-roots  in  the  medulla,  and  Magendie 
in  having  dealt  with  the  problem  experimentally  throughout  and  established 
the  fact  in  all  its  details.  Bell  is  said  to  have  been  deterred  by  the  painful- 
ness  of  the  experiment  from  pursuing  it  beyond  establishing  the  above- 
mentioned  fact  in  the  case  of  one  live  subject;  Magendie  on  the  other  hand, 
who  had  no  qualms  on  that  score,  carried  out  the  investigation  from  as 
many  sides  as  possible. 

Magendie  gathered  round  him  several  distinguished  pupils.  Among  these 
may  be  mentioned  Marie  Jean  Pierre  Flourens  (i  794-1 867),  who  continued 
his  master's  work  in  the  sphere  of  nerve-physiology,  besides  making  valu- 
able contributions  to  the  knowledge  of  the  function  of  the  skin  and  several 
other  organic  systems.  Chief  among  French  physiologists,  however,  must 
be  named  Claude  Bernard.  He  was  born  at  Saint-Julien,  near  the  Rhone,  in 


378  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

1 8 13,  of  poor  peasant  parents,  but  through  the  kindness  of  a  priest  was  given 
an  opportunity  of  studying.  For  a  time  he  served  as  an  apothecary's  appren- 
tice at  Lyons,  afterwards  trying  his  hand  at  literature,  but  eventually  he 
devoted  himself  to  medical  studies,  which  he  completed  in  Paris  under  great 
privations.  He  was  saved  from  the  necessity  of  having  to  seek  a  living  as  a 
country  doctor  by  Magendie,  who  discovered  his  brilliant  genius  and  made 
him  his  assistant.  After  holding  a  number  of  other  posts  he  became  his  mas- 
ter's successor,  but  in  his  old  age  exchanged  that  appointment  for  a  profes- 
sorship at  the  Jardin  des  Plantes.  He  had  to  carry  out  his  experiments  for  a 
great  number  of  years  in  chilly  and  damp  premises,  with  the  result  that  he 
contracted  an  illness  that  prevented  him  from  doing  any  practical  work  for 
about  ten  years.  Instead  he  spent  this  period  of  his  life  in  literary  work  on 
subjects  in  the  theoretical  sphere,  his  writings  being  very  highly  thought 
of.  Finally  he  succumbed  to  his  illness  in  1878.  During  the  last  years  of  his 
life  he  enjoyed  a  brilliant  reputation;  he  was  the  recipient  of  many  high 
distinctions,  both  at  home  and  abroad,  and  his  funeral  was  undertaken  at 
the  expense  of  the  French  Government.  A  competent  judge  (Chr.  Loven) 
declared  at  his  death  that  the  greatest  physiologist  of  the  age  had  passed 
away,  and  subsequent  generations  have  not  challenged  that  judgment.  And 
he  was  no  less  great  as  a  personality;  he  was  of  a  warm-hearted  and  modest 
nature,  and  at  the  same  time  a  brilliant  writer  and  an  eloquent  speaker.  His 
experiments  were  carried  out  in  less  brutal  fashion  than  Magendie's,  but 
they  w^ere  as  deeply  thought  out  and,  if  possible,  even  richer  in  results  than 
the  latter's. 

Bernard's  theoretical  conception 
As  will  have  been  seen  from  the  above,  Bernard's  research  work  comprises 
not  only  a  series  of  experimental  investigations,  but  also,  during  the  latter 
years  of  his  life,  a  collection  of  theoretical  speculations  upon  the  phenomena 
of  life.  He  had  already  formulated  his  theoretical  conceptions  in  their  main 
features  in  his  early  youth,  however,  and  throughout  his  life  worked  for 
the  creation  of  a  completely  elaborated  theory  of  life.  From  the  beginning 
he  rejects  as  emphatically  as  Magendie  the  vitalism  of  the  Bichat-Cuvier 
school,  though  he  is  not  content,  like  his  predecessor,  with  a  general  atti- 
tude of  scepticism,  but  endeavours  to  analyse  the  problem  of  what  life  really 
is.  Here  he  arrives  at  the  conclusion  that  it  is  not  possible  to  define  what 
life  is,  but  only  to  analyse  its  manifestations  —  that  is,  Galileo's  principle. 
He  groups  the  manifestations  of  life  under  the  following  headings:  "Or- 
ganisation, Generation,  Nutrition,  Evolution."  Of  these  he  finds  the  last  to  be 
both  the  most  characteristic  of  life  and  the  most  difficult  to  explain  from 
the  purely  mechanical  point  of  view;  the  development,  out  of  an  egg,  of  an 
individual,  all  of  whose  parts,  both  large  and  small,  are  produced  in  regular 
sequence  and  in  definite  likeness  to  its  parents'  —  it  is  that,  he  thinks,  which 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  379 

mostly  distinguishes  living  from  dead  matter.  But,  all  the  same,  it  is  not  to 
be  supposed  that  living  creatures  and  their  organs  are,  as  Bichat  imagined, 
independent  for  their  functions  of  the  laws  of  inorganic  nature;  on  the  con- 
trary, heat  and  cold,  electricity  and  chemical  reagents  exercise  a  law-bound 
influence  on  them  just  as  they  do  on  dead  matter.  But  vital  phenomena  defi- 
nitely differ  from  the  processes  of  inorganic  change  on  account  of  their  con- 
stant alternation  of  regeneration  and  dissolution,  of  building  up  and  breaking 
down.  This  relation  between  the  vital  phenomena  and  the  general  physio- 
chemical  conditions  that  govern  them  Bernard  calls  "determinism,"  a  term 
that  he  would  substitute  for  "vitalism"  and  "materialism,"  both  of  which 
he  rejects.  For  in  contrast  to  Magendie  he  considers  hypotheses  and  theories 
useful  to  science;  they  possess,  it  is  true,  little  real  value,  but  they  are  never- 
theless inevitable,  "for  in  every  science  it  is  impossible  to  proceed  from  a 
known  fact  to  an  unknown  fact  without  the  aid  of  an  abstract  idea  or  the- 
ory." And  yet  the  general  view  of  life  is  the  business  of  the  research-worker 
himself;  "no  one  asks  whether  Harvey  or  Haller  were  spiritualists  or  mate- 
rialists; we  only  know  that  they  were  great  physiologists,  and  it  is  their 
observations  and  experiments  that  have  been  handed  down  to  posterity." 
Bernard  thus  sought  to  compromise  between  the  sheer  unimaginative  estab- 
lishing of  facts,  and  speculation  that  in  its  efforts  to  create  a  general  theory 
of  existence  loses  sight  of  those  fundamental  realities  which  form  the  vital 
conditions  of  all  natural  science. 

His  investigations  into  nutrition 
Bernard's  fame,  however,  does  not  by  any  means  rest  primarily  on  the  theo- 
retical view  of  life  that  he  propounded.  It  is  as  a  practical  pioneer  in  the 
sphere  of  experimental  biology  that  he  has  acquired  so  great  a  name.  His 
investigations  have  especially  aimed  at  following  up  the  process  of  nutri- 
tion and  metabolism  in  the  animal  body,  and  the  result  he  attained  created 
in  many  respects  an  entirely  new  conception  of  them.  In  particular,  he 
showed  clearly  for  the  first  time  the  function  of  the  liver  in  the  process  of 
digestion;  he  established  the  percentage  of  sugar  in  the  liver  and  studied  the 
conditions  under  which  this  secretion  takes  place.  Likewise,  entirely  new 
light  was  thrown  by  him  on  the  part  played  by  the  liver  in  the  body's 
economy  in  general;  the  liver  is  characterized  by  him  as  " un  veritable  labora- 
toire  vital."  Whereas  after  the  discovery  of  the  lymphatic  system  the  liver 
was  considered  to  be  merely  an  organ  for  the  preparation  of  bile,  Bernard 
found  that  a  number  of  substances  from  the  intestine  are  conveyed  through 
the  cystic  vein  and  are  transformed  there.  Thus,  thanks  to  him,  the  knowl- 
edge of  the  absorption  of  nourishment  in  the  digestive  canal  was  placed  on 
a  new  basis.  In  connexion  with  this  subject  Bernard  studied  the  production 
of  sugar  in  the  human  body  and  in  animal  bodies  in  general.  He  established 
the  fact  that  a  stab  in  the  medulla  oblongata  of  an  animal  causes  diabetes  —  a 


380  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

fact  that  now  bears  his  name  and  laid  the  foundations  of  our  knowledge  of 
that  disease.  Further,  Bernard  found  out  the  function  of  the  pancreatic  juice 
in  the  process  of  digestion,  investigated  the  function  of  the  vasomotor  nerves 
and  the  problem  of  heat-production  in  animals,  and,  finally,  carried  out  a 
great  deal  of  important  work  in  the  sphere  of  pathology  —  for  instance,  in 
regard  to  the  effect  of  poisons  —  all  contributions  of  the  greatest  signifi- 
cance to  the  development  of  biology. 

Whereas  in  France,  then,  the  experimental  method  as  applied  to  biology 
was  used  for  the  purpose  of  finding  out  purely  physical  and  chemical  phe- 
nomena in  living  creatures,  in  Germany  the  same  method  had  a  somewhat 
different  application;  to  begin  with,  it  had  to  serve  the  purposes  of  the  purely 
speculative  philosophy  that  was  still  exercising  a  dominating  influence  at 
the  time  and  was  later  on  practised  in  connexion  with  comparative  anatomy, 
being  aided  by  the  use  of  the  microscope.  This  co-operation  had  brilliant 
results;  a  new  direction  was  given  to  biology,  which  placed  Germany  in 
the  first  rank  among  the  centres  of  research  in  that  science.  We  shall  now 
proceed  to  give  an  account  of  the  most  important  of  the  representatives  of 
this  school. 

Johannes  Evangelista  Purkinje  was  born  in  1787  at  Lobkowitz,  in 
Bohemia,  of  Czech  parents.  His  father,  who  was  a  bailiff  on  an  estate,  died 
early,  but  through  his  mother's  efforts  the  boy  became  a  pupil  at  a  theo- 
logical college,  where  he  learnt  German  and  general  school-subjects,  and 
for  three  years  devoted  himself  to  theology;  shortly  before  he  was  to  be 
ordained,  however,  he  relinquished  this  career  and  began  studying  philos- 
ophy and  medicine  at  Prague.  His  dissertation  was  on  the  subject  of  sight 
and  was  influenced  by  Goethe's  Farbenlehre,  with  the  result  that  it  attracted 
the  interest  of  the  poet;  through  the  latter's  influence  Purkinje,  who  had 
sought  in  vain  to  procure  a  situation  in  his  own  country,  was  invited  by 
the  Prussian  Government  to  become  professor  in  physiology  at  Breslau  in 
the  year  182.3.  '^^^  faculty  had  recommended  another  for  the  appointment, 
so  that  from  the  beginning  Purkinje  found  himself  in  a  difficult  position, 
which  was  still  further  complicated  by  the  fact  that  he  was  not  a  good  lec- 
turer, probably  owing  to  his  having  a  poor  ear  for  German.  For  many  years 
he  worked  and  struggled  to  get  a  physiological  institute  of  his  own,  and 
eventually,  having  overcome  the  opposition  of  his  superiors  and  colleagues, 
especially  his  lifelong  enemy  the  professor  in  anatomy,  he  was  able  to  open 
the  institute  in  1840  —  the  first  of  its  kind  in  Germany,  and  very  modestly 
equipped.  Hitherto  Purkinje  had  had  to  carry  out  his  experiments  in  his 
own  home,  the  comforts  of  which  he  had  for  many  years  sacrificed  to  the 
ends  he  desired  to  achieve.  From  here  emerged  a  number  of  pioneer  works 
in  various  spheres  of  biology,  performed  by  himself  and  the,  in  part,  very 
distinguished  pupils  he  had  gathered  around  him.  After  the  completion  of 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  381 

the  institute  Purkinje's  interest  in  science  began  to  wane;  instead  he  applied 
himself  more  and  more  to  his  country's  culture  and  politics.  Even  in  Breslau 
he  appeared  as  an  author  in  the  Czech  language,  translating  the  poems  of 
Schiller  and  Goethe  into  his  native  tongue.  Having  been  called  to  Prague  in 
1850,  he  devoted  himself  heart  and  soul  to  the  national  cause;  he  now  spelt 
his  name  Jan  Purkyne;  he  worked  hard  for  the  founding  of  a  purely  Czech 
university  and  was  a  member  of  the  Young  Czech  party  in  the  Bohemian 
Diet.  National  and  foreign  honours  were  showered  upon  him;  and,  wor- 
shipped by  his  countrymen,  though  at  the  same  time  hated  by  the  Germans 
in  his  country,  he  laboured  indefatigably  to  a  great  old  age.  He  died  in  1869. 

Purkinj".' s  discoveries 
PuRKiNjE  is  one  of  the  great  geniuses  in  the  field  of  biological  discovery; 
a  great  number  of  facts  of  the  highest  value  to  our  knowledge  of  life  have 
become  known  through  him.  On  the  other  hand,  he  never  systematically 
and  thoroughly  investigated  any  particular  field  of  inquiry,  nor  did  he  dis- 
cuss theoretical  problems.  Even  his  greatest  work,  his  investigations  into 
the  physiology  of  the  senses,  is  really  only  a  collection  of  different  experi- 
ments and  observations  without  any  connexion  other  than  the  organ  with 
which  they  deal.  His  experiments  on  sight-physiology,  the  ideas  for  which, 
as  mentioned  above,  he  obtained  from  Goethe's  FarbenleJore,  and  which,  in 
fact,  are  dedicated  to  the  poet,  represent  a  work  of  fundamental  importance 
in  their  sphere.  They  were  carried  out  with  extraordinarily  well-trained  and 
keen  powers  of  observation  and  a  corresponding  gift  for  experiment.  Visual 
sensations  induced  by  mechanical  influence,  by  galvanic  current,  by  various 
kinds  of  light-impressions,  are  described  and  analysed;  especially  well  known 
are  the  chapters  ' '  Indirektes  Seben ' '  and  ' '  Wabre  und  scbeitibare  Bewegungen  in 
der  Gesicbtssfbdre" ;  famous,  too,  is  the  venous  figure  named  after  him,  which 
is  caused  by  the  oblique  illumination  of  the  eye.  As  a  nicroscopist  Purkinje 
has  likewise  made  remarkable  discoveries,  among  which  should  be  men- 
tioned the  germinal  vesicle  in  the  chick,  discovered  two  years  before  von 
Baer  found  the  mammalian  tgg;  and,  further,  the  spiral  apertures  of  the 
sweat-glands  and  the  structure  of  cartilage.  Of  peculiar  interest  are  the  thor- 
ough investigations  into  the  existence  of  the  cilia  in  the  animal  kingdom; 
formerly  these  hairs  were  known  only  in  protozoa  and  molluscs.  Purkinje 
discovered  them  and  their  movement  in  the  oviduct  and  respiratory  duct  in 
vertebrates  —  he  established  the  movement's  independence  of  any  extra- 
neous force,  although,  not  yet  being  aware  of  the  nature  of  the  cell,  he  was 
unable  to  adduce  the  latter's  autonomous  life  as  a  cause  of  the  phenomenon. 
There  is  still  one  more  of  Purkinje's  discoveries  that  deserves  mention  here  — 
namely,  the  axis  cylinders  of  the  nerves,  and  the  large  ramified  cells  in  the 
cerebellum,  which  bear  his  name.  As  a  physiological  chemist  he  became 
known  for  his  investigations  into  the  effect  of  rennet  on  the  digestive 


38i  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

process.  There  are,  indeed,  still  several  of  his  discoveries  that  might  well 
be  referred  to  here  if  space  allowed. 

Contemporary  with  Purkinje  there  was  working  in  Germany  a  scien- 
tist who,  in  many  respects,  might  be  called  his  personal  antithesis,  but  who 
who  was  his  equal  in  importance  for  science. 

Johannes  Peter  Muller  was  born  in  1801  at  Coblenz,  on  the  Rhine, 
the  son  of  a  shoemaker.  He  was  of  a  well-to-do  family  and  was  able  to  indulge 
his  passion  for  study.  After  a  brilliant  career  at  school  he  went  to  Bonn, 
where  he  settled  down  to  the  study  of  medicine.  After  having  taken  his  doc- 
tor's degree  he  spent  three  terms  in  Berlin,  where  he  was  welcomed  with 
paternal  kindness  by  Rudolphi  and  received  impressions  that  proved  a  de- 
cisive factor  in  his  further  development.  Having  returned  to  Bonn,  he  became, 
first,  lecturer  and  afterwards,  in  1830,  professor  at  that  university.  When 
Rudolphi  died  and  the  question  of  his  successor  arose,  Muller  submitted  a 
letter  to  the  Prussian  Minister  of  Education  in  which  he  applied  for  the  ap- 
pointment, at  the  same  time  drawing  up  an  ambitious  program  for  his  future 
work.  He  was  accordingly  appointed  and  held  the  professorship  until  his 
death,  in  1858.  Both  as  a  teacher  and  as  a  scientist  he  worked  with  unique 
success;  the  circle  of  pupils  he  gathered  around  him  has  few  parallels  in  the 
history  of  science,  as  regards  both  results  and  the  fame  to  which  many  of 
them  attained.  Muller  began  by  devoting  himself  to  experimental  and  mi- 
croscopical research;  it  was  he  who  introduced  experimental  physiology  into 
Germany,  and  his  services  to  microscopy  were  of  no  small  value.  During  his 
later  years  he  applied  himself  chiefly  to  comparative  anatomy  and  evolution, 
and  in  connexion  therewith  to  marine  research,  which  had  first  been  taken 
up  by  Rathke.  For  this  latter  purpose  he  visited  both  the  Mediterranean 
and  the  Scandinavian  coasts,  everywhere  enriching  biology  with  his  valu- 
able observations.  The  violent  exertions  demanded  by  this  many-sided 
activity  had,  however,  told  upon  not  only  his  bodily  powers,  but  also  his 
mind;  anxieties  of  a  practical  nature  also  further  weakened  his  health.  He 
was  University  Warden  during  the  years  of  the  Revolution  of  1848  and,  being 
a  conservative,  came  into  repeated  conflict  with  the  revolutionary-minded 
students.  Some  years  later  he  was  in  a  serious  shipwreck,  which  cost  the 
life  of  one  of  his  friends.  These  events  seemed  to  have  proved  too  much  for 
his  powers.  Ever  since  his  youth  his  personality  had  been  a  curious  com- 
bination of  nervous  unrest,  proud  egotism,  and  deep  melancholy;  the  last 
gained  the  upper  hand  according  as  his  worries  increased  and  his  powers 
declined.  One  morning  he  was  found  dead  in  his  bed  without  sickness's 
having  intervened;  a  common  rumour,  which  was  never  contradicted,  de- 
clares that  in  despair  he  laid  violent  hands  upon  himself. 

Johannes  Miiller's  scientific  career  may  be  said  to  be  typical  of  that  of 
contemporary  German  biology  in  general  —  it  begins  in  natural  philosophy 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  383 

and  ends  with  exact  research,  first  physiological  and  then  comparative 
anatomical.  From  childhood  Miiller  possessed  a  mobile  and  imaginative 
temperament;  he  had  a  tendency  to  hallucinations,  which  he  later  on  studied 
from  a  scientific  point  of  view,  and  the  education  he  received  at  Bonn  was 
well  adapted  to  develop  this  over-imaginative  side  of  him.  Among  his 
tutors,  it  is  worth  noting,  were  Nees  von  Esenbeck,  the  fantastic  botanist, 
who  has  previously  been  described,  and  the  Schellingian  Brandis.  His  dis- 
sertation for  his  doctor's  degree.  On  the  Relations  of  Numbers  in  connexion  with 
the  Movements  of  Animals,  is  also  entirely  in  the  spirit  of  Oken;'  here  one  may 
read,  amongst  other  things,  that  "bending  and  stretching  are  the  two  poles 
of  life,  the  former  resembling  the  closed  bud,  the  latter  the  opened  but  with- 
ered flower;  in  both  night  prevails,  but  between  them  moves  life."  In  his 
old  age  Miiller  is  said  to  have  destroyed  all  the  copies  of  this  fantastic  pro- 
duction that  he  could  lay  hands  on.  His  visit  to  Rudolphi  distinctly  cooled 
his  ardour  for  extravaganzas  of  this  sort,  while  the  reading  of  Berzelius  is 
said  to  have  had  an  even  deeper  influence  upon  him  in  this  respect.  Before 
he  entirely  abandoned  the  natural-philosophical  school,  however,  Miiller 
published  his  investigations  into  subjective  sense-perceptions,  which  were 
undoubtedly  the  finest  work  on  natural  science  produced  by  German  ro- 
mantic philosophy.  Like  Purkinje,  who  in  this  subject  was  his  predecessor, 
Miiller  takes  as  his  starting-point  Goethe's  colour-theory.  The  physical 
qualities  of  light  do  not  interest  him  at  all  and  he  accepts  the  theory  of 
light's  "primal  phenomena  (Urphanomeny  although  he  is  not  blind  to  its 
weaknesses;  what  attracted  him  to  Goethe  is  the  latter 's  observations  on  the 
subjectivity  of  the  sense-perceptions;  taking  these  as  his  starting-point, 
Miiller  builds  up  with  ample  material  derived  from  personal  observations 
his  general  theory  of  the  specific  forms  of  energy  of  the  sensory  organs.  He 
establishes  the  fact  that  every  sensory  organ  reacts  in  its  own  special  way 
towards  every  kind  of  irritation;  for  instance,  the  eye  through  light-impres- 
sions reacts  just  as  much  to  blows  and  electric  current  as  to  daylight;  on  the 
other  hand,  different  organs  of  sense  react  each  in  its  own  way  to  the  same 
irritation;  thus,  to  irritation  caused  by  electricity  the  eye  responds  through 
light-impressions,  the  ear  through  sound,  the  tongue  through  taste;  and 
finally  each  sensory  organ  can  express  its  individual  reaction  to  impressions 
from  within,  in  which  are  produced  "imaginary  sense-phenomena,"  or  what 
would  nowadays  be  called  hallucinations.  Through  these  facts  Miiller  has 
laid  the  foundations  of  experimental  sense-physiology,  which  has  been  so 
diligently  studied  in  modern  times;  thanks  to  his  extraordinary  powers  of 
observation  and  clearness  of  thought,  he  succeeded  in  doing  so  in  spite  of 
the  natural-philosophical  principles  on  which  his  research  was  based.  We 

^  A  German  resume  of  this  work  is  included  in  the  1812.  number  of  Oken's  Ish. 


384  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

find  here,  for  instance,  a  number  of  statements  quite  in  the  spirit  of  Goethe's 
speculations.  The  experimental  method  is  scornfully  rejected  —  Magendie's 
experiments  in  particular  are  the  object  of  adverse  criticism  —  and  the 
search  for  "divine  life  in  nature"  is  highly  commended.  The  function  of 
physiology  is  said  to  be  to  comprehend  the  phenomena  of  life,  not  from  the 
point  of  view  of  experience,  but  from  that  of  the  idea  of  life.  This  again  is  a 
proof  that  a  keen  observer  can  create  fresh  values  in  spite  of  a  weak  theoreti- 
cal standpoint.  Miiller's  propensity  for  observing  the  life-manifestation  of 
his  own  senses  was  really  unique,  but  the  danger  that  always  attends  such 
self-introspection  threatened  him  no  less;  his  nervous  system  was  shattered 
by  his  "fantastic  sense-observations"  and  he  fell  into  a  state  of  melancholy 
bordering  on  insanity.  Rest  and  careful  tending  restored  him,  it  is  true,  but 
he  gave  up  for  ever  these  "subjective"  researches  and  therewith  also  most  of 
the  natural  philosophy  upon  which  they  were  based.  We  may  say  that  this 
mental  disease  involved  the  downfall  of  natural  philosophy  in  Germany. 

J.  Mulle/s  experiments  on  sensory  and  ?notor  nerves 
MiJLLER,  indeed,  never  abandoned  his  idealistic  view  of  life,  but  his  natural 
research  was  now  based  on  the  principles  laid  down  by  Rudolphi  —  a 
comparative  study  of  the  phenomena  of  life  based  on  the  knowledge  of  their 
organs  in  different  animal  forms.  He  thus  took  up  for  renewed  investigation 
the  Bell-Magendie  experiments  on  the  sensory  and  motor  nerve-roots  and  he 
succeeded  in  finding  a  more  suitable  subject  for  investigation  than  his  pre- 
decessors; they  had  experimented  on  dogs  and  rabbits,  while  Miiller  had  re- 
course to  frogs,  which  are  of  a  more  enduring  nature  and  can  therefore  lend 
themselves  to  more  careful  observation.  Miiller  in  fact  essentially  widened 
the  knowledge  of  these  important  phenomena.  His  reinvestigations  have 
thrown  a  special  light  on  reflex  movements.  Another  field  of  study  that  par- 
ticularly interested  him  was  the  embryonic  development  of  the  sexual  or- 
gans, in  which  he  considerably  widened  the  field  discovered  by  Rathke  and 
von  Baer;  he  also  threw  considerable  light  on  the  knowledge  of  the  evolu- 
tion of  the  mesonephros  or  middle  kidney.  Further,  he  made  important 
observations  in  regard  to  the  glandular  systems  of  the  higher  animals;  in 
particular,  he  definitely  determined  the  glands'  character  of  closed  tubes 
without  connexion  with  the  blood-vessels.  He  embodied  the  whole  of  his 
knowledge  on  this  subject  in  his  Handbucb  der  Physiologie  des  Menschen,  the 
work  which  contains  the  clearest  exposition  of  his  general  biological  views 
and  which  became  the  authoritative  source  of  the  contemporary  conception 
of  life-phenomena,  which  held  good  up  to  the  advent  of  Darwinism. 

Miiller  introduces  his  physiology  with  some  general  observations  on 
the  essence  of  life,  which  show  how  deep  was  the  influence  that  natural 
philosophy  still  had  on  him,  even  after  he  had  broken  away  from  it.  He  is  a 
vitalist,  and  a  much  more  positive  one  than  Bichat,  for  instance,  who  really 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  385 

only  maintained  that  the  life-process  was  inexplicable  by  chemical  and 
physical  methods.  Miiller,  on  the  other  hand,  definitely  declares  that  there 
is  a  special  "organic  creative  force"  that  is  the  essential  condition  of  life. 
He  points  out  the  resemblance  between  his  theory  and  that  of  Stahl,  but 
with  this  difference,  that  Stahl  considered  the  conscious  soul  to  be  the 
condition  of  life,  whereas  Miiller  holds  that  the  consciousness  is  something 
apart  from  the  organic  creative  force;  the  latter  belongs  to  all  living  beings, 
while  the  consciousness,  "which  does  not  create  any  organic  products,  but 
only  ideas,"  is  found  only  in  the  higher  animals.  "This  rational  creative 
force  manifests  itself  in  each  animal  in  accordance  with  a  strict  law,  which 
the  nature  of  every  animal  requires";  it  exists  in  the  embryo  before  its  parts 
are  present  and  it  produces  these  parts.  "Der  Keim  ist  das  Ganze,  Potentia; 
bet  der  Entwicklung  des  Keimes  entstehen  die  integrierenden  Teile  desselben  Actu." 
Here,  apparently,  Aristoteleanism  recurs  word  for  word,  and  it  is  still  more 
conspicuous  in  Miiller's  constant  declaration  that  the  organization  of  the 
living  being  is  governed  by  finality.  "Die  organischen  Kdrper  unterscheiden  sich 
nicht  bloss  von  den  unorganischen  dutch  die  Art  ibrer  Zusammensetzung  aus  Elemen- 
ten,  sondern  die  bestdndige  Tdtigkeit,  welche  in  der  lebenden  organischen  Maferie 
u'irkf,  schafft  auch  in  den  Geset^en  eines  vernunffige?z  Planes  mit  Ztveckmdssigkeit, 
indem  die  Teile  xu^n  Zwecke  eines  Ganzen  angeordnet  tverden,  und  dies  ist  gerade, 
was  den  Organismus  auszeichnet ."  This  gives  the  gist  of  Miiller's  biological 
views;  among  the  details  it  may  further  be  pointed  out  that  he  emphatically 
maintained  the  immutability  of  both  species  and  genera,  as  well  as  of  other 
higher  systematical  categories  in  the  animal  and  vegetable  kingdom;  and 
again  that  he  holds  the  same  epigenesis  theory  as  C.  F.  Wolff,  whom  he 
greatly  admired,  that  he  believes  with  Rudolphi  that  intestinal  worms  are 
produced  by  spontaneous  generation,  and  lastly  that  he  considers  the  spon- 
taneous generation  of  the  Infusoria  can  be  neither  proved  nor  disproved. 

His  vitalisffi 
It  need  hardly  be  specially  pointed  out  that  this  organic  creative  force  is  a 
product  of  natural-philosophical  thought;  likewise,  it  will  at  once  be  realized 
that  it  in  no  way  helps  to  explain  the  course  and  connexion  of  the  vital 
functions.  We  might  apply  to  it  Galileo's  above-quoted  words  on  the 
omnipotence  of  God  as  a  ground  for  natural  phenomena:  that  one  can  derive 
from  it  anything  whatsoever  because  it  is  based  on  no  kind  of  necessity.  And 
as  a  characteristic  consequence  of  this  mode  of  thought  results  the  idea  of 
finality  as  a  law  governing  organic  evolution.  Miiller's  strong  insistence  upon 
the  complete  finality  of  the  organisms  is  no  doubt  connected  with  his  often 
expressed  religious  respect  for  nature,  but  he  arrives  at  no  explanation  of 
nature  in  that  direction;  science  indeed  has  always  striven  to  give  to  its 
conclusions  the  character  of  laws  of  necessity,  but  where  the  domination  of 
necessity  is  established,  there  is  no  room  for  finality;  no  one  has  commended 


386  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

the  finality  of  mathematical  conclusions,  however  useful  they  may  have  been 
to  science.  Miiller's  ideas,  however,  deserve  all  possible  attention;  there  is 
no  doubt  that  he  largely  created  the  standard  of  thought  which  prevailed  in 
biological  circles  up  to  the  appearance  of  the  origin-of-species  theory,  and 
from  which  the  opposition  to  that  theory  largely  recruited  its  forces.  At  any 
rate,  this  legacy  of  Miiller's  from  the  age  of  romantic  natural  philosophy 
certainly  had  its  influence  on  successive  generations;  it  even  crept  into  bio- 
logical theories  fairly  effectively,  although  in  a  roundabout  way,  during 
the  greatest  days  of  Darwinism. 

The  influence  of  Miiller's  physiological  text-book  has  been  all  the  greater 
because  its  special  section  contains  information  of  great  value  based  on  the 
results  of  his  own  original  research-work;  here  we  find  a  very  careful  and 
exhaustive  account  of  the  law  of  specific  mental  energies  to  which  we  have 
previously  referred,  and  here  are  explained  in  a  manner  unexcelled  by  his 
age  the  functions  of  the  nervous  system;  here  his  above-mentioned  investiga- 
tions on  that  subject  are  summarily  described.  Further  he  declares  that  the 
ganglion-cells  of  the  brain  perform  the  latter's  functions,  and  he  explains 
the  connexion  between  them.  Specially  noteworthy  in  this  respect  as  a 
summary  of  his  results  is  the  chapter  on  "Mechanik  des  Nervetiprinzips," 
wherein  his  keen  powers  of  observation  and  combination,  undisturbed  by 
any  philosophical  adjuncts,  are  very  conspicuous.  His  exposition  of  the 
alimental  and  vascular  systems,  as  well  as  of  the  sexual  organs,  is  very  fine, 
although  somewhat  brief. 

After  the  "text-book"  had  been  completed,  Miiller  gave  up  physiology. 
According  to  his  own  statement,  he  shared  Rudolphi's  dislike  of  experi- 
menting on  live  animals,  as  practised  by  Magendie  and  his  school,  and  his 
physiological  works  were  actually  based  very  largely  on  comparative  ana- 
tomical observations.  He  clearly  realized  that  physiology  could  not  be  carried 
any  further  in  this  way  and  he  consequently  went  over  entirely  to  compara- 
tive anatomy,  which  at  that  time  had  very  large  fields  of  inquiry  still  un- 
exploited.  Miiller  made  a  particularly  happy  choice  when  he  devoted  himself 
to  investigations  into  the  structure  of  the  lowest  Vertebrata.  Among  his 
works  on  this  subject  may  be  mentioned  his  monograph  on  the  lancet-fish, 
which  exhaustively  supplements  Rathke's  previously  mentioned  work  on 
that  animal.  But  in  connexion  with  this  group  special  mention  should  be 
made  of  his  monumental  work  on  the  skeleton-system,  muscles,  and  nerves 
of  the  Myxinoidei,  on  which  he  spent  nearly  ten  years.  He  took  up  for  study 
this  subject  of  the  most  primitive  group  in  the  order  of  Cyclostomi  because, 
as  he  says,  the  boundary  forms  in  a  class  are  the  most  interesting  in  that  they 
lose  a  good  deal  of  the  character  of  the  class  and  thereby  show  us  the  type 
of  the  class  in  its  most  simple  form.  The  work  contains  a  detailed  description, 
exemplary  in  its  accuracy,  of  the  said  organic  systems  in  the  Myxine  glutinosa 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  387 

and  its  African  related  types;  taking  that  as  a  starting-point  he  makes  a 
detailed  comparison  of  the  skeleton,  muscular  and  nervous  systems  of  all 
Vertebrata.  It  is  not  only  the  accuracy  of  this  work  that  has  made  it  a  stand- 
ard for  the  future;  but  the  method  itself — starting  from  special  inquiry, 
comparing  the  results  with  the  conditions  existing  in  the  related  types  of 
the  subject  and  thus  throwing  light  on  the  form-connexion  in  a  wider  or 
narrower  group  of  living  types  —  was  imitated  during  an  entire  period  and 
is  to  this  very  day  by  no  means  exhausted.  It  would  take  too  long  to  examine 
in  detail  the  result  recorded  by  Miiller  in  this  work;  certain  it  is  that  his 
successors  have  had  little  to  add  to  the  material  he  investigated,  while  the 
comparative  section  is  also  of  immense  value,  although  naturally  some  of  its 
conclusions  have  since  been  disproved.  Thus,  Miiller  adopts  the  theory  of 
the  cranium's  being  formed  of  vertebras;  though  he  deals  with  the  subject 
more  cautiously  than  either  Oken  or  Goethe,  his  conclusions  are  at  any  rate 
too  far-fetched  to  be  acceptable  in  modern  times. 

His  marine  research  work 
The  result  of  Miiller's  occupying  himself  with  these  marine  animals  was 
that  he  took  up  with  increasing  interest  marine  research  work;  through  his 
holiday  trips  to  Heligoland,  the  coasts  of  Scandinavia,  and  the  Mediterra- 
nean he  was  irresistibly  attracted  to  the  study  of  the  life  of  marine  animals, 
which  had  been  so  very  little  investigated  before.  In  this  field,  as  also  in 
that  of  anatomy,  he  became  a  pioneer.  A  long  series  of  extremely  important 
discoveries  in  the  sphere  of  marine  biology  is  due  to  him;  chief  among  these 
should  be  mentioned  a  great  number  of  the  larval  forms  of  worms,  Echino- 
dermata,  and  molluscs,  the  evolution  of  which  was  found  out  partly  by  him 
and  partly  by  others  who  followed  his  example  later  on;  further,  the  dis- 
covery of  that  curious  parasitical  mollusc,  the  Entoconcha,  whose  origin 
in  the  host,  a  holothurian,  he  was  nevertheless  unable  to  discover,  and  fur- 
thermore a  number  of  interesting  observations  on  the  life  and  evolution  of 
fishes.  He  is  thus  not  only  a  pioneer  in  marine  zoology  but  also  one  of  the 
greatest  in  that  field  that  the  world  has  ever  seen.  The  idea  of  special  stations 
for  the  study  of  this  type  of  life  was  vigorously  promoted  by  him,  while  at 
the  same  time  he  originated  a  good  deal  of  the  methodology  applied  in  work 
on  the  subject.  If  we  add  that  Miiller  also  followed  in  Cuvier's  footsteps  as 
a  palsozoologist  with  great  credit,  we  shall  have  given  a  picture,  however 
incomplete,  of  one  of  the  most  prolific  scientific  achievements  that  the  his- 
tory of  biology  has  to  record. 

Miiller  was  also  very  distinguished  as  a  teacher.  Few  biologists,  if  any, 
have  succeeded  in  gathering  around  them  so  many  incipient  scientists  of  the 
highest  rank.  One  of  the  most  eminent  of  these  has  declared  that  the  master 
never  taught  dogmas,  but  only  his  own  method.  The  pupils  had  themselves 
to  form  their  own  ideas;  only  the  method  and  the  results  achieved  were 


388  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

common  to  all.  This  explains  to  a  certain  extent  how  it  was  that  so  many- 
scientists  of  independent  and  original  thought  could  be  trained  in  this 
school,  men  such  as  Schwann  and  Virchow,  Henle,  Remak,  Kolliker,  Du 
Bois-Reymond  and  Helmholtz;  the  same  circumstance  may  also  explain  the 
widely  differing  lines  of  research  upon  which  they  entered,  but  it  naturally 
confirms  also  the  extraordinary  many-sidedness  of  the  master  himself.  Thus, 
microscopy  and  cytology  as  well  as  experimental  physiology  in  its  most 
strictly  limited  sense  were  here  developed  side  by  side.  We  shall  now  con- 
sider, to  begin  with,  the  development  of  the  two  first-mentioned  branches 
of  research. 


CHAPTER    VII 


MICROSCOPY      AND      CYTOLOGY 


Improvement  of  the  microscope 

As  HAS  BEEN  PREVIOUSLY  POINTED  OUT,  microscopical  rcseafch  had  a  pe- 
riod of  brilliant  success  in  the  seventeenth  century,  the  age  of  Mal- 
L  pighi  and  Leeuwenhoek.  Afterwards,  however,  this  method  made 
no  further  advance  for  more  than  a  hundred  years;  the  eighteenth  century 
certainly  produced  some  microscopists  of  importance,  such  as,  for  instance, 
Lieberkiihn,  but  on  the  whole  little  was  achieved  during  this  period  with 
the  aid  of  magnifying  apparatus.  The  reason  for  this  was  that  the  aforesaid 
scientists  of  the  seventeenth  century  and  their  contemporaries  did  all  that 
could  be  done  with  the  instruments  at  their  disposal;  microscopes  were  and 
remained  imperfect,  and  improvements  were  a  long  time  in  coming.  The  most 
serious  difficulty  lay  in  the  chromatic  aberration  of  the  lenses;  a  colourless 
object  seen  under  the  microscope  would  shimmer  with  all  the  colours  of  the 
rainbow,  a  fact  which  naturally  gave  rise  to  countless  misinterpretations  of 
the  objects  investigated.  To  procure  achromatic  glass,  free  from  this  fault, 
was  a  task  that  occupied  many  scientists  at  that  time;  Newton  himself  de- 
clared the  problem  to  be  insoluble.  Eventually  a  Swede,  Samuel  Klingen- 
STIERNA  (1698-1765),  professor  of  physics  at  Upsala,  succeeded  in  working 
out  how  the  achromatic  glass  should  be  made,  and  under  his  instructions  an 
English  mechanician,  Dollond,  constructed  the  first  achromatic  lenses.  It 
was  some  time,  however,  before  the  invention  could  be  utilized  for  microscop- 
ical purposes.  Among  those  who  in  the  beginning  of  the  nineteenth  century 
constructed  microscopes  with  achromatic  lenses  may  be  mentioned  the 
Frenchman  Chevalier  and  the  Italian  Amici;  the  latter's  microscopes  in 
particular  were  very  fine,  and  there  soon  arose  in  every  country  microscope- 
makers  who  produced  gradually  perfected  instruments.  The  year  1817  is 
named  as  that  in  which  Amici  demonstrated  his  first  achromatic  lens-sys- 
tem and  during  the  thirties  the  biological  institutions,  at  least  the  more  im- 
portant ones,  were  able  to  obtain  specimens  of  these  improved  microscopes. 
It  was  at  the  beginning  of  that  decade  also  that  microscopical  biology  first 
showed  any  notable  advance,  and  after  that  the  great  discoveries  in  this  field 
followed  one  another  in  rapid  succession. 

There  were  two  spheres  in  which  the  pioneers  of  the  new  method  were 
induced  to  try  their  strength;  on  the  one  hand,  the  structure  of  the  higher 

389 


390  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

animals  and  plants  and  the  problem  of  their  fundamental  constituents,  and 
on  the  other  hand  that  world  of  minute,  independently  living  creatures  that 
the  new  instruments  made  it  possible  for  the  eye  to  see  —  in  collections  of 
water,  in  infusions  on  parts  of  plants  (hence  Infusoria),  and  indeed  every- 
where in  nature.  As  a  result  of  these  investigations  there  arises  an  entirely 
new  conception  of  the  composition  of  organisms  —  cytology,  or  the  knowl- 
edge of  cells.  An  attempt  to  show  the  development  of  this  branch  of  knowl- 
edge in  summary  form  offers  certain  special  difficulties;  as  Richard  Hertwig 
strikingly  remarks:  "The  way  was  paved  for  the  reform  of  the  cell  theory 
through  discoveries  made  in  very  different  spheres  and  not  until  late  in  time 
concentrated  in  a  focus."  We  must  therefore  give  a  brief  summary  of  these 
various  discoveries,  though  it  should  be  mentioned  in  this  connexion  that 
many  important  steps  were  taken  in  this  field  by  people  who  otherwise 
exercised  little  or  no  influence  upon  scientific  progress.  For  the  sake  of  brevity 
we  must  confine  ourselves  to  discussing  only  the  most  important  achieve- 
ments and  personalities  in  the  history  of  cytological  research. 

Works  on  -plant-tissues 
In  the  beginning  of  the  eighteen-thirties  Bichat's  tissue  theory  was  still 
accepted  in  zoology,  though  more  or  less  modified  by  various  investigators. 
In  botany  it  was  different.  Since  the  days  of  Malpighi  and  Grew  it  had  been 
known  that  the  wood  of  plants  is  composed  of  cells  —  minute  chambers 
having  more  or  less  thick  walls.  It  was  a  matter  of  dispute  whether  a  num- 
ber of  other  elements  in  the  plant,  especially  spiral  vessels  and  bast,  were 
compact  or  cellular.  The  first  who  attempted  to  compare  the  composition 
of  animal  and  plant  was  C.  F.  Wolff;  he  believed,  it  will  be  remembered, 
that  the  construction  of  each  represents  a  mass  of  cell-shaped  forms.  Among 
later  scientists  Blainville  produced  a  theory,  mentioned  in  the  foregoing, 
that  the  animal  organism  is  composed  of  cells,  but  this  theory  was  not  very 
clearly  developed  and  therefore  won  but  little  acceptance.  The  knowledge 
of  cells,  however,  made  steady,  if  slow,  progress,  the  botanists  still  leading 
the  way.  To  start  with,  it  was  a  question  of  deciding  whether  all  the  parts 
of  the  plant  consist -of  cells,  and  this  led  to  lively  discussion.  Among  those 
who  contributed  to  its  solution  may  be  mentioned  Charles  Francois 
MiRBEL  (1776-1854),  professor  of  botany  at  the  Jardin  des  Plantes,  and 
LuDOLF  Christian  Treviranus  (1779-1864),  professor  at  Bonn,  where  he 
succeeded  Nees  von  Esenbeck.  Mirbel  especially  examined  the  cell-structure 
in  certain  mosses,  making  valuable  contributions  to  the  subject,  besides 
which  he  resolutely  maintained  the  cell's  quality  as  a  basis  for  all  structures 
in  the  vegetable  kingdom.  Treviranus,  on  the  other  hand,  performed  a  signal 
service  in  the  observations  he  made  in  regard  to  the  regular  movements  of 
the  cellular  contents  in  a  number  of  vegetable  forms;  moreover,  he  observed 
that  the  spiral  vessels  in  plants  originate  in  cells  which  become  stratified 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  39I 

Upon  one  another  and  lose  their  intermediate  walls.  The  scientist  who  is 
generally  mentioned  as  the  creator  of  modern  plant-cytology,  is,  however, 
Hugo  Mohl.  He  was  born  in  1805  at  Stuttgart,  of  a  brilliantly  gifted  family 
in  the  Government  service.  He  became  a  doctor  of  medicine  and  a  professor, 
first  of  physiology  at  Berne,  then  —  in  1835  —  of  botany  at  Tubingen,  where 
he  remained  until  his  death,  in  1872..  His  life  was  typical  of  the  modest  and 
reserved  man  of  science;  being  unmarried,  he  spent  his  days  in  the  laboratory, 
and  his  evenings,  after  the  manner  of  his  countrymen,  at  a  "Stammtisch" 
with  a  few  friends.  Even  his  research  work  has  the  same  quiet  character; 
accurate  observation  of  phenomena,  a  great  capacity  for  placing  known 
facts  in  their  proper  light,  extremely  conscientious  examination  of  his  own 
ideas,  and  praiseworthy  consideration  for  those  of  others.  He  was  decidedly 
against  philosophical  speculations  and  he  never  produced  any  summary  of 
his  own  field  of  research;  his  writings  consist  of  a  large  number  of  short 
papers.  The  valuable  results  that  he  achieved,  however,  have  been  acknowl- 
edged by  both  his  own  and  succeeding  periods.  During  his  life  he  received 
many  honours,  including  that  of  being  raised  to  the  nobility  with  the  name 
of  von  Mohl,  and  after  his  death  his  reputation  was  still  further  enhanced. 

Mohl' s  work  on  cell-re-production 
Among  Mohl's  works  should  be  mentioned,  to  begin  with,  his  observations 
of  cell-reproduction.  Before  his  time,  and  even  later,  opinions  differed  on 
this  point.  He  upheld  clearly  and  convincingly  that  the  cells  in  alga;  and 
even  higher  plants  arise  through  partition-walls  being  formed  between 
previously  existing  cells.  These  partition-walls  he  investigated  and  described 
vvtth  great  accuracy.  We  must,  however,  leave  his  and  his  contemporaries' 
detailed  researches  in  this  sphere,  however  influential  they  may  have  been 
in  the  development  of  vegetable  anatomy;  it  need  only  be  mentioned  here 
that  Mohl  established  the  cellular  structure  in  spiral  vessels,  bast,  bark,  and 
other  components  of  plants,  a  point  that  had  formerly  been  much  debated. 
Further,  he  carefully  investigated  the  process  of  development  in  spores  of 
various  cryptogams,  finding  therein  both  a  confirmation  and  an  extension  of 
his  theory  of  cellular  division.  In  another  connexion  we  shall  make  reference 
to  some  of  his  further  important  contributions  to  this  subject.  For  the  rest, 
he  was  also  an  expert  optician;  a  work  which  was  unique  at  the  time  and 
which  is  still  worth  reading  was  his  Micrographie,  a  text-book  on  microscopy 
and  microtechnique. 

Discovery  of  the  cell-nucleus 
Among  the  investigators  who  contributed  to  the  development  of  cell  re- 
search, which  was  particularly  active  at  this  period,  may  further  be  men- 
tioned the  English  botanist  Robert  Brown,  a  scientist  of  many  parts,  whose 
work  will  be  described  in  another  connexion.  Here  it  need  only  be  pointed 
out  that  it  was  he  who,  in  1831,  published  the  discovery  that  to  the  contents 


392-  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

of  every  cell  there  belongs,  as  an  essential  component,  an  "areola"  or,  as  he 
also  calls  it,  a  nucleus;  this  cell-component  he  discovered  in  the  epidermis 
of  the  Orchidaceas  and  later  he  established  its  existence  in  a  great  number  of 
other  plant-cells.  It  was,  however,  reserved  to  other  investigators  to  dis- 
cover its  true  significance. 

Cytological  research  was  given  a  new  direction  by  Matthias  Jacob 
ScHLEiDEN,  one  of  the  strangest  scientific  personalities  of  his  age.  He  was 
born  in  Hamburg  in  1804,  the  son  of  an  eminent  doctor.  He  began  by  study- 
ing jurisprudence,  became  a  doctor  of  law,  and  took  up  a  practice  as  a  barris- 
ter in  his  native  town.  He  had,  however,  but  little  success  as  a  pleader,  a 
fact  that  increased  his  naturally  melancholy  disposition.  Finally,  in  a  fit  of 
despondency  he  shot  himself  in  the  forehead,  but  without  the  result  he  in- 
tended; he  recovered  and  then  resolved  to  devote  himself  to  natural  science.  He 
became  doctor  of  both  philosophy  and  medicine,  gained  a  great  reputation  by 
his  writings,  and  in  1850  became  professor  of  botany  at  Jena.  After  twelve 
years,  however,  he  resigned;  a  professorship  at  Dorpat,  to  which  he  was 
appointed  shortly  afterwards,  he  relinquished  within  the  year  and  after  that 
led  a  life  of  wandering,  with  brief  sojourns  in  various  German  towns,  which 
lasted  till  his  death,  in  1881.  The  life  he  led  fully  testifies  to  a  soul  without 
balance,  and  this  is  reflected  in  more  ways  than  one  in  his  scientific  work. 

The  work  that  at  once  brought  Schleiden  fame  was  an  essay  in  Miiller's 
archives  of  the  year  1838  entitled  "Beifrage  xur  Phytoge^zesis.''  The  question  he 
propounds  is:  How  does  the  cell  arise?  Here  Schleiden  takes  as  his  starting- 
point  Brown's  above-mentioned  discovery  of  the  cell-nucleus,  and  his  service 
to  science  lies  in  the  fact  that  he  was  able  to  appreciate  its  fundamental 
importance,  which  Brown  himself  failed  to  do.  From  the  nucleus,  or,  as  he 
calls  it,  the  cytoblast,  Schleiden  sought  to  reconstruct  the  course  of  develop- 
ment of  the  cell,  and  he  made  a  very  happy  choice  when  he  selected  for  the 
purpose  the  embryonic  cell  as  his  starting-point.  He  made  a  special  study  of 
the  embryo-sac  in  different  phanerogams,  carefully  examining  the  nuclei  in  the 
cells  in  question,  and  discovered  in  them  the  formation  that  is  now  termed  the 
nucleolus  or  nucleal  body.  This  discovery,  however,  led  him  to  continue 
the  investigation  along  the  wrong  lines;  he  thought  he  had  discovered  that 
the  nucleolus  is  first  formed  through  an  accumulation  of  granulate  mucus  in 
the  uniform  content  of  the  embryo-sac  and  he  believes  it  to  consist  of  gum; 
around  this  element  is  afterwards  stratified  the  rest  of  the  nucleus,  and  not 
until  the  latter  is  complete  is  there  formed  on  its  surface  a  small  vesicle  that 
grows  outwards  until  it  encloses  the  entire  nucleus;  the  walls  of  the  vesicle 
thicken,  and  thereby  the  cell  becomes  complete.  According  to  Schleiden, 
during  the  further  development  of  the  cell  the  nucleus  is  in  most  cases  dis- 
solved—  a  statement  that  of  course  does  not  accord  with  the  facts.  As  will 
be  seen,  the  whole  of  this  cell-formation  theory  is  quite  out  of  keeping  with 


MODERNBIOLOGY  393 

the  truth,  and  this  is  still  further  emphasized  in  the  eyes  of  a  modern  reader 
by  the  fact  that  Schleiden  uses  a  number  of  romantic-philosophical  terms: 
expressions  such  as  " pofetiz^erte  Zellen,"  "edlere  Sdjte,"  and  other  similar 
terms  are  clearly  reminiscent  of  Goethe.  What  made  this  paper  so  original 
is  its  insistence  upon  the  independence  of  the  cell;  the  plant  is  presented  for 
the  first  time  as  a  community  of  cells,  a  " Poljpsfock,"  as  it  is  expressly  called, 
and  it  was  from  this  standpoint  that  future  investigators  started  who  with  a 
finer  critical  sense  made  use  of  the  idea  that  Schleiden  had  produced. 

Schleiden' s  text-book  on  botany 
There  is  still  one  more  important  work  from  the  hand  of  Schleiden  that  is 
worthy  of  mention  —  his  Grundxiige  der  ivissenschaftlkhen  Botanik,  which  was 
published  in  i84Z  and  at  the  time  created  an  extraordinary  sensation,  criti- 
cism being  both  favourable  and  unfavourable.  Really  in  its  way  it  is  a 
pioneering  achievement;  it  implies  a  fundamental  agreement  both  with  the 
purely  systematic  botanical  training  that  had  hitherto  been  in  vogue,  and 
with  the  natural-philosophical  conception  of  the  phenomena  of  life.  In  a 
lengthy  "methodological  introduction"  Schleiden  propounds  his  general 
conception  of  nature,  which  represents  the  most  interesting  part  of  the  work. 
It  shows  that  he  held  a  well-thought-out  philosophical  view  of  nature,  ac- 
quired under  the  guidance  of  Jacob  Friedrich  Fries,  professor  of  philosophy 
at  Jena,  and  one  of  the  few  thinkers  who  during  the  age  of  romantic  specu- 
lation maintained  an  interest  in  Kant's  mode  of  thought.  Following  him, 
Schleiden  declares  that  the  aim  of  natural  science  is  "to  relate  all  physical 
theories  to  purely  mathematical  grounds  of  explanation."  With  this  ideal  of 
exact  research  before  him  he  tries  to  convert  botany  into  a  comparative  in- 
vestigation of  life -forms  and  life-manifestations,  with  special  reference  to 
the  evolutional  phenomena  in  the  vegetable  kingdom.  As  the  cause  of  all 
that  happens  in  nature,  both  animate  and  inanimate,  he  assumes  one  and 
the  same  "form-building  force";  on  the  other  hand,  he  strongly  denies  the 
existence  of  any  special  life-force,  and,  as  had  often  been  done  before,  he 
refers  the  growth  of  the  crystal  and  the  organ  to  the  same  category  of  phe- 
nomena. In  spite  of  this  he  is  definitely  opposed  to  the  idea  of  spontaneous 
generation  of  the  higher  animals  and  even  rejects  Meckel's  "biogenetical 
principles."  In  a  purely  philosophical  connexion  he  maintains,  with  Kant, 
the  contrast  between  subject  and  object,  and  consequently  also  between 
spiritual  and  material  entities.  Schelling's  and  Hegel's  theories  on  the  unity 
of  spirit  and  matter  he  dismisses  with  scorn.  His  "free-thinking"  brought 
him  into  dispute  with  the  theologians;  at  that  period  the  latter  were  monists, 
following  Hegel,  while  dualism  was  upheld  by  their  opponents  among  the 
biologists;  in  Haeckel's  time,  it  will  be  remembered,  just  the  contrary  was 
the  case,  which  fact  indicates  that  it  was  really  the  contrast  between  per- 
sonalities that  was  the  essential  point 


/•  > 


394  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

In  the  special  section  of  the  handbook  Schleiden  gives  an  explanation 
of  the  cytology,  morphology,  and  physiology  of  plants,  after  much  the 
same  plan  as  has  been  followed  in  similar  works  since  then.  This  method  of 
presentation  really  bears  the  stamp  of  genius;  the  actual  contents,  however, 
offer  nothing  essentially  new  from  the  point  of  view  of  that  age;  with  con- 
stant and  often  extremely  abusive  criticism  of  the  botanists  of  the  time  — 
Brown  and  Mohl  are  the  only  ones  who  are  let  off  lightly  —  he  presents  a 
summary  of  the  facts  already  known.  Concerning  the  formation  of  the  cell 
he  propounds  his  old  theory,  although  by  that  time  it  had  lost  much  of  the 
validity  it  formerly  possessed.  In  fact,  another  scientist  had  entered  this 
field  of  research  with  an  entirely  new  idea  that  eventually  directed  its  fur- 
ther line  of  development. 

Theodor  Schwann  was  born  in  1810  in  a  small  town  in  Rhenish  Prus- 
sia, where  his  father  had  a  book-shop.  He  studied  under  his  fellow-country- 
man J.  Miiller,  at  both  Bonn  and  Berlin;  having  taken  his  doctor's  degree, 
he  became  his  master's  assistant.  In  1839  he  was  called  to  the  chair  of  anat- 
omy at  the  Roman  Catholic  University  of  Louvain,  and  some  years  later  to 
Liege,  where  he  worked  until  shortly  before  his  death,  in  iSSz.  He  was  of  a 
gentle  and  reserved  disposition;  he  avoided  polemics  and  therefore  accepted 
none  of  the  professorships  that  were  offered  to  him  at  German  universities  — 
he  did  not  like  the  way  the  German  histologists  quarrelled,  he  said  —  and 
throughout  his  life  he  remained  a  devout  Catholic;  thus,  he  was  in  every- 
thing a  contrast  to  Schleiden,  with  whom  nevertheless  he  was  on  friendly 
terms.  His  scientific  activities  fall  entirely  within  the  period  during  which 
he  worked  with  Miiller;  it  apparently  needed  his  master's  will-power  to 
spur  his  easy-going  and  peaceful  nature  on  to  any  exertion.  As  a  professor  he 
published  only  some  few  text-books  and  summaries.  His  teaching  was  always 
conscientiously  carried  out. 

Schwann's  work  on  cell-structure 
Schwann's  research  work  during  hh  Berlin  period  was  both  many-sided 
and  important.  His  doctor's  dissertation  dealt  with  the  respiration  of  the 
embryo  of  the  chick;  he  discovered  the  ferment  of  gastric  juice,  to  which  he 
gave  the  name  "pepsin";  he  studied  Infusoria  and  experimented  with  fer- 
mentative phenomena,  which  led  him  to  deny  spontaneous  generation  and 
to  declare  that  fermentation  and  putrefaction  are  caused  by  organisms.  All 
these  works,  however,  fall  into  the  shade  beside  that  by  which  he  established 
his  fame  as  one  of  the  pioneers  of  biology  —  the  work  published  in  1839  en- 
titled: Mikroskopische  Untersuchungen  tiber  die  Ubereinstimjnung  in  der  Struktur 
und  dem  Wachstum  der  Tiere  und  Pflan':(en.  He  here  takes  as  his  starting-point 
Schleiden's  above-mentioned  cell-formation  theory,  which  he  accepts  in  its 
entirety  and  expands  into  a  general  theory  of  the  basis  and  origin  of  life- 
phenomena.  By  way  of  introduction  he  points  out  the  fundamental  difference 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  395 

between  animal  and  plant,  which  the  biology  of  preceding  ages  had  realized 
in  the  fact  that  animals  possess  a  vascular  system,  which  plants  lack;  the 
plants'  "gefassloses  Wachstum'  was  accounted  for  by  the  cell-structure  or, 
as  it  was  then  called,  the  plant's  composition  of  independent  units.  Now, 
Schwann  had  discovered  in  the  notochord  of  tadpoles  cells  provided  with 
nuclei,  similar  to  the  plant-cells,  and  both  there  and  in  the  embryonic 
cartilage  he  believed  he  saw  a  process  of  cell-reproduction  such  as  Schlciden 
had  described.  This  induced  him  to  look  for  cells  in  all  the  tissues  of  the 
animal  body,  and  by  examining  these  in  the  embryonic  stage  and  afterwards 
following  their  development  he  succeeded  in  establishing  the  fact  of  cell- 
structure  even  in  tissues  that  in  a  state  of  full  growth  show  little  or  no  trace 
of  any  such  structure.  It  is  not  difficult  to  realize  the  great  influence  that 
this  discovery  was  to  have  on  the  tissue  theory,  and  what  follows  will  make 
it  still  clearer.  Of  still  greater  significance  for  the  future,  however,  was  his 
general  cell-theory,  according  to  which,  as  he  says,  "one  common  principle 
of  evolution  is  laid  down  for  the  most  highly  differentiated  elementary  parts 
of  the  organisms,  and  this  principle  of  evolution  is  the  cell-formation." 
This  conception  of  the  cell  as  a  general  unit  of  life  and  as  a  common  basis 
for  the  vital  phenomena  in  both  the  animal  and  the  vegetable  kingdom  was 
immediately  and  universally  accepted;  so  self-evident  did  its  truth  seem  to 
be  that  it  met  with  hardly  any  opposition,  and  in  fact  became  the  foundation 
on  which  since  then  both  animal  and  vegetable  biology  have  developed.  It 
is  thanks  to  this  theory  that  the  present  age  has  been  able  to  work  out  its 
conception  of  life-phenomena  as  a  connected  whole;  without  Schwann, 
Darwinism  would  hardly  have  been  victorious. 

In  its  details,  however,  Schwann's  cell  theory  is  very  primitive;  he  not 
only  embraces  Schleiden's  belief  in  a  free  cell-formation  out  of  moisture,  but 
takes  it  further.  Out  of  moisture  is  concentrated,  first  the  nucleolus,  then 
the  nucleus,  and  finally  the  cell;  this  process  is  explicitly  compared  with 
crystallization,  and  the  whole  concludes  with  reflections  as  to  whether  the 
hollow  form  of  the  cell  might  not  be  accounted  for  by  the  "Imbibitions- 
fdhigkeit"  of  its  component  parts  —  in  modern  terminology,  its  colloidal 
qualities;  according  to  him,  then,  the  cell-formation  would  be  a  kind  of 
crystallization  in  non-crystalline  elements.  For  the  essential  part  of  the  cell 
is,  in  Schwann's  view,  its  hollowness;  in  its  essence  it  is  a  space  surrounded 
by  walls;  its  content  is  a  moisture,  which  runs  out  if  the  wall  is  damaged, 
while  the  nucleus  is  a  transitory  formation,  which  disappears  in  later  stages 
of  development.  These  views  were  in  their  essentials  corrected  in  the  im- 
mediately succeeding  future.  For  the  rest,  Schwann  made  his  cell-formation 
theory  the  basis  of  a  general  theory  of  life,  which  proved  to  be  considerably 
more  materialistic  than  that  of  his  master,  J.  Miiller;  as  a  devout  Christian 
he  believed  in  the  world's  serving  a  purpose  given  it  by  the  Creator,  but  in 


396  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

contrast  to  Miiller  he  found  no  further  or  greater  finality  in  living  nature 
than  existed  in  inanimate  nature;  the  same  purely  mechanical  forces  shape 
both  the  cell  and  the  crystal. 

Further  development  of  the  cell  theory 
The  cell-theory  which  has  just  been  described,  and  which  has  always  been 
called  the  Schleiden-Schwann  theory,  after  its  founders,  was  adopted  and 
at  once  followed  up  by  other  investigators,  while,  as  mentioned  above,  the 
two  pioneers  withdrew  from  the  field.  The  most  important  contributions 
made  during  the  next  few  years  were  those  of  Mohl,  who  published  a  series 
of  new  observations  regarding  the  role  of  the  cell  in  the  vegetable  kingdom. 
In  these  brief  but  weighty  papers  he  analyses  the  different  components  of 
the  cell.  To  him  the  cell  is  still  "a  vesicle  formed  of  a  fixed  membrane  and 
containing  a  moisture";  the  character  of  the  membrane  is  the  essential  thing, 
and  the  shape,  consistency,  and  interrelation  of  the  cellular  walls  are  de- 
scribed before  anything  else.  Moreover,  an  account  is  also  given  of  the  con- 
tents of  the  cell:  the  "viscid  moisture"  that  forms  its  fundamental  constituent 
is  carefully  described;  its  currents,  which  were  discovered  by  the  Italian 
CoRTi  and  rediscovered  by  Treviranus,  are  depicted  in  detail  in  various  plant- 
forms  —  inter  alia  in  those,  since  then,  classical  objects  of  demonstration, 
the  Tradescantia  hairs  —  similarly,  the  evolution  of  the  cell-content  is 
followed  through  its  different  stages  of  growth,  and  the  secondary  forma- 
tions that  accompany  it  —  vacuoles,  chlorophyll-  and  starch-granules  — 
are  described.  The  fundamental  substance  in  the  cell  Mohl  calls  protoplasm; 
he  thereby  establishes  the  fact  that  the  cell-content  is  an  element  by  itself 
and  not  merely  "slime"  of  some  indeterminate  kind,  as  Schleiden  supposed. 
The  name,  which  in  spite  of  its  clumsiness  has  come  into  permanent  use,  is, 
as  a  matter  of  fact,  based  on  the  false  assumption  that  all  the  component  parts 
of  the  cell,  even  (and  above  all)  the  nucleus,  originate  in  this  element,  the 
"primal  slime."  The  nucleus  is  described  by  Mohl  in  greater  detail  than  by 
his  predecessors;  true,  it  is  still  stated  to  be,  as  mentioned  above,  a  deriva- 
tive of  protoplasm  come  into  being  through  an  accumulation  of  a  granulate 
substance  in  young  cells  and  disappearing  in  the  older  ones,  but  the  grossly 
mechanical  precipitation-theory  that  Schleiden  and  Schwann  held  was  ac- 
cepted with  reserve.  And,  above  all,  division  is  mentioned  as  being  the  nor- 
mal method  of  cell-reproduction;  independent  cell-formation  is  confined  to 
the  embryo-sac  alone.  In  regard  also  to  the  alimental  physiology  of  the  cell, 
Mohl  offers  some  interesting  observations,  but  they  must  be  passed  over 
here. 

At  the  same  time,  valuable  contributions  to  the  evolution  of  the  cell 
were  made  by  Karl  Nageli,  an  investigator  whose  far-reaching  activities 
will  be  described  later  on.  In  an  essay  on  the  pollen-formation  in  the  phan- 
erogams, particularly  in  the  Liliaceas,  he  describes  the  cell-divisions  (in  1841) 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  397 

with  such  care  and  reliability  as  had  never  been  done  before;  even  the  division 
of  the  nucleus  was  observed  with  great  accuracy.  His  ' '  transitory  cytoblasts" 
are  chromosomes,  although,  with  the  inferior  means  at  his  disposal  at  that 
time,  he  was  unable  either  to  follow  the  course  of  development  to  the  end 
or  to  interpret  it  aright. 

While,  then,  plant-cytology  was  making  rapid  progress,  cell  research 
in  the  animal  kingdom  was  by  no  means  unproductive.  Among  those  who 
collaborated  in  the  working  up  of  this  field  of  research  it  is  only  possible 
to  name  a  few  of  the  most  influential:  to  begin  with,  some  of  Johannes 
Miiller's  pupils,  Henle,  Reichert,  Remak,  and  Kolliker. 

Jacob  Henle  was  born  at  Fiirth,  near  Nuremberg,  in  1809,  the  son  of  a 
Jewish  merchant  who  later,  with  his  entire  family,  adopted  Christianity. 
He  studied  at  Bonn  under  Miiller,  afterwards  becoming  the  latter's  prosector 
in  anatomy  at  Berlin.  There,  however,  he  became  the  victim  of  political 
persecution;  he  was  a  liberal  and  a  member  of  the  Burschenschaft,  with  the 
consequence  that,  like  so  many  other  youths  at  that  time,  he  was  arrested 
by  the  scarified  Prussian  police  and  after  lengthy  law-court  proceedings  was 
condemned  for  treason.  His  scientific  reputation,  however,  saved  him  from 
further  rigorous  treatment;  Humboldt,  among  others,  interceded  for  him, 
with  the  result  that  he  was  pardoned,  but  he  received  no  further  appoint- 
ment from  the  Prussian  Government.  In  1840  he  accepted  a  professorship  at 
Zurich,  somewhat  later  one  at  Heidelberg,  and  finally,  in  1851,  one  at 
Gottingen,  where  he  worked  until  his  death,  in  1885. 

Under  Miiller's  leadership  Henle  worked  both  as  an  anatomist  and  as 
a  biologist  in  the  invertebrate  field;  afterwards  he  also  devoted  himself  to 
pathology.  His  activities  as  a  student  of  cell-life  are  associated  with  a 
number  of  special  essays,  and  also  with  his  Allgemeine  Anatomie,  an  excellent 
work  for  its  period.  Among  his  contributions  in  the  sphere  of  invertebrate 
research  his  discovery  of  the  hair-sac  mites  is  universally  known.  Best  of 
all  his  speci/lized  work,  however,  is  his  investigation  of  the  histology  of 
the  intestinal  epithelium;  it  was  he  who  discovered  the  cylindrical  epithe- 
lial cells  and  explained  the  existence  of  the  pavement  and  columnar  epithe- 
lium in  the  various  parts  of  the  intestinal  canal.  He  also  carefully  studied 
the  ciliated  epithelium  and  its  distribution  and  it  was  he  who  created  the 
term  "epithelium."  In  connexion  with  the  intestinal  mucous  membrane,  he 
investigated  the  chyle  vessels  with  great  care,  particularly  with  reference 
to  their  terminal  ramifications,  which  had  hitherto  been  misinterpreted. 

Henle's  General  Anatomy  is  the  first  histological  handbook  based  entirely 
upon  cytology  and  undoubtedly  the  most  original  since  the  days  of  Bichat. 
It  begins  with  a  chapter  on  animal  chemistry,  viewed  from  a  contemporary 
standpoint,  and  goes  on  to  describe  the  part  played  by  the  cell  as  a  primary 
formation.  His  cell-theory  is  on  the  whole  that  of  the  Schleiden-Schwann 


398  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

school,  which  has  previously  been  mentioned:  the  nucleus  formed  through 
an  accumulation  of  a  granulate  substance,  the  cell  formed  round  the  nucleus 
and  consisting  of  membrane,  nucleus,  and  fluid  content.  Cell-division  is 
denied  as  far  as  the  animal  kingdom  is  concerned;  the  cell-formation  is 
rather  compared  with  the  emulsive  phenomena  that  arise  when  oil  and  al- 
bumen are  shaken  together  —  an  attempt  at  an  explanation  which,  as  is 
well  known,  has  been  the  subject  of  endless  variations  in  modern  time.  On 
the  other  hand,  Schwann's  comparisons  between  cell-formation  and  crys- 
tallization are  not  accepted.  Henle  adopts  a  decidedly  critical  attitude  in 
regard  to  speculations  on  the  primary  vital  phenomena.  "Explaining  a 
physiological  fact  means  tracing  its  necessity  from  physical  and  chemical 
natural  laws.  It  is  true,  even  these  laws  offer  no  explanation  as  to  the  ulti- 
mate grounds,  but  they  make  it  possible  to  combine  a  mass  of  details  under 
one  point  of  view."  On  the  life -force  theory  adopted  universally  by  his  con- 
temporaries he  passes  the  following  striking  judgment:  "The  life-force  is 
formally  as  good  an  explanation  as  the  force  of  gravity,  but  it  is  one  force 
the  more  and  this  is  at  variance  with  our  striving  after  unity." 

Henle  thereupon  proceeds  to  give  an  account  of  the  tissues,  and,  of 
these,  first  of  all  the  epithelial  system,  which  indeed  was  best  mastered 
and  is  very  well  expounded.  A  number  of  other  details  are  also  excellently 
explained,  especially  the  vascular  musculature,  which  is  here  for  the  first 
time  satisfactorily  dealt  with.  In  regard  to  the  division  of  tissues,  Henle  is, 
of  course,  far  in  advance  of  Bichat,  but  even  his  system  is,  from  the  modern 
point  of  view,  difficult  of  comprehension;  in  particular,  the  category  nowa- 
days called  connective  tissue  is  split  up  into  a  mass  of  sub-headings  which  are 
often  somewhat  unhappily  formulated.  Another  weak  chapter  is  that  on 
the  glandular  system,  as  indeed  Henle  himself  admits,  referring  to  the 
paucity  of  the  investigations  that  have  been  made  in  that  sphere.  But,  on 
the  whole,  Henle's  general  anatomy  deserves  the  judgment  passed  on  it  by 
a  later  histologist  who  declared  that  it  laid  the  foundation  of  modern  his- 
tology and  on  that  account  will  survive. 

Karl  Bogislaus  Reichert  was  born  in  181 1  in  a  provincial  town  in  East 
Prussia,  where  his  father  was  mayor.  He  studied  at  Konigsberg  under  von 
Baer  and  in  Berlin  under  Miiller,  was  called  to  a  professorial  chair  first  at 
Dorpat,  then  at  Breslau,  and  finally  in  Berlin,  where  after  Miiller's  death, 
when  the  latter's  professorship  was  divided,  he  took  over  the  professorship 
of  anatomy,  which  he  retained  until  his  death,  in  1883.  He  began  his  activi- 
ties as  a  comparative  anatomist  with  a  valuable  work  on  the  development  of 
the  gill-arches  in  the  Vertebrata  and  another  equally  eminent  work  on  the 
embryonic  formation  of  the  frog's  head.  He  then  devoted  himself  to  cytology 
in  the  spirit  of  Schwann  and  applied  the  latter's  theories  to  the  evolution  of 
frog's  spawn,  not,  it  is  true,  without  falling  into  the  misconception  prevalent 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  399 

at  the  time  —  he  believed  that  the  separate  granules  in  the  yolk  of  the  egg 
are  independent  cells  —  but  nevertheless  with  great  accuracy  in  his  obser- 
vations of  the  consecutive  stages  of  development,  resulting  in  his  establishing 
the  cell  character  of  the  products  of  division,  out  of  which  the  embryo  is 
formed.  Even  the  two  afterwards  oft-recurring  expressions  "BiUungs-"  and 
"Nahrungsdotter"  originate  from  him.  One  or  two  works  on  the  evolution 
of  the  tadpole  likewise  contain  sound  observations;  one  of  them  contains  a 
number  of  general  reflections  on  the  subject  of  organic  formation  by  means 
of  invagination,  which  in  a  certain  degree  foreshadowed  Haeckel's  gastra^a 
theory.  Reichert's  greatest  contribution,  however,  lies  in  his  study  of  the 
evolution  of  the  connective  substance;  he  introduced  this  term  to  imply  a 
number  of  connecting-tissue  elements  of  different  structure  and  has  based 
it  upon  arguments  from  evolutional  history.  In  his  old  age  Reichert  was  com- 
pletely isolated;  he  refused  to  accept  the  new  protoplasm  theories,  and  still 
more  the  origin-of-species  theory,  and  he  made  no  attempt  to  hide  his  disgust 
when  these  ideas  prevailed.  In  particular,  he  attacked  with  great  vehemence 
Haeckel's  theory  of  the  germ  layers  being  homologous  throughout  the  ani- 
mal kingdom;  instead,  he  maintained  the  independent  origin  of  the  separate 
organs.  While  he  was  scorned  by  Haeckel  and  his  contemporaries,  Reichert 
has  to  a  certain  extent  been  justified  by  the  results  of  modern  research,  where- 
on we  shall  have  more  to  say  in  a  later  chapter. 

Robert  Remak  was  born  at  Posen  in  181 5.  Like  Henle,  he  was  of  Jewish 
extraction,  but  in  contrast  to  him  held  to  the  faith  of  his  fathers.  After 
studying  under  Miiller  he  became  his  assistant  lecturer,  eventually  being 
given  the  honorary  title  of  professor,  though  never  holding  a  post  as  or- 
dinary professor.  He  made  a  living  by  carrying  on  a  medical  practice,  and 
this  gradually  diverted  him  from  a  scientific  career.  He  died  in  1865.  His 
contribution  in  the  field  of  cell  research  is  concerned  partly  with  neurology 
and  partly  with  embryology.  Thus,  he  discovered  and  described  the  sym- 
pathetic nerve  fibres  called  after  him,  and  he  established  the  fact  that  in  the 
embryonic  life  the  nerves  are  constructed  in  the  form  of  fibres  which  grow  out 
from  the  nerve-cells.  He  is  specially  worthy  of  remembrance,  however,  for  the 
determined  opposition  he  made  to  Schwann's  theory  of  free  cell-formation; 
he  studied  the  evolution  of  frogs'  eggs  and  thereby  proved  that  the  egg  is  a 
cell  that  divides  itself  up  into  new  cells  and  that  this  division  starts  from  the 
nuclei;  he  does  not  accept  any  cell-formation  by  accumulation  in  a  formless 
matter.  Further  he  drew  a  comparison  between  the  embryonic  development 
in  the  egg  of  the  frog  and  in  that  of  a  bird:  it  was  he  who  invented  the  terms 
"holoblastic"  and  "meroblastic,"  which  are  still  used  for  these  two  types 
of  egg.  He  distinguishes  three  germinal  layers,  which  he  believes  to  be  com- 
mon to  the  embryonic  development  of  all  vertebrates  and  which  giwe  rise, 
the  outermost  to  the  nervous  system,  the  middlemost  to  the  musculature, 


400  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

and  the  innermost  to  the  intestinal  tube  —  all  observations  that  have  been 
confirmed  by  modern  research.  In  his  later  years  Remak  paid  special  atten- 
tion to  the  study  of  electrotherapy,  making  in  this  sphere  a  valuable  con- 
tribution, which,  however,  does  not  belong  to  the  history  of  biology. 

Rudolf  Albert  Kolliker  was  born  in  1817  at  Zurich,  the  son  of  a 
wealthy  merchant.  He  studied  zoology  in  his  native  town  under  the  aged 
Oken  and  afterwards  went  to  Berlin,  where,  under  the  guidance  of  Miiller 
and  Henle,  he  was  initiated  into  their  method  of  research.  When  Henle  went 
to  Zurich,  Kolliker  became  his  prosector,  but  in  1847  he  was  invited  to 
become  professor  at  Wiirzburg.  There  he  gave  lectures  up  to  1901,  when  he 
resigned;  he  died  three  years  later.  He  remained  a  Swiss  subject  all  through 
his  life.  He  was  one  of  the  foremost  teachers  of  his  age;  many  of  the  most 
eminent  biologists  of  the  succeeding  generation  belonged  to  his  school. 

Kolliker's  research  activities  lasted  as  long  as  his  educational  career. 
He  was  active  far  into  his  ninth  decade  and  was  successful  to  the  end;  his 
later  work  therefore  belongs  to  the  following  epoch.  As  a  research-worker 
he  was  above  all  a  microscopist;  the  connecting  link  in  his  work  was  formed 
by  the  microscopical  method,  which  he  employed  in  a  great  number  of  fields 
of  research,  everywhere  with  immense  success,  although  no  discovery  or  idea 
of  supreme  importance  attaches  to  his  name.  He  gave  a  splendid  summary  of 
contemporary  knowledge  on  this  subject  in  his  Handbuch  der  Geivebelehre  des 
Menschen,  published  in  the  year  i85z,  which  deserves  to  be  called  the  first 
modern  histology.  Its  purely  external  form  has  been  repeated,  with  the  nec- 
essary modifications  required  by  the  progress  of  science,  in  innumerable 
text-books  on  this  subject.  Kolliker  here  expounds  with  impartiality  and 
far-sightedness  the  contemporary  cell  and  tissue  doctrine;  he  does  not,  indeed, 
entirely  deny  free  cell-formation,  but  he  limits  its  existence  as  much  as  pos- 
sible. The  cells  themselves  he  considers  to  be  constructed  of  elemental  parts : 
granular  and  vesicular  formations,  to  which  he  ascribes  a  certain  degree  of 
independence  in  growth  and  development  —  an  idea  which  was  later  adopted 
by  many  others.  He  strongly  insists  upon  the  importance  of  the  role  played 
by  the  nucleus  in  the  life  of  the  cell,  in  its  multiplication  by  division  and  its 
other  vital  manifestations.  We  must  pass  over  his  classification  of  tissues; 
he  did  not  adopt  Reichert's  connective-substance  category,  but  otherwise  his 
classification  is  clear  and  concise  and  his  elucidation  of  the  structure  and 
vital  manifestations  of  the  different  tissues  is  full  of  original  observations 
and  excellent  in  its  form.  Kolliker  produced  another  splendid  text-book  in 
his  Entwicklungsgeschichte  des  Menschen  und  der  hoheren  Tiere  (1861),  a  summary 
in  clear  and  comprehensive  form  of  the  embryological  knowledge  of  the  time. 

Kolliker  s  investigations 
Of  Kolliker's  numerous  original  investigations  it  is  possible  to  quote  here 
only  a  few  of  the  most  important,  in  so  far  as  they  come  within  the  period 


MODERNBIOLOGY  401 

now  being  dealt  with.  Especially  noteworthy  is  his  investigation  into  the 
spermatozoa  (1841),  in  which  he  proves  that  they  are  not  parasites,  but  a 
true  sexual  product.  Further,  his  fine  monograph  Entwkklungsgeschkhte  der 
Cephalopoden  (1844),  which  he  worked  out  in  the  course  of  a  visit  to  Naples 
and  which  contains  an  account  of  egg-division  and  embryonic  development 
in  those  animals,  to  which  account  subsequent  research  has  had  but  little 
to  add.  Of  great  importance,  too,  was  his  study  of  the  smooth  musculature, 
the  elements  of  which  he  definitely  isolated  for  the  first  time,  describing 
them  as  single-celled  fibrillar;  their  distribution  in  the  different  organs  of 
man  and  the  mammals  he  elucidated  with  unprecedented  completeness. 
Henle,  indeed,  had  established  the  musculature  of  the  blood-vessels,  but  it 
was  Kolliker  who  explained  its  character  in  detail.  In  the  sphere  of  neurology 
he  also  made  valuable  discoveries;  thus,  he  proved  convincingly  that  the 
nerve-fibres  are  connected  with  processes  of  the  ganglion-cells,  thereby 
making  important  contributions  to  the  knowledge  of  their  structure.  If  we 
add  that  Kolliker  investigated  with  valuable  results  certain  unicellular 
animals,  as,  for  instance,  the  gregarines,  we  shall  have  given  some  idea  of 
his  extraordinarily  many-sided  research  work. 

There  is  one  scientist  who  is  worthy  of  mention  by  the  side  of  Kolliker 
—  namely,  Franz  Leydig  (1811-1905),  who  was  a  native  of  Wiirttemberg 
and  who  was  professor  at  Bonn  from  1875  to  1895.  As  a  cytologist  he  was 
remarkable  for  his  investigations  into  the  invertebrates.  He,  too,  published 
a  Lehrbuch  der  Histologic,  which,  remarkably  enough,  pays  as  much  attention 
to  the  tissues  of  the  invertebrate  animals  as  to  those  of  the  vertebrates, 
thereby  laying  the  foundations  of  comparative  histology,  which  has  since 
been  so  extensively  developed. 

Leydig's  classification  of  tissues  is  more  in  accordance  with  the  modern 
method  than  that  of  Kolliker;  thus  he  groups  under  the  heading  "connec- 
tive substance"  not  only  connective  tissue  and  cartilage,  but  also  bone  tissue, 
which  Reichert  still  kept  separate.  His  presentation  of  the  life  and  develop- 
ment of  the  cell  is  likewise  more  modern  than  Kolliker's,  but  Leydig's  book 
was  published  four  years  later,  and  during  that  period  cytology  made  great 
strides  year  by  year.  A  good  deal  of  Leydig's  own  pioneering  research-work 
is  recorded  in  this  treatise;  his  detailed  studies  of  the  structure  of  the  insects, 
especially  their  digestive,  glandular,  and  sensory  organs,  should  be  men- 
tioned first  of  all.  Leydig's  other  extremely  conscientious  microscopical  in- 
vestigations into  worms  and  molluscs,  as  well  as  vertebrates,  belong  to  the 
specialized  literature  on  those  subjects;  no  histological  specialist  can  aff^ord 
to  neglect  them,  but  considerations  of  space  forbid  any  further  reference  to 
them  here. 

Cell  research  entered  upon  a  new  phase  through  the  work  of  Rudolf 
LuDwiG  Carl  Virchow.  He  was  born  in  Pomerania  in  182.1,  the  son  of  a 


401  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

country  shopkeeper,  and  after  finishing  school  applied  himself  to  medicine. 
He  was  a  pupil  of  J.  Miiller  and  after  completing  his  studies  he  became  as- 
sistant at  the  Charite  Hospital  in  Berlin,  rapidly  acquiring  a  reputation  on 
account  of  his  writings  on  pathology  and  his  Archiv  fur  pathologische  Anatomic 
und  Physiologie,  which  he  founded  in  1847  and  edited  until  his  death.  He  was 
sent  by  the  Government  to  be  a  medical  officer  in  an  industrial  district  in 
Silesia,  where  a  serious  epidemic  of  typhus  had  broken  out;  in  the  report  on 
his  mission  he  represented  social  distress  in  the  district  as  being  the  true 
cause  of  the  disease  in  such  terms  as  created  resentment  in  high  bureaucratic 
circles.  When,  moreover,  during  the  revolutionary  year  1848  he  joined  the 
opposition,  he  was  dismissed  from  his  post.  He  then  moved  to  Wiirzburg, 
where  he  became  professor  in  pathological  anatomy  and  developed  such  bril- 
liant activities  in  the  spheres  of  research  and  education  that  his  school  soon 
rivalled  that  of  his  master,  Miiller.  The  Prussian  Government  recalled  him 
in  1856,  and  from  that  date  until  shortly  before  his  death  he  was  one  of  the 
most  brilliant  personalities  at  the  University  of  Berlin.  He  died  in  1902.  as 
the  result  of  an  accident.  He  remained  throughout  his  life  faithful  to  his 
liberal  ideas;  as  a  member  of  the  Prussian  Diet  and  the  German  Parliament 
he  indefatigably  supported  the  cause  of  liberalism  and  thereby  came  into 
constant  conflict  with  Bismarck  and  the  adherents  of  that  statesman.  Vir- 
chow  naturally  had  no  chance  against  such  an  antagonist,  and  his  purely 
political  activities  were  unproductive.  On  the  other  hand,  his  influence  on 
the  public  health  services  in  Germany  was  extraordinarily  effective;  it  was 
largely  due  to  him  that  the  German  medical  system  became  a  model  for 
other  countries.  His  energy  sufficed  for  all  claims  made  upon  it,  from  the 
reform  of  the  sanitary  system  in  Berlin  to  the  organizing  of  the  medical  corps 
during  the  War  of  1870.  Above  all,  however,  the  care  of  the  sick  in  Berlin 
stands  as  a  monument  to  his  organizing  genius. 

Virchow' s  cellular  pathology 
As  a  research-worker  Virchow  was  really  a  pathologist;  it  was  diseases  and 
their  causes  that  was  the  chief  object  of  his  investigations.  This  led  him 
to  the  problem  of  the  cells  as  fundamental  constituents  of  the  organism  both 
in  health  and  sickness,  and  in  the  middle  of  the  eighteen-fifties  he  laid  the 
foundations  of  his  "cellular  pathology":  a  theory  of  the  cells  as  the  true 
causes  of  disease.  When,  therefore,  a  decade  later,  bacteriology  began  to 
make  headway,  he  refused  to  accept  its  results.  An  important  work  that  he 
published  on  tumours  was  never  completed,  and  he  subsequently  devoted 
himself,  apart  from  politics,  mostly  to  anthropology  and  archaeology.  In 
these  spheres  also  he  achieved  much  that  is  of  value,  not  least  on  account 
of  his  initiative  —  the  great  Museum  fiir  Volkerkunde  in  Berlin,  for  in- 
stance, was  founded  by  him  —  but  this  work  is  by  no  means  to  be  compared 
in  importance  with  the  products  of  his  youth. 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  403 

Virchow's  cellular  pathological-theory  has  been  of  great  importance 
to  the  development  of  biology,  owing  to  the  fact  that  he  established,  as 
no  one  else  had  done  before  him,  the  cell's  character  as  an  independent  life- 
unit.  He  denies  any  form  of  spontaneous  generation,  whether  within  the 
organism  or  without  in  nature.  Just  as  it  is  impossible  for  an  ascaris  worm 
to  arise  out  of  intestinal  slime  or  an  infusorian  out  of  decaying  matter,  so 
it  is  not  permitted  in  the  physiological  or  pathological  tissue-theory  for  a 
cell  to  be  constructed  " aus  irgend  einer  unxelligen  Substanz,."  And  he  continues: 
Wo  eine  Zdle  entsteht,  da  muss  eine  Zelle  vorausgegangen  sem,  ebenso  ivie  das  Tier 
nur  aus  dem  Tiere,  die  Pfian^e  nur  aus  der  Pflanze  entstehen  kann."  It  is  this  prin- 
ciple of  cell  multiplication,  and  thereby  also  of  the  cell's  role  in  the  organ- 
ism as  a  whole,  that  represents  Virchow's  great  contribution  to  the  history 
of  biology.  He  himself  applied  his  principle  mostly  to  the  sphere  of  path- 
ology, in  which  he  created  with  its  aid  a  new  theory  of  the  origin  not  only 
of  tumours  and  other  new  growths,  but  also  of  purulent  bodies.  Otherwise, 
his  conception  of  the  cell  was  in  no  way  original;  he  mentions  as  its  neces- 
sary components  the  membrane  and  the  nucleus,  and  considers  its  other 
"fluid"  contents  to  be  less  essential.  In  his  general  conception  of  the  vital 
phenomena  Virchow  is  to  a  certain  extent  undecided;  on  the  one  hand,  he 
declares  that  there  is  a  special  life-force,  that  life  is  not  a  mechanical  result 
of  the  molecular  forces  of  the  bodily  parts,  while,  on  the  other  hand,  he 
holds  that  this  life -force  is  probably  of  mechanical  origin.  Throughout  his 
life  Virchow  was  of  a  very  pugnacious  disposition  and  used  to  defend  his 
views  with  great  vehemence;  with  Haeckel  in  particular  —  once  his  own 
pupil  —  he  entered  into  violent  controversies,  not  only  on  scientific,  but 
also  on  social  questions,  which  both  disputants  were  strongly  inclined  to 
confuse  with  one  another.  But  these  disputes  belong  to  the  next  era. 

The  modern  conception  of  the  life  and  component  parts  of  the  cell  was 
founded  by  Max  Schultze,  a  man  who,  in  spite  of  a  short  life,  made  a  last- 
ing name  in  the  history  of  biology.  Max  Johann  Sigismund  Schultze  was 
born  at  Freiburg  in  1815  and  studied  at  Greifswald  (his  father  had  been  pro- 
fessor of  anatomy  in  both  places),  and  he  also  attended  the  lectures  of 
J.  Miiller  in  Berlin  for  a  short  time.  He  was  at  one  time  a  lecturer  at  Halle 
and  from  there  was  appointed  to  a  professorship  at  Bonn.  He  worked  with 
success  there,  but  died  in  1874. 

Schultze's  field  of  activities  was  very  extensive;  he  devoted  himself  to 
microscopical  subjects  in  a  number  of  animal  classes.  Specially  famous  are 
his  writings  on  the  single-celled  animals,  to  which  further  reference  will  be 
made  later  on;  they  form  one  of  the  foundations  of  his  cell  theory.  Further- 
more he  carried  out  important  investigations  into  the  microscopical  anatomy 
of  worms  and  molluscs;  in  the  Vertebrata  he  studied  the  terminal  rami- 
fications of  the  nervous  system,  and  made  weighty  contributions  to  the 


404  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

knowledge  of  the  structure  of  the  electrical  organs.  All  these  works,  val- 
uable as  they  are,  are  nevertheless  put  in  the  shade  by  a  short  essay  in  the 
Archiv  fur  Anatomic  und  Physiologic  of  the  year  1861,  entitled  "  Uber  Muskel- 
korferchen  und  was  man  cine  Zellc  zu  nennen  habe."  Schultze  has  hereby  laid  the 
foundations  of  the  modern  idea  of  the  cell.  "What  is  the  most  essential 
thing  in  a  cell?"  he  asks  at  the  beginning  of  the  essay.  The  old  theory^ 
which,  as  we  have  seen,  Virchow  still  embraced,  would  answer:  "  A  vesicle 
surrounded  by  a  membrane,  with  a  nucleus  and  fluid  contents."  Schultze 
refers  to  the  embryonic  cells  and  points  out  that  these  consist  of  a  mass  of 
protoplasm  with  nucleus,  but  without  any  surrounding  walls;  the  membrane 
which  had  previously  been  supposed  to  surround  these  cells,  and  which  cer- 
tain investigators  had  brought  out  by  chemical  means,  he  proves  to  be  an 
artificial  product.  He  further  points  out  that  only  cells  without  any  mem- 
brane can  multiply  by  division;  those  cells  possessing  a  membrane  which  are 
found  in  the  animal  kingdom  thus  lead  a  restricted  and  limited  existence  — 
"They  may  be  likened  to  an  incapsulated  infusorian  or  an  imprisoned  ani- 
mal." Again,  the  substance  that  surrounds  the  nuclei  in  the  different  tissues 
—  muscular  fibrillas,  connective  substance  —  is  not,  as  has  been  declared, 
a  substance  foreign  to  the  cell,  but  a  transformation  of  the  protoplasm  itself. 
Accordingly,  the  protoplasm,  in  conjunction  with  the  nucleus,  is  the  basis 
of  all  the  life-manifestations  of  the  cell,  and  the  very  name  "protoplasm," 
which  had  hitherto  been  used  only  by  the  botanists,  is  introduced  as  the 
universal  term  for  the  fundamental  substance  in  the  cell.  And  in  connexion 
therewith  this  substance  is  characterized  with  reference  to  the  conditions 
obtaining  in  plants,  in  the  lower  and  higher  animals;  it  is  maintained  that 
the  cell-mass  is  by  no  means  a  fluid,  but  an  element  having  a  definite  form, 
a  consistency  which  is  different  in  different  animal  forms  and  different  kinds 
of  cell;  it  is  indissoluble  in  water  and  possesses,  when  it  is  free  to  do  so,  an 
independent  power  of  motion,  which  is  characteristic  for  different  cases.  It 
is  sometimes  possible  also  for  a  number  of  nuclei  to  be  surrounded  by  a  com- 
mon protoplasm,  which  again  can  afterwards  form  cell-boundaries  and  thus 
produce  isolated  cells.  The  actual  word  "cell"  Schultze  reserves  for  the  vital 
element  represented  by  the  nucleus  and  the  protoplasm,  and  this  meaning 
has  also  been  retained  since,  illogical  though  it  is,  seeing  that  the  word 
"cell"  means  a  space  ivith  walls,  whereas  the  living  cell  is  characterized 
by  the  fact  that  it  lacks  walls. 

Improvement  of  histological  technics 
This  contribution  made  by  Schultze  laid  the  foundations  on  which  cell  re- 
search has  since  been  built,  and  this  marks  a  new  era  in  the  science  of  cy- 
tology. The  aids  to  research  that  the  students  of  the  period  just  described 
had  at  their  disposal  had  been  comparatively  limited  —  microscopes  of  prim- 
itive construction,  with  which  cells  and  tissues  were  studied  in  their  natural 


MODERNBIOLOGY  405 

State  or  at  the  most  after  dissection.  Just  at  this  transition  period,  however, 
there  appears  a  new  and  far  more  perfected  method;  it  was  not  merely  that 
microscopes  were  rapidly  improved,  but  mechanical  and  chemical  means  of 
a  kind  hitherto  unknown  were  now  beginning  to  be  discovered  and  to  be- 
come widely  used.  Of  means  of  preservation  there  were  already  known  spirits 
and  certain  saline  solutions,  which,  in  conjunction  with  boiling,  were  used 
for  the  purpose  of  giving  the  objects  of  investigation  greater  durability.  Now 
the  method  was  introduced  of  "fixing,"  by  various  means  worked  out  for 
each  particular  purpose,  the  structures  that  it  was  intended  to  examine.  Of 
these  methods,  chromic  acid  was  introduced  as  early  as  in  the  thirties  by 
Jacobson,  potassium  bichromate  at  the  same  period  by  Heinrich  Muller, 
and  osmium  acid  in  the  sixties  by  Schultze,  not  to  mention  a  number  of 
similar  means  that  have  been  discovered  since.  By  the  use  of  different  colour- 
ing-matter it  is  possible  for  the  structures  thus  fixed  to  be  brought  out  clearly 
even  in  the  thinnest  and  most  transparent  sections;  in  1849  carmine  colour- 
ing was  introduced  by  Harting,  in  1863  Waldeyer's  hematoxylin  was  pro- 
duced from  Campeachy  wood,  and  in  the  same  year  Benecke's  colouring 
with  analine  associations,  which,  as  is  well  known,  have  since  then  been 
produced  in  immense  numbers.  In  1870  His  introduced  the  microtome,  an 
instrument  that  can  make  extremely  thin  sections  through  the  tissues,  the 
construction  of  which  has  been  varied  in  many  ways.  The  new  discoveries 
that  were  made  possible  by  this  methodology  belonged  to  the  next  period. 


CHAPTER    VIII 

THE    CONTINUED    DEVELOPMENT    OF    BIOLOGY    UNTIL 
THE     ADVENT     OF     DARWINISM 


I .  Experimental  Rearch  Work 

Development  of  organic  chemistry 

WHILE  BIOLOGICAL  RESEARCH  was  yielding  the  abundant  results  which 
have  been  described  above,  it  was  subject  to  very  important  in- 
fluences from  other  natural  sciences  in  two  special  spheres.  We 
have  described  how,  thanks  to  Berzelius,  chemistry  had  extended  its  inquiries 
to  the  sphere  of  living  beings,  and  how  an  immense  number  of  substances  of 
quite  a  peculiar  kind  were  analysed  and  described.  These  substances,  which 
nowhere  exist  in  inanimate  nature  and  might  consequently  appear  exclusively 
to  have  "life"  to  thank  for  their  origin,  were  called  organic  associations; 
their  existence  was  considered  to  be  one  of  the  most  palpable  proofs  that 
life  itself  was  in  its  essence  utterly  distinct  from  the  phenomena  that  take 
place  in  inanimate  nature,  and  even  independent  of  the  chemical  and  phys- 
ical laws  that  govern  lifeless  matter.  Organic  chemistry  thus  became,  the 
more  it  developed,  the  strongest  support  for  the  theory  of  a  special  life- 
force  as  the  essential  precondition  for  all  that  takes  place  in  animate  nature. 
The  theories  maintaining  this  force  therefore  gained  ground  amongst  an  ever- 
increasing  number  of  biologists;  as  we  have  seen,  Johannes  Miiller  embraced 
a  theory  of  this  nature,  as  also  did  many  of  his  school,  and  even  a  scientist 
like  Magendie,  opposed  to  speculation  though  he  was,  could  not  help  ac- 
knowledging the  invalidity  of  the  ordinary  chemical  laws  when  applied  to 
living  nature.  It  was  in  these  circumstances  that  Wohler  made  his  great  con- 
tribution to  natural  science. 

Friedrich  Wohler  was  born  in  1800  near  Frankfurt  am  Main;  he  be- 
came a  doctor,  but  after  taking  his  degree  he  devoted  himself  entirely  to 
chemistry.  In  order  to  obtain  the  best  training  available  at  the  time  he  went 
to  Berzelius  and  worked  in  his  laboratory  for  a  year  under  the  strict  control 
of  the  master.  Having  returned  home,  he  became  a  teacher  at  a  Geiverbe- 
schule  in  Berlin  and  eventually  professor  at  Gottingen,  where  he  died  in  i88i. 
He  was  a  very  distinguished  student  of  chemistry,  but  his  other  activities 
are  overshadowed  by  his  synthesis  of  urea  out  of  cyanammonium.  By  this 

406 


MODERNBIOLOGY  4°7 

discovery  an  element  of  pronounced  '•vital-  character  had  been  produced 
out  of  components  that  in  their  turn  may  be  entirely  produced  out  of  simple, 
inoreanic  elements.  This  first  synthesis  of  an  organic  element  out  of  inor- 
ganic components  was  naturally  succeeded  by  countless  others;  organic  chem- 
fstry  which  at  one  time  had  been  thought  to  embrace  elements  produced  by 
life  and  impossible  to  arrive  at  in  any  other  way,  thus  became  a  chemistry  of 
the  carbon^compounds,  the  unique  character  of  which  is  due  to  the  nature 
of  the  elements  with  which  it  operates,  but  which  otherwise  has  recourse 
entirely  to  the  methods  and  theories  of  general  chemistry.  The  science  ot 
chemistry  has  thus  become  a  knowledge  of  phenomena  that  are  governed 
throughout  nature  by  the  same  laws,  with  the  result  that  a  new  possibility 
arose  of  combining  separate  phenomena  under  one  common  point  of  view. 

Indestructibility  of  energy 
Op  still  more  radical  importance,  however,  was  another  discovery   which 
was  made  at  a  somewhat  later  date  than  that  just  mentioned  and  which  led 
to  the  well-known  law  of  the  indestructibility  of  energy.  In  earlier  times 
Leat  was  regarded  as  an  element,  a  kind  of  'fluid,"  like  electricity    and 
although  Lavoisier  proved  its  imponderability,  both  he  and  his  pupils  re- 
tained the  ancient  idea  as  to  its  essence.  Gradually,  however,  attention  was 
once  more  attracted  to  the  fact,  known  ever  since  ancient  times,  that  heat 
arises  through  friction,  whence  conclusions  were  drawn  as  to  the  connexion 
between  heat  and  mechanical  action.  The  law-bound  condition  that  arises 
therein  was  elucidated  in  the  forties  by  several  investigators  working  on 
the  subject  simultaneously  and  independently  of  one  another  -  which  only 
proves  how  ripe  for  solution  the  problem  really  was.  Although  the  phenome- 
non falls  entirely  within  the  sphere  of  physics,  there  were,  strangely  enough 
two  scientists  with  an  essentially  biological  training  who  played  a  deci  ive 
part  in  its  solution,  and  this  fact,  as  well  as  the  impottance  of  the  subject 
in  itself,  justifies  our  going  into  it  in  somewhat  greater  detail. 

Touus  Robert  Mayer  was  born  in  .814  at  Heilbronn  the  son  of  a  well- 
to-do  apothecary.  He  studied  medicine  and,  having  passed  his  examinations 
became  a  practitioner  in  his  native  town.  He  was  seized,  however,  with  a 
d  re  to  see  something  of  the  world  and  he  succeeded  in  obtaining  an  ap- 
ponment  as  a  doctor  on  a  Dutch  vessel  sailing  to  Java.  Having  returned 
home,  he  once  more  settled  down  as  a  doctor  in  Heilbronn  and  died  there 

'°  '  Du'ting  hTs'stay  in  Java  Mayer  had  noticed  that  in  venesection  the  blood 
in  the  veins  was  of  a  far  lighter  colour  than  that  in  Europe.  He  star  ed  ou 
to  discover  the  reason  for  this  and  finally  came  to  the  conclusion  that  the 
metabolism  in  the  body  is  dependent  on  the  temperature  "f/^e  "mosphe  e, 
the  warmer  the  temperature,  the  weaker  the  conversion  of  subs  ance  is  re- 
qu ird  to  be  in  order  that  the  body  may  perform  its  normal  functions 


4o8  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

retaining  its  normal  heat.  But  then  there  must  also  be  a  definite  ratio  between 
the  heat  produced  by  combustion  in  the  body  and  the  work  that  the  body 
performs  during  a  given  period,  or,  in  still  more  general  terms,  a  certain 
amount  of  heat  must  correspond  to  a  certain  amount  of  work.  Upon  his  re- 
turn home  Mayer  published  in  Liebig's  Annalen  der  Chemie  in  1841  an  essay 
in  which  he  expounded  his  theory,  and  in  connexion  therewith  the  method, 
which  is  still  in  use,  of  calculating  the  dynamical  equivalent  of  heat  when 
the  unit  of  heat  represents  the  amount  it  takes  to  heat  up  a  given  quantity 
of  water  one  degree,  and  the  unit  of  work  represents  the  force  required  to 
lift  a  given  weight  to  a  given  height  —  in  our  days  one  kilogram  one  metre. 
For  this  ratio  he  gave  a  number,  which,  however,  was  later  found  to  be  in- 
correct. Shortly  after  the  publication  of  Mayer's  report  the  English  physi- 
cist J.  P.  Joule  published  a  theory  based  on  years  of  experiment  and  having 
the  same  gist  as  Mayer's,  but  giving  a  more  correct  number  to  represent  the 
heat  equivalent;  moreover,  it  was  founded  on  more  substantial  proofs  and 
supported  by  a  greater  number  of  facts.  Then  in  the  year  1847  came  out 
Helmholtz's  essay  Von  der  Erhaltung  der  Kraft,  in  which  the  law  of  the  in- 
destructibility of  energy  was  elucidated  from  all  points  of  view  and  was  given 
its  mathematical  formula.  During  the  succeeding  years,  however,  Mayer  had 
further  elaborated  his  theory;  of  particular  value  to  biology  was  his  essay 
Die  organische  Beivegung  in  ihrem  Zusammenhange  mit  dem  Stojfwechsel,  which  was 
printed  in  1845  as  a  pamphlet  because  it  was  refused  by  the  editors  of  scien- 
tific journals.  In  this  essay  he  applies  the  law  of  the  indestructibility  of  en- 
ergy to  the  vital  phenomena  in  the  animal  and  vegetable  kingdoms,  gives 
an  account  of  the  mutual  relation  between  muscular  action  and  the  digestion 
in  the  body's  exertion  of  energy,  and  at  the  same  time  shows  the  process  of 
assimilation  in  plants  to  be  the  foundation  of  life  on  the  earth,  and  solar 
energy  to  be  its  ultimate  source.  In  consequence  of  this  he  feels  it  to  be 
superfluous  to  assume  a  special  life-force  as  a  source  of  the  metabolism  in 
the  living  body.  This  caused  but  little  feeling  of  satisfaction  amongst  the 
biologists  of  his  age;  as  a  matter  of  fact,  the  whole  theory  of  the  nature  of 
force  met  with  opposition  even  on  the  part  of  the  older  physicists.  When 
this  theory  eventually  won  the  day,  Mayer  considered  that  due  attention 
had  not  been  paid  to  his  right  of  priority.  This  wounded  his  naturally  sen- 
sitive feelings,  which  were  exposed  to  still  more  serious  shocks  in  the  year 
of  the  revolution,  1848;  he  was,  in  fact,  from  both  a  political  and  a  religious 
point  of  view,  strictly  conservative,  with  the  result  that  he  joined  a  differ- 
ent camp  from  that  of  the  majority  of  natural  scientists,  who  were  for  the 
most  part  liberals,  and  besides  he  fell  out  with  his  brothers,  who  took  part 
in  the  revolution.  As  a  result  of  all  these  vicissitudes  his  nerves  were  com- 
pletely shattered;  finally,  after  an  attempt  at  suicide,  he  had  to  be  placed 
under  restraint,  and  in  accordance  with  the  custom  of  the  time  he  was  put 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  409 

into  a  strait  waistcoat.  By  degrees,  however,  he  recovered  his  health  and 
in  his  old  age  had  the  satisfaction  of  being  universally  recognized  as  the  one 
who  had  first  laid  down  the  principle  of  the  conservation  of  energy. 

Of  Mayer's  rivals  Joule  belongs  entirely  to  the  history  of  physics.  Helm- 
holtz,  on  the  other  hand,  worked  both  as  a  physicist  and  as  a  biologist 
and  therefore  deserves  further  mention  in  this  place.  Hermann  Ludwig  Fer- 
dinand Helmholtz  was  born  in  i8ii  at  Potsdam,  where  his  father  was  a 
teacher  in  the  gymnasium.  He  studied  medicine  in  Berlin,  where  he  was  one 
of  J.  Miiller's  pupils,  and  became  first  of  all  an  army  doctor,  afterwards  being 
appointed  professor  of  physiology  at  Konigsberg  (in  1849),  ^^'^  later  holding 
the  same  appointment  at  Bonn  and  Heidelberg.  In  1871,  however,  he  was 
made  professor  of  physics  at  the  University  of  Berlin,  and  somewhat  later 
he  became  director  of  a  newly-founded  physico-technical  institute  at  Char- 
lottenburg.  These  two  posts  he  held  until  his  death,  in  1894.  Being  univer- 
sally regarded  as  one  of  the  foremost  scientists  of  his  day,  he  was  the  recipient 
of  innumerable  honours  both  at  home  and  abroad.  His  research  activities 
were  also  as  multifarious  as  any  that  natural  science  has  had  to  record  in 
recent  times.  As  his  career  testifies,  he  was  an  expert  in  both  biology  and 
physics;  besides  this,  he  was  not  only  a  mathematician  and  a  philosopher 
of  high  standing,  but  also  an  excellent  stylist  and  an  eloquent  speaker.  As 
his  doctor's  dissertation  he  published  a  valuable  account  of  the  nerve-cells 
in  ganglia  and  the  nervous  ramifications  emanating  therefrom  in  different 
animal  forms.  His  measurement  of  the  rapidity  of  the  reproduction  of  im- 
pressions through  nerve-fibres  was  of  fundamental  importance.  Of  still 
greater  significance,  however,  was  his  work  as  a  sense-physiologist.  Modern 
physiological  optics  in  particular  were  in  all  essentials  founded  by  him.  He 
invented  the  ophthalmoscope,  by  the  aid  of  which  it  has  become  possible  for 
doctors  to  examine  the  retina  of  the  eye;  he  further  explained  the  mechanism 
of  lens-accommodation  and  also  founded  the  theory  of  colours  and  colour- 
perceptions  that  has  been  adopted  in  modern  times.  Physiological  acoustics 
were  likewise  founded  by  him;  he  explained  the  connexion  and  mechanical 
action  of  the  bones  of  the  ear,  as  also  the  part  played  by  the  organ  of  Corti 
in  the  perception  of  tone  quality.  Again,  from  the  point  of  view  of  purely 
theoretical  science,  he  worked  out  a  theory  of  the  sense-perceptions,  in 
which  he  dealt  with  such  abstract  and  complicated  questions  as  the  rela- 
tion of  the  geometrical  quantities  to  the  conception  of  sense,  and  the  justi- 
fication of  the  geometrical  principles  based  thereon.  His  purely  physical 
and  mathematical  work  naturally  falls  outside  the  scope  of  this  history. 

Helmholtz  works  out  the  theory  of  indestructibility 
The  above-mentioned  paper  tjher  die  Erhaltung  der  Kraft  (On  the  Conservation 
of  Forced,  nevertheless,  deserves  further  mention  here.  As  a  result  of  it,  the 
law  of  the  conservation  of  energy  was  given  the  theoretical  formula  that 


4IO  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

has  been  adopted  ever  since.  Helmholtz,  who  was  physicist,  mathematician, 
and  biologist,  had,  in  fact,  special  qualifications  for  laying  down  on  an  em- 
pirical basis  an  exact  formula  for  this  generally  accepted  principle,  and  dur- 
ing the  succeeding  epoch  it  was  his  name  that  was  most  often  associated 
with  this  radical  change  in  the  general  conception  of  nature.  It  was  this  very 
contribution,  however,  that  caused  Helmholtz  a  good  deal  of  unpleasant- 
ness. In  his  paper  he  had  made  no  mention  of  Mayer,  because  he  was  not 
aware  of  his  first  essay,  but  in  a  later  lecture  he  fully  acknowledged  Mayer's 
priority.  This,  however,  was  not  enough  to  satisfy  Mayer's  admirers;  one  of 
them,  E.  Diihring,  a  lecturer  in  philosophy,  made  an  extremely  bitter  and  per- 
sonal attack  on  Helmholtz,  as  if  he  had  sought  to  appropriate  an  honour  to 
which  he  had  no  right.  Disciplinary  action  was  taken  against  Diihring,  but 
Helmholtz  kept  silent  until  Mayer,  broken  in  health,  had  passed  away;  then 
he  took  up  the  challenge  and  pointed  out  how  Mayer,  with  all  due  acknowl- 
edgment both  to  his  genius  and  to  his  right  of  priority,  had  nevertheless 
based  his  views  on  speculation  rather  than  on  empirical  research.  On  this 
point  Helmholtz  was  undoubtedly  right;  Mayer  was  no  experimental  scien- 
tist —  he  never  had  a  laboratory  at  his  disposal  —  but  he  was  a  brilliant 
thinker  who,  with  the  aid  of  the  observations  of  others  and  his  own  ideas, 
achieved  his  epoch-making  results  by  theoretical  means.  The  history  of 
natural  science  proves,  however,  that  theoretical  conclusions  of  this  kind  are 
seldom  given  the  same  significance  as  conclusions  drawn  from  the  student's 
own  empirical  observations  —  Swedenborg's  brilliant  scientific  speculation, 
which,  though  the  work  of  a  genius,  was  nevertheless  forgotten  by  the  im- 
mediately succeeding  generations,  is  of  course  the  classical  example  of  this  — 
and  besides  through  his  ill  health  Mayer  was  prevented  from  following  up 
his  idea,  which  he  would  undoubtedly  have  done  had  circumstances  per- 
mitted. As  it  was,  he  had  to  divide  the  honour  with  Joule,  the  experimenter, 
and  Helmholtz,  the  universally  trained  thinker  and  observer;  all  three  con- 
tributed towards  working  out  the  principle  of  the  conservation  of  energy  — 
certainly  the  most  important  theoretical  contribution  of  the  past  century  in 
the  field  of  natural  science. 

Through  the  principle  of  the  conservation  of  energy  the  experimental 
study  of  living  organisms  received  a  powerful  stimulus;  immediate  steps  were 
taken  to  apply  to  as  many  life-phenomena  as  possible  this  new  conception, 
which  placed  all  phenomena  in  existence,  both  animate  and  inanimate,  in 
one  single  simple  and  clear  causal  connexion,  and  which  offered  the  hope  of 
being  able  to  bring  all  manifestations  of  life,  even  the  most  complex,  under 
the  same  simple  explanatory  principles  that  physics  and  chemistry  had  al- 
ready adopted.  The  following  decades  were  therefore  a  period  of  brilliant 
achievement  in  the  field  of  experimental  physiology;  both  its  aims  and  its 
methods  took  definite  form  during  that  period,  so  that  in  the  medical  fac- 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  411 

ulties  at  the  universities  this  science  likewise  has  its  own  representatives  and 
its  own  laboratories  provided  with  special  equipment.  One  or  two  of  the 
most  important  representatives  of  this  line  of  research  will  be  cited  here  as 
examples  showing  the  aims  of  physiology  during  this  period  and  its  attempts 
to  realize  them. 

Emil  du  Bois-Reymond  was  born  in  1818  in  Berlin.  His  parents  were  of 
French  extraction  and  came  from  Neuchatel,  which  then  belonged  to  Prus- 
sia. Some  time  after  their  son's  birth  they  moved  back  to  their  home  district, 
so  that  the  boy  grew  up  in  a  French  environment,  but  at  the  same  time, 
thanks  to  family  influence  —  his  father  was  a  Prussian  official  —  he  ac- 
quired a  strong  affection  for  Prussia.  After  completing  his  school  studies, 
therefore,  he  went  to  the  University  of  Berlin,  where,  after  some  wavering 
as  to  a  career,  he  applied  himself  to  medical  studies  and  became  a  pupil  of 
J.  Miiller.  In  1858  he  became  Miiller's  successor  as  professor  of  physiology 
and  held  this  post  until  his  death,  in  1896.  He  never  had  any  very  large  cir- 
cle of  pupils;  but  the  influence  on  the  educated  public  which  he  exercised 
as  secretary  to  the  Berlin  Academy  of  Science  was  all  the  greater.  The  lec- 
tures that  he  had  to  hold  annually  in  this  capacity  proved  to  be  brilliantly 
eloquent;  he  usually  took  some  subject  from  the  theory  of  history  or  natu- 
ral science,  sometimes  even  discussing  political  questions  of  the  day,  for 
Du  Bois-Reymond  was,  in  spite  of  his  French  mother-tongue,  a  warm  Ger- 
man, or  rather  Prussian,  patriot,  with  an  almost  devout  reverence  for  the 
reigning  family.  These  lectures  displayed  deep  scientific  general  knowledge 
and  keenness  of  thought  and  they  possessed  a  lasting  value  in  German  lit- 
erature. 

Electric  currents  in  the  living  body 
In  1840  Du  Bois-Reymond  was  commissioned  by  J.  Miiller  to  study  the  phe- 
nomena of  electric  currents  in  the  nervous  and  muscular  systems  and  he  was 
thus  led  to  take  up  a  field  of  research  that  he  never  afterwards  abandoned. 
He  recorded  his  results  in  an  important  work  entitled  Untersucbungen  tiber 
tierische  Electrizitdt,  the  first  part  of  which  came  out  in  1848,  hut  the  work 
was  never  completed;  the  last  part  was  published  in  1884.  Au  R.  Tigerstedt 
has  justly  remarked,  it  is  seldom  that  an  investigator  has  for  so  long  occupied 
himself  exclusively  with  so  limited  a  sphere  of  research.  That  Du  Bois-Rey- 
mond must  nevertheless  be  counted  amongst  the  pioneering  natural  scien- 
tists of  his  age  is  due  to  the  general  principles  he  expressed  and  consistently 
applied  in  his  research  work.  In  the  foreword  to  his  great  book  he  expounds 
his  ideas  on  the  innermost  essence  of  vital  phenomena,  and  pf-obably  the 
weaker  sides  of  the  vitalistic  theory  have  never  before  and  seldom  since 
been  subject  to  such  keen  and  striking  criticism  as  here.  The  old  life-force 
is  reviewed  from  all  sides  and  the  arguments  in  its  favour  are  refuted  one 
after  another;  the  finality  of  the  living  organisms,  which  so  impressed 


411  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

J.  Miiller,  is  rejected  in  view  of  the  equal  finality  prevailing  in  the  inanimate 
universe;  the  life-force's  quality  of  resisting  the  chemical  disintegration  of 
the  organism  —  the  basis  of  Stahl's  and  Bichat's  systems  —  is  likewise  cast 
aside  in  consideration  of  the  fact  that  a  force  which  without  a  struggle  aban- 
dons its  material  foundation  is  inconceivable,  for  force  is  in  reality  nothing 
but  a  quality  of  matter;  both  belong  to  one  another  and  together  represent 
an  expression  for  natural  phenomena,  such  as  science  imagines  them  to  be. 
Force  and  matter  are  ' '  von  verscbiedenen  Standptinkten  aus  auj gcnotnmene  Ah- 
stractionen  der  Dinge  wte  sie  sind.  Sie  ergdnzen  einander  und  sie  setzen  einander 
voraus."  From  this  he  draws  the  bold  conclusion  that  the  difference  between 
organic  and  inorganic  nature  is  of  no  importance  whatever,  and  he  finds  ad- 
ditional support  for  this  assertion  in  the  principle  of  the  permanence  of  force 
as  formulated  by  Helmholtz.  He  maintains  also  that  if  the  organism  presents 
phenomena  which  do  not  exist  in  inorganic  nature,  this  may  be  due  to  the 
fact  that  the  elements  intrinsic  in  them,  though  they  may  be  provided  with 
the  same  qualities  and  none  others,  nevertheless  enter  into  new  connexions 
with  one  another  and  therefore  display  new  qualities.  On  these  grounds  phys- 
iology should  come  entirely  under  organic  physics  and  chemistry.  His  own 
contribution  to  this  plan  consists  in  his  investigations  into  electrical  phe- 
nomena in  the  animal  kingdom.  His  most  important  discovery  in  this  field 
is  the  very  fact  that  the  muscles  and  nerves  of  animals  during  their  state  of 
activity  produce  electric  currents  that  can  be  observed  and  measured  with 
the  aid  of  the  usual  apparatus  of  electro-physics.  As  a  result  of  his  study  of 
these  currents  he  demonstrated  in  practice  that  phenomena  which  in  the 
most  marked  degree  belonged  to  the  manifestations  of  life  may  be  dealt  w4th 
with  quite  as  much  exactitude  as  the  ordinary  physical  phenomena,  thereby 
providing  the  most  patent  proofs  of  his  theory  of  the  physico-chemical  qual- 
ities of  vital  phenomena.  He  based  his  explanation  of  these  electrical  phe- 
nomena, however,  upon  a  theory  that  is  untenable,  a  theory  according  to 
which  the  muscles  and  nerves  are  composed  of  a  kind  of  electrical  molecules. 
Generally  speaking,  it  was  a  weak  point  in  the  physiologists  of  that  era 
that  they  overlooked  the  complex  structural  conditions  of  cells  and  tissues 
and  were  thus  tempted  to  deal  with  the  phenomena  of  life  more  schemati- 
cally than  accords  with  the  reality. 

Besides  this  limited  but  nevertheless  important  specialized  research,  Du 
Bois-Reymond,  as  already  mentioned,  contributed  a  number  of  ideas  on  ques- 
tions of  general  science;  specially  remarkable  is  his  lecture  "  Uber  die  Gren- 
Xen  des  Naturerkennens"  (iSyi),  wherein  he  seeks  to  establish  the  limits  of 
natural  research  and  comes  to  the  conclusion  that,  though  biology  might 
eventually  master  the  laws  governing  vital  phenomena  as  completely  as 
the  astronomers  when  they  calculate  the  motions  of  the  heavenly  bodies, 
yet  science  would  never  be  able  to  determine  what  matter  is  or  what  con- 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  413 

sciousness  is;  in  regard  to  both  these  fundamental  hypotheses  science  must 
pronounce  not  only  an  "ignoramus,"  but  also  an  "  ignorabhnus."  While  this 
statement  was  received  with  unreserved  approbation  in  many  quarters  — 
inter  alia,  by  such  a  keen-minded  thinker  as  Albert  Lange  —  on  the  other 
hand,  it  excited  feelings  of  extraordinary  bitterness  on  the  part  of  radical 
students  of  nature,  headed  by  Haeckel.  However,  this  subject,  as  also  Du 
Bois-Reymond's  opinions  regarding  the  theory  of  origin,  belongs  to  the 
next  period  and  will  be  dealt  with  when  the  time  comes  to  describe  it. 

Karl  Friedrich  Wilhelm  Ludwig  appears  by  the  side  of  Helmholtz 
and  Du  Bois-Reymond  as  a  pioneer  in  the  field  of  exact  physiology.  He  was 
born  at  Hessen  in  1816,  studied  at  Marburg  and  Erlangen,  and,  having  taken 
his  doctor's  degree,  spent  some  time  in  Berlin,  where  he  joined  J.  Miiller's 
circle,  without,  however,  being  included  among  his  direct  pupils.  In  1846 
he  became  professor  of  physiology  at  Zurich,  and  was  called  thence  to  Vienna 
and  later  to  Leipzig,  where  a  new  institute  was  founded  for  his  benefit.  There 
he  laboured  for  thirty  years  as  a  professor,  gathering  around  him  pupils 
from  all  countries.  He  possessed  rare  powers  of  organization,  which  were 
best  displayed  in  the  manner  in  which  he  arranged  and  guided  his  pupils' 
work.  In  his  earlier  years  he  developed,  with  their  assistance,  a  considerable 
literary  production;  later  on  he  preferred,  modest  as  he  was,  to  let  his  pupils 
publish  the  ideas  he  suggested  to  them.  Universally  respected,  he  worked 
with  undiminished  powers  until  the  end;  he  died  in  1895. 

Ludwig's  original  investigations  primarily  concern  the  functions  of  the 
vegetative  organs.  Thus,  he  has  explained  the  connexion  between  the  secre- 
tion of  the  salivary  glands  and  the  nerves  that  affect  those  organs;  he  investi- 
gated the  function  of  the  heart  in  detail  and  analysed  its  various  phases;  he 
experimented  with  the  circulation  of  the  blood  and  took  valuable  measure- 
ments of  its  rapidity.  Furthermore,  he  invented  the  graphic  method,  which 
has  since  then  played  an  important  part  in  physiology.  In  a  Lehrbuch  der  Phy- 
siologic of  the  year  i85x  he  summarized  his  views  on  the  phenomena  of  life. 
Characteristically  enough,  this  work  starts  with  a  chapter  on  Physiologie  der 
Atome,"  which  is  really  a  survey  of  animal  chemistry,  while  the  following 
chapter,  "Physiologie  der  Aggrcgatzustdnde,"  deals  with  the  phenomena  of  dis- 
solution, diffusion,  and  currents.  Consequently  the  functions  of  the  different 
organs  are  presented  from  a  purely  physical  and  chemical  point  of  view,  the 
author's  special  subjects,  the  phenomena  of  circulation  and  secretion,  natu- 
rally receiving  specially  radical  and  expert  treatment.  Ludwig's  teaching 
was,  of  course,  conducted  on  similar  lines;  through  his  pupils  the  conception 
of  vital  phenomena  here  described  spread  to  all  civilized  countries. 

Of  radical  importance  for  the  development  of  biology  was  the  fact  that 
the  vital  phenomena  were  thus  explained  by  means  of  the  same  experimental 
method  that  had  been  worked  out  earlier  in  physics  and  chemistry;  it  was 


414  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

established  once  and  for  all  that  the  same  processes  that  take  place  in  inor- 
ganic nature  exist  also  in  the  living  organism  —  in  other  words,  every  vital 
process  has  its  purely  physico-chemical  progress.  As  usual,  however,  the 
great  advance  thus  made  led  to  an  overestimation  of  the  possibilities  thereby 
opened  up  for  science;  the  pioneers  of  experimental  biology,  as  R.  Tigerstedt 
justly  remarks,  entirely  overlooked  the  part  played  by  the  cell  and  its  various 
structural  forms  in  the  vital  processes.  They  saw  in  the  living  body  merely 
the  basis  for  simple  physical  and  chemical  processes  and  they  overlooked  the 
extremely  complex  structures  which  represent  the  fundamental  condition  for 
the  operation  of  these  forces  and  on  account  of  which  the  phenomena  of  life 
actually  become  infinitely  more  complex  than  the  physiologists  were  pre- 
pared to  admit.  As,  later  on,  knowledge  of  the  cell-structure  increased,  there 
arose  in  connexion  therewith  a  mistrust  of  the  over-simplified  idea  of  the 
phenomena  of  life,  which  in  certain  quarters  caused  a  return  to  that  vitalis- 
tic  biology  that  exact  physiology  imagined  it  had  disposed  of  for  all  time. 
We  shall  shortly  make  the  acquaintance  of  this  so-called  neo-vitalism. 


2..   Morphology  and  Classification 

As  far  as  comparative  anatomy  and  morphology  are  concerned,  the  period  we 
are  now  describing  is  one  of  transition,  during  which  the  remains  of  the  old 
natural-philosophical  manner  of  viewing  life  appears  side  by  side  with  ideas 
produced  by  the  great  discoveries  that  have  been  recorded  in  the  foregoing. 
Besides  this,  we  find  in  the  research  work  of  this  era  much  that  fore-shadows 
the  advent  of  the  origin-of-species  theory.  A  review  of  the  most  important 
events  in  the  morphological  research  work  of  this  period  will  therefore 
form  a  suitable  transition  to  the  great  epoch-making  discovery  of  the  sixties. 
Contemporary  with  J.  Miiller  in  Germany  there  appeared  in  England 
a  comparative  anatomist  of  more  than  ordinarily  wide  significance.  Richard 
Owen  was  born  in  1804  at  Lancaster,  the  son  of  a  merchant.  At  school  he 
gave  no  special  indication  of  genius  and  was  therefore  apprenticed  to  an 
apothecary;  then,  after  some  years,  he  went  to  Edinburgh  to  study  medi- 
cine and  there  obtained  his  doctor's  degree.  Having  established  himself  in 
practice  in  London,  he  devoted  his  leisure  hours  to  the  study  of  anatomy  and 
as  a  result  of  his  work  on  the  subject,  he  became  an  amanuensis  at  the  Hunter 
Museum,  and  later,  after  the  resignation  of  Charles  Bell,  he  was  appointed 
its  director.  In  i860  he  was  made  head  of  the  natural-science  department  of 
the  British  Museum  and  carried  out  its  removal  to  South  Kensington.  He 
held  his  position  for  an  extraordinary  length  of  time;  in  his  eightieth  year 
he  resigned  and  after  that  lived  for  some  years  in  retirement;  after  failing  in 
health  for  some  time  he  died  in  1891, 


Pi 

< 
ffl 

2 

o 
> 

H 

w 
1-1 


w 
h-) 
h-1 


e4 
H 

w 

w 

2; 

< 

X 

o 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  415 

Owen  is  generally  counted  as  England's  greatest  comparative  anato- 
mist. His  activities  were  extraordinarily  many-sided,  and,  thanks  to  his 
position  as  head  of  one  of  the  world's  largest  museums,  he  had  particularly 
favourable  opportunities  for  investigating  a  quantity  of  rare  animal  forms, 
both  still  existing  and  extinct,  which  he  described  in  essays  illustrated  with 
very  fine  and  carefully  drawn  pictures.  Among  these  special  investigations 
may  be  mentioned  his  description  of  the  nautilus  —  the  first  specimen  that 
had  ever  been  seen  of  the  animal  itself,  the  shell  of  which,  however,  had 
been  known  since  antiquity,  and,  further,  the  anatomy  of  the  Brachiopoda 
and  the  lung-fishes.  Furthermore,  he  made  a  thorough  study  of  the  gorilla 
and  certain  other  rare  forms  of  the  ape  family  and  the  curious  finger-animals 
from  Madagascar;  and  amongst  fossil  forms,  the  Saurian  bird,  Archnsop- 
teryx,  and  the  extinct  giant  birds  of  New  Zealand.  His  monumental  work 
on  dental  forms  in  the  Vertebrata  should  also  be  recorded. 

Homology  and  analogy 
On  the  basis  of  this  unique  wealth  of  material  he  built  up  a  number  of  theo- 
retical speculations  upon  the  organization  of  the  entire  animal  kingdom, 
which  had  a  great  influence  on  the  biology  of  the  succeeding  age.  In  one  of 
the  courses  of  lectures  which  he  as  curator  of  the  Hunter  Museum  had  to 
give  each  year  on  the  subject  of  comparative  anatomy,  he  takes  as  his  start- 
ing-point his  predecessor's  plan  of  comparing  the  same  organ  through  all 
the  animal  groups  and  combines  it  with  Cuvier's  principle  of  examining  the 
mutual  relationship  of  the  different  organs  in  one  and  the  same  animal  form 
in  order  to  be  able  thus  to  ascertain  the  causes  of  the  changes  that  the  organs 
have  undergone  in  the  different  animal  types.  As  a  matter  of  fact,  he  adheres 
to  Cuvier's  type  theory  throughout,  condemning  Bonnet's  simple  evolutional 
series  covering  the  entire  animal  kingdom.  In  making  this  comparison,  he 
proves  that  the  same  function  can  be  exercised  in  different  animal  forms 
partly  by  similar  and  partly  by  entirely  dissimilar  organs;  the  dragon-lizard 
flies  with  its  outstretched  ribs,  the  flying  fish  and  the  bird  with  their  extremi- 
ties, the  insects,  again,  with  folds  in  the  skin,  which  were  originally  gills. 
This  last  idea,  according  to  his  own  statement,  he  got  from  Oken;  the  gills 
of  the  fishes  and  the  lungs  of  the  higher  animals  possess  the  same  function, 
but  are  not  the  same  organs;  rather  the  swimming-bladder  and  the  lungs 
correspond  to  one  another,  as  is  proved  by  the  lung-fishes.  This  contrasting 
relation  between  the  function  and  the  character  of  the  organs  he  expresses 
by  the  terms  "analogy"  and  "homology";  "analogue"  denotes  "a  part 
or  organ  in  one  animal  which  has  the  same  function  as  another  part  or  organ 
in  a  different  animal,"  and  "homologue"  denotes  "the  same  organ  in  dif- 
ferent animals  under  every  variety  of  form  and  function."  The  homologies 
are  of  course  the  object  of  his  special  interest,  chiefly  those  in  the  Verte- 
brata, the  bone-structure  of  which  he  made  the  subject  of  a  special  work. 


4l6  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

He  there  mentions  three  distinct  types  of  homologies:  special  homology,  or 
agreement  between  a  part  or  an  organ  and  a  part  or  an  organ  in  another 
animal;  general  homology,  or  the  relation  between  an  organ  or  a  series  of 
organs  and  the  general  type  in  conformity  with  which  the  animal  in  ques- 
tion is  constructed;  and,  finally,  the  series  homology,  or  what  would  nowa- 
days be  called  metamerk  homology  —  that  is,  the  repetition  of  certain  organs 
in  the  same  individual,  segment  for  segment.  He  dilates  upon  these  differ- 
ent forms  of  homology,  citing  numerous  examples.  "Special"  homology  in 
particular  is  discussed  in  detail,  a  uniform  nomenclature,  on  Linnasan  lines, 
being  given  for  homologous  bones  throughout  the  whole  vertebrate  series; 
many  bones  that  had  hitherto  been  denoted  by  a  prolix  character  here  ac- 
quire for  the  first  time  names  of  their  own,  besides  which  a  number  of  other 
names  are  rejected  as  unsuitable. 

Anyone  with  any  knowledge  of  modern  comparative  anatomy  must  at 
once  realize  how  important  these  terms  and  ideas  created  by  Owen  have  been 
to  present-day  biology.  Indeed,  the  very  idea  of  homology  has  proved  one 
of  the  most  fertile  grounds  for  comparative  anatomy,  although  its  real  mean- 
ing has  become  somewhat  altered  in  the  course  of  time.  And  the  special 
applications  referred  to  —  the  comparison  between  swimming-bladders  and 
lungs,  the  derivation  of  insects'  wings  from  respiratory  organs  —  we  find 
amongst  the  most  frequently  quoted  arguments  on  behalf  of  the  modern  the- 
ory of  evolution. 

Owen  s  romanticism 
Yet  Owen  himself  was  by  no  means  a  modern  biologist  in  his  general  con- 
ception of  nature;  rather,  he  stood  considerably  nearer  romantic  natural 
philosophy.  He  was  a  great  admirer  of  Oken,  whom  he  extols  as  being  a  par- 
ticularly deep  thinker  and  whose  theory  of  the  cranium's  being  composed  of 
vertebra;  he  adopted  and  endeavoured  to  apply  further;  also  he  highly  ad- 
mired GeofFroy  Saint-Hilaire,  with  whom  he  really  has  more  spiritual  affin- 
ity than  he  has  with  Vicq  d'Azyr  and  Cuvier.  Like  GeofFroy,  he  speculates 
upon  a  common  "archetype"  for  all  vertebrates;  he  reconstructs  one  and 
illustrates  it  in  one  of  his  works,  and  to  this  archetype  are  referred  the  "gen- 
eral homologies"  mentioned  above.  And  he  preferred  not  to  recognize  the 
origin  of  the  higher  life-forms  from  the  lower  and  the  parallel  derivation 
of  the  more  highly  developed  organs  from  the  more  primitive.  He  was  ir- 
reconcilably hostile  to  Darwin's  theory  in  particular;  upon  its  appearance 
he  challenged  it  anonymously  and  in  quite  a  heated  controversial  spirit, 
which  certainly  resulted  in  the  exposure  of  a  few  weak  points,  but  showed 
a  great  lack  of  understanding  of  the  true  value  of  the  theory.  Later,  however, 
while  maintaining  the  purely  hypothetical  character  of  the  origin-of-species 
theory,  he  acknowledged  the  correctness  of  Lamarck's  assertion  that  only 
individuals  exist  and  that  the  term  "species"  is  relative.  On  account  of  this 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  417 

attitude,  however,  Owen  became  more  and  more  isolated  towards  the  end 
of  his  life,  and  after  his  death  there  were  erected  in  the  museum  he  had 
founded  the  statues  of  Darwin  and  Huxley,  but  not  his  own.  Nevertheless, 
there  are  to  be  found  deep  traces  of  his  influence  even  in  the  champions  of 
the  origin-of-species  theory,  chiefly  perhaps  in  Haeckel,  whose  principal 
work  even  in  its  very  title  —  Generelle  Morphologic  —  recalls  one  of  Owen's 
expressions  referred  to  in  the  foregoing,  and  whose  method  of  morphological 
comparison  shows  obvious  traces  of  the  influence  of  the  English  anti-Dar- 
winist. 

In  the  same  year  as  Owen  there  was  born  another  of  the  foremost  biol- 
ogists of  that  period  —  namely,  Karl  Theodor  Ernst  von  Siebold.  At 
the  time  of  his  birth  (1804)  his  father  was  a  professor  at  Wiirzburg,  but  was 
afterwards  called  to  Berlin.  The  son  studied  there  under  Rudolphi  and  at 
Gottingen  under  Blumenbach,  but  after  attaining  his  doctor's  degree  had 
to  take  up  a  practice,  first  in  the  provinces  and  afterwards  in  Danzig,  whither 
he  removed  in  order  to  have  an  opportunity  of  studying  marine  animals.  On 
account  of  his  writings  he  was  appointed  professor,  first  of  anatomy  and 
physiology  at  Erlangen,  later,  in  succession  to  Purkinje,  at  Breslau,  and 
afterwards  of  zoology  and  comparative  anatomy  at  Munich.  There  he  died 
in  1885,  having  for  some  years  previously  been  incapable  of  fulfilling  his 
duties  owing  to  ill  health. 

Besides  Siebold  we  should  mention  his  friend  Friedrich  Hermann  Stan- 
Nius  (1808-83).  Born  in  Hamburg,  he  studied  at  Breslau  and  Berlin  under 
J.  Miiller;  he  became  a  lecturer  under  him  and  later  professor  at  Rostock. 
Thanks  to  his  activities  there,  that  small  and  ill-conducted  provincial  uni- 
versity acquired  a  wide  reputation.  Unfortunately  his  career  was  prematurely 
cut  short;  after  some  years  of  failing  health  he  became  the  victim  of  an  in- 
curable mental  disease  and  spent  the  last  two  decades  of  his  life  in  an  asylum. 

The  results  of  the  collaboration  of  these  two  scientists  were  recorded  in 
a  Lehrbuch  der  vergleichenden  Anatomie,  in  which  Siebold  took  the  invertebrate 
section  and  Stannius  the  vertebrates.  This  work  was  published  in  1846  — 
that  is  to  say,  about  the  same  time  as  Owen's  work  just  referred  to,  and 
manifestly  quite  independently  of  it.  A  comparison  between  the  two  works 
is  therefore  not  without  its  interest.  In  both  the  manner  of  presentation  is 
largely  the  same;  the  organs  are  dealt  with  no  longer  throughout  the  entire 
animal  kingdom,  but  each  larger  main  group  is  considered  by  itself,  and  the 
organs  are  compared  within  that  group;  the  natural-philosophical  method 
of  comparison  of  the  early  years  of  the  century  is  abandoned.  The  two  Ger- 
man biologists  generally  avoid  all  speculation;  their  presentation  is  based 
solely  on  fact;  thus,  they  do  not  possess  the  wealth  of  ideas  of  Owen,  but 
their  presentation  is  founded  on  a  particularly  many-sided  knowledge  of 
detail;  they  also  pay  special  attention  to  microscopical  anatomy,  which 


4l8  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

Owen  does  only  in  a  minor  degree.  Through  their  comparative  anatomy 
Siebold  and  Stannius  made  an  extremely  valuable  contribution  to  the  de- 
velopment of  morphological  science.  Each  also  laboured  separately  and  pro- 
duced important  results. 

Stannius  w^as  especially  many-sided,  both  as  a  teacher  and  as  an  in- 
vestigator; he  taught  pathology,  physiology,  and  anatomy  and  has  made 
valuable  additions  to  our  knowledge  in  all  these  spheres.  As  a  physiologist 
he  became  famous  for  his  attempts  at  underbinding  the  va^^ious  parts  of 
the  heart  of  the  frog;  further,  he  investigated  the  nerves  of  the  tongue  with 
reference  to  their  functions  of  taste  and  movement,  and  also  the  dependence 
of  muscular  contraction  upon  nervous  irritation.  As  a  comparative  anato- 
mist he  was  especially  remarkable  for  the  splendid  work  he  wrote  on  the 
peripheral  nervous  system  of  the  fishes,  which  is  still  authoritative,  in  spite 
of  all  the  more  recent  work  accomplished  in  that  field. 

Siebold,  as  is  evidenced  by  the  share  he  took  in  the  Comparative  Anatomy, 
devoted  himself  mostly  to  invertebrate  research.  In  this  sphere  he  was 
without  doubt  one  of  the  foremost  of  his  age.  With  a  view  to  furthering 
the  development  of  research  in  his  own  special  sphere  he  founded,  in  asso- 
ciation with  Kolliker,  the  Zeitscbrift  fiir  wissenschaftUche  Zoologie  —  the  title 
being  chosen  of  set  purpose  in  opposition  to  the  soulless  method  of  classi- 
fication —  which  was  started  in  i^^i.  and  has  since  been  one  of  the  chief 
organs  for  the  furtherance  of  biological  science.  In  many  specialized  fields  of 
invertebrate  research  Siebold 's  contributions  have  been  considerable.  Fore- 
most in  this  regard  come  his  investigations  into  parasites.  It  may  be  recalled 
that  even  Rudolphi  believed  that  intestinal  worms  arose  as  the  result  of 
a  diseased  process  in  the  host.  At  an  early  stage  Siebold  was  quite  convinced 
that  this  kind  of  spontaneous  generation  could  not  be  accepted  as  rational. 
He  adduced  in  proof  of  this  argument  the  existence  of  large  quantities  of 
eggs  in  the  intestinal  worms,  which  obviously  indicated  that  these  animals 
reproduced  themselves  in  the  same  way  as  other  animals.  But  the  question 
that  still  required  an  answer  was  how  the  offspring  of  the  parasites  come 
to  harbour  in  a  fresh  host.  As  yet  this  question  was  insoluble.  To  answer 
it  required  a  knowledge  of  a  phenomenon  of  evolution  —  the  alternation 
of  generations  —  which  was  still  unknown  at  the  time  and  was  elucidated 
by  another  scientist,  who  must  therefore  be  described  in  this  connexion. 

Johannes  Japetus  Smith  Steenstrup  (1813-97)  was  the  son  of  a  priest 
from  Jutland,  in  Denmark;  he  studied  in  Copenhagen,  becoming  professor 
of  zoology  there  after  having  been  a  schoolmaster  for  some  years.  He  was 
an  extraordinarily  gifted  and  many-sided  investigator,  working  in  many 
widely  differing  fields  of  research;  particularly  celebrated  are  his  investiga- 
tions of  peat-mosses,  which  he  explored  not  only  for  zoological,  but  also 
for  botanical,  geological,  and  archsological  purposes.  He  also  discovered 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  419 

the  ancient  shell-mounds  from  the  Stone  Age  that  are  called  kjokkenwoddinger 
(refuse-heaps),  and  studied  them  with  valuable  zoological  and  ethnographi- 
cal results.  He  was,  moreover,  interested  in  marine  research  and  he  made  a 
discovery  in  this  field  that  more  than  anything  else  ensured  to  him  a  place 
in  the  history  of  biology  —  namely,  the  alternation  of  generations.  A.  von 
Chamisso,  famous  as  a  poet  and  circumnavigator,  had  already  proved  that 
in  the  Salpa  free  individuals  and  individuals  bound  together  in  chains  al- 
ternate with  one  another  by  generations,  but  this  discovery  had  been  almost 
entirely  neglected.  Other  observations  of  a  similar  kind  had  also  been  made 
before,  as,  for  instance,  by  Michael  Sars  in  Norway  and  Sven  Loven  in 
Sweden,  and  also  by  Siebold  himself  in  Danzig,  but  it  was  reserved  for  Steen- 
strup  to  complete  the  material  for  observation  and  to  place  it  under  one 
common  point  of  view.  In  1841  he  published  his  work  on  the  alternation 
of  generations,  in  which  he  gives  an  account  of  the  evolution  of  the  medusas, 
the  Campanularia;,  the  Salpa,  and  the  Trematoda,  and  finds  the  phenomenon 
common  to  them  all  —  namely,  that  there  exists  in  them  an  alternation  be- 
tween the  adolescent  stages,  which  he  terms  "nurses,"  because  without  sex- 
ual reproduction  they  develop  a  new  generation,  the  sexually  mature,  and 
this  sexual  stage,  which,  in  its  turn,  gives  rise  by  means  of  ordinary  sexual 
reproduction  to  new  "nurses."  Of  such  asexual  generations  he  sometimes 
finds  many,  one  after  another,  particularly  in  the  Trematoda,  in  which  they 
are  often  described  as  one  independent  genus,  the  cercarias.  In  its  details  this 
work  certainly  required  both  correction  and  completion,  but  its  service  lies 
in  the  fact  that  it  laid  down  a  common  principle  that  proved  to  be  indis- 
pensable if  a  conception  was  to  be  formed  of  the  evolution  of  a  great  many 
of  the  lower  animals.  The  fact  that  Steenstrup  regarded  these  phenomena 
from  a  strictly  romantic-philosophical  point  of  view  was  only  in  accordance 
with  the  practice  of  the  time;  he  saw  in  the  alternation  of  generations  a 
striving  on  the  part  of  nature  after  freedom  and  perfection,  and  on  these 
grounds  he  accounted  for  even  the  insect  communities  by  the  alternation 
of  generations:  the  sexless  workers  he  considered  to  be  "nurses,"  which 
devote  to  the  offspring  a  care  of  a  more  ideal  character  than  that  which  the 
Salpa  series  and  the  cercarias  give  to  their  own  progeny. 

Evolution  of  intestinal  ivorms  ascertained 
It  was  Siebold  who  now  succeeded  in  making  practical  use  of  the  alternation- 
of-generations  idea,  for  he  realized  its  fundamental  importance  for  ascer- 
taining the  evolution  of  intestinal  worms.  He  at  once  began  to  try  to  find 
out  by  experimental  means  the  connexion  between  a  number  of  parasite 
formations  that  had  hitherto  been  regarded  as  independent  of  one  another. 
Thus  he  proved  that  the  parasite  which  by  insinuating  itself  in  the  brain 
of  the  sheep  causes  the  disease  called  "gid"  or  "sturdy,"  and  which  had 
hitherto  been  described  as  Coenurus  cerebralis,  is  actually  an  adolescent  stage 


4XO  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

of  a  tapeworm  that  lives  in  the  intestinal  canal  of  the  dog  —  if  dogs  were 
fed  on  coenurus-affected  sheep's  brains  they  would  infallibly  be  infected  with 
this  tapeworm,  which  is  now  called  Tania  canurus.  Through  the  excrement 
of  the  dog  the  eggs  of  the  tapeworm  are  scattered  about  the  pastures  and 
thus  infect  the  sheep.  In  the  same  way  another  tapeworm  in  the  dog  was 
traced  to  bladder-worms  in  the  liver  of  hares,  and  a  tapeworm  in  the  cat 
to  similar  formations  in  the  rat.  Again,  the  large  and  often  fatal  liver-para- 
site echinococcus,  which  occurs  in  man,  was  found  to  give  rise  to  an  almost 
microscopically  small,  and  therefore  hitherto  unknown,  tapeworm  occurring 
in  the  dog,  the  Tania  echinococcus ,  the  eggs  of  which  are  conveyed,  through 
too  intimate  contact  with  the  dog,  to  the  human  mouth  and  thence  to  the 
intestinal  canal.  As  a  result  of  these  researches  the  knowledge  of  the  intesti- 
nal parasites,  or  helminthology,  as  it  had  already  been  termed  previously, 
was  placed  on  entirely  rational  footing,  and  it  only  remained  for  later  ob- 
servers, by  working  along  the  lines  laid  down  by  Siebold,  to  collect  fresh 
facts  in  order  to  fill  the  gaps  in  the  knowledge  of  the  subject. 

Likewise,  as  regards  insect  communities,  Siebold  produced  the  idea 
which  has  since  been  pursued  up  to  the  present  time.  At  first  he  held  with 
Steenstrup's  attempts  to  explain  the  reproduction  of  the  bees  as  a  form  of 
alternation  of  generations,  but  he  realized  his  mistake,  chiefly  through  col- 
laboration with  a  pioneer  in  the  field  of  practical  apiculture,  the  Roman 
Catholic  priest  Johann  Dzierzon  (1811-1906),  of  Silesia.  He  is  of  course 
famous  as  the  founder  of  modern  rational  bee-keeping,  and  it  was  he,  too, 
who,  notwithstanding  his  lack  of  anatomical  training,  realized  before  any- 
one else  the  true  relationship  between  the  sexes  in  the  community  life  of  the 
bees.  He  discovered  that  the  queen-bee  is  fertilized  only  once  in  her  life  and 
this  while  in  flight  through  the  air,  not  inside  the  beehive,  and  that  the 
drones  are  evolved  out  of  unfertilized  eggs,  while  workers'  and  queen-bees' 
larvas  are  developed  from  fertilized  eggs,  both  having  female  characters,  al- 
though in  the  workers  they  become  stunted,  owing  to  lack  of  nourishment. 
These  important  discoveries,  upon  which  Dzierzon  based  his  reform  of  api- 
culture, were  received  with  strong  opposition  on  the  part  of  most  bee-keepers 
and  would  certainly  have  failed  to  win  general  acceptance  had  not  Siebold 
given  them  the  support  of  his  authority.  Already  a  long  while  previously 
(in  1837)  he  had  carried  out  a  careful  investigation  into  the  bees'  sexual 
apparatus,  with  the  result  that  he  had  discovered  the  queen's  receptaculum 
seminis;  now  —  at  the  beginning  of  the  fifties  —  he  placed  himself  definitely 
on  Dzierzon 's  side  and  by  means  of  a  series  of  experiments  and  treatises  on 
the  subject  obtained  victory  for  his  views.  In  connexion  therewith  Siebold 
elucidated  for  the  first  time  the  conditions  obtaining  in  parthenogenesis  in 
insects  in  general,  thereby  introducing  into  biological  science  a  field  of  re- 
search that,  especially  in  recent  times,  has  aroused  keen  interest. 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  4x1 

By  the  side  of  Siebold,  Leuckart  deserves  mention  as  one  of  those  who 
contributed  towards  the  progress  of  biology  in  the  middle  of  last  century. 
Karl  Georg  Friedrich  Rudolf  Leuckart  was  born  in  iSiz  at  Helmstadt, 
where  his  father  was  a  business  man,  and  studied  at  Gottingen,  especially 
under  the  physiologist  Rudolf  Wagner;  he  became  a  lecturer  there,  then 
professor  of  zoology  at  Giessen  in  1855,  and  was  called  thence  to  the  same 
chair  in  Leipzig  in  1869.  There  he  worked  until  his  death,  in  1898.  Being 
still  keenly  interested  in  the  advancement  of  science  even  in  his  old  age,  he 
gathered  around  him  large  numbers  of  pupils  up  to  the  end;  helpful  and 
warm-hearted,  original  and  good-humoured,  he  won  their  affection  and  was 
universally  praised  after  his  death. 

Leuckart's  scientific  activities  were  many-sided  and  of  deep  significance. 
While  still  a  young  lecturer  he  published  an  epoch-making  work,  Uber  die 
Morpbologk  der  wirbellosen  Tiere.  "Descriptive  zoology,"  he  says,  "must  per- 
mit of  the  same  comparative,  morphological  treatment  as  anatomy."  From 
this  point  of  view  he  discusses  the  zoological  system  prevalent  at  the  time, 
taking  as  his  starting-point  Cuvier,  whose  type  theory  he  unreservedly  de- 
fends against  the  earlier  belief  in  one  single  evolutional  series,  at  the  same 
time  upholding  the  idea  of  idealistic  morphology  of  a  fundamental  form 
after  which  "nature  has  constructed"  the  separate  life-forms.  Leuckart  is 
definitely  opposed  to  such  systematical  categories  as  are  based  upon  nega- 
tive characters,  as,  for  instance,  the  Lamarckian  group  of  Invertebrata.  Nor 
indeed  do  Cuvier' s  four  types  meet  the  requirements  of  comparative  mor- 
phology: apart  from  the  Protozoa,  whose  then  still  undiscovered  structure 
did  not  permit  of  definitive  morphological  treatment,  and  the  Vertebrata, 
whose  place  was  already  established,  Leuckart  sets  up  five  fundamental  types 
—  namely,  Coelenterata,  Echinodermata,  Vermes,  Arthropoda,  and  Mol- 
lusca.  These  have,  of  course,  been  generally  accepted  since  then,  although 
with  sundry  modifications:  Vermes  have  been  further  divided  and  Tunicata 
have  been  separated  from  the  Mollusca.  Through  this  reform,  however, 
Leuckart  brought  the  system  a  good  step  nearer  the  point  that  it  has  reached 
today.  In  particular  his  treatment  of  the  Coelenterata  was  epoch-making; 
besides  establishing  the  difference  in  anatomical  structure  between  them  and 
the  similarly  radially  symmetrical  Echinodermata,  he  explains  the  curious 
division  of  labour  that  takes  place  between  the  individuals  in  certain  colony- 
building  forms  within  this  class,  principally  in  the  group  Siphonophora, 
wherein  the  individuals  in  a  colony  are  converted  for  the  purpose  of  per- 
forming a  number  of  special  functions  necessary  for  the  welfare  of  the  whole 
community.  As  a  result  of  this  elucidation  of  the  structure  of  these  so-called 
"polymorphous"  animal  stocks,  to  a  certain  extent  fresh  light  was  thrown 
on  the  term  "individual"  in  the  animal  kingdom.  The  fact  that  Leuckart 
believed  he  could  compare  the  plants  in  general  with  these  colony-formations 


42-2.  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

does  not  detract  very  much  from  the  value  of  the  service  he  rendered  in 
throwing  light  on  an  important  field  in  the  biology  of  the  lower  animals. 

Leuckart's  discovery  of  micropj/le 
Leuckart  made  another  valuable  contribution  to  the  development  of  bi- 
ology in  his  discovery  that  the  thick-shelled  egg  of  insects  is  invariably 
provided  with  a  canal  through  which  fertilization  takes  place.  This  canal, 
which  Leuckart,  associating  it  with  a  corresponding  formation  in  the  vege- 
table kingdom,  called  "micropyle,"  was  studied  by  him  with  great  thor- 
oughness in  a  large  number  of  eggs  of  various  insects.  His  investigation  led 
him  to  the  discovery  that  the  spermatozoa  actually  do  penetrate  into  the 
yolk  of  the  egg  through  the  canal  —  a  discovery  that  essentially  deepened 
our  knowledge  of  fertilization.  That  the  spermatozoa  thus  play  a  vital  part 
in  fertilization  was  a  point  which  many  investigators  have  had  difficulty  in 
realizing;  after  all,  it  was  not  so  long  ago  that  Spallanzani's  theory  of  the 
decisive  importance  of  the  spermatic  fluid  had  eminent  supporters.  J.  Miiller, 
it  is  true,  had  already  discovered  a  similar  canal  in  the  eggs  of  the  sea-urchin, 
but  it  was  Leuckart  who  proved  its  widespread  existence  and  thereby  also 
its  significance.  Henceforth  there  was  no  doubt  that  the  spermatozoon  pro- 
duced fertilization  by  penetrating  the  egg;  it  was  then  reserved  for  the  fu- 
ture to  ascertain  the  cytological  course  of  development. 

Of  Leuckart's  other  works  should  be  mentioned  his  investigations  of 
the  Spongida,  which  he  referred  to  the  Coelenterata  as  a  result  of  detailed 
study  of  their  structure.  Further,  his  experiments  on  the  intestinal  worms, 
conducted  in  competition  with  Siebold;  it  was  Leuckart  who  found  out  the 
evolutional  process  in  the  two  well-known  human  parasites  Tania  solium 
and  saginata,  as  also  in  the  liver-fluke,  which  is  so  fatal  to  domestic  animals. 
It  was  also  thanks  to  him  that  the  Trichinas  first  became  thoroughly  known. 
His  important  text-book  on  the  human  parasites  is  the  work  on  which  all 
subsequent  research  in  this  field  has  been  based. 

A  peculiar  form  of  parasitism  is  presented  by  the  crustaceans  that  make 
fishes  their  hosts;  in  these  the  parasitic  degeneration  assumes  forms  such  as 
scarcely  exist  anywhere  in  the  rest  of  the  animal  kingdom.  The  first  real 
knowledge  of  these  animal  forms  was  established  by  Alexander  von  Nord- 
MANN.  He  was  born  in  1805  of  a  Germanized  Finnish  family  in  the  county 
of  Wiborg,  Finland,  studied  at  Abo  and  from  there  went  to  Berlin,  where 
he  became  a  pupil  of  Rudolphi.  There  he  wrote  his  work  Mikrographische 
Beitrage,  in  which  he  deals  with  certain  parasitic  Trematoda,  but  chiefly 
with  the  parasitic  Crustacea,  which  were  hereby  brought  to  the  knowledge 
of  science.  The  work  attracted  universal  notice;  J.  Miiller  in  a  letter  speaks 
of  its  "  herrliche  Beobachtungen,"  and  on  account  of  it  the  author  was  called 
to  a  professorial  chair  in  Odessa.  There  he  applied  himself  to  exploring  the 
animal  world  of  South  Russia,  both  recent  and  extinct,  which  he  described 


MODERNBIOLOGY  4^3 

in  a  number  of  important  works.  In  1849  he  was  appointed  professor  in  Hel- 
singfors,  where  he  laboured  until  his  death,  in  1866.  In  his  old  age  he  be- 
came an  original  character,  and  nothing  of  his  later  production  achieved 
the  fame  of  his  early  work. 

The  epoch  now  under  discussion  was  on  the  whole  prolific  in  bio- 
logical students  of  high  distinction;  in  the  foregoing  it  has  been  possible  to 
name  only  a  few  of  those  who  took  a  prominent  part  in  furthering  the  de- 
velopment of  the  science  in  particular  branches;  we  shall  now  mention  a 
further  group  of  important  scientists  who  made  a  special  study  of  marine 
research  and,  above  all,  investigated  the  hitherto  practically  untouched 
lower  animal  world  of  the  ocean.  Scandinavia  was  at  the  time  one  of  the 
main  quarters  of  Europe  in  which  interest  was  awakened  in  marine  biology. 
As  one  of  its  original  promoters  the  Norwegian  Michael  Sars  is  worthy  of 
mention.  Born  in  1805,  he  studied  theology  and  became  a  priest  on  the  west 
coast  of  Norway.  There  he  began  to  interest  himself  in  marine  animal  life 
and  published  his  observations  in  a  couple  of  treatises,  which  attracted 
widespread  attention.  He  continued  to  follow  the  course  he  had  thus  entered 
upon,  and  in  1854  he  became  professor  of  zoology  in  Christiania,  where  he 
worked  until  his  death,  in  1869.  Among  his  valuable  contributions  may 
be  mentioned  the  discovery  of  metamorphosis  in  the  marine  Mollusca,  his 
observations  of  the  Crinoidea  that  are  found  at  great  ocean-depths  and  his 
establishing  their  likeness  to  large  groups  of  similar  animals  from  earlier 
epochs.  He  was  a  pioneer  in  introducing  marine  research  into  Scandinavia. 

In  Sweden  the  study  of  marine  animal  life  was  taken  up  by  Sven  Ludvig 
LovEN.  Born  in  Stockholm  in  1809,  he  studied  in  Lund,  where  he  took  his 
degree,  and  in  Berlin  under  Rudolphi  and  Ehrenberg,  made  a  journey  of 
exploration  to  Spitsbergen  in  a  fishing-sloop  —  the  first  of  the  many  voyages 
of  polar  exploration  that  have  started  from  Sweden  —  and  finally  became 
curator  of  the  zoological  department  of  the  State  museum  in  Stockholm, 
where  he  laboured  for  over  fifty  years.  He  died  in  1895.  He  very  greatly 
enriched  the  museum's  collections  and  founded  Sweden's  zoological  marine 
laboratory  at  Kristineberg. 

Of  Loven's  observations,  most  frequently  published  in  the  proceedings  of 
the  Swedish  Academy  of  Science,  may  be  mentioned  his  investigation  of  the 
metamorphosis  of  the  Annelida  —  the  name  "Loven's  larva"  still  recalls 
the  fact  —  his  study  of  the  evolution  of  the  genus  Campanularia,  which 
provided  Steenstrup  with  one  of  his  ideas  for  the  alternation-of-generations 
theory,  and,  above  all,  his  investigations  into  the  evolution  of  the  marine 
Mollusca,  in  the  course  of  which  he  established  the  formation  of  the  so- 
called  polar  bodies  and  their  expulsion  from  the  egg  —  a  phenomenon  the 
evolutional  universality  of  which  was  not  determined  until  a  long  time 
afterwards.  He  was  especially  interested  in  the  embryology  of  the  lovser 


414  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

animals  and  he  carried  out  many  valuable  investigations  in  that  field.  He  re- 
tained his  youthful  interest  in  polar  research  and  keenly  promoted  Sw^edish 
voyages  of  polar  exploration  in  his  later  years.  When  the  theory  of  the  glacial 
period  was  first  advanced,  he  embraced  it  with  enthusiasm  and  produced 
valuable  zoological  proofs  of  it,  establishing  the  existence  in  some  of  the 
deeper  inland  seas  of  peculiar  animal  forms  that  otherwise  belong  to  the 
fauna  of  the  polar  seas  and  which  have  manifestly  survived  in  the  lakes 
since  some  earlier  period  when  the  sea  covered  the  land.  These  surviving 
forms  Loven  named  "relicts,"  and  since  then  Scandinavian  research  has  been 
occupied  in  their  study. 

The  foremost  Swedish  biologist  during  this  period,  however,  was  un- 
doubtedly Anders  Adolf  Retzius  (1796-1860).  Born  at  Lund,  where  his 
father  was  a  distinguished  natural  scientist,  he  studied  under  him  and  the 
anatomist  Florman,  and  later  in  Copenhagen  under  Ludvig  Jacobson.  When 
still  a  young  man  he  was  appointed  professor  at  the  Veterinary  Institute 
in  Stockholm  and  at  the  same  time  held  a  post  at  the  Carolinian  Institute, 
where  he  at  once  became  the  greatest  force  the  Institute  had  with  the  excep- 
tion of  Berzelius.  This  twofold  work  as  a  teacher,  however,  did  not  prevent 
him  from  following  up  his  biological  researches  both  at  home  and  on  expedi- 
tions, in  the  course  of  which  he  came  into  close  contact  with  many  eminent 
scientists,  including  J.  Miiller,  who  became  a  loyal  friend,  and  Purkinje,  from 
whom  he  learned  microscopical  technique.  He  is  the  pioneer  of  comparative 
anatomy  in  Sweden;  he  introduced  it  into  the  country  not  merely  as  a  sub- 
ject for  research,  but  also  —  after  overcoming  strong  opposition  on  the  part 
of  older  authorities  —  as  a  subject  of  medical  training.  His  own  works  are  ex- 
traordinarily many-sided.  A  biographer  has  said  of  them  that  they  are  seldom 
consistently  worked  out  and  that  the  whole  of  his  research  work  was  marked 
by  a  certain  restlessness.  As  a  matter  of  fact,  most  of  his  literary  production 
consists  of  short  articles  for  journals,  written  simply  in  the  form  of  notes 
without  any  theoretical  reasoning  or  even  observations  on  the  earlier  his- 
tory of  the  problem  under  discussion.  Nevertheless,  many  of  these  articles 
have  had  a  deep  influence  on  the  development  of  biology,  owing  to  the  great 
value  of  the  facts  set  forth  in  them,  as,  for  instance,  his  account  of  the  anat- 
omy of  the  Myxinoidei,  written  in  18x2.,  in  which  these  animals'  vascular 
and  nervous  systems,  head-cartilage,  and  various  other  organs  are  described 
—  a  work  which  formed  the  basis  of  J.  Miiller's  important  monograph  on 
the  Myxinoidei  —  and,  further,  his  study  of  the  connexion  between  the 
spinal  and  the  sympathetic  nervous  system  in  the  horse  —  one  of  the  first 
of  its  kind,  and  a  beautifully  illustrated  work.  Like  Purkinje,  Retzius  in- 
vestigated the  microscopical  structure  of  dental  bone,  extending  this  inves- 
tigation to  a  number  of  animal  forms.  In  1841  he  went  with  J.  Miiller  to 
the  west  coast  of  Sweden  and  there  applied  himself,  inter  alia,  to  the  study 


MODERNBIOLOGY  4x5 

of  the  Amphioxus.  In  his  later  years,  an  ophthalmic  disease  having  put  an 
end  to  his  microscopical  work,  he  entered  upon  a  new  field  of  research,  in 
which  he  undoubtedly  carried  out  the  most  important  work  of  his  life  — 
namely,  comparative  anthropology.  Till  then  this  science  had  followed  the 
lines  of  Blumenbach;  mankind  had  been  divided  into  races  for  the  most  part 
according  to  the  colour  of  the  skin.  Retzius  began  to  take  an  interest  in 
the  discovery  of  human  remains  in  the  prehistoric  graves  of  Scandinavia, 
and  in  the  course  of  his  investigations  found  considerable  variation  in  the 
shape  of  the  brain-cap.  He  extended  these  researches  to  include  other  human 
races  and  thereupon  found  that  the  skulls  may  be  divided,  according  to  the 
proportion  between  length  and  breadth,  into  long  and  short  skulls  —  doli- 
chocephalic and  brachycephalic  —  and,  further,  after  the  shape  of  the  facial 
bones,  into  orthognathic  and  prognathic.  Several  peoples  externally  akin 
were  found  to  differ  in  these  respects  — •  thus,  for  instance,  the  Germanic 
are  long-skulled,  the  Slav  short-skulled  —  and  as  a  result  of  this  idea  there 
was  created  a  field  of  human  research  based  on  true  comparative  anatomy, 
which  was  afterwards  followed  up  with  splendid  results  by  other  investi- 
gators: Virchow,  Broca,  the  younger  Retzius,  and  many  others. 

In  France  during  this  period  marine  biology  made  rapid  progress  and 
contributed  much  of  importance  to  the  general  development  of  our  knowl- 
edge in  this  sphere;  of  the  students  who  distinguished  themselves  here,  two 
are  especially  worthy  of  mention.  Henri  Milne-Edwards  (1800-85)  ^^^ 
a  native  of  Belgium,  but  of  English  descent.  He  came  early  to  Paris  and  even- 
tually worked  as  a  professor  there.  Having  been  a  pupil  of  Cuvier's,  he  car- 
ried on  with  distinction  the  latter's  work  in  the  sphere  of  invertebrate 
research.  When  quite  a  young  man  he  published  an  extremely  useful  work, 
a  comparative  study  of  the  vascular  and  nervous  systems  of  the  Crustacea; 
after  that  followed  an  extensive  work  on  the  fauna  of  the  French  coast, 
in  which  the  Annelida  in  particular  were  described  with  minute  care.  A 
masterpiece  of  its  kind  is  his  Histoin  naturelle  des  crustacees,  wherein  this 
order  is  treated  with  thoroughness  and  perspicacity,  and  a  system,  based  on 
comparative  anatomy,  is  worked  out  which  is  largely  applied  even  today. 
Further  we  may  mention  his  work  on  the  coral  animals  and  his  study  of 
the  evolution  of  the  ascidians,  as  well  as  a  large  number  of  deep-sea  investi- 
gations. 

Another  who  worked  along  the  same  lines  was  Felix  Joseph  Henri 
Lacaze-Duthiers  (182.1-1901).  Born  in  the  south  of  France  of  a  distinguished 
family,  he  devoted  himself  to  the  study  of  medicine  and  became  a  professor, 
first  of  all  at  Lille  and  then  in  Paris.  His  numerous  works  deal  chiefly  with 
the  MoUusca,  the  anatomy  and  evolution  of  which  he  worked  out  in  detail; 
amongst  other  things  he  worked  out  the  anatomy  of  the  purpura  and  its 
colour-secretion,   which  was   known   to  the  ancients,  but  had  since  been 


4^6  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

forgotten.  He  is  best  known,  however,  as  the  founder  of  France's  zoological 
marine  stations  at  RoscofF  and  Banyuls.  On  these  institutions  he  spent  large 
sums  out  of  his  own  purse  and  laid  down  the  lines  and  methods  on  which 
they  were  to  work.  Being  a  man  of  essentially  conservative  views,  it  was 
only  after  a  long  time  and  after  much  hesitation  that  he  accepted  the  theory 
of  the  origin  of  species.  He  viewed  with  scepticism  many  of  the  movements 
of  his  time;  he  had  written  up  over  the  door  of  his  laboratory  the  words: 
"Science  has  neither  religion  nor  politics"  —  a  sentiment  that  certainly  de- 
serves greater  attention  than  has  been  given  to  it  in  modern  times. 


3 .    Microbiology 

That  there  exists  a  world  of  organisms  which  owing  to  its  small  size  eludes 
observation  with  the  naked  eye  has  been  known  since  the  invention  of  the 
microscope,  but  our  knowledge  of  these  creatures  may  be  said  nevertheless 
to  begin  from  the  age  with  which  we  are  now  dealing,  when  an  improved 
microscopical  technique  first  made  possible  a  more  thorough  exploration  of 
this  extensive  field.  Leeuwenhoek,  the  foremost  microscopist  of  the  seven- 
teenth century,  discovered,  as  previously  mentioned,  a  number  of  minute 
animals,  partly  in  water  taken  from  rivers  and  lakes,  partly  in  putrefying 
matter  of  various  kinds.  He  studied  them  as  carefully  as  he  could,  was  con- 
vinced of  their  character  of  living  creatures,  and  declared  that  they  multiplied 
only  by  reproduction.  During  the  succeeding  century  these  investigations 
went  on  with  fresh  observations  in  isolated  cases,  but  without  yielding  any 
really  novel  results.  It  was  found  that  these  minute  animals  exist  especially 
in  water  which  has  been  allowed  to  stand  over  parts  of  plants  or  other  simi- 
lar growths,  and  from  the  fact  of  their  existence  in  such  "infusions"  they 
were  called  Infusoria,  or  infusion-animals.  BufFon,  in  accordance  with  his 
general  theory  of  life,  believed  them  to  be  products  of  the  life-units  existing 
everywhere,  while  Spallanzani  firmly  rejected  the  idea  of  their  spontaneous 
generation.  The  scientist  who  first  made  a  special  study  of  the  Infusoria, 
however,  was  the  Dane  O.  F.  Miiller,  who  is  therefore  worthy  of  further 
mention  in  this  connexion. 

Otto  Frederik  Muller  was  born  in  1730  in  Copenhagen,  where  his 
father  was  a  musician.  He  grew  up  in  poverty,  was  given  an  opportunity 
of  studying  theology  at  the  university,  and  then  went  in  for  jurisprudence, 
but  the  whole  time  he  had  to  earn  his  living  as  a  tutor  in  aristocratic  fami- 
lies, on  whom  his  amiable  social  qualities  made  a  particularly  favourable 
impression.  During  his  visits  to  their  estates  he  began  to  interest  himself 
in  nature,  particularly  in  insects,  which  he  collected  and  described  in  a  series 
'^^mall  treatises.  As  private  tutor  to  a  young  count  he  had  an  opportunity 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  417 

of  making  a  journey  through  Europe,  thereby  increasing  his  knowledge  and 
widening  his  connexions.  Having  returned  home,  he  received  an  oflicial  ap- 
pointment, but  resigned  from  the  Government  service  upon  contracting  a 
wealthy  marriage,  and  afterwards  lived  as  a  private  scholar  until  his  death, 
in  1784.  His  most  important  work  was  published  posthumously.  During  his 
lifetime  he  was  generally  regarded  as  an  amiable  and  kind-hearted  man, 
though  somewhat  vain.  Of  his  immense  literary  production  one  or  two  zo- 
ological works  have  preserved  his  name  for  posterity. 

As  will  be  realized  from  the  above,  O.  F.  Miiller  as  a  zoologist  was  es- 
sentially autodidactic;  he  had  educated  himself  by  studying  the  writings  of 
Linn^us,  but  he  devoted  his  research  work  to  spheres  that  Linnaeus  and  his 
pupils  had  overlooked.  In  two  works,  Entomostraca  Dania  and  Hydrachna, 
he  describes  in  detail,  and  extremely  well  considering  the  period,  two  hith- 
erto entirely  neglected  groups  of  Articulata.  Still  more  remarkable  are  his 
two  works  on  the  Infusoria,  the  last  of  which,  mentioned  above,  was  pub- 
lished by  Fabricius  in  1786.  In  these  works  he  makes  an  attempt  for  the  first 
time  to  present  a  systematic  description  and  classification  of  the  Infusoria, 
supplemented  with  detailed  diagnoses  of  genus  and  species  and  illustrated 
with  accurate  and  finely  drawn  pictures.  Quite  a  number  of  them,  especially 
the  larger  Ciliata,  he  has  described  so  well  that  they  are  still  recognizable 
and  their  names  are  still  in  use  today.  As  was  usual  in  his  age,  he  paid  but 
little  attention  to  the  internal  structure  of  the  creatures;  in  regard  to  the 
origin  of  the  Infusoria,  he  believes  in  the  spontaneous  generation  of  the  lesser 
forms,  while  assuming  that  the  larger  and  more  highly  developed  forms  mul- 
tiply by  reproduction. 

O.  F.  Miiller's  contemporaries  and  immediate  successors  made  a  number 
of  fresh  discoveries  in  the  sphere  of  the  Infusoria,  as  well  as  various  attempts 
to  systematize  the  forms  already  known.  The  same  period  that  gave  rise  to 
cell  research  —  the  eighteen-thirties  —  provided  also  a  fresh  impetus  to  mi- 
crobiology. In  this  the  pioneer  was  Christian  Gottfried  Ehrenberg.  Born 
in  1795  in  the  neighbourhood  of  Leipzig,  he  studied  medicine  there  and  was 
afterwards  given  an  opportunity  of  making  a  six  years'  voyage  of  explora- 
tion to  the  East,  whence  he  brought  home  important  collections.  This  ex- 
pedition having  brought  him  fame,  he  was  invited  to  accompany  Humboldt 
on  his  Asiatic  expedition,  after  which  he  became  professor  of  medical  his- 
tory at  Berlin  and  secretary  to  the  Academy  of  Science  there.  He  died  in  1876, 
having  long  given  up  active  participation  in  scientific  developments. 

Infusoria  as  " complefe  organistns" 
Ehrenberg's  great  contribution  to  biology  was  his  work  on  the  Infusoria, 
the  results  of  which  were  published  originally  in  a  number  of  brief  essays 
and  afterwards  in  the  important  and  splendidly  got  up  work  entitled  Die 
Infusionstiercben  als  vollkomtnene  Organismen,  printed  in  1838.  The  result  of  this 


4X8  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

and  other  works  of  his  was  that  the  number  of  known  Infusoria  was  consider- 
ably increased,  and  their  classification  essentially  advanced.  Anguillulidas 
and  cercaria,  which  had  hitherto  been  counted  amongst  them,  were  excluded, 
the  Rotatoria  were  separated,  and  the  genus-  and  species-diagnosis  pre- 
cisely defined,  many  of  them  still  holding  good.  The  whole  of  this  careful 
and  praiseworthy  work,  however,  Ehrenberg  used  in  support  of  an  utterly 
unprofitable  theory;  starting  from  the  then  prevalent  belief  in  one  single 
primal  type  for  all  animals,  he  tried  to  discover  in  the  Infusoria  the  same 
organs  as  in  the  higher  animals;  the  vacuoles  that  are  visible  in  the  Ciliata, 
and  which  partly  alter  shape,  were  seen  in  his  imagination  to  possess  canal- 
shaped  outlets  and  were  thus  made  the  basis  of  an  artificially  ramified  di- 
gestive system;  he  believed  he  had  found  sexual  organs  and  eggs  in  the  objects 
he  investigated  —  in  a  word,  they  were  to  his  mind,  as  the  title  of  his  work 
indicated,  "complete  organisms."  That  he  entirely  rejected  the  belief  in  the 
spontaneous  generation  of  such  creatures  is  self-evident;  indeed,  this  dis- 
belief in  the  spontaneous-generation  hypothesis  may  have  been  firmly  rooted 
in  him  before  he  began  to  study  the  Infusoria  and  perhaps  contributed  in 
some  degree  towards  inducing  in  him  these  efi^orts  at  finding  in  them  as 
complete  a  form  as  possible.  His  theory  won  many  adherents  among  his 
contemporaries  —  it  was  embraced,  inter  alia,  by  Owen  in  his  earlier  works; 
when  eventually  it  was  exploded,  Ehrenberg,  after  spending  some  years  in 
vainly  defending  his  cause,  withdrew  entirely  from  all  research  work. 

The  scientist  who  from  the  outset  came  forward  as  a  decided  opponent 
of  Ehrenberg  and  who  rapidly  won  a  victory  for  his  views  was  Felix  Du- 
jARDiN  (i8oi-6i),  professor  first  at  Toulouse,  then  at  Rennes.  In  certain  of 
his  works,  the  last  and  most  comprehensive  of  which  is  dated  1841,  he  laid 
the  foundations  of  a  new  conception  of  the  Infusoria.  He  achieved  this  first 
of  all  by  incorporating  with  them  a  category  of  still  lower  organisms,  which 
he  made  the  subject  of  special  investigation,  namely  the  Rhizopoda.  These, 
which  include  types  without  any  external  organs,  and  indeed  without  any 
definite  external  bodily  form,  offered  the  best  possible  proof  against  the 
lowest  animals'  acceptance  as  "complete  organisms."  Dujardin  found  that 
both  these  and  the  higher  Infusoria  consist  of  a  homogenous  mass,  which 
possesses  the  power  of  absorbing  nourishment,  contracting  and  moving,  and 
reacting  to  external  impressions.  This  mass  he  called  "sarcode,"a  name  that 
\yas  at  one  time  used,  especially  in  France,  to  denote  that  fundamental  sub- 
stance of  which  living  creatures  in  general  are  built  up,  until  it  was  sup- 
planted by  the  word  "protoplasm."  In  the  sarcode  Dujardin  found  vacuoles 
and  granules,  but  no  permanent  organs,  and  the  cilia;  that  cover  the  body 
of  the  higher  Infusoria  possess  in  his  view  no  affinity  with  the  hairy  forma- 
tions of  the  higher  animals.  In  all  this  Dujardin  stood  undeniably  on  surer 
ground  than  Ehrenberg;   on   the   other  hand,  he  failed   to  elucidate   the 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  419 

Infusoria's  character  of  simple  ceils;  their  nuclei,  which  Ehrenberg  believed 
to  be  sexual  organs,  Dujardin  was  unable  to  explain  more  exactly,  but 
considered  them  to  be  simply  concretions  in  the  sarcode. 

Siebold  on  Infusoria 
It  was  reserved  for  Siebold  to  put  the  Infusoria  in  their  right  place.  As  early 
as  his  Comparative  Anatomy  of  1845,  which  has  been  referred  to  above,  he 
combines  Infusoria  and  Rhizopoda  under  the  common  term  Protozoa  and 
characterizes  them  as  ' '  Tiere,  in  ivelchen  die  verschiedenen  Systeme  der  Organe  nicht 
scbarf  aiisgeschieden  sind,  und  dercn  unregelmdssige  Form  tmd  einjache  Organisation 
sich  auj  eine  Zelle  rediixjeren  lassen.''  This  definition  he  bases  on  a  careful  de- 
marcation of  the  forms  included  in  the  group;  the  Rotatoria  are  definitely 
separated  as  being  more  highly  organized,  and  a  number  of  multicellular, 
but  primitive  life-forms,  which  produce  chlorophyll  —  Closterines,  Vol- 
vocines  —  are  transferred  to  the  vegetable  kingdom.  It  is  pointed  out  in 
connexion  therewith  that  cilia-  and  flagella-movements  can  also  exist  in 
the  vegetable  kingdom,  while  on  the  other  hand  a  special  free  mobility  of 
a  higher  type  is  attributable  to  the  Protozoa.  The  various  organic  systems 
that  Ehrenberg  ascribed  to  the  Infusoria  are  examined  and  rejected;  there 
thus  remains  the  simple  cell,  provided  with  nucleus  and  vacuoles,  which  is 
hereby  proved  to  be  capable  of  sustaining  a  free  and  independent  existence, 
being  reproduced  by  division  without  any  special  sexual  organs. 

In  a  paper  published  some  years  later  Siebold  further  examines  the  exist- 
ence of  and  the  relation  between  single-celled  animals  and  plants,  being  sup- 
ported in  his  views  particularly  by  a  work  by  Nageli,  which  had  then  been 
recently  published,  on  unicellular  algx,  in  which  these  organisms  had  been 
thoroughly  characterized  and  described.  As  a  result  of  these  works  micro- 
biology was  directed  on  the  right  way  and  during  the  next-epoch  came  to 
exercise  a  great  influence  on  the  development  of  biology  in  general.  In  the 
Protozoa,  "the  primary  animals,"  had  been  found  a  category  of  living 
creatures  from  which,  as  the  name  implies,  the  other  higher  organisms 
could  be  derived,  besides  which  the  cell  idea  was  hereby  made  to  cover  an 
entirely  new  area;  it  was  possible  to  see  in  the  cell  not  only  the  basic  element 
in  the  structure  of  the  organisms,  but  also  a  true  elementary  organism  capable 
of  leading  an  independent  life  or,  as  a  transition  to  the  higher  cell-structures, 
of  forming  colonies  of  similar  elements,  such  as  the  Volvox  referred  to  above. 
Space  forbids  our  going  further  into  the  maze  of  works  which  were  now  de- 
voted to  the  single-celled  animals  and  plants.  During  the  succeeding  period 
in  particular,  research  work  in  this  field  went  on  apace  without  interruption. 
Of  the  works  on  the  Protozoa  that  appeared  during  this  era  may  be  mentioned 
those  of  Friedrich  Stein  (1818-85),  professor  at  Prague,  on  the  Infusoria, 
which  form  the  basis  for  all  later  research  on  the  subject. 

There  still  remains  to  deal  with  in  this  connexion  one  more  group  of 


430  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

single-celled  organisms  —  namely,  the  bacteria  or  Schizomycetes,  which, 
as  is  well  known,  have  since  been  found  to  play  a  most  vital  part  in  human 
life  and  which  have  accordingly  been  investigated  ever  since  the  middle  of 
the  last  century  as  a  special  field  of  research.  In  connexion  with  this  branch 
of  research  there  have  existed  a  number  of  theoretical  problems  of  the  greatest 
significance;  the  problems  of  spontaneous  generation,  fermenting  processes, 
and  the  origin  of  various  diseases.  The  problems  of  the  causes  of  disease 
can  of  course  be  dealt  with  only  cursorily  here;  they  have  of  old  formed  a 
science  of  their  own  — •  pathology.  The  questions  of  spontaneous  generation 
and  the  fermenting  process,  on  the  other  hand,  have  possessed  immense 
theoretical  interest  and  on  the  decisive  occasion  mentioned  below  their 
treatment  has  happened  to  coincide.  We  may  therefore  suitably  begin  our 
review  of  the  history  of  bacteriology  with  a  glance  at  these  two  questions. 

Bacteriology  and  spontaneous  generation 
The  belief  in  spontaneous  generation  has  been  mentioned  on  various  oc- 
casions in  the  foregoing:  how  the  earlier  naturalists  generally  believed  that 
the  lower  animals,  especially  such  as  appeared  suddenly  and  possessed  more 
or  less  the  characters  of  parasites  or  vermin,  could  arise  through  some  kind 
of  transmutation  process  in  lifeless  matter;  Aristotle  believed  that  fleas 
and  mosquitoes  originated  in  putrefying  matter  —  a  belief  with  which  even 
Harvey  at  least  partially  associated  himself,  while  van  Helmont  had  seen 
rats  arise  out  of  bran  and  old  rags.  In  the  seventeenth  century  Francesco 
Redi  (16x6-98),  court  physician  and  academician  in  Florence,  proved  that 
worms  in  rotting  meat  arise,  not  in  consequence  of  the  putrefaction,  but  out 
of  eggs  laid  by  flies  on  the  meat;  if  the  latter  is  protected  with  thin  cloth,  no 
worms  arise  in  it,  in  spite  of  the  putrefaction.  On  the  other  hand,  Redi  be- 
lieved in  the  spontaneous  generation  of  intestinal  worms  and  gall-flies.  For 
theoretical  reasons  Swammerdam  denied  spontaneous  generation;  the  doc- 
trine of  preformation  that  he  founded  actually  precluded  any  belief  in  this 
kind  of  propagation  and  during  the  greater  part  of  the  eighteenth  century 
held  it  in  discredit.  Nevertheless  Buffon,  as  we  have  seen  in  a  previous  sec- 
tion, believed  in  a  spontaneous  generation  through  minute  life-units  scattered 
throughout  the  universe  and  was  supported  in  his  belief  by  his  friend  the 
English  microscopist  Needham;  and  Lamarck  associated  himself  with  this 
view.  On  the  other  hand,  Spallanzani,  the  preformationist,  strongly  op- 
posed the  doctrine  of  spontaneous  generation  and  sought  to  prove  that  by 
boiling  organic  elements  in  air-tight  vessels  it  was  possible  to  prevent  living 
creatures  from  arising  in  them.  This  theory  was  put  to  practical  use  some 
decades  later  by  a  French  chef,  Appert,  who  invented  the  still  commonly 
practised  hermetical  inspissation  of  food.  A  French  physicist,  however, 
found  out  that  the  air  in  the  preserving  jars  lacks  oxygen  —  this  element  is 
really  consumed  by  oxidation  processes  in  the  contents  —  and  concluded 


MODERNBIOLOGY  43 1 

therefrom  that  the  sterility  was  due  to  lack  of  oxygen.  At  the  beginning  of 
the  nineteenth  century  the  belief  in  spontaneous  generation  received  fresh 
impetus,  not  least  as  a  result  of  the  victory  of  Wolff's  epigenesis  theory; 
Rudolphi  believed  in  the  spontaneous  generation  of  tapeworms,  and  the 
entomologists  held  the  same  belief  in  regard  to  parasites  from  the  insect 
world.  It  was  chiefly,  however,  the  increased  knowledge  of  the  Infusoria 
that  strengthened  the  belief  in  spontaneous  generation;  Ehrenberg's  protests 
died  away  unheard  when  the  exaggerations  in  his  description  of  the  organi- 
zation of  these  animals  had  been  made  manifest. 

Chemists  on  fermeriting 
The  idea  of  spontaneous  generation  received  fresh  support  in  the  increased 
knowledge  of  the  fermenting  process.  Both  Lavoisier  and  Berzelius  had 
studied  the  fermentation  of  alcohol  and  had  sought  to  ascertain  the  process 
of  sugar-disintegration  in  alcohol  and  carbonic  acid;  the  yeast  that  floats  up 
when  it  is  brewed  was  believed  to  consist  of  albuminous  elements,  which 
were  separated  upon  the  decomposition  of  the  malt.  This  conception  of 
fermentation  as  a  purely  chemical  process  found  support  in  the  discovery  of  a 
substance  existing  in  malt  that,  when  added  to  a  solution  of  starch,  converts 
the  starch  into  sugar.  This  substance  was  called  "diastase,"  and  similar 
substances,  "ferments"  as  they  were  called,  were  soon  discovered  in  other 
quarters:  in  saliva  and  intestinal  fluids  in  man  and  animals,  as  also  in  many 
places  in  the  vegetable  kingdom.  Chemists  believed  that  they  now  had  in 
their  hands  the  substances  that  produce  fermentation  and  similar  processes, 
and  these  chemical  changes,  in  the  course  of  which  albuminous  compounds 
were  formed  as  a  by-product,  also  gave  a  clear  indication  as  to  the  direction 
in  which  the  spontaneous  generation  of  minute  creatures  might  be  looked 
for;  fermentation  was  in  fact  a  part  of  the  process  of  spontaneous  generation. 
Then  there  appeared,  in  1836,  the  Frenchman  Charles  Cagniard  de 
Latour  (1777-1859),  an  engineer  by  profession,  with  the  assertion  that  the 
yeast  really  consists  of  minute  organisms  and  that  it  is  their  activity  that 
causes  the  fermentation.  Shortly  after  this  the  question  was  taken  up  by 
Schwann,  who  tried  to  demonstrate  by  experiment  that  putrefaction  and 
fermentation  are  processes  which  are  not  due  to  the  oxygen  in  the  air,  but 
rather  to  a  special  element  that  exists  in  the  air  and  is  destroyed  by  heating; 
he  boiled  special  easily  decomposable  organic  substances  and  then  brought 
them  into  contact  with  air  that  had  first  passed  through  a  red-hot  pipe, 
whereupon  no  chemical  change  took  place,  while  there  was  a  change  if 
ordinary  air  was  allowed  access  to  them.  The  leading  chemists  —  Berzelius, 
Wohler,  Liebig  —  regarded  these  theories  as  a  chimera,  and  they  won  the 
day  all  the  more  easily  because  Schwann's  experiments  were,  from  the  tech- 
nical point  of  view,  rather  poor;  other  investigators  repeated  them  and  ob- 
tained results  quite  different  from  those  published  by  Schwann.  Thus  matters 


432.  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

Stood  when  a  scientist  arose  who  as  the  result  of  unchallengeable  experiments 
clinched  the  matter  once  and  for  all  and  thereby  entirely  changed  the  course 
of  microbiology. 

Louis  Pasteur  was  born  in  i8ix  at  Dole,  a  town  in  the  ancient  province 
of  Franche-Comte.  His  parents  belonged  to  the  industrial  class;  his  father 
had  served  as  a  non-commissioned  officer  under  Napoleon  and  after  his  de- 
mobilization had  entered  the  tanning  trade,  moving  his  business  from  one 
place  to  another.  Young  Louis  attended  the  country  school  and  afterwards 
studied,  under  circumstances  of  privation  and  with  numerous  interruptions, 
in  Paris.  He  was  mostly  interested  in  the  natural  sciences  and  the  teaching 
profession  was  his  aim  in  life.  He  became  a  teacher  at  the  gymnasium  at 
Strassburg  and  married  a  daughter  of  the  rector  of  the  school.  There  he 
carried  out  his  first  chemical  work,  which  procured  his  removal  to  the  then 
newly-founded  University  of  Lille,  where  he  became  professor  of  chemistry 
in  1855.  Four  years  later  he  was  called  to  Paris,  to  the  Ecole  Normale.  At 
the  same  time  he  was  carrying  on  his  investigations  into  the  fermentation 
process,  which  at  once  brought  him  world-wide  fame,  and  after  that,  success 
and  honours  came  to  him  rapidly.  It  was  given  to  him  in  a  specially  high 
degree  to  make  the  results  of  his  investigations  of  practical  use  to  mankind, 
whether  it  was  a  question  of  inventing  a  method  of  preserving  food,  combat- 
ing the  diseases  of  domestic  animals,  or  treating  rabies,  which  had  hitherto 
been  considered  incurable.  This  last-mentioned  discovery  made  him  particu- 
larly popular:  through  an  international  fund  there  was  founded  in  1889  an 
institute  for  the  purpose  of  investigating  those  fields  of  research  to  which 
he  had  devoted  himself,  which  bore  his  name  and  to  the  management  of 
which  he  afterwards  devoted  all  his  energies.  Previously  pupils  had  already 
flocked  to  his  laboratory  from  all  parts  of  the  world;  many  of  them  have 
themselves  won  great  fame.  Nevertheless,  this  brilliant  career  had  certainly 
not  been  entirely  free  from  shadows.  In  his  political  views  Pasteur  was  a 
conservative  and  a  warm  partisan  of  the  French  Empire,  and  moreover  a 
strictly  faithful  Catholic.  This  caused  him  a  good  deal  of  unpleasantness, 
owing  to  radical  opposition,  producing  an  atmosphere  that  is  even  reflected 
in  the  scientific  polemics  waged  against  him.  Ultimately,  however,  these 
hostile  voices  were  silenced,  and  the  more  easily  as  he  never  meddled  in 
political  questions.  But  instead  he  suff'ered  in  his  old  age  from  increasing  ill- 
health;  as  early  as  in  1868  he  had  had  a  paralytic  stroke  which  impaired  the 
use  of  one  of  his  arms,  but  which  did  not  succeed  in  preventmg  him  from 
continuing  his  activities  with  as  great  success  as  before;  gradually,  however, 
his  powers  declined  and  he  passed  peacefully  away  in  1895.  His  name  lives 
in  his  work  and  in  the  "Pasteur  Institutes"  which  have  been  established  in 
all  civilized  countries;  he  is  without  doubt  one  of  the  greatest  scientists  of 
his  century. 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  433 

Pasteur  denies  spontaneous  generation 
Pasteur  began  his  researches  in  the  purely  chemical  sphere;  he  investigated 
organic  acids,  chiefly  the  isomeric,  and  he  obtained  valuable  results  in  con- 
nexion therewith.  Thence  he  was  led  to  study  the  question  of  the  molecular 
structure  of  sugar  and  the  manner  in  which  this  substance  is  converted  into 
different  isomeric  alcohols  and  acids  —  in  other  words,  into  the  process  of 
fermentation.  His  first  experiments  in  this  field  were  concerned  with  the 
formation  of  lactic  acid;  he  found  on  the  surface  of  sour  milk  minute  greyish 
spots,  which  he  examined  microscopically  and  experimentally.  Under  the 
microscope  they  appeared  as  a  mass  of  minute  globular  formations,  smaller 
in  size  than  those  of  which  ordinary  yeast  is  composed;  when  placed  in  a 
saccharine  solution  they  at  once  disintegrated  it  into  lactic  acid.  Without 
at  the  moment  drawing  any  conclusion  as  to  their  origin,  he  maintains  that 
all  fermentation  is  caused  by  similar  minute  organisms.  If  we  plant  out  such 
organisms  of  a  definite  type  in  a  saccharine  solution,  wt  get  a  definite  form 
of  fermentation:  alcoholic  fermentation,  br.tyric-acid  formation;  if,  on  the 
other  hand,  a  suitable  saccharine  solution  is  allowed  to  stand  by  itself,  there 
are  set  up  a  number  of  simultaneously  disintegrating  processes  induced  by 
different  organisms  operating  at  the  same  time. 

It  goes  without  saying  that  the  chemists  of  the  old  school  did  not  feel 
that  they  had  much  to  gain  from  these  new  discoveries.  They  at  once  found 
a  keen  supporter  in  Felix  Archimede  Pouchet  (1800-71),  professor  at  Rouen, 
who  was  reputed  both  as  a  botanist  and  as  a  zoologist.  In  a  series  of  investi- 
gations he  tried  to  prove  that  the  micro-organisms  arising  upon  fermentation 
and  putrefaction  are  spontaneously  generated,  and  this  owing  to  the  very 
fact  of  those  chemical  changes;  the  fermentation  forms  the  initial  stage  of 
the  process  whereby  living  creatures  arise  from  the  decomposition  of  existing 
organic  substance.  In  the  view  of  such  a  theory  Pasteur's  fermentation  experi- 
ments were,  of  course,  pure  irrational  nonsense,  and  thus  began  a  lengthy 
controversy  betw^een  these  two  experimental  scientists,  in  which  the  scientific 
world  and  eventually  the  enlightened  public  became  keenly  interested. 

Controversy  between  Pasteur  and  Pouchet 
To  Pasteur  the  specific  character  of  the  different  fermentative  organisms  was 
in  itself  a  proof  that  they  are  not  the  product  of  chemical  change,  but  actual 
species  of  living  beings ,  which  come  into  existence  through  the  multiplication 
of  existing  individuals.  But  whence,  then,  come  all  those  different  organisms 
which  immediately  populate  saccharine  solutions  that  are  allowed  to  stand, 
and  food  that  is  kept  too  long?  Schwann  had  derived  putrefaction  from  the 
air,  and  Pasteur  endeavoured  to  prove  this  by  experiment;  he  filtered  air  by 
sucking  it  in  through  a  tube  filled  with  cotton-wool,  thereby  obtaining  a 
collection  of  dust  particles,  which  were  transferred  with  great  care  to  a 
retort  filled  beforehand  with  boiled  and  cooled  saccharine  solution;  the  neck 


43  4  THEHISTORYOFBIOLOGY 

of  the  retort  was  melted  together  and  after  some  days  there  was  found  in  the 
fluid  an  abundant  vegetation  of  micro-organisms.  Their  origin  was  thus 
proved;  these  creatures  had  existed  in  atmospheric  dust  in  a  dried  state.  On 
the  other  hand,  a  saccharine  solution  boiled  in  a  retort  the  neck  of  which 
was  melted  together  in  the  course  of  boiling  could  be  preserved  for  any 
length  of  time  without  changing.  Pouchet  tried  by  various  means  to  dis- 
credit these  experiments;  he  tried  to  prove  that  the  organisms  cannot  stand 
being  dried,  that  they  do  not  exist  scattered  in  the  air  as  Pasteur  declares, 
that  milk  becomes  sour  in  spite  of  being  boiled.  Space  forbids  our  following 
this  dispute  in  all  its  phases  —  how  both  parties  collected  air  on  high 
mountains  with  a  view  to  proving  their  arguments  on  that  evidence;  how 
Pasteur  found  that  certain  organisms  can  endure  heating  up  to  the  boiling 
point  of  water  without  perishing  (which  explains  how  it  is  that  boiled 
milk  turns  sour);  how  he  thought  out  a  whole  series  of  ingenious  apparatus 
to  prove  his  statement  that  the  fermenting  organisms  always  originate  in 
the  outer  air  and  that  the  boiling  of  the  experimental  fluids  and  the  heating 
of  the  air  which  comes  into  contact  with  them,  infallibly  exclude  the  exist- 
ence of  organic  life  in  them.  The  two  antagonists  were  allowed  to  carry  out 
their  experiments  before  the  French  Academy  of  Science,  and  Pasteur  at  once 
succeeded  in  convincing  some  of  its  foremost  members  —  Milne-Edwards 
and  Claude  Bernard,  and  the  chemist  Chevreul.  Pouchet  likewise  had  his 
supporters,  and  especially  among  the  scientifically  educated  and  half-educated 
public  he  gained  many  adherents  who  regarded  spontaneous  generation  as  a 
"philosophical  necessity,"  indispensable  for  a  natural-scientific  explanation 
of  the  origin  of  life,  which  Pasteur,  faithful  Catholic  as  he  was,  naturally  felt 
himself  compelled  to  explain  dogmatically.  Thus  argument  opposed  argu- 
ment, and  party  faced  party.  In  these  circumstances  the  solution  of  the  prob- 
lem would  never  have  become  possible  had  not  Pasteur  been  able  to  put  his 
ideas  into  practice  on  a  large  scale.  During  the  succeeding  years  he  invented 
his  well-known  methods  of  preserving  milk  by  "Pasteurizing"  —  that  is, 
by  heating  —  of  improving  the  manufacture  of  wine  and  beer  by  controlling 
the  conditions  of  fermentation,  of  securing  immunity  from  the  silk-worm 
disease  and  chicken  cholera  by  eliminating  the  micro-organisms  that  produce 
them.  These  discoveries,  however,  belong  to  the  next  period,  as  also  the  de- 
velopment and  perfecting  of  bacteriology  and  fermentation  research  achieved 
by  other  investigators  —  Koch,  Hansen,  and  many  others.  Finally  Pasteur's 
views  on  the  origin  of  the  micro-organisms  received  splendid  practical  con- 
firmation as  a  result  of  the  development  of  modern  medicine:  antiseptics  and 
aseptics  in  surgery,  disinfection,  and  the  treatment  of  infectious  disease. 
Owing  to  these  facts,  which  found  fresh  confirmation  daily,  spontaneous 
generation  has  entirely  ceased  to  exist  as  a  possibility  to  be  reckoned  with  in 
modern  biology,  nor  does  it  come  into  serious  question  when  we  have  to 


MODERNBIOLOGY  43  5 

explain  actual  phenomena.  That  its  theoretical  possibility  nevertheless  still 
continues  to  be  keenly  discussed  is  due  to  modern  natural-philosophical 
speculation  —  a  subject  that  will  be  dealt  with  in  a  later  chapter. 


4.     Botany 

Plant  classification  after  Linnaus 
A  SURVEY  of  the  most  important  data  in  the  history  of  botany,  particularly 
of  plant  classification,  up  to  the  period  covered  by  our  chapter  heading,  is 
necessary  if  we  are  to  obtain  a  universal  view  of  the  development  of  biology 
during  the  period  now  being  described.  In  order  to  obtain  this  view  we  must 
first  of  all  return  to  the  days  of  Linnasus.  It  will  be  remembered  that  Linnaeus 
set  up,  in  the  first  place,  an  artificial  system  based  exclusively  on  the  structure 
of  the  various  parts  of  flowers  and  especially  intended  to  be  used  for  practical 
examination  purposes,  and,  in  the  second  place,  a  natural  system,  based  on 
the  common  forms  of  plants  —  a  system  which  he  worked  at  throughout 
his  life,  without,  however,  being  able  to  find  a  satisfactory  conclusion  to  it. 
His  immediate  successors  paid  but  little  attention  to  this  latter  legacy  from 
him,  although  it  really  offers  immense  possibilities  for  development;  they 
contented  themselves  rather  with  examining  as  many  new  plants  as  possible 
according  to  the  sexual  system.  During  this  time,  however,  there  were 
published  a  considerable  Tiumber  of  sound  systematic  works;  the  study  of 
cryptogams  in  particular  made  rapid  progress,  but  nothing  was  contributed 
to  the  development  of  the  system  itself  until  twenty  years  after  Linnaus 's 
days,  when  Jussieu's  systematic  work.  Genera  -plantarmn,  was  published. 

Antoine  Laurent  de  Jussieu  came  of  a  family  that  had  already  given 
France  two  eminent  botanists,  principally  in  the  spirit  of  Tournefort;  es- 
pecially Bernard  de  Jussieu,  uncle  of  the  above-named,  who  had  made  con- 
siderable additions  to  a  natural  system,  without,  however,  succeeding  in 
completing  it.  A.  de  Jussieu  was  born  at  Lyons  in  1748,  studied  medicine  in 
Paris,  and  became  professor  at  the  Jardin  des  Plantes,  after  which  he  held 
some  other  botanical  and  medical  posts  and  finally  became  professor  of  phar- 
macy in  the  faculty  of  medicine.  He  was  active  for  many  years  and  attained  a 
great  age;  he  died  in  1836.  In  his  principal  work,  mentioned  above,  Jussieu 
has  set  up  a  complete  natural  vegetable  system,  the  first  of  its  kind.  Like  Ray, 
he  makes  the  cotyledons  the  chief  basis  of  classification  for  the  vegetable  king- 
dom; in  his  view  this  is  justified,  because  the  plant  arises  out  of  the  seed,  and 
the  latter's  most  vital  part  is  the  cotyledon  —  it  is  compared  with  the  heart 
of  animals.  Consequently  plants  are  divided  into:  acotyledons,  monocoty- 
ledons, and  dicotyledons,  a  system  of  classification  that,  thanks  to  him,  has 
become  permanent.  These  three  main  divisions  are  then  divided  into  orders. 


43  6  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

the  names  and  demarcations  of  which  are  taken  partly  from  Linn^us's  plan 
for  a  natural  system  and  partly  from  the  preliminary  work  of  Antoine's 
uncle  Bernard.  Some  of  these  orders  are,  in  fact,  quite  natural,  while  others 
are  extremely  ill  arranged,  especially  in  the  acotyledon  group,  in  which  are 
included  not  only  Linn^eus's  cryptogams,  but  also  the  naiads;  thus,  he  in- 
cludes the  ferns  among  the  Cycas,  which  is  placed  between  the  Polypodia 
and  the  Equiseta.  Jussieu  has  formed  his  genera  mainly  after  Tournefort, 
while  his  definition  of  species  is  reminiscent  of  Ray  rather  than  of  Linnasus. 
Jussieu,  therefore,  was  not  a  very  original  observer,  but  his  service  to  science 
lies  in  the  fact  that  he  really  worked  out  a  natural  system,  which  he  set  up 
in  determined  opposition  to  Linn^us's  sexual  system,  and  which  has,  in 
fact,  been  the  starting-point  for  all  subsequent  systematic  improvement. 

A  far  more  important  observer  was  Robert  Brown  (1773-1858),  who 
has  been  mentioned  before  as  the  discoverer  of  the  cell-nucleus.  The  son  of  a 
Scottish  clergyman,  he  studied  medicine  in  Edinburgh  and  became  an  army 
surgeon,  but  at  the  same  time  he  applied  himself  to  botany  and  was  appointed 
botanist  to  an  expedition  to  Australia,  which  was  led  by  a  Captain  Flinders. 
Brown  stayed  four  years  on  that  continent  and  brought  home  large  collec- 
tions; on  his  return  he  was  made  librarian  to  the  Linnean  Society  and  cura- 
tor at  the  British  Museum.  In  this  position  he  enjoyed  the  reputation  of 
being  one  of  the  finest  botanists  of  his  time;  he  never  published  any  very 
important  work,  however,  and  his  papers  were,  curiously  enough,  collected 
and  published  in  a  German  translation,  done  by  Nees  von  Esenbeck,  with 
whom  he  had  but  little  in  common  from  a  scientific  point  of  view.  Nor  did 
he  work  out  any  system  of  his  own;  in  his  works  heuses  sometimes  Linnasus's, 
sometimes,  and  more  often,  Jussieu's  natural  system.  His  service  to  science 
lies  in  the  care  and  keen-sightedness  with  which  he  works  out  and  analyses 
the  various  orders,  or  families,  as  he  more  frequently  terms  them:^  his  studies 
of  the  Compositic,  Asclepiadace^,  and  many  other  families  have  been  men- 
tioned as  models  for  the  research  work  of  the  succeeding  age  and  have  con- 
tributed much  towards  finding  a  place  for  the  natural  system  in  the  scientific 
mind.  Brown  was,  moreover,  an  eminent  plant-geographer  and  made  a  special 
study  of  the  distribution  of  the  different  families  in  different  climates;  in  this 
respect  his  earlier  work  on  the  flora  of  Australia  was  unrivalled  and  attracted 
the  attention  of  Humboldt,  who  highly  commended  it. 

As  one  of  the  foremost  pioneers  of  botany  should  also  be  mentioned 
AuGusTiN  Pyrame  de  Candolle.  He  was  born  in  1778  at  Geneva,  where  his 
family  had  for  generations  enjoyed  a  great  reputation.  At  an  early  age  he 
began  to  study  the  natural  sciences,  which  at  that  time  —  the  age  of  Bonnet 

^  The  term  family"  as  an  expression  for  the  natural  groups  in  the  vegetable  kingdom  ap- 
parently comes  from  the  French  botanist  Michel  Adanson  (i 717-1 806),  whose  attempt,  influ- 
enced by  Buffon,  to  form  a  natural  system  for  the  vegetable  kingdom  was  somewhat  of  a  failure. 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  437 

and  Saussure  —  stood  in  high  favour  in  his  native  town.  After  preliminary- 
studies  there,  he  betook  himself  to  Paris  in  order  to  continue  his  education 
as  a  botanist.  In  the  company  of  Lamarck,  Cuvier,  and  Geoffroy  he  spent  ten 
years  there,  during  which  his  reputation  increased  year  by  year  and  public 
commissions  were  entrusted  to  him;  amongst  other  things  he  was  sent,  with 
the  financial  assistance  of  the  State,  on  scientific  expeditions  in  different  parts 
of  France;  Lamarck  handed  over  to  him  the  editing  of  his  French  flora  and 
he  was  finally  elected  professor  at  Montpellier.  In  1816,  however,  he  returned 
to  Geneva,  which  during  the  Revolution  had  become  incorporated  with 
France,  but  after  the  fall  of  Napoleon  was  again  united  to  Switzerland.  He 
then  lived  in  his  native  town  as  professor  of  botany  and  member  of  the  high 
council,  honoured  and  respected  until  his  death,  in  1841. 

De  Candolle  on  -plant  morphology  and  physiology 
De  Candolle  mastered  the  whole  field  of  botany  better  than  anyone  else  in 
his  time;  he  was  at  once  systematist,  morphologist,  and  physiologist.  He 
started  a  gigantic  work,  Prodromus  systematis  naturalis  regni  vegetabilis,  which 
was  to  describe  all  known  plants,  but  which  for  obvious  reasons  was  never 
completed  in  his  lifetime;  his  son  and  many  others  worked  at  it  after  his  death. 
The  principles  on  which  he  classified  the  vegetable  kingdom  he  laid  down 
in  a  work  published  in  18 13  entitled  Theorie  elementaire  de  la  botanique,  which 
he  revised  several  times  and  which  is  without  doubt  his  finest  work,  worthy 
'to  be  associated  with,  and  at  the  same  time  representing  a  great  advance  on 
Linnasus's  Philosophica  hotanica,  which  doubtless  gave  him  the  idea.  It  starts 
with  a  general  scientific  theory,  according  to  which  nature  is  controlled  by 
four  great  forces :  attraction,  and  affinity,  which  are  the  basis  of  physical  and 
chemical  phenomena,  the  life-force,  which  is  common  to  ail  living  creatures, 
and  sensibility,  which  is  the  characteristic  of  animal  life  as  opposed  to  vege- 
table life.  Each  of  these  four  forces  has  its  own  science:  physics,  chemistry, 
physiology,  and  psychology.  It  is  thus  a  markedly  vitalistic  conception, 
which  is  still  more  emphasized  in  such  an  assertion  as  that  "the  life-force 
annuls  or  modifies,  as  necessity  dictates,  the  ordinary  laws  of  matter."  De 
Candolle  is  by  no  means  a  fantastic  natural  philosopher,  however;  on  the 
contrary,  he  has  the  same  sober  and  critical  conception  of  natural  phenomena 
as  Cuvier,  whose  correlation  theory  he  applies  to  the  vegetable  kingdom. 
He  maintains  that  the  two  most  vital  organic  systems  in  the  plants,  the  vege- 
tative and  the  sexual,  are  dependent  upon  one  another;  a  plant  with  highly 
developed  fertilizing  organs  cannot  possess  primitive  vegetative  organs,  and 
vice  versa;  therefore  a  natural  system,  set  up  with  comprehensive  regard  to 
the  entire  reproductive  organization,  should  at  once  conform  to  such  a 
system  set  up  with  a  view  to  the  vegetative  organs,  and  this,  indeed,  he 
proves  by  means  of  examples.  In  connexion  herewith  he  maintains,  under  ac- 
knowledgment to  Linnasus,  that  there  is  throughout  the  vegetable  kingdom 


43  8  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

a  universal  symmetry,  a  standard  of  organization,  which  is  modified  in  the 
individual  by  the  same  organ's  being  capable  of  serving  different  purposes 
and  the  other  organs'  undergoing  corresponding  changes.  Among  these 
changes  he  includes  especially  stunted  growth,  degeneration,  and  accretion; 
in  his  view  a  flower  with  free  petals  is  higher  than  one  with  accrete  petals  — 
a  principle  which  he  applied  in  his  system,  though  it  failed  to  gain  the  ac- 
ceptance of  posterity.  For  the  rest,  he  introduced  into  his  system  reforms  of 
lasting  value;  the  difference  between  vascular  and  cellular  plants  was  estab- 
lished by  him,  as  also  the  contrast  between  the  bole-plants  and  the  higher 
plants.  Further,  his  classification  of  the  dicotyledons  has  been  largely  ac- 
cepted by  subsequent  botanists.  Otherwise,  de  Candolle  strongly  repudiates 
Lamarck's  theory  of  one  single  evolutional  chain  in  the  organisms,  instead 
associating  himself  with  Linnasus's  idea  of  the  natural  system's  likeness  to 
a  map;  in  fact,  his  idea  of  species  is  not  unlike  the  Linnasan:  according  to 
de  Candolle,  a  species  is  "the  sum  total  of  all  the  individuals  which  mutually 
resemble  one  another  more  than  they  resemble  others,  which  are  capable  by 
mutual  fertilization  of  producing  fertile  individuals,  and  which  are  multi- 
plied by  generation,  so  that  it  is  possible  by  analogy  to  assume  that  they 
have  originally  sprung  from  a  single  individual."  Varieties  arise,  he  con- 
siders, partly  through  the  influence  of  local  conditions  of  life  and  partly 
through  hybridization;  moreover,  there  are  in  certain  quarters  varieties 
which  must  be  regarded  as  constant,  like  the  species,  and  which  should  be 
distinguished  from  the  accidental  local  varieties.  The  genus  is  defined  as  a 
collection  of  species  with  a  striking  mutual  resemblance  in  regard  to  all 
organs;  families  and  higher  categories  are  given  similar  definitions. 

Among  de  Candolle 's  other  works  may  be  mentioned  his  Organography, 
an  account  of  the  organic  systems  of  plants,  and  his  Physiologie  vegetale,  a 
work  of  great  merit  for  its  time,  based  on  a  thorough  knowledge  of  the  vital 
conditions  of  plants  and  of  chemical  and  physical  processes  belonging  thereto. 
We  must,  however,  pass  over  these  works  here;  as  a  matter  of  fact,  it  is 
mostly  as  a  reformer  and  theoretician  in  the  sphere  of  classification  that 
de  Candolle  has  made  his  best  contribution  to  the  development  of  biology. 

End  lie  her' s  sysfem 
The  development  of  plant  classification  received  further  impetus  through 
Stephan  Ladislaus  Endlicher  (1805-49).  Bo"*^  of  wealthy  parents  at  Press- 
burg,  he  studied  first  of  all  theology,  but  afterwards  devoted  himself  both 
to  botany  and  oriental  languages.  He  became  professor  of  botany  and  head 
of  the  botanical  gardens  in  Vienna,  acquiring  fame  for  the  splendid  initiative 
he  took  in  furthering  the  development  of  natural  science  in  Austria,  gener- 
ously contributing  towards  that  end  out  of  his  own  private  purse.  He  pre- 
sented his  herbarium  to  the  State  and  published  a  botanical  journal  at  his 
own  expense.  At  the  same  time  he  made  a  name  for  himself  as  an  expert  in 


MODERNBIOLOGY  43  9 

the  Chinese  language.  As  a  teacher  he  won  the  affection  of  his  pupils.  In  the 
year  of  revolution,  1848,  he  took  advantage  of  his  popularity  to  plead  the 
Government's  cause  before  the  rebellious  students,  but  they  became  em- 
bittered against  him  and  drove  him  out  of  Vienna.  This  he  felt  very  deeply 
and  he  died  shortly  afterwards,  some  say  by  his  own  hand.  His  great  work 
on  plant  classification  is  his  Genera  plantarum,  which  comprises  all  the  then 
known  vegetable  genera  arranged  in  a  natural  system;  he  has  given  a  brief 
summary  of  the  subject  in  his  Enchiridion.  His  service  lies  not  so  much  in  the 
new  ideas  that  he  produced  in  the  sphere  of  classification  as  in  the  particu- 
larly clear,  concise,  and  complete  characterization  and  demarcation  of  fami- 
lies and  genera  which  he  created  and  which  made  his  work  the  basis  for  all 
later  plant  classification. 

Hedwig  on  mosses 
By  the  side  of  this  generally  systematic  and  morphological  research  there 
developed  a  keen  interest  in  the  specialized  study  of  particular  botanical 
subjects,  the  hitherto  neglected  lower  plants  offering,  of  course,  an  especially 
attractive  field  of  study.  As  a  pioneer  in  this  sphere  Johann  Hedwig  (1730- 
99)  is  worthy  of  mention.  He  was  born  in  Hungary,  but  he  worked  mostly  in 
Leipzig,  first  as  a  physician  and  then  as  professor  of  botany.  He  applied  him- 
self to  the  study  of  the  multiplication  of  the  cryptogams,  making  careful 
observations  of  the  propagation  and  germination  of  the  spores.  It  was 
chiefly. the  mosses,  however,  that  occupied  his  attention,  and  in  this  field 
he  was  a  pioneer;  he  divided  the  large  and  unwieldy  genera  that  Linnasus 
had  created  into  a  number  of  well-characterized  genera,  which  are  in  part 
still  retained,  and  he  found  for  them  a  good  basis  of  classification  in  the  shape 
and  marginal  formation  of  the  capsules.  Many  other  naturalists  have  since 
followed  in  his  footsteps,  so  that  muscology  is  now  a  thoroughly  elaborated 
specialized  section  of  botany. 

The  Algas  and  the  Fungi  became  subjects  of  special  treatment  much  later 
than  the  mosses.  Of  the  pioneers  of  Algx-research  we  have  already  described 
one  of  the  foremost,  Carl  Adolf  Agardh  (Part  II,  p.  u^i).  His  son,  Jacob 
Georg  (1813-1901),  followed  in  his  father's  footsteps  with  credit. 

Vries  on  fungi 
In  the  Fungi  as  a  field  of  research  Sweden  has  also  produced  one  of  the  most 
eminent  names,  that  of  Elias  Fries,  who  has  likewise  been  one  of  the  most 
distinguished  Swedish  botanists  since  Linnxus.  Born  in  1794,  the  son  of  a 
priest  in  the  province  of  Smaland,  Fries  devoted  himself,  even  as  a  boy,  to 
the  study  of  botany,  and  of  Fungi  in  particular;  when  still  a  youth  he  became 
a  lecturer  at  Lund  and  in  the  year  1834  professor  at  Upsala,  where  he  was 
active  until  1859,  when  he  became  professor  emeritus;  he  died  there  in  1878. 
When  Fries  first  went  to  Upsala  the  University  was  a  centre  of  romantic 
reverie  and  metaphysical  speculation;  he  took  up  the  cudgels  with  success 


440  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

and  honour  on  behalf  of  the  cause  of  exact  research,  by  no  means  allowing 
his  own  special  sphere  to  be  put  in  the  shade;  in  speeches  and  writing  he 
championed  the  cause  of  biology,  and  his  plea  was  heard  far  and  wide. 
Being  a  brilliant  stylist  and  an  eloquent  speaker,  he  was  elected  a  member 
of  the  Swedish  Academy,  and  in  his  old  age  he  held  the  position  of  a  recog- 
nized patriarch  in  the  sphere  of  natural  science  in  his  own  country.  Although 
no  friend  of  fantastic  speculations,  he  shared  his  age's  idealistic  conception 
of  nature  and  thus  found  it  easier  to  gain  a  hearing  for  his  high  aims;  in  one 
of  his  writings  he  expressly  calls  biology  a  "supernatural"  science,  for  life 
is  something  higher,  given  from  above,  and  its  influences  must  not  be  ex- 
plained according  to  the  laws  of  inorganic  nature.  To  his  mind,  biology 
belongs  not  to  the  exact  sciences,  but  to  the  historical;  it  is  more  closely 
akin  to  theology  than  to  physics  and  chemistry.^  In  his  special  research  work, 
however.  Fries  is  quite  exact.  His  chief  productions  are  his  great  works  on 
the  Fungi,  which  have  since  formed  the  basis  of  classification  in  this  class; 
he  has  described  quantities  of  species  and  given  characters  to  genera  and 
families  that  still  hold  good.  Next  to  these  works  should  be  mentioned  his 
treatises  on  the  lichens;  here  he  had  a  precursor  in  his  fellow-countryman 
Erik  Acharius  —  born  in  1757  and  mentioned  as  Linnseus's  last  pupil, 
afterwards  provincial  physician  at  Vadstena,  died  in  18 19  —  but  it  was  Fries 
who  established  the  lichen  system,  which  was  generally  accepted  until  the 
eighteen-sixties.  Fries  also  performed  a  considerable  service  in  producing 
his  classification  of  the  phanerogams;  among  other  things  he  maintained, 
in  opposition  to  de  Candolle,  that  the  Compositie  are  the  highest-developed 
of  the  phanerogams,  and  in  this  posterity  has  shown  him  to  have  been  right. 
His  natural  system  has,  with  certain  modifications,  been  generally  utilized  in 
Scandinavia. 

At  this  point  our  description  of  the  different  spheres  of  biology  has 
brought  us  up  to  the  period  that  is  characterized  by  the  launching  of  the 
theory  of  the  origin  of  species.  It  now  remains  for  us  to  give  a  glance  at 
certain  phenomena  in  the  sphere  of  theoretical  speculation  that  have  given 
direction  to  our  modern  biological  views. 

^  Botanical  Excursions  {Botaniska  utflykter^  I,  pp.  11-13.  Curiously  enough,  Haeckel  from 
his  standpoint  arrived  at  similar  conclusions,  of  which  more  anon. 


CHAPTER    IX 

POSITIVIST      AND      MATERIALIST      NATURAL      PHILOSOPHY 

Romanticism  and  positivism 

IN  HIS  History  of  the  Philosophy  of  Later  Times  HofFding  declares  that  there 
are  two  intellectual  currents  characteristic  of  the  nineteenth  century:  ro- 
manticism and  positivism,  the  former  starting  from  the  ideal  of  thought, 
the  latter  from  that  which  is  based  on  fact.  This  division  is  undoubtedly  in 
accordance  with  the  actual  course  of  events  dominating  the  whole  world  of 
culture;  the  contrast  indicated  is  discerned  no  less  clearly  in  the  development 
of  biology.  The  romantic  conception  of  nature  that  prevailed  at  the  begin- 
ning of  the  century  saw  the  true  reality  in  an  idea,  of  which  the  actual  life- 
forms  were  merely  modifications;  they  sought  therefore  for  a  primary  form 
or  archetype,  with  which  the  living  forms  were  compared,  as  was  done,  each 
in  his  own  way,  by  Goethe,  Geoffroy  Saint-Hilaire,  and  R.  Owen,  the  last- 
mentioned  still  as  late  as  towards  the  middle  of  the  century.  By  that  time  an 
entirely  different  conception  of  natural  phenomena  had  already  appeared, 
which  fought  its  way  year  by  year  into  the  general  consciousness;  although 
champions  of  the  old  ideal  still  survived  far  into  the  latter  half  of  the  century, 
nevertheless  it  may  be  claimed  that  the  victory  of  the  new  conception  was 
already  fully  confirmed  by  the  beginning  of  the  sixties.  Opposition  to  the 
old  concept  first  came  from  the  social  and  political  spheres,  after  which  it 
took  in  its  stride  the  scientific  and  literary  world.  Its  original  home,  there- 
fore, was  in  the  two  countries  in  which  public  life  manifested  the  greatest 
mobility  —  France  and  England.  It  was  not  until  later,  and  then  under 
different  forms,  that  it  appeared  in  Germany  and  Scandinavia. 

In  France  there  set  in  during  the  time  of  Napoleon,  and  still  more  im- 
mediately after  that  era,  a  violent  reaction  against  those  radical  ideas  that 
the  enlightenment  of  the  eighteenth  century  had  created  and  the  Revolution 
had  sought  to  realize  —  a  reaction  especially  in  the  social  and  political 
spheres,  less  in  the  scientific,  although  it  certainly  had  its  learned  theorists, 
as,  for  instance,  the  brilliant  and  fanatical  Joseph  de  Maistre.  But  neverthe- 
less the  theories  of  the  period  of  enlightenment  could  never  be  wholly 
suppressed;  they  survived,  as  did  the  longing  for  the  political  freedom  of  the 
Revolution,  and  they  found  support  in  the  natural  sciences,  which  at  that 
time  were  passing  through  a  brilliant  phase  in  France,  being  sustained  by  men 
who  worked  for  the  most  part  undisturbed  by  any  theoretical  speculations. 

441 


442.  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

In  a  previous  chapter  we  have  described  the  most  important  repre- 
sentatives of  biology  in  France  during  that  period;  physics,  chemistry,  and 
astronomy  at  the  same  time  could  boast  of  no  less  brilliant  representatives. 
And  the  results  that  these  sciences  achieved  were  very  clearly  brought  home 
to  the  world  in  general,  owing  to  their  splendid  application  to  practical 
life,  which  was  then  just  beginning  and  which  afterwards  represented  per- 
haps the  most  striking  characteristic  feature  of  the  century;  it  was  then  that 
the  influence  of  steam-power  on  industry  and  communications  first  began 
to  be  realized;  it  was  then  that  the  significance  of  chemistry  in  numberless 
fields  of  activity  began  to  make  itself  felt  in  the  daily  life  of  humanity, 
not  to  speak  of  the  somewhat  later  application  of  electrical  phenomena  in 
practical  everyday  life.  As  a  result  of  all  this  the  natural  sciences  began  to 
influence  the  public  mind  more  than  they  had  ever  done  before;  mankind  ex- 
pected them  to  lead  to  new  and  happier  times,  while  theology  and  philoso- 
phy, which  had  served  the  oppressors  of  the  people,  reaped  nothing  but 
hatred  and  contempt.  Would  it  not  be  possible  for  all  forms  of  human  life, 
for  the  whole  of  human  culture,,  to  be  placed  under  the  a^gis  of  the  natural 
sciences,  to  be  explained  through  them  and  developed  in  their  spirit?  This 
question  was  answered  by  many  with  an  unreserved  yes;  foremost  of  these 
was  Comte,  one  of  the  most  gifted  thinkers  that  France  has  ever  produced 
and  certainly  the  most  influential  during  the  past  century. 

Isidore  Auguste  Marie  Francois  Xavier  Comte  was  born  in  1798  at 
Montpellier.  He  belonged  to  an  ultra-Catholic  and  strongly  conservative 
family  and  received  a  strict  upbringing  in  the  same  spirit.  Even  when  he  was 
fourteen  years  old,  however,  he  began  to  doubt  the  correctness  of  the  dog- 
mas on  which  he  had  been  brought  up,  and  when,  later  on,  he  went  to  study 
at  the  Ecole  Polytechnique  in  Paris,  his  oppositional  attitude  became  clearly 
defined  and  was  all  the  more  strengthened  when  the  Government  disestab- 
lished that  institution,  which  was  feared  as  a  centre  of  opposition,  before 
he  had  had  time  to  complete  his  studies  there.  Thus  he  passed  no  examina- 
tion, a  fact  that  had  a  disastrous  efi^ect  upon  his  future;  nevertheless,  in  spite 
of  his  parents'  opposition,  he  continued  his  studies  in  Paris,  steadily  im- 
proving the  substantial  knowledge  he  had  already  acquired  of  mathematics, 
physics,  and  chemistry.  He  soon  won  a  reputation  for  his  genius  and  eru- 
dition —  among  his  patrons  and  friends  he  counted  men  such  as  Humboldt 
and  Blainville  —  yet  he  was  never  able  to  obtain  a  post  in  the  Government 
service,  but  all  his  life  he  had  to  earn  his  living  by  private  tutoring,  except 
for  some  years  when  he  was  employed  as  an  assistant  teacher.  This  may  to  a 
certain  extent  be  explained  as  due  to  the  peculiar  theoretical  point  of  view 
he  adopted;  even  in  his  youth  he  resolved  to  devote  his  life  to  creating  a 
general  system,  which  was  to  deal,  along  natural-scientific  lines,  with  the 
whole  of  existence,  both  of  nature  and  of  human  life,  and  thus  to  arrive  at 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  443 

a  universal  knowledge,  whereby  all  the  problems  of  life  would  be  solved, 
not  only  the  theoretically  scientific,  but  also,  and  above  all,  the  social  and 
political.  The  first  concept  of  this  system  was  drawn  up  in  the  form  of  private 
lectures,  to  which  he  succeeded  in  attracting  a  large  number  of  listeners; 
then  during  the  period  1830-4^  he  worked  out  his  famous  Cours  de  philosophie 
positive  in  six  large  volumes.  His  method  of  working  was  peculiar  to  him- 
self; trusting  to  his  phenomenal  memory,  he  had  recourse  to  no  literature 
of  any  kind  when  at  work,  and  he  used  to  write  down  the  contents  of  a 
whole  volume  at  a  time  without  corrections,  after  having  worked  out  in  his 
head  the  gist  of  what  he  was  going  to  write.  It  is  natural  that  in  such  cir- 
cumstances his  work  should  be  full  of  inaccuracies  in  matters  of  fact  as  well 
as  of  stylistic  redundancies.  In  several  cultural  circles  the  influence  of  the 
work  has  been  deep;  in  view  of  the  important  part  that  biology  plays  in  it, 
it  is  worth  giving  a  summary  of  the  book  here,  all  the  more  so  as  it  had  its 
effect  on  the  biological  theories  of  the  succeeding  era. 

Comte  s  positive  philosophy 
It  is  a  "positive  philosophy"  that  Comte  desires  to  create;  by  "philosophy" 
he  means,  as  did  Aristotk;  whom  he  greatly  admired,  a  knowledge  of  the 
whole  of  existence;  by  "positive"  he  means  "/<«  77ieme  chose  que  reel  et  utile.'' 
This  "real  and  useful"  knowledge  he  will  substitute  for  the  theological 
and  metaphysical,  which  he  considers  to  have  predominated  during  previous 
epochs.  He  finds  the  essence  of  existence  to  be  in  the  development  that  has 
always  taken,  and  is  still  taking,  place;  in  this  instance  he  paved  the  way 
for  the  explanation  of  life  that  has  governed  human  culture  since  his  time. 
In  contrast  to  so  many  later  positivist  thinkers,  however,  he  does  not  look 
for  this  development  in  nature  —  it  is  characteristic  that  geology  does  not 
interest  him  at  all  —  but  in  human  life.  In  the  history  of  human  thought 
three  successive  phases  have  followed  one  another:  the  theological,  in  which 
it  was  believed  that  personal  divine  powers  were  the  cause  of  all  that  hap- 
pened; the  metaphysical,  when  for  these  were  substituted  impersonal  forces; 
and  the  positivist,  in  which  men  no  longer  ruminate  over  the  causes  of  all 
that  takes  place,  but  are  content  to  establish  facts  and  determine  their 
course.  The  theological  stage  culminated  in  the  Catholicism  of  the  Middle 
Ages,  for  which  Comte,  in  spite  of  all,  expresses  great  sympathy.  As  the 
founders  of  positivism  he  cites  Bacon  and  Galileo,  whose  explanation  of 
nature  should,  in  his  opinion,  be  applied  to  all  phenomena.  The  middle 
phase,  the  metaphysical,  is,  in  his  view,  the  worst  of  all;  it  is  the  belief  of 
the  idealistic  philosophy  in  spiritual  reality,  beginning  with  Descartes  and 
ending  with  the  romantic  philosophy,  that  is  sharply,  and  for  the  most  part 
justly,  criticized.  Instead,  his  explanation  of  nature  is  the  same  as  Galileo's  — 
that  it  is  not  possible  to  find  out  what  the  forces  of  nature  are,  but  only  how 
they  operate.  In  this  he  is  undeniably  right;  his  weakness,  on  the  other  hand, 


444  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

lies  in  his  mania  for  formally  reducing  to  simple  formulas  all  phenomena, 
even  those  of  the  most  complex  character.  He  thus  forgets  Galileo's  second 
great  exhortation:  to  measure  what  is  measurable  and  to  make  measurable 
what  is  not.  He  believes,  for  instance,  that  every  being,  and  especially  every 
living  being,  can  be  studied  from  two  sides,  the  static  and  the  dynamic  — 
that  is  to  say,  as  potentially  active  and  as  actually  active.  Thus,  biology  has 
a  static  side,  anatomy,  and  a  dynamic  side,  physiology,  and  other  sciences  in 
like  manner.  Conite  himself  declares  that  he  borrowed  this  division  into 
static  and  dynamic  from  Blainville;  it  again  occurs  in  Haeckel's  Generelle 
Morpbologie.  According  to  Comte,  all  science  should  be  classified  after  the 
method  employed  by  botanists  and  zoologists;  by  this  method  we  get  six 
separate  branches  of  science:  mathematics,  astronomy,  physics,  chemistry, 
biology,  and  social  physics,  or,  in  a  single  word,  invented  by  Comte  and 
now  generally  accepted,  sociology.  Each  of  these  sciences  is  based  on  all 
the  previous  ones  in  the  series  and  cannot  be  mastered  without  a  knowledge 
of  them.  The  biological  section  is,  of  course,  the  one  that  affords  chief  in- 
terest to  the  present  history. 

His  biological  ideas 
As  he  repeatedly  asserts,  Comte's  biological  speculations  are  most  closely 
associated  with  those  of  Blainville,  but  are,  of  course,  entirely  outside  the 
scope  of  the  control  which  the  theories  of  that  distinguished  zoologist 
exercised  in  his  special  research-work.  Blainville's  view  that  life  consists  of 
"composition  et  decomposition  '  is  thus  embraced  by  Comte,  who  with  its 
support  rejects  both  Stahl's  vitalism  and  Boerhaave's  mechanism.  On  the 
other  hand,  he  accepts  Bichat's  tissue  theory,  strongly  supporting  the  idea 
of  structure's  being  the  essential  factor  in  the  living  organism;  Bichat's 
"organic  and  animal  life"  is  also  adopted  by  Comte.  Life  itself  he  defines  as 
"the  relation  between  organism  and  environment."  It  can  be  studied,  as  to 
both  its  static  and  its  dynamic  side,  after  three  different  methods:  observa- 
tion, experiment,  and  comparison.  Observation  is  the  fundamental  method 
and  should  be  carried  out  with  all  available  technical  appliances.  Experiment, 
on  the  other  hand,  is  condemned,  especially  vivisection,  which  disturbs  the 
relation  between  the  organism  and  its  natural  environment  and  thus  merely 
creates  abnormal  states  and,  moreover,  leads  to  cruelty  —  Comte  does  not 
mention  Magendie's  name,  but  obviously  refers  to  him.  —  The  finest  biologi- 
cal method  is  the  comparative,  which  is  applicable,  on  the  one  hand,  to  dif- 
ferent parts  and  stages  of  development  in  the  same  individual,  and,  on  the 
other  hand,  to  different  life-forms.  The  latter  type  of  comparison  should  be 
concerned  with  both  organs  and  tissues;  Comte  assumes  a  primal  tissue  from 
which  all  other  forms  of  tissue  and  organ  can  be  derived,  but  he  rejects  the 
cell  theories  that  were  just  then  making  their  appearance.  This  derivation, 
however,  turns  out  to  be  as  idealistic  as  Cuvier's  comparative  anatomy; 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  445 

Comte,  indeed,  maintains  with  the  latter  that  the  species  are  invariable,  "for 
the  idea  of  species  would  inevitably  cease  to  represent  an  exact  scientific 
definition  if  we  were  to  allow  an  unlimited  modification  of  different  species, 
the  one  in  the  other."  This  opposition  of  Comte's  to  the  theory  of  the  origin 
of  species  was  undoubtedly  the  cause  of  Haeckel's  refusing  to  acknowledge 
him  as  a  precursor  in  respect  of  monism,  which  he  nevertheless  was  far  more 
than  any  of  those  whom  Haeckel  enumerates. 

The  details  of  Comte's  biological  speculations  are,  of  course,  of  interest 
only  from  the  point  of  view  of  curiosity.  He  associates  himself  with  Blain- 
ville's  animal  system,  with  its  exclusive  reference  to  external  characteristics; 
he  himself  lays  down  three  main  types  for  the  entire  animal  kingdom: 
Osteozoa,  Entomozoa,  and  Malacozoa  —  that  is,  Vertebrata,  Articulata, 
and  Mollusca  —  a  classification  the  clumsiness  of  which  scarcely  needs 
pointing  out;  indeed,  the  Mollusca  group  in  particular,  a  reversion  to  Lin- 
naeus's  Vermes,  was  at  the  time  utterly  absurd.  Still  worse,  however,  is 
Comte's  attempt  to  analyse  "the  intellectual  and  moral  cerebral  functions," 
for  here  he  becomes  infatuated  with  Gall's  phrenology.  It  is  only  natural 
from  his  point  of  view  that  he  should  reject  Descartes's  theory  of  the  parallel 
existence  of  the  soul  and  the  body,  and  the  other  "metaphysicians"  likewise 
offer  many  points  of  attack.  In  his  criticism  of  the  earlier  psychology,  then, 
Comte  has  shown  very  keen  observation,  but  the  psychology  that  he  him- 
self created  is  all  the  more  lacking  in  criticism.  He  denies  the  possibility  of 
psychical  self-observation,  for  one  cannot  divide  oneself  into  two  parts  for 
the  one  part  to  observe  the  other,  and  besides  one  cannot  in  this  way  find  out 
the  mental  life  of  the  animals,  which  is  the  vital  preliminary  stage  to  that 
of  man.  True  psychology  should,  according  to  Comte,  be  based  on  Gall's 
theory  of  intellectual  and  moral  areas  in  the  brain,  which  is  the  beginning  of 
an  entirely  new  psychology.  Here  modern  psycho-physical  research  has  pro- 
ceeded along  a  line  which  Comte  never  dreamt  of  and  which  led  to  the 
complete  acceptance  of  that  idea  of  "self-observation"  which  he  despised. 

His  sociology 
The  last  three  sections  of  Comte's  work  deal  with  sociology,  the  doctrine 
of  social  statics  (that  is,  organization),  and  dynamics  (that  is,  progress). 
Eventually  these  problems  entirely  usurped  the  place  of  natural  science  in  his 
life's  work.  It  is  true  that  he  produced  ideas  of  value  in  this  sphere  too:  the 
actual  principle  of  studying  social  life  from,  so  to  speak,  a  biological  point 
of  view  has  indeed  won  adherents  in  modern  times,  and  a  number  of  items 
in  his  program,  as,  for  instance,  mixed  schools,  have  actually  been  adopted. 
But  on  the  whole  his  social  theory  is  only  a  curiosity.  This  is  due  mostly  to 
the  strange  development  that  he  himself  underwent.  While  still  a  young 
man  he  had  for  a  year  been  a  lunatic,  but  he  afterwards  recovered  his  mental 
balance.  When  he  had  concluded  his  great  book,  he  added  to  it  a  general 


446  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

introduction  which  led  to  his  being  accused  of  megalomania  and  persecutory 
paranoia,  and  after  that  period  he  became  engrossed  in  ever  stranger  social 
Utopias;  he  founded  a  new  religion,  "a  Catholicism  without  Christianity," 
as  Huxley  called  it,  with  catechism,  a  calendar  of  saints,  comprising  great 
men  to  whom  prayers  should  be  addressed  —  beginning  with  Moses  and  end- 
ing with  Bichat  and  Gall  —  and  a  ritual  of  divine  service.  His  scientifically 
educated  friends  deserted  him,  and  only  a  small  group  of  a  less  intelligent  type 
gathered  round  him  at  his  death,  in  1857. 

The  influences  that  Comte  exercised  upon  the  conception  of  life  held  by 
subsequent  generations  is  not  easy  to  estimate.  All  that  in  modern  times  has 
gone  under  the  name  of  positivism,  monism,  utilitarianism,  and  various 
other  isms  has  either  directly  or,  at  any  rate,  intermediately  been  influenced 
by  his  doctrines.  In  conscious  opposition  to  the  ideal  unity,  in  which  roman- 
ticism saw  the  connexion  of  existence,  he  took  evolution  to  be  the  connecting 
force  in  life.  He  certainly  did  not  view  biological  evolution  in  the  same  light 
as  modern  biology  —  if  he  had,  he  would  not  have  rejected  Lamarck  —  but 
he  observed  with  all  the  keener  vision  the  evolution  that  is  taking  place  in 
human  culture.  He  was  thus  able  to  do  justice  to  the  various  stages  of  his- 
tory —  a  thing  which  the  period  of  enlightenment  of  the  eighteenth  century 
was  unable  to  do  —  while,  on  the  other  hand,  he  could  point  to  a  goal  in 
the  future  towards  which  to  strive.  And  this  belief  in  the  evolution  of  man- 
kind was,  as  we  shall  find  later  on,  a  precondition  before  the  theory  of  evolu- 
tion in  nature  could  gain  a  hearing;  Comte  therefore  paved  the  way  for  the 
doctrine  of  the  origin  of  species  more  than  most  others  did.  And  though  his 
own  biological  concept  was  deficient,  it  has  nevertheless  had  its  influence; 
we  have  already  pointed  out  traces  of  it  in  Haeckel,  and  these  could  probably 
be  supplemented;  even  in  later  times  there  has  been  a  corresponding  tendency 
reminiscent  of  such  characteristics  as  a  preference  for  comparative  investi- 
gation and  a  dislike  for  experiment.  Comte's  name  has,  in  fact,  a  definite 
place  in  the  history  of  biology. 

English  -positivism 
The  other  representatives  of  positivism  in  France  —  Comte's  pupils  —  de- 
voted themselves  principally  to  social  and  general  cultural  problems  and 
may  be  passed  over  here,  however  deep  their  influence  may  have  been  on  the 
general  conception  of  life,  both  inside  and  outside  their  own  country.  The 
same  is  to  a  certain  extent  true  of  the  precursors  of  the  same  realistic  trend 
of  thought  in  England.  That  country  was  indeed  the  cradle  of  eighteenth- 
century  enlightenment,  and  the  ideas  of  the  era  of  enlightenment  never  quite 
died  out  there,  even  in  the  days  of  romanticism.  These  ideas  took  rather 
the  form  of  strivings  after  practical  social  reforms,  as  in  Jeremy  Bentham 
and  James  Mill,  who  are  named  as  the  founders  of  utilitarianism,  a  general 
philosophy  of  life  with  a  social  aim,  based  upon  the  highest  possible  happiness 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  447 

for  the  greatest  possible  number  of  people,  a  happiness  that  would  infallibly 
be  attained  through  the  activities  of  the  individual  being  as  little  as  possible 
restricted  by  the  various  organs  of  the  community.  Here,  then,  we  find  the 
same  belief  in  evolution  as  in  Comte,  although  in  a  more  practical  form.  The 
foremost  supporter  of  these  ideas,  however,  is  John  Stuart  Mill  (1806-73), 
son  of  the  above-mentioned  James  Mill.  He  was  taught  by  his  father  and 
never  studied  at  a  university,  but  as  a  young  man  entered  the  Civil  Service. 
For  a  time  he  was  a  friend  of  Comte  and  was  influenced  by  him.  Among  his 
works  should  be  first  mentioned  his  System  of  Logic,  an  analysis  of  the  laws  of 
thought,  which  had  a  great  influence  on  the  generation  that  felt  the  first 
effects  of  Darwin's  theory;  Haeckel  especially  cites  its  doctrines  frequently. 
Mill  derives  all  knowledge  from  experience,  and  this  in  its  turn  from  sense- 
impressions;  of  special  interest  is  his  analysis  of  the  different  ideas  of  the 
natural-scientific  systems,  particularly  the  idea  of  species ;  he  considers  a  well- 
defined  species  to  be  a  reality,  not  merely  a  conventional  term,  but,  on  the 
other  hand,  he  maintains  that  the  species  should  be  based  on  characters  and 
not  on  any  imaginary  ideal  type.  The  closer  study  of  these  extremely  detailed 
analyses  of  ideas  is,  however,  more  a  concern  of  philosophy  than  of  the  his- 
tory of  biology.  For  the  rest.  Mill  was  active  both  in  theory  and  in  practice 
as  a  liberal  social  politician  and  as  such  possessed  a  wide  influence. 

Dotvnfall  of  romanticism  in  Germany 
The  advent  of  the  realistic  conception  of  life  took  an  entirely  different  turn 
in  Germany.  It  will  have  been  seen  from  the  foregoing  how  education  in 
that  country  had  for  half  a  century  been  entirely  dominated  by  the  romantic 
philosophy,  with  the  result  that  even  natural  science  came  to  a  great  extent 
under  the  influence  of  its  modes  of  thought.  The  Schellingian  polarity-theory 
certainly  had  very  soon  to  give  ground,  but  in  the  world  of  speculation  the 
Hegelian  philosophy,  with  its  dialectical  method  and  its  contempt  for  all 
empirical  research,  prevailed  all  the  longer.  But  after  the  death  of  the  master 
the  school  was  divided  against  itself,  and  many  of  its  members  developed 
their  doctrines  along  distinctly  radical  lines,  as,  for  instance,  Karl  Marx, 
the  famous  founder  of  socialism,  and  Ludwig  Feuerbach  (1804-72.),  whose 
views  closely  approached  the  positivism  of  Comte  and  who  was  otherwise 
a  thinker  mostly  engaged  in  problems  of  religious  philosophy,  and  also 
D.  F.  Strauss,  the  well-known  Bible-commentator.  Other  philosophers  re- 
mained on  the  old  ground,  while  still  a  number,  including  some  of  the  most 
keen-sighted,  returned  to  Kant's  critical  studies.  Whereas,  then,  the  roman- 
tic philosophy  was  being  internally  disrupted,  the  natural  sciences  made  the 
splendid  advance  that  has  been  described  in  the  foregoing.  It  is  no  wonder, 
therefore,  that  natural-science  students  took  courage;  the  results  of  philoso- 
phy had  resolved  themselves  into  vain  squabbles;  why  not,  then,  let  scientific 
research  be  self-sufficient  and  solve  the  riddle  of  existence  on  its  own  account? 


448  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

Good  progress  had  already  been  made  when  science  was  backed  by  such 
sound  victories  as  Mayer's  law  of  energy  and  Wohler's  organic  syntheses. 

German  materialism 
It  was  in  these  circumstances  that  the  new  realistic  natural  philosophy  arose, 
whose  different  ideas  have  occupied  the  attention  of  so  many  thinkers  and 
writers  up  to  the  present  day,  and  which  has  gone  under  so  many  different 
names,  such  as  positivism,  materialism,  monism,  agnosticism,  and  other 
isms.  Its  main  characteristic  has  been  the  endeavour  to  build  up,  on  an  exact 
natural-scientific  basis,  an  explanation  of  the  whole  0/ existence  —  that  is,  to 
base  on  the  limited  results  of  research  an  explanation  of  the  illimitable,  by 
means  of  weights  and  measures  to  explain  the  immeasurable  and  imponder- 
able. These  natural  explanations  might  have  been  fully  justified  as  expressions 
of  a  personal  view  of  life,  if  their  originators  had  clearly  realized  the  differ- 
ence between  facts  and  hypotheses,  between  manifestations  that  are  actually 
capable  of  being  observed  and  turned  to  practical  use,  and  theoretical  con- 
structions of  such  as  are  inaccessible  to  any  observation  whatsoever.  This  clear 
thinking,  however,  has  unfortunately  been  somewhat  rare;  far  more  common 
has  been  the  tendency  to  work  up  explanations  of  nature  and  then  insist  upon 
having  them  regarded  as  the  results  of  natural-scientific  research  —  a  weak- 
ness that  has  often  been  apparent  in  men  who  in  their  own  special  sphere 
have  been  keen  and  conscientious  observers.  From  the  outset  this  temptation 
was  no  doubt  due  to  the  influence  of  romantic  philosophy,  which  had  con- 
fidently proclaimed  the  infallibility  of  its  absolute  natural  explanations. 
Another  factor,  especially  as  regards  the  more  popular  scientific  literature, 
was  the  rivalry  with  the  ecclesiastical  tenets,  which  maintained  the  absolute 
truth  of  the  words  of  Scripture,  even  in  questions  of  natural  science.  And, 
finally,  there  were  in  Germany  the  political  points  of  view  to  be  reckoned 
with;  the  ruling  powers  did  their  utmost  to  preserve  the  old  belief  in  au- 
thority, which  was  considered  to  conduce  to  obedience  to  government;  the 
opponents  of  this  belief  were  consequently  on  the  side  of  natural  science. 
The  contrast  was  still  further  sharpened  by  the  revolutionary  outbreak  of 
1848  and  was  by  no  means  softened  by  the  stern  measures  which  the  Govern- 
ments adopted  after  their  victory,  in  order  to  maintain  their  authority.  Con- 
siderable light  is  thrown  upon  these  conditions  by  the  so-called  materialist 
dispute  in  the  beginning  of  the  eighteen-fifties,  a  controversy  which  not 
only  caused  great  excitement  at  the  time,  but  also  produced  after  efi^ects  that 
have  been  felt  ever  since.  It  may  therefore  be  worth  glancing  at,  all  the  more 
so  as  the  parties  to  the  dispute  were  exclusively  scientific  investigators,  some 
of  whom  were  very  distinguished,  while  philosophical  and  theological 
opinions  do  not  come  into  consideration  at  all. 

Among  those  who  became  involved  in  this  dispute  Justus  Liebig  (1803- 
73)  ranks  first;  on  thewhole,  he  may  be  considered  one  of  the  greatest  scientists 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  449 

of  the  century.  The  son  of  a  colour-man  at  Darmstadt,  he  acquired  in  his 
father's  shop  even  as  a  child  an  interest  in  chemistry  and  its  practical  applica- 
tion. At  one  time  he  endeavoured  to  follow  his  bent  as  an  apprentice  to  an 
apothecary,  but  did  not  get  on  well  there,  and  he  then  studied  for  a  couple  of 
years  at  German  universities,  during  which  time  he  associated  himself  with 
Schellingianism;  he  soon  wearied  of  this  also  and  went  to  Paris,  where  he 
eventually  found  the  training  he  sought  for  in  the  laboratory  of  the  famous 
Gay-Lussac.  On  the  recommendation  of  Humboldt  he  was  called  to  the  chair 
of  chemistry  at  Giessen,  and  after  struggling  for  years  against  jealousy  and 
hostility  he  succeeded  in  bringing  into  being  the  first  chemical  university- 
laboratory  in  Germany.  As  a  teacher  he  resembled  J.  Miiller  in  his  capacity 
for  gathering  around  him  and  educating  numbers  of  pupils;  indeed,  the  re- 
vival of  chemistry  in  Germany  is  attributable  to  him.  Towards  the  close  of 
his  life  he  became  a  professor  at  Munich.  He  was  a  pioneer  in  his  purely 
chemical  discoveries,  especially  in  the  field  of  organic  chemistry;  he  gave 
to  organic  elemental  analysis  the  form  that  it  has  retained  ever  since,  while 
his  investigations  into  organic  acids  were  of  epoch-making  importance,  as 
were  also  his  discoveries  in  the  sphere  of  zymurgy.  These  latter  discoveries 
made  him  the  foremost  supporter  of  the  chemical  fermentation  theory,  and 
Pasteur's  stubborn  opponent.  He  is  of  greatest  importance,  however,  as  the 
creator  of  practical  agricultural  chemistry;  hitherto  it  had  been  thought 
generally  that  plants  absorbed  their  principal  nourishment  out  of  the  sur- 
face-soil, but  he  proved  that  the  surface-mould  was  rather  augmented  by 
cultivation,  that  carbonic  acid  was  the  plants'  sole  source  of  carbon,  and 
ammonia  its  source  of  nitrogen,  and  to  prove  his  theory  he  instituted  experi- 
ments with  manure  on  an  expensive  scale.  As  a  result  of  these  experiments  he 
placed  agricultural  economy  on  a  natural-scientific  basis,  but  he  certainly 
shot  far  beyond  the  mark  —  partly  owing  to  his  ignorance  of  vegetable 
anatomy  —  and  he  gained  many  enemies  on  account  of  his  overbearing 
polemic,  especially  against  the  plant-physiologists.  These  in  their  turn  ex- 
posed a  number  of  Leibig's  inaccuracies;  he  denied  the  value  of  nitrogenous 
manures,  he  wanted  to  supply  the  earth  with  insoluble  instead  of  soluble 
phosphoric  acid  and  potassic  salts,  and  he  entirely  ignored  the  respiration  of 
plants.  On  many  points  he  received  sharp  criticism  at  the  hands  of  Schleiden 
and  Mohl.  As  an  animal-physiologist  Liebig  also  acquired  fame  for  his  pio- 
neer studies  of  the  preparation  and  utilization  of  foodstuffs;  he  ascertained  the 
chemical  compounds  that  are  conveyed  to  the  body  through  the  food,  but 
here,  too,  he  often  went  wrong,  as  when  he  divided  food-substances  into 
"plastic"  and  "respiratory,"  including  albuminous  substances  among  the 
former,  and  fats  and  carbohydrates  among  the  latter. 

In  this   sphere  Liebig  was  opposed  by  a  young  Dutch  physiologist, 
Jacob  Moleschott  (18x2.-93).  The  son  of  a  physician,  he  studied  physiology 


450  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

—  and  at  the  same  time  Hegel's  philosophy  —  at  Heidelberg  and  became  a 
lecturer  there,  but  was  dismissed  on  account  of  his  "materialistic"  views. 
He  then  became  professor  at  Turin  and  afterwards  at  Rome.  He  introduced 
research  in  experimental  physiology  into  Italy  and  carried  out  valuable 
investigations,  especially  in  the  sphere  of  the  phenomena  of  respiration. 
These  brought  him  into  conflict  with  Liebig,  whose  theory  of  the  influence 
of  food-substances  upon  breathing  he  rejected.  But  at  the  same  time  he  made 
a  violent  attack  upon  Liebig's  entire  conception  of  the  cosmos.  In  a  series  of 
popular  papers,  Chemische  Briefe,  the  latter  gave  an  account  of  the  progress 
of  chemistry,  in  the  course  of  which,  confirmed  Schellingian  that  he  was,  he 
extolled  in  fervent  eulogy  the  wisdom  and  might  of  the  Creator.  In  opposition 
to  these  letters  Moleschott  wrote  a  book,  Kreislauf  des  Lebens,  in  which  he 
attacked  Liebig  in  vigorous  though  courteous  terms,  and  in  connexion  there- 
with produced  a  purely  materialistic  conception  of  the  world.  This  he  bases 
on  the  theory  of  the  permanence  of  energy  and  on  the  syntheses  of  Wohler; 
on  the  other  hand,  unlike  Comte,  he  propounds  no  original  ideas  on  evolu- 
tion. To  him  life  is  a  magnificent  process  of  metabolism;  thought  is  a  product 
of  the  activities  of  the  brain.  As  a  confirmed  Hegelian  he  delights  in  abstract 
speculations;  through  combining  these  with  physiological  theories  he  often 
becomes  involved  in  a  helpless  confusion  of  thought.  Albert  Lange  in  his 
Geschkhte  des  Mater ialismus  quotes  some  amusing  instances  of  Moleschott 's 
muddled  attempts  to  get  away  from  the  contrasts  between  subjective  mental 
impressions  and  objective  reality,  and  of  his  still  more  confused  ideas  of 
matter  and  energy;  after  quoting  a  more  than  usually  vague  page  of  Moles- 
chott's  book,  he  asks:  "What  part  of  the  philosophical  backwoods  are  we  in 
now?"  In  fact,  Moleschott  has  no  idea  of  the  limits  of  scientific  research;  in 
accordance  with  the  idealistic  philosophy  that  he  once  embraced  he  imagines 
that  he  can  explain  the  whole  of  existence  by  a  few  artificial  ideas.  On  the 
other  hand,  Liebig  certainly  had  no  thought  of  letting  natural  science  hold 
its  own  and  leave  it  to  religion  to  satisfy  the  ideal  requirements  of  life  — 
showing  that  he  too  was  a  victim  of  the  vagueness  of  thought  that  romantic 
philosophy  left  in  men's  minds. 

Another  important  naturalist  who  was  involved  in  a  similar  controversy 
was  Rudolph  Wagner  (1805-64).  He  had  studied  medicine  and  taken  his 
degree  at  Wiirzburg  and  afterwards  worked  under  Cuvier  in  Paris,  eventually 
being  appointed  Blumenbach's  successor  at  Gottingen.  He  was  a  creditable 
investigator  and  teacher;  among  his  pupils  were  such  men  as  Leuckart  and 
the  philosopher  Lotze,  and  among  his  works  his  investigations  into  sper- 
mato-  and  ovogenesis  and  into  the  tactive  corpuscles  are  especially  worthy 
of  mention;  he  was  also  reputed  as  an  anthropologist,  in  the  spirit  of  Blumen- 
bach.  At  a  scientific  meeting  at  Gottingen  in  1854  he  gave  a  lecture  on 
Menschenschopfung  und  Seelensubsfan^,  in  which  he  discussed  the  question  of 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  451 

the  origin  of  man  from  one  single  pair  in  accordance  with  the  Church's 
doctrines  of  creation  —  a  question  which  he  certainly  believed  anthropology 
to  be  incapable  of  proving  or  disproving,  but  which  gave  him  an  opportunity 
of  making  a  violent  attack  upon  the  materialistic  soul-theories  of  the  time, 
which  he  inveighed  against  from  the  point  of  view  of  both  science  and  moral- 
ity. He  himself  worked  out  a  theory  of  the  soul  as  a  kind  of  ethereal  sub- 
stance, which  leaves  the  body  at  death  and  imparts  itself  to  the  children  that 
are  born  —  an  idea  somewhat  reminiscent  of  Swedenborg's  spirit  theory.  His 
antagonist  on  this  subject  was  KarlVogt  (1817-95),  who  ^^'^  been  professor 
at  Giessen  between  the  years  1847-9,  but  had  been  removed  on  account  of  his 
having  participated  in  the  revolutionary  movements  of  that  period;  he  after- 
wards became  professor  at  Geneva,  gaining  a  reputation  especially  as  an 
author  of  sound  text-books  and  popular  scientific  works.  Between  him  and 
Wagner  there  ensued  a  controversy  on  the  question  of  the  creation  and  the 
soul  of  man,  which  rapidly  degenerated  on  both  sides  into  sheer  lampoonery, 
involving  personal  insults  of  the  basest  kind.  In  this  Vogt  maintained  that 
the  different  human  races  cannot  have  a  common  origin  and  in  support  of  his 
argument  adduced  a  number  of  proofs  of  the  constancy  of  species  and  varie- 
ties, which  were  not  quite  in  the  spirit  of  the  theory  of  the  origin  of  species. 
Further,  there  was  considerable  discussion  as  to  the  fertility  of  hybrids,  which 
Vogt  upheld  and  Wagner  denied,  and  finally  Vogt  found  an  easy  butt  for  his 
witticism  in  Wagner's  divisible  soul-substance,  and  at  the  same  time  main- 
tained the  assertion  that  the  soul  was  a  product  of  the  brain,  which  "pro- 
duces ideas  as  the  liver  produces  bile  and  the  kidneys  urine."  On  the  whole, 
Vogt  seems  to  have  been  entirely  unmoved  by  the  earlier  natural  philosophy; 
this  frees  him  from  having  to  solve  a  number  of  problems  that  his  philo- 
sophically trained  contemporaries  felt  themselves  bound  to  take  up  for  dis- 
cussion, but,  on  the  other  hand,  it  involved  him  in  gross  self-contradictions. 
The  most  painful  feature  of  this  polemic,  however,  was  its  markedly  political 
character;  on  the  one  hand,  a  Christian  conservative  professor,  holding  a 
good  position  and  boasting  of  his  friendship  with  statesmen  and  ministers, 
and,  on  the  other  hand,  an  exiled  revolutionary,  embittered  by  the  shipwreck 
of  his  ideals  and  by  his  own  misfortunes.  It  would  almost  appear  as  if  the 
whole  of  this  scientific  controversy  was  merely  an  excuse  for  giving  two  in- 
dividuals from  opposite  political  camps  an  opportunity  of  coming  to  grips. 
In  fact,  the  antagonism  of  the  two  ideas,  materialism  and  idealism,  retained 
this  character  in  Germany  not  only  during  the  decade  with  which  we  are 
dealing,  but  also  up  to  a  far  later  period;  the  points  of  view  as  to  the  soul's 
"to  be  or  not  to  be"  coincide  with  the  attitude:  supporter  of  the  Government 
or  supporter  of  the  opposition.  During  the  eighteen-fifties,  as  we  have  seen, 
the  representatives  of  radical  ideas  at  the  universities  found  themselves  in 
quite  a  difficult  position  as  far  as  regards  educational  freedom;  this  state  of 


45  2.  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

things  was  certainly  improved  at  a  later  date,  but  for  some  considerable  time 
to  come  Christian  conservatism  was  an  officially  approved  standpoint. 

A  radical  thinker  who  never  succeeded  in  acquiring  any  permanent 
right  to  give  instruction  was  Biichner,  one  of  the  most  widely  read  of  the 
authors  who  wrote  on  the  materialism  controversy.  Friedrich  Karl  Chris- 
tian LuDwiG  BiJcHNER  (18x4-99)  belonged  to  a  very  gifted  family,  especially 
in  regard  to  literature.  He  studied  medicine  and  concurrently  also  philosophy, 
was  a  lecturer  for  a  time,  but  having  been  dismissed,  he  earned  his  living  by 
taking  up  a  medical  practice.  He  was  of  noble  character  and  a  keen  upholder 
of  liberty  and  justice,  and  from  his  early  youth  he  enthusiastically  adopted 
materialistic  ideas,  in  which  he  saw  a  means  of  bringing  humanity  out  of 
darkness  and  superstition.  His  famous  work  Kraft  und  Staff,  one  of  the  most 
widely  read  popular  scientific  works  of  his  age,  is  really  a  collection  of 
talks  on  various  theoretical  questions  in  connexion  with  natural  science, 
written  in  an  attractive  form,  but  without  any  very  great  originality.  The 
old  theme  —  the  indestructibility  of  energy,  the  permanency  of  matter,  the 
soul  as  a  combination  of  cerebral  functions  —  is  played  upon  with  constant 
variations  and  in  a  spirit  of  incessant  controversy  against  theologians  and 
philosophers.  Biichner  certainly  has  a  better  idea  of  the  limitations  of 
natural  science  than  Vogt;  he  admits  that  existence  is  full  of  riddles  that 
cannot  be  solved;  but  like  Moleschott  and  Vogt  he  never  attained  to  that 
clearly  formulated  self-limitation  that  Comte  in  his  great  work  imposed 
upon  positivism.  Nor  did  any  of  them  realize  the  importance  of  evolution  as 
Comte  did.  All  of  them  hailed  the  advent  of  Darwin  with  enthusiasm;  his 
doctrine  gave  to  their  conception  of  nature  an  impetus  that  it  never  had  be- 
fore. The  fact  is,  the  idea  of  the  origin  of  species  gave  to  the  realistic  natural 
philosophy  the  connexion  that  the  idealistic  conception  of  nature  had  in  its 
theory  of  ideas.  Energy  and  matter  were  far  too  abstract  and  difficult  ideas 
to  support  a  popular  theory  of  life,  all  the  more  so  as  the  above-mentioned 
champions  of  their  omnipotence  lacked  that  thought-training  which  would 
have  made  them  capable  of  mastering  a  subject  so  hard  to  elucidate.  Their 
service  to  natural  science  and  their  labours  for  its  propagation  among  a 
larger  public  are  at  any  rate  deserving  of  recognition. 


FROM    DARWIN    TO    OUR    OWN    DAY 


CHAPTER    X 

THE    PRECONDITIONS     OF     DARWINISM 

I.   Modern  Geology 

DURING  THE  ZENITH  of  the  power  of  Darwinism  it  was  considered  in 
certain  quarters  that  one  of  the  chief  missions  of  cultural  history- 
was  to  seek  after  "pre-Darwinists."  It  was  obvious  that  in  such 
circumstances  aspirants  to  this  honour  should  come  forward  in  large  num- 
bers; to  begin  with,  the  old  Greek  natural  philosophers  Anaximandros  and 
Empedocles  were  named,  and  the  number  increased  the  nearer  one  came  to 
modern  times.  There  came  another  period  when  the  list  of  personalities  thus 
accumulated  could  be  used  to  depreciate  Darwin,  as  Kohlbrugge  used  it.'  If, 
however,  we  damp  our  enthusiasm  somewhat  and  have  regard  to  actual 
facts,  we  shall  find  that  the  precursors  of  Darwin  were  far  fewer.  He  him- 
self has  acknowledged  the  influence  that  he  derived  from  Lyell's  geological 
theories  and  Malthus's  studies  of  population,  and  it  seems  only  fair  when 
reviewing  a  scientist's  development  to  take  into  consideration  his  own  re- 
marks on  the  subject.  If  we  do  this,  we  get  two  preconditions  for  the  origin  of 
the  Darwinian  theory  —  a  natural  scientific,  or,  more  exactly,  a  geological,  and 
a  socio-political.  We  shall  now  proceed  to  consider  the  former  of  these  two. 
Compared  with  biology,  modern  geology  is  a  young  science.  Some  of 
its  pioneers  have  been  mentioned  in  the  foregoing:  da  Vinci,  Steno,  BufFon. 
The  creator  of  geological  study  as  a  special  branch  of  science  is  without 
doubt  Abraham  Gottlob  Werner  (1750-1817),  professor  at  the  mining 
academy  at  Freiberg,  a  teacher  of  Humboldt  and  many  other  geologists  and 
mineralogists.  He  systematically  explored  the  geology  of  his  own  district, 
determined  the  sequence  of  the  rock-beds,  examined  their  composition,  and 
on  the  results  thereof  based  a  rational  mining-industry.  He  never  actually 
printed  his  theories;  it  is  only  through  the  medium  of  his  pupils  that  the 
world  has  become  acquainted  with  them.  He  is  best  known  as  the  advocate 

^  Kohlbrugge,  "War  Darwin  tin  originates  Genid"  Biologisches  Zcntralblatt,  Vol.  XXXV,  p.  93. 

453 


454  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

of  "Neptunism";  he  believed  that  all  mineral  species,  even  basalt,  are  pre- 
cipitated in  water.  The  narrowness  of  his  conclusions  was  largely  due  to 
the  fact  that  he  never  made  any  journeys;  he  presumed  that  the  geological 
conditions  all  over  the  world  were  like  those  in  his  own  country.  The  energy 
with  which  he  defended  his  views  was,  however,  impressive,  and  his  pupils, 
who  came  from  all  parts  of  the  world,  endeavoured  faithfully  to  apply  the 
master's  doctrines,  however  difficult  they  might  prove  to  be  in  practice.  The 
whole  of  the  earliest  generation  of  geologists,  as  a  matter  of  fact,  shared 
this  failing  of  Werner's  —  even  the  scientist  who  is  named  with  Werner  as 
the  creator  of  geology,  Hutton,  had  never  been  outside  his  own  country. 

James  Hutton  (172.6-97)  was  the  son  of  a  Scottish  landowner,  and 
studied  medicine  in  his  youth,  but,  having  inherited  a  fortune,  he  after- 
wards devoted  himself  entirely  to  scientific  research,  especially  geology.  It 
was  not  until  late  in  life  that  he  published  the  work  Theory  of  the  Earth,  in 
which  he  expounds  his  original  ideas,  though  in  a  not  very  clear  form.  He 
considers  that  geology  has  nothing  to  do  with  the  history  of  creation;  its 
function  is  to  describe  the  rock  and  earth  strata  now  existing  and  to  account 
for  their  origin.  He  believes  that  the  present  rock-beds  have  arisen  through 
the  destruction  of  older  strata,  similar  to  that  which  takes  place  daily 
through  the  influence  of  water.  This  principle  of  explaining  the  past  out 
of  the  present  represents  his  most  valuable  contribution  to  the  development 
of  geology,  though  his  own  applications  of  that  principle  were  often  not 
very  successful. 

It  was  not  possible  to  ascertain  the  reciprocal  age  of  the  different  rock 
strata,  and  thereby  also  to  create  a  history  of  the  evolution  of  the  earth's 
surface,  until  attention  had  been  paid  to  the  remains  of  living  creatures  that 
are  found  in  the  various  geological  beds.  This,  indeed,  Buffon  had  already 
done,  but  the  one  who  really  systematized  palaeontology  was  Cuvier.  His 
work  in  this  sphere  has  already  been  described  and  its  deep  significance 
pointed  out;  his  catastrophe  theory,  the  gist  of  which  has  likewise  been 
explained  above,  had  disastrous  consequences.  Its  influence  was  felt  least  in 
England,  where  geology  was  developed  independently  in  this  field  also.  The 
scientist  who  introduced  into  that  country  the  knowledge  of  fossils  as  a 
guide  to  geological  research  was  William  Smith  (1769-183 9).  Born  of  poor 
parents  in  the  country,  he  received  a  deficient  school-education  and  after- 
wards became  apprentice  to  a  surveyor,  who  taught  him  sound  professional 
knowledge,  with  the  result  that  he  was  sought  after  as  a  surveyor  and  level- 
ler, making  a  fortune  in  that  profession  and  at  the  same  time  having  oppor- 
tunities for  studying  very  different  geological  strata  and  rock  formations. 
He  quickly  came  to  realize  that  these  possessed  a  settled  order  of  succession 
and  that  different  animals  and  vegetable  remains  characterize  the  different 
stratifications.  The  fossils  he  himself  was  unable  to  determine,  this  being 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  455 

done  by  some  of  his  friends,  but  he  had  a  keen  eye  to  the  place  into  which 
each  form  should  fall  in  the  strata  system.  Eventually  he  published  the 
results  of  his  life-work  in  a  great  geological  atlas  of  England,  which  cost 
him  his  whole  fortune.  For  a  time  he  suffered  want,  but  was  eventually 
granted  a  government  pension,  which  ensured  him  a  peaceful  old  age.  It 
was  through  him  that  the  use  of  guiding  fossils  for  identifying  the  age  of 
geological  formations  was  introduced  into  science. 

An  investigator  who  surveyed,  and  in  a  high  degree  developed,  the 
geological  knowledge  of  his  age  was  Christian  Leopold  von  Buch  (1774- 
1853).  He  belonged  to  a  distinguished  and  wealthy  Prussian  family,  and 
studied  under  Werner  at  Freiberg  together  with  Humboldt  with  a  view  to 
entering  the  mining  service,  but  he  soon  applied  himself  entirely  to  geology, 
which,  thanks  to  his  inherited  wealth,  he  was  able  to  study  without  having 
to  earn  his  living.  He  made  extensive  expeditions,  in  the  course  of  which 
he  made  a  particularly  fine  collection  of  comparative  material  from  various 
countries.  The  result  of  this  research  work  soon  led  him  from  the  Neptun- 
ism  of  Werner  to  the  opposite  extreme;  he  ascribed  to  volcanic  activity  an 
important,  and  indeed  far  too  important,  part  in  the  history  of  the  earth's 
surface.  His  investigations,  carried  out  in  different  regions,  are  nevertheless 
of  lasting  value;  he  w^as,  moreover,  an  eminent  palaeontologist,  making 
valuable  investigations  of  special  subjects,  particularly  of  fossil  inverte- 
brates: Cephalopoda,  Brachiopoda,  and  others. 

Charles  Lyell  is,  however,  the  scientist  that  is  first  worthy  of  mention 
as  the  founder  of  modern  geology  and  thereby  as  a  pioneer  of  the  descent 
theory.  He  was  born  in  1797,  the  son  of  a  Scottish  landowner,  who  was  also 
interested  in  botany  and  who  inspired  in  his  son  a  passion  for  nature  study. 
The  latter  took  his  degree  at  Oxford  and  afterwards  adopted  the  profession 
of  a  lawyer.  But  he  did  not  go  far  in  that  career,  for  eye-trouble  compelled 
him  to  give  up  public  work  of  any  kind.  Long  before  this,  however,  geology 
had  attracted  him,  W.  Smith's  investigations  especially  interesting  him,  and 
for  the  rest  of  his  life  he  devoted  himself  to  that  study,  bearing  with  un- 
paralleled courage  the  severe  deprivation  that  defective  vision  always  means 
to  a  scientist,  especially  a  natural  scientist.  One  source  of  comfort  in  these 
circumstances  was  the  fact  that  his  wife  with  devoted  self-sacrifice  dedicated 
her  life  to  helping  him  in  his  work.  He  thus  became  one  of  the  many  bril- 
liant private  scholars  in  which  the  cultural  history  of  England  abounds,  and 
he  was  the  recipient  of  not  a  few  honours.  He  undertook  a  number  of  long 
voyages  of  exploration;  he  considered  them  to  be  indispensable  for  a  geol- 
ogist, for  it  is  only  thus  that  he  can  gain  that  living  idea  of  the  various 
forms  of  the  earth's  surface  which  may  serve  as  a  basis  for  a  theory  of  its 
history.  The  rest  of  his  time  he  spent  in  London,  where  he  was  a  member  of 
many  learned  societies  and  was  also  otherwise  held  in  high  repute.  He  died 


45  6  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

in  1875,  ^^^^^  having  some  years  previously  lost  both  his  sight  and  his  wife, 
who  had  been  the  mainstay  of  his  life  and  his  work. 

Ly ell's  act uali Stic  geology 
Like  Hutton,  Lyell  takes  as  his  starting-point  the  present  form  of  the  earth's 
surface,  studies  its  changes  as  the  result  of  various  natural  influences,  and 
finally  draws  the  conclusion  that  the  same  forces  have  always,  and  approxi- 
mately in  the  same  degree  as  in  our  own  time,  been  operating  on  the  earth's 
surface;  he  who  declares  otherwise  must  substantiate  his  argument  with 
proofs;  it  is  the  upholders  of  the  catastrophe  theory  whose  duty  it  is  to 
prove  the  correctness  of  their  views,  and  not  vice  versa.  This  conception  of 
the  evolution  of  the  earth  —  it  has  been  named  the  "actualistic"  —  forces 
Lyell  to  follow  it  through  to  its  extreme  consequences  and  far  beyond  what 
science  in  modern  time  is  prepared  to  admit.  Thus,  in  his  Principles  of  Geol- 
ogy he  absolutely  denies  the  possibility  of  the  earth's  having  originally 
existed  in  an  incandescent  state;  he  likewise  definitely  rejects  Lamarck's 
theory  that  the  animal  world  in  earlier  ages  consisted  of  entirely  different 
species  from  those  in  modern  times  and  declares  that  mammals  and  birds 
have  existed  from  the  very  earliest  times.  But  apart  from  these  extravagant 
statements,  which  as  a  matter  of  fact  he  afterwards  partly  corrected,  his 
strict  adherence  to  the  principle  that  the  phenomena  of  past  ages  should 
be  explained  from  what  is  known  from  the  phenomena  of  the  present  time 
has  formed  the  basis  on  which  it  has  been  possible  to  construct  a  truly 
scientific  geology.  The  earlier  geological  theories,  both  ingenious  and  fool- 
ish, had  all  been  mere  products  of  the  imagination;  Lyell  introduced  the 
principle,  which  must  inevitably  be  adopted  by  every  empirical  science,  of 
starting  from  what  is  known  and  has  been  investigated  and  thence  pro- 
ceeding gradually  towards  the  more  remote  and  the  unknown.  If  past  natu- 
ral phenomena  in  general  are  to  be  calculated  or  at  least  reconstructed  with 
fair  probability,  it  is  necessary  to  start  from  the  present,  whose  course 
of  events  it  is  possible  to  survey.  This  astronony  has  long  done  with  its 
calculations  of  the  position  and  motions  of  the  heavenly  bodies  in  past  ages; 
and  modern  geology  has  in  certain  spheres,  as,  for  instance,  in  the  deter- 
mination of  annual  stratifications  out  of  water  during  preceding  periods, 
reached  a  degree  of  accuracy  that  should  not  be  far  inferior  to  astronomi- 
cal calculation.  And  this  principle  essentially  represents  Lyell's  service  to 
science. 

His  criticism  of  La7narck 
Moreover,  Lyell  has  made  important  contributions  in  his  above-mentioned 
work  to  problems  of  the  development  of  life  upon  the  earth.  His  criticism 
of  Lamarck's  theory  undeniably  touches  the  latter's  weakest  spot,  when  he 
maintains  that  Lamarck  never  even  attempted  to  find  out  the  origin  of  a 
single  vital  organ,  but  merely  occupies  himself  with  modifications  in  those 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  457 

already  existing.  He  can  hardly  be  blamed  for  the  fact  that  he  does  not  con- 
sider that  he  had  found  any  actual  proof  of  the  transition  of  one  species  to 
another,  since  it  has  indeed  scarcely  been  possible  to  discover  one  even  in 
our  own  time.  He  does  not  believe  in  the  possibility  of  the  various  species' 
being  able  to  vary  beyond  a  certain  limited  extent,  and  this  limit  is  soon 
reached;  if  we  try  to  force  a  form  beyond  this,  it  perishes;  as  an  instance  he 
quotes  the  adaptability  of  species  to  different  climates.  Man's  domestic  ani- 
mals have  from  the  beginning  been  especially  suitable  for  taming,  while 
other  equally  or  more  intelligent  animals,  the  apes,  for  instance,  have  to 
be  left  at  liberty.  It  is  primarily,  however,  the  rare  existence  of  and  sterility 
in  hybrids  that  to  Lyell's  mind  gives  proof  of  the  constancy  of  the  species. 
The  similarity  between  embryos  of  various  kinds  merely  testifies  to  a  com- 
mon plan  in  their  structure,  but  no  common  origin.  He  believes  that  every 
species  has  been  created  in  a  locality  suitable  to  it  and  has  spread  from  there 
under  the  constant  influence  of  the  climate,  means  of  subsistence,  and  com- 
petition with  other  life-forms.  In  disproof  of  Lamarck's  theory  of  species- 
modification  he  maintains  that  an  alteration  in  the  climatic  changes  or  other 
alterations  in  the  conditions  of  life  would  give  certain  species  advantage 
over  others,  so  that  the  adaptability  assumed  by  Lamarck  would  never  be 
realized  in  the  latter.  If  a  lake  were  to  be  converted  into  a  swamp,  already 
existing  marsh-plants  would  be  ready  to  overrun  its  area,  while  the  aquatic 
plants  would  die  out  before  they  had  time  to  adapt  themselves  to  swamp 
conditions.  How  the  species  came  to  be  created  is  a  question  that  Lyell 
refuses  to  discuss;  he  speaks  of  "creative  force,"  though  he  attributes  no 
personality  to  it,  regarding  the  whole  problem  as  insoluble.  Instead  he  dis- 
cusses in  detail  the  conditions  governing  the  distribution  of  species,  their 
development  and  extinction  during  different  geological  epochs.  The  whole 
of  this  exposition  exercised  a  very  great  influence  on  Darwin,  both  positive 
and  negative,  by  calling  forth  a  contradiction  from  him  —  a  point  on  which 
more  light  will  be  thrown  later. 

But  the  main  point  is  that  Lyell's  theory  of  geological  evolution  offered 
at  the  time  particularly  valuable  support  to  the  idea  of  evolution,  which 
was  one  of  the  watchwords  of  the  age;  here  indeed  there  was  confirmation 
in  nature  herself  of  the  idea  of  an  uninterrupted  development  as  the  funda- 
mental force  in  existence.  The  result  was  that  Lyell's  name  became  one  of 
the  most  popular  at  the  time,  and  he  himself  enhanced  his  reputation  by 
his  ability  to  keep  pace  with  scientific  developments;  he,  the  opponent  of 
Lamarck,  associated  himself  directly  and  without  reservation  with  Darwin. 
His  activities  as  the  promoter  of  Darwinism  will  be  dealt  with  in  the  next 
section. 


458  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

X.    The  Ideal  Preconditions  of  Darwinism 

Failure  of  Lamarck' s  theory 
The  question  has  not  infrequently  been  discussed:  Why  did  not  Lamarck's 
theory  of  evolution  succeed?  The  reason  has  been  put  down  to  the  opposi- 
tion of  the  Church,  but  certainly  without  justification;  as  far  as  is  known, 
Lamarck  was  never  interfered  with  by  the  Church,  and  the  latter's  opposi- 
tion to  the  theories  of  origin  and  species-m.odification  is,  as  we  shall  find, 
of  a  far  later  date.  We  are,  then,  far  more  justified  in  blaming  the  romantic 
natural  philosophy,  which,  seeking,  as  it  did,  after  one  common  idea  for 
every  life -form,  lacked  all  feeling  for  material  development.  For  herein  lies 
the  real  gist  of  the  problem:  if  a  theory  of  evolution  is  to  attract  general 
attention,  there  must  naturally  be  evinced  an  interest  in  evolution.  Our  next 
duty,  therefore,  will  be  to  try  to  explain  how  this  interest  arose  and  how  it 
expressed  itself  at  the  time  of  Darwin's  appearance. 

It  is  common  knowledge  that  mankind  is  always  ready  to  fix  its  ideals 
in  antiquity  —  "the  good  old  times."  One  is  most  inclined  to  deplore  the 
present  and  to  view  the  future  with  feelings  of  anxiety.  And  just  like  indi- 
viduals, the  public  opinion  of  the  different  epochs  has  done  the  same;  if 
man  has  carried  out  reforms,  it  has  mostly  been  done  under  the  form  of 
reviving  the  ideal  conditions  of  ages  long  past;  so  it  was  during  the  Refor- 
mation, when  people  vv^ished  to  revert  to  the  conditions  of  early  Christianity, 
and  so  too  during  the  French  Revolution,  when  people  raved  over  the  re- 
publics of  antiquity,  and  imaginative  popular  leaders  called  themselves  An- 
acharsis  or  Gracchus.  If  one  has  dared  to  cast  a  glance  at  the  future,  one  has 
most  probably  expected  to  find  happiness  in  some  vast  catastrophe  resulting 
in  the  total  annihilation  of  the  present;  thus  all  apocalyptical  enthusiasts 
of  antiquity  and  ever  since,  and  thus  too  the  political  extreme  tendencies  of 
modern  times.  Belief  in  a  gradually  progressive,  law-bound  development  has 
always  been  limited  to  a  few,  and  these  perhaps  are  to  be  found  among  the 
men  of  action  rather  than  men  of  thoughts  and  words.  The  most  pronounced 
faith  in  progress  that  has  ever  existed  has  been  the  liberalism  of  the  nine- 
teenth century,  a  current  of  ideas  which  had  just  reached  its  zenith  by  the 
middle  of  the  century,  when  the  theory  of  origin  came  to  the  fore.  The  co- 
incidence is  of  course  not  accidental;  on  the  contrary,  the  one  idea  is  de- 
pendent on  the  other,  and  therefore  the  victory  of  Darwinism  is  inexplicable 
without  some  insight  into  the  general  intellectual  conditions  at  the  time 
of  its  birth. 

Liberalism  of  the  nineteenth  century 
The  optimistic  belief  of  liberalism  in  the  progress  of  the  human  race  had  its 
true  origin  in  England,  where  throughout  the  entire  eighteenth  century 
prosperity  and  enlightenment  increased  slowly  but  surely,  where  humane 


Pi 
< 
Q 

< 
u 


^^ 

Si 

i 

^•'^^ 

^  ''^^BSBBL I         ^ 

iW          .^1 

B^^ 

v^fii^^^H 

■:^BQH^^^^H^^^^^^BB    j 

|jj|i  w 

^■hq 

1 

^^<<^^,<  ■v\^IHp 

W^.:':     *      .     I      .^ 

lir  ? 

iSte.^ 

r^  /( 

"^■•^=1 

IL 

^^B- 

^V^HHBI^>' 

I 

PC] 
1/3 

w 

<5 
u 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  459 

legislation  and  democratic  social  development  were  demanded  and  even  grad- 
ually achieved  without  violent  upheavals.  This  beliefwas  strongly  influenced 
by  Rousseau's  doctrines  of  the  natural  goodness  of  man;  which  has  only  been 
perverted  by  social  life  and  by  the  oppression  of  evil  kings  and  priests;  it 
found  expression  in  the  democratic  reforms  of  the  French  Revolution,  but 
it  acquired  its  true  character  through  the  great  technical  and  material  prog- 
ress made  during  the  nineteenth  century,  to  which  reference  has  already  been 
made  above.  The  new  big-scale  industrial  development  and  world  trade,  ren- 
dered possible  by  steam-power,  created  an  intelligent  middle  class,  which 
felt  well  satisfied  with  the  present  and  hoped  for  still  greater  benefits  from 
the  future;  the  labouring  classes  were  not  yet  organized  and  their  discontent 
was  thus  perceptible  only  in  isolated  instances.  The  vast  production  of  ma- 
terial values  set  its  mark  upon  the  age  and  was  met  by  the  belief,  adopted 
from  Rousseau,  in  the  natural  goodness  of  the  human  race  and  in  Bentham's 
doctrine  of  happiness  for  as  many  as  possible  as  the  chief  aim  in  life;  hap- 
piness was  made  the  synonym  for  material  welfare,  and  this  could  best  be 
attained  by  letting  mankind,  endowed  by  nature  with  goodness  and  intel- 
ligence, look  after  themselves,  undisturbed  by  oppression  and  superfluous 
regulations.  Human  life  thus  came  to  be  regarded  as  a  dominion  of  imper- 
sonal forces  guiding  humanity  with  the  necessity  of  a  natural  law  towards 
better  times,  if  only  they  were  allowed  to  operate  freely.  The  people  —  the 
impersonal  summary  of  the  individuals  living  in  a  country  —  were  better 
advised  than  any  single  person;  if  only  they  were  allowed  to  look  after 
themselves,  their  activities  would  conduce  to  a  successful  development,  to 
which  there  seemed  to  be  no  limits.  Free  competition  both  in  the  material 
and  in  the  spiritual  world  and  no  interference  with  the  individual's  liberty 
of  action  were  the  watchwords  of  the  age;  how  the  free  will  of  the  indi- 
vidual was  eventually  to  be  reconciled  with  the  popular  will  was  a  question 
that  did  not  bother  the  minds  of  many;  for  the  time  being,  the  individuals 
looked  up  to  the  popular  will  as  to  a  higher  power,  the  only  fault  of  which 
was  that  it  had  not  yet  had  sufficient  time  in  which  to  operate. 

This  conception  of  life,  which  naturally  appeared  under  quite  different 
forms  in  different  quarters  —  in  historians  like  Buckle,  in  thinkers  like  Mill 
and  Spencer,  not  to  speak  of  their  pupils  and  imitators  on  the  Continent  — 
was  without  doubt  the  most  favourable  soil  possible  in  which  to  cultivate 
a  general  theory  of  evolution.  Evolution,  Progress,  were  in  fact  the  slogan 
of  the  age.  It  had  been  employed  in  Comte's  system,  described  above,  but 
only  as  far  as  regards  human  culture;  through  Darwin  evolution  was  ele- 
vated to  a  natural  law  governing  all  life.  It  is  no  wonder,  then,  that  his 
theory  was  hailed  with  enthusiasm  by  all  those  who  cherished  the  ideals 
of  the  new  age.  It  was  indeed  the  ideal  itself  that  was  hereby  sanctioned  to 
embrace  the  whole  of  nature;  on  the  other  hand,  it  affords  an  explanation 


460  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

for  the  violent  opposition  on  the  part  of  all  adherents  to  the  old  order  of 
society,  which  was  not  yet  won  over  and  which  towards  the  close  of  the 
century  was  to  muster  increasingly  stronger  forces.  But  Darwin  himself  was 
influenced  by  the  new  conception  of  community  life;  it  was  from  one  of  its 
theorists  that  he  obtained  the  actual  idea  for  his  theory  of  selection  — 
namely,  Malthus,  wherefore  he  is  worthy  of  a  place  in  the  history  of  biology. 
Thomas  Robert  Malthus  (1766-1834)  was  the  son  of  a  landowner, 
took  his  degree  at  Cambridge,  was  ordained  priest,  and  obtained  a  curacy, 
but  at  the  same  time  devoted  himself  to  the  study  of  national  economics. 
On  account  of  his  writings  he  was  given  a  professorship  in  London,  where 
he  afterwards  worked  with  great  success.  His  father  had  been  a  personal 
pupil  of  Rousseau  and  entertained  rather  radical  views  on  the  improvement 
of  the  human  race  by  a  fair  distribution  of  wealth  —  an  idea  which  had  then, 
as  it  had  later,  many  supporters.  Against  them  there  appeared  the  younger 
Malthus  with  his  chief  work.  The  Principle  of  Population,  which  came  out 
in  many  editions  and  has  been  very  widely  discussed.  Although  himself  a 
liberal,  he  is  in  no  wise  a  revolutionary  optimist;  he  sees  the  cause  of  human 
misery  not  in  an  unfair  distribution  of  property,  but  in  man's  own  habit  of 
living  thoughtlessly  and  frivolously.  The  cure  for  this  he  sees  in  bringing 
mankind  up  to  exercise  self-control,  every  man  being  taught  not  to  raise 
a  family  without  definitely  guaranteed  means  of  subsistence.  It  is,  he  be- 
lieves, a  fact  throughout  nature,  in  plants,  animals,  and  human  beings,  that 
natural  procreation  is  stronger  than  the  possibilities  of  maintaining  life; 
from  this  there  arises  in  nature  a  violent  competition  for  the  maintenance 
of  life,  and  in  human  life  there  is,  further,  helpless  and  ever-increasing  misery 
among  the  poverty-stricken  classes,  which  no  philosophical  measures  can 
remedy.  He  then  tries  by  means  of  historical  and  geographical-statistical 
investigations  to  find  out  how  it  is  that  the  increase  in  the  population  never 
has  followed,  and  does  not  follow  now,  its  natural  course,  but  is  restricted, 
more  or  less  owing  to  the  fact  that  the  supply  of  maintenance  is  limited, 
with  the  result  that  want,  with  its  concomitant  vice  and  crime,  thins  out 
a  great  number  of  the  poorest  in  each  community.  Upon  its  first  appearance 
this  doctrine  was  violently  opposed  from  both  conservative  and  radical  quar- 
ters; it  is  not,  however,  within  the  scope  of  this  work  to  enter  into  a  detailed 
discussion  of  the  subject;  it  is  sufficient  to  point  out  the  above-mentioned 
theory  of  competition,  which  gave  Darwin  the  idea  for  his  theory  of  selec- 
tion. To  this  latter  we  shall  now  proceed. 


CHAPTER    XI 


DARWIN 


CHARLES  Robert  Darwin  was  born  in  1809  at  Shrewsbury  in  the  west 
of  England.  His  father,  Robert  Waring  Darwin,  was  the  son  of  the 
physician  and  natural  philosopher  Erasmus  Darwin  and  was  him- 
self a  physician.  He  was  married  to  Susannah  Wedgwood,  daughter  of  the 
famous  procelain  manufacturer  Josiah  Wedgwood,  who,  from  being  a  poor 
and  ignorant  apprentice  to  a  potter  had  made  a  successful  career,  acquiring 
a  splendid  fortune  and  a  famous  name  in  the  history  of  ceramics.  Charles 
was  the  sixth  out  of  eight  children.  He  went  through  a  school  of  the  usual 
English  type,  his  education  consisting  almost  exclusively  of  the  classical 
languages,  and  was  afterwards  sent  to  Edinburgh  in  order  to  study  medicine 
in  the  family  tradition.  The  Latin  he  learnt  at  school  did  not  interest  him 
very  much  and  he  was  utterly  bored  by  the  anatomy  lectures.  Darwin  broke 
off  his  medical  studies  after  a  couple  of  years,  so  that  he  never  became  an 
anatomist,  to  his  own  great  loss.  He  now  decided  to  try  his  hand  at  theology 
at  Cambridge,  where  he  spent  three  years  and  took  his  degree  of  bachelor  of 
arts,  but  he  spent  most  of  his  time  pursuing  the  usual  occupation  of  the 
well-to-do  English  undergraduate  —  sport,  especially  shooting.  He  also  col- 
lected insects  and  plants  for  his  own  amusement,  but  he  chiefly  interested 
himself  in  geology,  receiving  a  sound  elementary  training  in  that  subject 
under  the  guidance  of  the  eminent  professor  Adam  Sedgwick  (1785-1873), 
whom  he  accompanied  on  several  expeditions.  On  the  recommendation  of 
a  friend  he  was  offered  in  1831  the  unsalaried  post  of  naturalist  on  board 
the  cruiser  Beagle,  which  was  to  circumnavigate  the  world  for  mainly  carto- 
graphical purposes.  This  voyage,  which  lasted  five  years,  gave  him,  as  he 
himself  says,  his  real  training  as  a  naturalist,  as  it  also  determined  the  di- 
rection that  his  future  work  was  to  take.  He  worked  with  zeal  and  sent  home 
from  the  various  stopping-places  on  the  way  both  notes  and  collections. 
Of  these  the  geological  possessed  the  greatest  value;  the  zoological  and 
botanical  were  regarded  by  contemporary  judges  as  nothing  extraordinary. 
This  persevering  activity  was  so  much  the  more  praiseworthy  as  Darwin 
suffered  throughout  the  journey  from  incurable  seasickness,  which  gradually 
irremediably  impaired  his  health.  On  his  return  home  he  devoted  himself 
for  years  to  the  working  up  of  the  natural  objects  and  the  material  for  ideas 
that  he  had  gathered  in  the  course  of  the  voyage.  During  that  period  there 

461 


46z  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

slowly  developed  in  his  mind  the  theory  which  bears  his  name.  In  1833  he 
married  his  cousin  Hannah  Wedgwood.  Her  wealth  added  to  his  own  made 
it  possible  for  him  during  his  remaining  years  to  lead  the  quiet  life  of  a  pri- 
vate scholar,  which  in  fact  became  in  time  an  absolute  necessity,  owing  to 
his  increasing  ill  health.  Three  years  after  his  marriage  he  left  London  and 
settled  in  Down,  a  small  town  in  Kent,  where  he  spent  the  rest  of  his  life 
in  his  own  comfortable  house,  with  a  delightful  garden.  Even  in  these  cir- 
cumstances, however,  his  health  did  not  improve;  he  suffered  from  a  nerv- 
ous stomachic  trouble,  which  occasioned  constant  vomitings  and  frequent 
insomnia.  It  was  only  through  living  a  painfully  regular  life  under  the  self- 
sacrificing  care  of  his  wife  that  he  was  able  to  hold  out  as  long  as  he  did. 
His  days  passed  with  brief  but  intensively  concentrated  periods  of  work,  al- 
ternating with  medical  attention,  walks,  and  literary  diversion;  journeys 
and  social  life  were  restricted  to  a  minimum.  During  this  period  there  was 
given  to  the  world  that  unique  production  —  considerable  even  in  its  extent 
—  which  made  his  name  immortal.  His  bodily  existence,  so  full  of  suffering, 
was  compensated  for  throughout  his  life  by  a  rare  spiritual  poise;  complete 
freedom  from  passion,  from  hate,  envy,  and  ambition,  and  an  almost  tender 
amiability,  which  certainly  found  it  difficult  to  refuse  a  petition,  however 
unreasonable,  but  which  also  made  it  easy  for  him  to  enjoy  and  find  child- 
like pleasure  in  the  narrow  life  to  which  his  ill  health  restricted  him.  His 
was  no  critical  character;  towards  the  statements  of  others  he  used  to  show, 
as  Johannsen  says,  "an  amiable  credulity,"  and  his  own  experiments  were 
often  consciously  childish.  His  sensitiveness,  however,  was  in  no  way  as- 
sociated with  weakness  of  character;  on  the  contrary,  few  students  of  nature 
have  striven  with  such  unbending  determination  for  years  and  years  towards 
a  given  goal,  and  adhered  to  a  point  of  view  when  once  adopted  with  such 
firm  conviction.  His  ideas  were,  as  is  well  known,  both  unreservedly  praised 
and  violently  vituperated;  attacks  were  met  by  him  with  unfailing  stead- 
fastness and  a  noble  calm,  so  that  he  never  allowed  himself  to  be  involved 
in  personal  polemics,  but  he  always  took  note  of  and  parried  material  ob- 
jections. Thanks  to  these  qualities,  Darwin  came  in  the  course  of  years  to 
enjoy  personal  esteem  such  as  seldom  falls  to  the  lot  of  scientists.  Occupied 
in  constant  work,  his  life  moved  quietly  towards  its  close.  He  died  in  i88z 
and  was  buried  in  Westminster  Abbey,  not  far  from  Newton,  followed  to 
the  grave  by  the  most  distinguished  men  in  the  country  both  in  the  social 
and  in  the  scientific  world.  Shortly  before  his  death  he  had  wTitten  down  in 
some  notes  on  his  own  life  the  oft-quoted  words:  "As  for  myself,  I  believe 
that  I  have  acted  rightly  in  steadily  following  and  devoting  my  life  to  sci- 
ence. I  feel  no  remorse  from  having  committed  any  great  sin,  but  have  often 
and  often  regretted  that  I  have  not  done  more  direct  good  to  my  fellow 
creatures." 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  463 

In  his  youth  Danvin  was  a  confirmed  lover  of  the  open-air  life;  a  good 
shot,  an  enthusiastic  huntsman,  and  a  keen  observer  of  life  in  nature.  This 
love  of  animate  life  in  the  open  air  he  retained  even  in  his  old  age;  long 
after  ill  health  had  compelled  him  to  give  up  shooting  and  voyages  of  ex- 
ploration, he  applied  himself  with  indefatigable  devotion  to  the  care  and 
observation  of  life  in  his  park  and  garden.  Dogs  and  cats,  birds,  insects,  and 
earthworms,  no  less  than  plants  of  the  most  varied  kinds,  were  to  him  a 
never-wearying  source  of  joy  and  observation;  all  their  manifestations  of 
life  in  the  minutest  detail  were  the  object  of  his  most  careful  study;  animals' 
actions,  instincts,  and  manifestations  of  intelligence  were  observed,  analysed, 
and  summarized  by  him  day  by  day  and  year  by  year  with  never-failing  in- 
terest. His  theoretical  training,  on  the  other  hand,  was  deficient — -most  thor- 
ough in  the  sphere  of  geology,  whereas  in  biology  it  was,  on  the  whole, 
limited  to  the  systematic  side.  His  observations  made  during  the  circum- 
navigation of  the  world  also  bear  witness  to  this  restricted  basis  on  which 
his  education  was  founded.  He  was,  moreover,  in  his  youth  a  firm  believer 
in  the  Christian  faith  —  he  intended,  in  fact,  to  become  a  clergyman  —  and  he 
accepted  without  criticism  the  traditional  dogmas,  including,  of  course,  the 
doctrine  of  the  origin  of  living  species  as  the  result  of  a  divine  act  of  crea- 
tion. During  his  voyage,  however,  he  found  that  this  belief  conflicted  with 
the  results  of  his  observations.  His  diary  contains  many  proofs  of  this;  in 
particular,  the  existence  of  many  species  with  a  small  area  of  distribution, 
of  forms  closely  allied  to  one  another,  but  not  alike,  and  taking  the  place 
of  one  another  in  different  localities,  yet  not  existing  together,  seemed  to 
him  difficult  to  reconcile  with  "nature's  great  plan."  Why  had  it  been  neces- 
sary to  create  all  these  slightly  differentiated  and  narrowly  distributed  spe- 
cies? He  spent  one  month  on  the  desolate  Galapagos  Islands,  situated  a  long 
way  off  the  coast  of  South  America  and  composed  of  volcanic  lava  compara- 
tively recently  cast  up  out  of  the  ocean;  here  he  felt  himself  "placed  in  prox- 
imity to  the  very  act  of  creation  itself."  But  here  he  found  a  fauna  of  markedly 
South  American  genera,  though  possessing  peculiar  species;  of  many  birds 
each  separate  island  had  its  own  species.  That  one  species  should  have  been 
created  for  each  small  island  seemed  to  him  irrational;  but  how,  then,  had 
the  different  species  arisen  and  why  did  they  belong  to  the  South  American 
genera?  This  problem,  having  once  penetrated  his  mind,  gave  him  no  rest. 
Upon  his  return  home  he  at  once  started  to  record  in  a  separate  book  his 
experiences  in  connexion  with  the  question  of  the  formation  of  species,  and 
he  sought  long  and  restlessly  for  proofs  of  the  correctness  of  his  ideas.  In 
1844  he  writes  in  a  letter  to  his  friend  the  botanist  Hooker:  "I  have  read 
heaps  of  agricultural  and  horticultural  books  and  have  never  ceased  col- 
lecting facts.  At  last  gleams  of  light  have  come,  and  I  am  almost  convinced 
(quite  contrary  to  the  opinion  I  started  with)  that  species  are  not  (it  is  like 


464  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

confessing  a  murder)  immutable."  Lamarck's  theory  of  the  modification  of 
species,  however,  Darwin  was  unable  to  accept;  it  appeared  to  him  to  be 
"rubbish"  —  "Heaven  forfend  me  from  Lamarck's  nonsense  of  'a  tendency 
to  progression. '  "  Nor  indeed  in  any  other  biological  literature  accessible  to 
him  could  he  find  any  way  out  of  the  difficulty  involved  in  the  origin  of 
species. 

Darwin  s  experiments  to  -prove  the  mutability  of  species 
During  this  period  he  was  closely  associated  with  Lyell,  the  scientist  who 
most  influenced  him  —  he  too,  as  we  have  seen,  no  friend  of  Lamarck  — 
and  resolved  to  deal  with  the  species  as  Lyell  had  dealt  with  the  geological 
strata  of  the  earth  —  namely,  to  collect  as  many  facts  as  possible  regarding 
the  transition  from  one  form  to  another.  In  this  respect  domestic  animals 
seemed  to  him  to  give  the  best  suggestions :  that  each  separate  domestic  animal 
was  a  true  species  no  systematist  had  ever  denied  and  it  was  likewise  ac- 
knowledged that  man  had  produced  a  mass  of  different  forms  of  every  species 
of  that  kind.  Darwin  placed  himself  in  communication  with  a  great  many 
animal-breeders,  and  himself  for  years  bred  different  races  of  pigeons,  all 
for  the  purpose  of  discovering  how  the  different  races  arose.  Expert  breeders 
believed  that  by  a  selection  of  suitable  parents  it  was  possible  gradually  to 
modify  the  progeny  at  will.  Darwin  also  came  to  accept  this  view;  all  the 
young  in  a  litter  of  domestic  animals  are  indeed  somewhat  unlike  one  another 
and  their  parents  —  they  "vary"  as  he  says  —  and  by  selecting  the  suitable 
variations  it  is  possible  to  guide  the  breed  in  the  required  direction.  But  if 
man  was  able  by  selection  to  produce  out  of  the  uniform  canine  type  that 
still  exists  among  wild  tribes  such  a  large  quantity  of  different  forms,  should 
it  not  then  be  possible  for  species  to  be  modified  by  nature  in  the  same  way? 
The  difference  between  a  greyhound  and  a  bulldog  is  far  greater  than  that 
between  many  wild  life-forms  which  without  doubt  pass  for  good  species. 
But  is  there  in  nature  a  force  operating  in  the  same  direction  as  the  breeder 
when  he  selects  new  forms  of  domestic  animals?  Here  lay  the  worst  stum- 
bling-block. Then  Darwin  happened  to  read  Malthus's  above-mentioned 
work  on  population :  how  both  in  nature  and  in  human  life  there  are  produced 
individuals  in  far  greater  numbers  than  there  are  means  for  maintaining,  and 
how  the  weakest  perish  in  the  competition  for  food.  This  gave  him  his  idea; 
in  the  struggle  for  existence  those  life-forms  are  destroyed  that  are  least  ca- 
pable of  adapting  themselves  to  prevailing  conditions,  while  the  strongest 
individuals  survive  and  reproduce  those  qualities  that  have  a  greater  chance 
of  survival.  Thus  the  external  conditions  themselves  come  to  multiply  the 
differences  brought  about  by  the  variability  of  the  offspring  in  relation  to 
the  parents,  until  new  varieties  and  new  species  arise.  Consequently,  the 
struggle  for  existence  induces  a  natural  selection  that  operates  similarly  to 
the  choice  of  races  among  domestic  animals  exercised  by  man,  only  with 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  465 

this  difference  —  that  vast  expanses  of  time  are  available  for  natural  selec- 
tion, which  justifies  the  assumption  that  all  the  manifold  forms  of  life  on 
the  earth,  both  those  which  have  existed  and  those  which  still  exist,  have 
been  developed  through  its  influence.  These  facts,  then  —  the  dissimilarity 
between  the  offspring  and  the  parents  (that  is,  variability)  and  the  struggle 
for  existence,  with  the  resultant  natural  selection  —  explain,  according  to 
Darwin,  the  origin  of  species. 

His  Zoological  works 
For  two  decades  Darwin  kept  this  theory  to  himself  in  an  unceasing  search 
for  fresh  proofs  of  its  universal  application.  Finally,  in  1859,  he  published 
it  in  a  work  entitled  On  the  Origin  of  Species  by  Means  of  Natural  Selection,  one 
of  the  most  famous  works  of  natural  history  that  have  ever  been  written. 
Even  before  that,  however,  he  had  won  a  high  reputation  as  the  result  of 
a  number  of  monographs  on  various  subjects.  Among  these  may  be  mentioned 
two  geological  treatises:  On  Volcanic  Islands  and  On  Coral  Reefs,  the  latter 
being  specially  famous  for  its  universally  accepted  theory  of  the  arising  of 
atolls  or  circular  reefs  through  the  sinking  of  the  land  area  around  which 
the  coral  reefs  had  originally  grown  up.  Among  his  zoological  works  may 
be  especially  mentioned  an  extensive  work  on  the  Cirripedia,  in  which  he 
gives  a  detailed  and  exhaustive  description  of  the  system  and  evolutional 
history  of  these  animal  forms  —  their  peculiar  dwarf  males  discovered  by 
him  —  besides  which  he  has  also  dealt  with  the  fossil  forms  of  that  animal 
group.  Moreover,  as  editor  of  the  scientific  results  of  the  Beagle  expedition 
he  contributed  much  of  great  value.  It  was  thus  a  naturalist  with  a  good 
reputation  who  came  forward  with  the  work  on  the  origin  of  species.  The 
violent  controversy  that  it  occasioned  brought  immediate  world-wide  fame 
to  its  author.  A  somewhat  detailed  account  of  the  main  ideas  of  the  work  is 
therefore  called  for,  all  the  more  so  as,  in  spite  of  its  immense  popularity, 
it  would  seem  to  have  been  less  widely  read  in  recent  times  than  one  might 
suppose,  and  the  exposition  of  the  theory  of  origin  to  be  found  in  the  usual 
text-books  has  been  strongly  influenced  by  that  comparative  morphology 
with  which  Darwin  himself  was  more  or  less  unfamiliar. 

The  theory  of  origin  that  Darwin  created  is  decidedly  characterized  by 
the  personality  of  its  founder.  Darwin  brought  to  his  work,  as  we  have 
observed  above,  a  deficient  theoretical  training,  particularly  in  the  sphere 
of  anatomy,  an  intense  geographical  and  systematical  interest,  and,  as  a 
standpoint  beyond  which  he  had  already  advanced  some  way,  a  somewhat 
ingenuous  orthodox-Christian  belief  in  the  creation.  Being  a  systematist,  he 
saw  in  the  problem  of  species  the  central  point  of  biology,  and  to  him  the 
centre  of  this  problem  was,  in  its  turn,  the  problem  of  creation.  This  must 
be  borne  in  mind  if  we  are  to  understand  Darwin's  relation  to  the  earlier 
morphologically   inclined   generation   of  scientists   of  the  Cuvier  school. 


466  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

Whatever  their  view  of  life,  the  species  idea  was  to  them  essentially  a  prac- 
tical basis  for  comparative  morphology,  whereas  the  problem  of  creation 
was  a  question  that  was  entirely  put  aside  as  not  concerning  natural  science.  It 
must  at  once  be  admitted  that  it  was  certainly  due  to  Darwin's  dilettante 
conception  of  nature  that  he  thus  adopted  just  the  problem  of  creation  as 
a  starting-point  for  many  years  of  research  work  and  cogitation;  on  the 
other  hand,  it  was  his  treatment  of  the  problem  that  caused  such  a  public 
sensation  over  his  work. 

Immutability  and  creation 
LiNN^us  in  his  youth  defined  the  species  as  the  progeny  of  those  animals 
that  had  been  created  in  the  beginning;  he  afterwards  altered  his  view,  in 
that  he  assumed  a  few  species  to  have  been  created,  out  of  which  the  others 
were  evolved  at  a  later  period.  To  the  systematists  who  succeeded  him  it 
was  the  immutability  of  the  species  that  was  the  essential  point,  the  actual 
basis  of  the  system,  while  the  problem  of  creation  was  seldom  discussed. 
De  CandoUe,  it  will  be  remembered,  has  a  definition  of  species  based  on 
mutual  similarity  and  fertility  between  the  individuals,  but  without  any 
mention's  being  made  of  the  creation.  To  Darwin,  however,  "immutable" 
and  "created,"  in  regard  to  species,  are  inseparable  terms;  doubt  of  the  im- 
mutability of  the  species  is  induced  by  doubt  of  the  creation,  which  in  its 
turn  has  been  caused  by  the  species'  conditions  of  distribution  and  not  by 
any  doubts  as  to  the  assumption  of  a  supernatural  act  of  creation  being  in 
itself  an  explanation  of  nature.^  Then  he  gets  the  idea  of  the  variations 
which  by  means  of  natural  selection  are  adapted  to  prevailing  external  con- 
ditions, thus  giving  rise  to,  first  of  all,  new  varieties,  and  then  new  species. 
Even  earlier  systematists  had  taken  it  for  granted  that  varieties  are  produced 
by  external  conditions,  flourish,  and  disappear;  what  is  novel  in  Darwin's 
theory  is  that  the  species  are  nothing  but  more  fully  developed  varieties, 
which  selection,  resulting  from  the  struggle  for  existence,  has  determined, 
while  the  intermediary  varieties,  as  being  less  capable  of  defying  competi- 
tion, have  perished.  He  adduces  a  great  many  arguments  to  prove  that  those 
species  which  are  most  widely  scattered  and,  where  they  exist,  are  richest 
in  individuals  are  also  those  which  produce  the  most  varieties,  which  in 
his  view  is  the  same  as  initial  species.  And  he  points  out  how  vague  the 
boundaries  between  species  and  varieties  really  are  in  the  minds  of  different 
systematists  and  how  difficult  it  is  to  define  what  is  meant  by  species.  He 
considers  that  this  name  is  given  arbitrarily  and  for  the  sake  of  convenience 
to  a  number  of  individuals  which  highly  resemble  one  another,  and  that  it 


^  In  his  diary  of  the  voyage  Darwin  in  one  place  explains  the  absence  of  certain  fossils 
in  a  geological  deposit  by  assuming  that  animals  of  that  kind  had  not  been  created  at  the  time 
when  the  deposit  came  into  being  (Life  and  Letters,  II,  p.  i).  Again,  in  the  Origin  of  Species  a 
Creator  is  mentioned  as  the  ultimate  cause  of  life. 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  467 

is  not  essentially  different  from  the  term  "variety,"  which  is  used  for  less 
distinct  and  more  iluctuating  forms. 

Variations  in  progeny 
The  causes  of  these  variations,  which  by  means  of  selection  —  natural  in 
wild  life,  human  in  domestic  animals  —  are  developed  into  varieties  and 
species,  involve  a  problem  that  occupied  the  mind  of  Darwin  a  great  deal. 
He  at  once  points  out  that  only  hereditary  variations  have  any  significance 
and  also  that  the  essential  causes  of  them  have  never  been  really  ascertained. 
On  this  question  he  adopts  a  somewhat  hesitant  attitude;  it  is  true,  he  as- 
serts, and  collects  ample  material  to  prove,  that  external  conditions  pro- 
duce variations  in  the  progeny,  which  is  a  view  strongly  reminiscent  of 
Lamarck,  but,  on  the  other  hand,  he  definitely  rejects  all  Lamarckian  ideas. 
As  a  matter  of  fact,  this  theory  of  the  heredity  of  variations  is  the  basis 
of  the  Darwinian  theory,  but  it  is  also  one  of  its  weakest  points;  in  this 
connexion  modern  research  into  the  problem  of  heredity  has  passed  severe 
judgment  on  him  —  often  indeed  unfairly  severe,  it  being  forgotten  that  he 
had  not  that  accumulation  of  facts  to  build  upon  which  is  available  in  modern 
times,  but  here  he  certainly  does  touch  upon  extremely  vague  conceptions, 
which  make  the  chapter  on  the  law  of  variation  difficult  to  comprehend. 
Among  the  circumstances  that  influence  the  individual's  reproductive  or- 
gans and  thus  affect  the  offspring,  he  mentions  climatic  conditions  of  vari- 
ous kinds  and  alimental  conditions,  as  well  as  the  correlation  between 
different  parts  of  the  body.  Nevertheless,  he  always  insists  upon  the  im- 
portance of  natural  selection  as  being  greater  than  the  direct  influence  of 
environment.  For  instance,  a  number  of  insect  forms  on  islands  in  mid-ocean 
have  restricted  powers  of  flight  as  compared  with  their  relations  on  the 
mainland;  this  has  arisen  through  the  fact  that  those  specimens  that  are 
best  at  flying  have  been  blown  out  to  sea  and  perished,  while  the  wxaker 
fliers  have  continued  to  propagate,  rather  than  through  the  animals'  not 
having  dared  to  use  their  wings,  with  the  result  that  their  growth  has  be- 
come stunted.  Correlation,  again,  compels  other  organs  to  follow  suit  when 
one  organ  has  been  modified  as  a  result  of  selection.  Further,  he  holds  that 
parts  of  the  body  that  have  become  especially  developed  in  one  species,  as 
compared  with  corresponding  parts  in  closely  related  species,  are  liable  to 
peculiar  variation;  thus,  the  length  of  the  arms  of  the  orang-utan  varies, 
just  as,  in  general,  every  strongly  developed  characteristic  indicates  strong 
variation  in  the  previous  generation.  On  the  other  hand,  the  wings  of  the 
bat  do  not  vary,  abnormal  though  they  are  in  comparison  with  the  extremi- 
ties of  other  mammals,  for  the  entire  group  has  wings  of  the  same  kind; 
the  law  would  hold  good  only  if  one  species  had  longer  pairs  of  wings  than 
other  species  of  the  same  genus.  On  these  grounds  he  believes  also  that 
species-characters  vary  more  than  genus-characters,  but  the  variations  of 


468  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

Species  of  the  same  genus  are  analogous.  In  connexion  with  this  point  he 
accounts  for  what  he  calls  the  "tendency  to  reversion"  —  the  frequent  and 
unexpected  tendency,  especially  in  domestic  animals,  for  forms  to  arise  hav- 
ing the  characters  of  the  wild  species:  tame  pigeons  resembling  the  wild 
rock-pigeon,  horses  with  zebra-like  streaks,  and  other  similar  instances. 

Difficulties  of  the  evolution  theory 
Darwin  having  thus  sought  to  determine  the  laws  of  variation,  he  takes 
up  for  study  the  difficulties  offered  by  the  theory  of  evolution  by  means  of 
natural  selection.  The  chapters  devoted  to  this  task  comprise  more  than 
half  the  book  and  represent  a  strange  miscellany.  As  a  matter  of  fact,  Darwin 
acknowledges  no  limitations  to  his  duty  to  answer  all  objections  to  his  the- 
ory, and  he  always  finds  some  way  out  of  a  difficulty,  however  desperate  it 
may  at  first  appear.  He  himself  considers  that  the  most  difficult  phenomenon 
to  explain  according  to  the  theory  of  selection  is  how  the  ants'  workers 
have  acquired  their  intelligence;  they  cannot  reproduce  themselves  and  thus 
transfer  their  favourable  variations  by  heredity  to  any  offspring.  The  diffi- 
culty is  solved  by  the  assumption  that  here  it  is  actually  the  community  as 
a  whole  which  derives  the  advantage  from  variations;  the  sex-individuals 
that  have  produced  workers  with  the  best  and  most  advantageous  qualities 
have  been  victorious  in  the  struggle  for  existence,  and  thus  have  arisen  both 
the  highly  cultivated  worker  types  and  the  strongly  developed  instincts  to 
make  slaves,  tend  aphides,  etc.  Darwin  undertakes  another  particularly  dif- 
ferent task  in  seeking  to  explain  how  such  a  complicated  organ  as  the  eye 
came  to  be  formed.  This  explanation,  which  was  ill  received  by  contempo- 
rary critics,  is  certainly  rather  far-fetched;  there  is  no  direct  transition  be- 
tween the  vertebrate  animals'  type  of  eye  and  that  of  the  Arthropoda  — it  is 
not  stated  why  association  is  not  sought  with  the  molluscs  instead,  in  which 
order  the  highly  developed  visual  organs  of  the  ink-fish  might  have  served 
as  a  transition.  —  And  so  the  whole  work  concludes  with  some  general 
assurances  as  to  the  metamorphosing  power  of  selection.  It  is  much  easier, 
of  course,  to  explain  the  origin  of  the  lungs  from  the  swimming-bladder; 
on  this  subject  earlier  comparative-anatomical  observations  have  been  avail- 
able as  a  basis  of  study.  Darwin  even  undertakes  to  defend  the  old  objection 
of  the  sterility  of  hybrids,  which  has  so  often  been  brought  forward  in  favour 
of  the  constancy  of  species.  He  differentiates  between  infertility  as  the  result  of 
crossing  species  on  the  one  hand,  and  the  sterility  of  hybrids  on  the  other; 
as  far  as  the  sterility  between  the  species  is  concerned,  he  finds  that  it  varies 
greatly  in  different  organisms  —  Koelreuter's  and  Gartner's  experiments 
are  especially  cited  as  instances  — ■  and  the  final  conclusion  is  that  "accidental 
and  unknown  circumstances"  are  the  cause  of  it  in  the  different  cases.  The 
sterility  of  hybrids,  again,  is  compared  with  the  infertility  of  wild  animals 
in  captivity;  each  is  attributed  to  the  direct  influence  of  external  conditions 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  469 

Upon  the  sexual  organs.  Here,  too,  reference  is  made  to  the  varying  results 
to  which  different  experiments  have  led.  The  fertility  of  variety-crosses,  on 
the  other  hand,  is  attributed  to  favourable  conditions  of  variations  in  closely 
related  characters.  The  result  of  this  is  a  proof  that  transition  forms  exist 
between  species  and  varieties. 

Darwin  and  Mendel 
If  we  compare  these  discussions  of  Darwin's  on  heredity  and  hybridization 
with  the  experiments  that  Mendel  concurrently  carried  out  for  the  same  pur- 
pose, the  English  scientist  naturally  gets  left  hopelessly  behind  —  on  his 
part,  widely  vacillating  speculations;  on  thepart  of  Mendel,  clearly  conceived 
and  exact  experiments.  The  very  starting-point  brings  this  out  clearly; 
Mendel  starts  from  a  few  simple  and  easily  determined  characters  and  es- 
tablishes their  appearance  in  different  generations  in  various  combinations; 
Darwin,  on  the  other  hand,  starts  from  the  ideas  of  species  and  variety  — 
that  is,  from  the  most  abstract  terms  in  biology  and  the  most  difficult  to 
define.  In  fact,  in  this  starting-point  lies  the  whole  weakness  of  Darwin's 
research  work  and  speculation.  His  successors,  indeed,  almost  immediately 
abandoned  this  standpoint  and  instead  sought  for  proofs  of  their  theory  by 
recourse  to  the  material  and  methods  of  comparative  anatomy;  Cuvier  and 
his  successors  had  already  studied  the  changes  undergone  by  one  and  the 
same  organ  in  a  series  of  diff'erent  animal  forms.  It  was  through  this  com- 
parative method's  being  placed  at  the  service  of  the  theory  of  origin  that 
Darwinism,  especially  through  Gegenbaur  and  his  school,  came  to  use  for 
purposes  of  investigation  objects  of  a  definite  and  concrete  nature.  But  Dar- 
win himself  had  but  little  mind  for  comparative  anatomy;  he  certainly  cites 
for  the  purposes  of  his  theory  a  number  of  proofs  derived  from  morphology, 
but  in  quite  a  brief  and  summary  fashion.  He  was  more  interested  in  embry- 
ology. Although  he  himself  had  never  worked  practically  as  an  embryologist, 
he  nevertheless  realized  the  value  of  comparative  investigations  into  diff'erent 
stages  of  development  and  he  works  out  the  basis  for  a  "biogenetic  prin- 
ciple," which  Fritz  Miiller  and  Haeckel  only  had  to  supplement. 

Darwin  on  questions  of  geography 
Darwin  is,  however,  far  more  at  home  in  the  sphere  of  geology  and  geog- 
raphy and  he  firmly  rejects  any  attempts  at  employing  the  results  of  these 
sciences  to  disprove  his  theory.  The  incompleteness  of  palasontological  re- 
mains he  considers  to  be  sufficient  argument  against  those  who  inquire  after 
"missing  links"  between  now  existing  genera  and  species,  while  the  con- 
ditions of  distribution  of  living  creatures  seemed  to  him  from  the  very  out- 
set to  be  the  surest  guarantee  of  the  truth  of  his  doctrine.  Climatic  changes 
have  in  the  course  of  the  ages  given  the  most  powerful  impulses  both  to  new 
variations  and  to  the  struggle  for  existence  under  new  conditions,  while 
newly-formed  natural  barriers,  mountain  ranges  and  encroachments  of  the 


470  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

sea,  have  split  up  uniform  groups  of  life-forms  and  created  isolated  areas  of 
development  with  accompanying  new  forms  of  genera  and  species.   And 
always  variation  and  natural  selection  are  sufficient  to  explain  all  phenom- 
ena; since  Aristotle  produced  his  explanation  of  nature,  no  biologist  has 
ever  conceived  it  his  duty  to  the  extent  that  Darwin  did  to  explain  anything 
whatsoever.  In  this  respect  he  takes  the  most  extraordinary  trouble  to  achieve 
his  purpose;  in  a  letter  to  Lyell  he  expresses  surprise  that  the  bats  of  New 
Zealand  —  of  old  the  sole  representatives  of  the  mammals  on  the  island  — 
had  not  made  their  home  on  the  ground  and  developed  into  land-animals, 
seeing  that  they  had  no  competitors.  And  he  ascribes  to  selection  the  most 
remarkable  powers;  a  traveller  had  seen  a  bear  swimming  in  a  North  Ameri- 
can river  and  snapping  at  insects  in  the  water;  Darwin  thinks  it  not  impos- 
sible that,  if  food  of  this  kind  were  abundant  and  there  were  no  competitors, 
a  number  of  bears  would  become  aquatic  animals  and  would  gradually 
acquire  larger  and  larger  mouths,  eventually  becoming  as  monstrous  as 
whales.  This  strange  conclusion,  which  is  given  in  the  first  edition  of  the 
work,  but  was  modified  in  succeeding  editions,  gives  striking  evidence  of 
another  weakness  in  Darwin's  speculation:  his  lack  of  sense  of  a  law-bound 
necessity  in  existence.  "I  believe  in  no  law  of  necessary  development,"  he 
expressly  declares.  The  variations  are  certainly  guided  by  laws,  as  mentioned 
above,  not,  however,  in  any  given  direction,  but  in  all  possible  directions, 
and  they  are  influenced,  depending  upon  every  chance,  quite  incalculably 
by  natural  selection.  But  if,  then,  natural  selection  were  guided  by  chance, 
it  would  exclude  the  possibility  of  any  law-bound  phenomenon  in  existence. 
Herein  really  lies  the  greatest  weakness  of  the  Darwinian  doctrine  of  selec- 
tion. It  has,  in  fact,  been  sharply  criticized  —  in  modern  times  especially  by 
Oscar  Hertwig  in  his  work  Das  Werden  der  Organismen,  the  subject  of  which 
is  indicated  by  the  subtitle:  Eine  Widerlegiing  von  Danvins  Zujallstheorie.  A 
similar  judgment  was  passed  by  Radl,  who,  moreover,  points  out  that  Dar- 
win really  applied  the  social  conception  of  contemporary  liberalism  to  life 
in  nature;  which,  as  a  matter  of  fact,  is  at  once  realized  from  the  acknowl- 
edged part  played  by  Malthus's  social  doctrine  in  the  working-out  of  Dar- 
win's theory.  This  human-social  conception  of  nature  stands  out  clearly  in 
the  above-mentioned  statement  regarding  the  bear,  which,  if  the  chance 
offers,  can  take  to  swimming  and  develop  into  a  whale.  More  applicable  to 
human-social  life  than  to  nature  is  also  the  form  that  his  utterances  often 
take  of  fancies  thrown  out  at  random,  which  reminds  one  of  a  social  re- 
former's improvement  schemes  rather  than  of  the  binding  conclusions  of  a 
scientific  investigator;  "it  would  be  easy,"  "it  would  offer  no  difficulty  to 
suppose,"  and  other  similar  expressions  frequently  occur.  This,  of  course,  is 
also  due  to  his  oft-recurring  tendency  to  allow  his  thoughts  to  dally  with  all 
kinds  of  possibilities  —  a  tendency  which,  when  combined  with  a  belief  in 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  471 

the  ability  of  his  theory,  once  advanced,  to  explain  practically  any  biologi- 
cal phenomena  whatsoever,  is  bound  to  lead  to  far-reaching  conclusions. 
Another  result  of  the  selection  theory  is  the  constant  reference  to  the  greatest 
possible  adaptability  to  prevailing  conditions,  with  the  consequent  insist- 
ence upon  the  finality  existing  in  nature.  It  has  already  been  pointed  out  how 
unsatisfactory  this  explanation  of  nature  is  and  further  reference  will  be 
made  to  it  later  on;  here  it  need  only  be  observed  that  this  belief  in  a  pur- 
poseful adaptability  to  prevailing  conditions  has  in  no  small  degree  contrib- 
uted towards  retarding  the  development  of  biology  into  an  exact  science. 

The  influence  that  Darwin's  Origin  of  Species  exercised  will  be  described 
in  the  following.  His  fame  in  no  wise  induced  the  author  to  rest  on  his 
laurels;  on  the  contrary,  he  laboured  indefatigably  throughout  his  life  still 
further  to  develop  the  theory  that  he  had  created  and  to  apply  it  to  different 
life-phenomena.  The  greatest  and  most  important  of  his  subsequent  works 
was  published  in  1868  in  two  volumes  and  bore  the  title  Animals  and  Plants 
under  Domestication.  In  the  first  volume  he  gives  a  detailed  account  of  his 
intensive  racial-biological  studies  of  domestic  animals  and  cultivated  plants. 
The  systematic  biology  of  preceding  ages  had,  as  a  general  rule,  depreciated 
these  beings:  they  were  not  true  species,  only  a  medley  of  varieties  that  no 
one  could  make  anything  of.  Darwin  then  showed  how  great  is  the  interest 
that  this  racial  research  possesses  and  what  important  results  can  be  pro- 
duced from  it.  All  later  racial  research  is,  in  fact,  based  on  his  initiative.  In 
point  of  exactness  these  investigations  of  Darwin's  certainly  cannot  be  com- 
pared with  those  carried  out  concurrently  by  Mendel,  but  they  are  far  more 
many-sided,  as  regards  both  material  and  conclusions,  and  they  also  caused 
an  immense  sensation,  especially  amongst  those  who  led  a  practical  life. 
Darwin  himself  largely  had  recourse  to  data  provided  by  animal-breeders 
and  gardening  experts,  and  he  was  certainly  not  very  particular  about  weed- 
ing out  their  alleged  results.  In  the  second  part  of  this  work  he  makes  fresh 
contributions  to  his  descent  theory.  Here  he  dilates  at  length  upon  his  con- 
ception of  heredity,  which  played  such  a  radical  part  in  the  cultural  history 
of  the  nineteenth  century,  although  it  is  now  entirely  abandoned.  As  has 
often  been  pointed  out,  heredity  is  to  him  equivalent  to  the  direct  trans- 
mission of  qualities  from  the  parents  to  the  offspring,  a  transmission  that  is 
influenced  by  a  vast  number  of  external  circumstances.  Further,  he  charac- 
terizes atavism  —  the  recurrence  of  qualities  similar  to  those  of  earlier 
generations  —  as  due  to  the  contrast  between  the  transmission  of  qualities 
and  evolution,  and,  moreover,  he  points  out  a  number  of  other  hereditary 
phenomena  —  the  transmission  of  qualities  confined  to  only  one  sex,  and  the 
inheritance  of  qualities  that  come  out  at  some  special  period  in  life.  He  also 
sought  to  explain  that  phenomenon  which  is  now  termed  the  "dominance" 
of  certain  qualities;  he  calls  it  the  "prepotency  of  transmission"  and  finds 


472.  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

its  existence  extremely  hard  to  explain,  but  puts  it  most  closely  in  connexion 
with  the  age  of  the  qualities  in  question.  Also  "latent,"  or,  as  they  are  called 
nowadays,  "recessive"  qualities,  he  made  the  subjects  of  observation  and 
speculation.  Particular  care  was  devoted  by  him  to  the  problem  of  hybridi- 
zation; he  is  all  the  time  procuring  from  his  experiments  proofs  of  the  over- 
lapping of  varieties  and  species.  Further,  he  investigated  the  cross  and 
self-fertilization  of  plants,  which  he  was  to  deal  with  more  fully  in  a  subse- 
quent special  work.  His  speculations  on  fertilization  and  hybridization  should 
not  be  judged  by  modern  standards;  he  knew  as  little  as  his  contemporaries  of 
the  true  course  of  fertilization  and  so  easily  became  deeply  involved  in  specu- 
lations as  to  the  consequences  of  the  effect  upon  the  egg  of  adequate  or  inade- 
quate quantities  of  sperm.  He  then  discusses  his  favourite  theory  of  the  laws 
of  variation,  which  he  now  considerably  expands,  with  an  increasing  ten- 
dency towards  Lamarckism,  external  circumstances  —  climate,  food,  and 
even  the  use  and  non-use  of  organs  —  being  definitely  stated  as  influencing 
the  forms  of  variation.  Even  hybridization  and  atavism  are  cited  as  causes  of 
variation,  besides  which  the  phenomena  of  correlation  are  more  closely 
analysed  in  connexion  with  variability. 

Pangenesis 
The  anxiety  to  find  a  universally  applicable  explanation  of  the  phenomena 
of  heredity  and  variation  led  Darwin  to  think  out  what  he  called  a  "pro- 
visional hypothesis  of  pangenesis."  In  this  theory  he  gives  to  the  cytology 
of  the  time,  with  which  he  otherwise  had  had  nothing  to  do,  a  new  and 
curious  interpretation.  He  believes  that  every  cell,  every  tissue-  or  organ-unit 
in  the  body,  produces  and  gives  off  minute  "atoms,"  which  he  calls  gem- 
mules,  and  that  these  latter,  scattered  throughout  the  body  by  the  currents 
of  blood  and  other  juices,  conjoin  as  required,  and  then  re-create  those 
"units"  from  which  they  are  derived.  The  sexual  products  thus  contain 
'  'gemmules"  from  all  parts  of  the  body,  and  these  are  combined  in  the  embryo, 
and  it  is  for  that  reason  that  all  the  latter's  parts  resemble  those  of  the  father 
or  mother,  according  to  whose  gemmules  have  constructed  the  part  of  the 
body  in  question.  Unused  gemmules  may  be  transmitted  to  the  next  genera- 
tion, with  the  result  that  some  individuals  resemble  their  father's  or  mother's 
parents.  In  the  same  way  the  bud  of  a  plant  is  formed  by  the  gemmules  of 
those  parts  that  are  evolved  out  of  it,  and  the  regeneration  of  the  severed 
foot  of  a  salamander  takes  place  through  the  extremity  gemmules  accumu- 
lating at  the  mutilated  end;  if,  as  sometimes  occurs,  a  malformation  takes 
place,  then  the  wrong  gemmules  have  come  into  operation.  This  theory  has 
been  shattered  by  modern  research  in  the  sphere  of  heredity  and  need  not 
therefore  be  discussed  any  further  in  this  place;  Darwin  himself,  it  is  true, 
considered  it  to  be  only  provisional,  but  he  holds  that  it  explains  the  prob- 
lems at  issue  better  than  any  other  theory  and  should  therefore  be  allowed 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  47:^ 

to  Stand.  This  is  characteristic  of  him;  the  more  a  theory  takes  it  upon  itself 
to  explain,  the  more  convincing  does  he  consider  it  to  be.^  But  exact  and 
critical  research  has  not  dealt  thus  with  the  theories;  it  has  set  up  theories 
according  as  special  research  has  required  them,  but  it  has  never  expanded 
them  beyond  the  bounds  of  absolute  necessity.  Darwin  is  here,  as  so  often 
elsewhere,  a  speculative  natural  philosopher,  not  a  natural  scientist. 

Darwin  on  the  descent  of  man 
This  speculative  characteristic  is  still  more  conspicuous  in  his  next  work, 
The  Descent  of  Man,  and  Selection  in  Relation  to  Sex,  which  was  published  three 
years  after  the  former  book,  but  which  was  likewise  written  after  many 
years  of  preparation.  In  The  Origin  of  Species  he  had  already  in  passing  ex- 
pressed the  opinion  that  natural  selection  would  without  doubt  eventually 
throw  light  also  on  the  origin  of  man  —  an  assertion  that  was  enough  to 
excite  very  great  attention.  The  subject  had  already  been  taken  up  by  others: 
by  Huxley  and,  above  all,  by  Haeckel,  and  it  was  thus  no  longer  a  matter 
of  real  urgency.  Darwin's  presentation  of  it,  however,  possesses  an  interest  of 
its  own.  His  arguments  that  man  has  through  natural  selection  by  means  of 
the  struggle  for  existence  been  evolved  from  a  series  of  animal  forms  are, 
of  course,  the  same  as  those  he  had  previously  developed  in  regard  to  the 
animals;  the  anatomical  and  embryological  argumentation  he  was  able  to 
borrow  from  his  above-mentioned  predecessors.  It  may  be  pointed  out, 
however,  that  he  does  not  insist  upon  man's  relationship  with  the  anthropoid 
apes,  as  Haeckel  has  done;  he  observes,  it  is  true,  physical  and  psychical 
agreements,  but  otherwise  maintains  for  the  most  part  man's  character  of  a 
mammal.  Of  greater  interest,  however,  is  his  derivation  of  the  human 
psychical  qualities;  he  analyses  a  number  of  such  qualities  of  different  kinds  — 
curiosity,  the  tendency  to  imitate,  memory,  imagination,  reflection  —  and 
he  finds  them  existing  also  in  the  animals.  He  even  notices  an  equivalent  to 
religious  feelings  in  the  dog's  awe  of  his  master.  On  the  whole,  he  falls  into 
the  same  error  as  innumerable  animal  psychologists  since  then,  of  letting 
qualities  that  man  has  through  training  inculcated  into  his  domestic  animals 
be  regarded  as  spontaneous  manifestations  of  the  intellect.  As  to  the  existence 
of  moral  qualities,  he  refers  to  the  characteristics  of  self-sacrifice  and  social 
sense  to  be  found  in  many  animal  forms  —  in  regard  to  the  ants  he  holds  in 
this  respect  the  same  exaggerated  ideas  as  many  of  his  contemporaries  — 

^  As  an  instance  of  how  boldly  Darwin  takes  up  the  most  difficult  problems  for  discussion, 
and  how  casually  he  afterwards  solves  them,  the  following  may  be  cited  (Variations,  I,  p.  8). 
He  maintains  that,  in  spite  of  natural  selection,  very  simple  life-forms  have  nevertheless  been 
preserved  through  the  ages  by  adapting  themselves  to  very  simple  conditions  of  life:  "for  what 
would  it  profit  an  Infusorial  animalcule  for  instance  or  an  intestinal  worm  to  become  highly 
organized?"  It  must  be  admitted  that,  if  the  problem  is  difficult  to  solve,  the  answer  certainly 
makes  it  none  the  easier. 


474  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

and  maintains  that  even  amongst  wild  tribes  only  social  virtues  are  respected. 
He  has  no  interest  in  individual  soul-life  —  a  lack  of  interest  which  he  like- 
wise shared  with  many  scientists  of  his  age  and  which  involves  him  in 
anthropomorphitic  interpretations  of  purely  instinctive  phenomena,  not  to 
mention  the  credulity  that  he  shows  towards  the  statements  of  other  owners 
of  domestic  animals  regarding  the  purely  human  intelligence  manifested  by 
their  four-legged  friends.  As  to  the  time  and  place  of  the  first  appearance  of 
the  human  race  he  expresses  himself  with  a  certain  amount  of  caution,  as  he 
does  also  in  regard  to  the  racial  problem. 

Sexual  selection 
By  far  the  greater  portion  of  the  work  under  discussion  deals,  however, 
with  another  question  —  namely,  the  origin  of  the  secondary  sexual  char- 
acters. To  these  Darwin  considers  that  the  theory  of  natural  selection 
in  the  ordinary  sense  cannot  be  applied;  he  does  not  believe  he  can  use  it 
to  explain  the  origin  of  such  features  as  the  horns  of  the  stag-beetle  and 
the  males  of  other  coleopters,  the  brilliant  coloration  of  male  butterflies, 
the  cock's-comb,  the  horns  of  the  stag,  and  other  similar  characteristics. 
He  considers  rather  that  these  features  have  arisen  as  a  result  of  special 
sexual  selection;  the  males  have  competed  for  the  favour  of  the  females, 
and  the  most  attractive  or  the  strongest  have  gone  off  victorious  and  been 
allowed  to  propagate  and  to  transmit  their  characteristics  by  inheritance 
to  their  offspring.  He  finds  proofs  of  this  in  the  playing  and  the  fighting 
that  takes  place  between  the  males  in  the  mating-season;  the  butterflies' 
sport  in  the  air,  the  combats  of  cocks  and  stags,  the  song  of  the  nightingale 
and  the  lark,  the  play  of  the  wood-grouse,  and  the  stately  mating-dance  of 
the  cock  of  the  rock.  But  it  is  not  only  the  male  qualities,  but  also  certain 
common  characteristics  that  he  attributes  to  this  kind  of  selection,  as  for 
instance  the  coloration  of  the  butterflies,  which  he  believes  to  have  arisen 
owing  to  the  females'  also  having  acquired  their  share  of  the  inheritance 
of  sexual  selection.  This  doctrine  of  sexual  selection  was  rejected  even  earlier 
than  the  general  theory  of  selection  and  is  nowadays  embraced  by  hardly  any 
true  scientists,  although  popular  literature  shows  traces  of  it.  What  really 
brought  about  its  rejection  is  the  increased  knowledge  of  internal  secretion 
and  the  connexion  of  the  secondary  sexual  characters  with  it;  both  sexual 
coloration  and  mating-play  have  their  explanation  in  this.  That  Darwin 
knew  nothing  of  this  cannot,  of  course,  be  laid  at  his  door,  but  even  apart 
from  this  fact,  the  sexual-selection  theory  certainly  gives  strong  evidence  of 
his  tendency  to  attribute  without  criticism  purely  human  ideas  to  the  ani- 
mal kingdom,  to  believe  in  "beauty  competitions"  among  butterflies  and 
beetles,  fishes  and  newts,  or  that  grasshoppers  and  crickets  have  a  musical 
ear.  It  has  also  been  pointed  out  that  it  is  purely  physical  strength  and  not 
beauty   at   all  that  makes  cocks  and  stags  successful  with  the  females, 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  475 

besides  which  it  may  often  happen  that  the  strongest  males  spur  or  butt  one 
another  to  death,  with  the  result  that  afterwards  comparatively  weak  speci- 
mens win  a  place  among  the  females.  In  support  of  his  theory  Darwin  placed 
the  male  intelligence  at  a  radically  higher  value  than  the  female.  He  over- 
looked the  fact  that  the  females  also  exercise  an  important  function,  which 
likewise  demands  intelligence,  in  the  care  and  protection  of  their  offspring. 
His  theories  on  this  subject  nevertheless  won  strong  support  in  certain  liter- 
ary quarters;  it  is  well  known  that,  among  others,  Strindberg  has  referred 
to  them  with  enthusiasm. 

In  connexion  with  the  last-mentioned  work  Darwin  published  another 
book,  entitled  Expression  of  the  Emotions  in  Man  and  Animals,  in  which  he 
records  a  large  number  of  facts  regarding  emotions  in  man  and  the  animals, 
which  he  had  amassed  and  compiled  and  to  which  he,  of  course,  applies 
his  theory  of  selection  and  descent.  Further,  in  his  later  years  he  published 
a  number  of  works  on  special  subjects  that  are  in  part  extremely  valuable. 
Among  these  may  be  mentioned  his  work  on  insectivorous  plants  —  it  was 
he  who  first  pointed  out  that  these  plants  really  digest  and  resorb  the  im- 
prisoned animals  —  another  on  the  climbing  organs  of  plants,  in  which  these 
organs  are  described  with  exhaustive  thoroughness  and  from  numerous  fresh 
points  of  view,  and  finally  a  work  on  cross-  and  self-fertilization  in  plants, 
as  also  a  book  of  fundamental  importance  wherein  he  continues  Sprengel's 
work,  which  he  had  rescued  from  oblivion,  and  paves  the  way  for  modern 
heredity-research.  In  the  year  before  his  death  he  also  published  a  brief  but 
ingenious  work  on  the  formation  of  vegetable  mould  through  the  action  of 
worms,  in  which  he  establishes,  on  the  strength  of  a  large  number  of  ob- 
servations and  experiments,  the  important  role  played  by  these  animals  as 
re-formers  of  the  earth's  surface,  in  that  a  considerable  portion  of  the  earth's 
outer  layers  passes  through  their  intestinal  canal  and  is  thereby  influenced 
physically  and  chemically  —  facts  which  research  had  previously  failed  to 
observe,  but  which  have  latterly  been  fully  confirmed. 

Darwin  s  general  opinion  of  life 
During  the  greater  part  of  his  life  Darwin  devoted  himself  to  his  own  par- 
ticular field  of  research  more  thoroughly  than  most  other  scientists.  He  never 
went  in  for  teaching  nor  took  up  any  other  public  appointment,  while  owing 
to  his  ill  health  he  had  to  give  up  social  life,  with  the  result  that  his  activi- 
ties became  more  and  more  confined  to  biological  speculations  and  experi- 
ments. This  may  explain  why  he  embraced  with  such  intensity,  but  also 
with  such  limitations,  the  theories  he  set  up.  He  was  but  little  influenced 
by  other  natural-scientific  tendencies,  eventually  losing  interest  even  in  gen- 
eral cultural  problems.  In  his  youth  he  had  been  interested  in  art,  poetry,  and 
music,  but  in  his  old  age  even  these  lost  their  attraction  for  him.  True,  by 
way  of  diversion  he  used  to  have  novels  read  to  him,  requiring  only  that 


476  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

they  should  have  a  happy  ending;  he  paid  but  little  attention  to  literary 
faults.  And  his  religious  interests  went  the  same  way  as  the  literary;  the 
Christian  faith  of  his  youth  had  undoubtedly  been  traditional  from  the  very 
beginning,  without  any  feelings  of  personal  experience;  his  faith  died  grad- 
ually and  without  any  crisis,  leaving  behind  a  peaceful  and  untroubled  res- 
ignation in  face  of  the  ultimate  problems  of  existence,  a  resignation  which 
was  never  disturbed  by  anything  except  the  innumerable  senseless  and  irra- 
tional inquiries  he  received  on  the  subject  and  to  which  he  invariably  replied 
conscientiously.  It  is  worth  quoting  the  following  out  of  one  of  these  re- 
plies as  a  final  touch  to  the  description  of  his  character:  "The  safest  con- 
clusion seems  to  me  that  the  whole  subject  is  beyond  the  scope  of  man's 
intellect;  but  man  can  do  his  duty." 

Judgments  on  Darwin 
Very  different  judgments  have  been  passed  on  Darwin.  Even  on  his  first 
appearance  he  was  either  extolled  as  one  of  the  greatest  geniuses  in  the 
world  or  abused  as  an  ignorant  and  unreliable  dilettante,  according  to  the 
different  points  of  view.  Nor  have  subsequent  generations  been  any  more 
unanimous;  especially  since  the  theory  of  selection  has  been  condemned  — 
at  least  in  its  original  form  —  hard  words  have  not  been  spared  against  its 
creator  —  as  a  matter  of  fact,  a  natural  reaction  against  the  adoration  meted 
out  to  him  towards  the  close  of  his  life,  which  received  confirmation  in  his 
being  buried  beside  the  grave  of  Newton.  Was  this  apotheosis  justified  or 
not?  This  question  has  been  answered  and  can  still  be  answered  either  way. 
To  raise  the  theory  of  selection,  as  has  often  been  done,  to  the  rank  of  a 
"natural  law"  comparable  in  value  with  the  law  of  gravity  established  by 
Newton  is,  of  course,  quite  irrational,  as  time  has  already  shown;  Darwin's 
theory  of  the  origin  of  species  was  long  ago  abandoned.  Other  facts  estab- 
lished by  Darwin  are  all  of  second-rate  value.  But  if  we  measure  him  by  his 
influence  on  the  general  cultural  development  of  humanity,  then  the  prox- 
imity of  his  grave  to  Newton's  is  fully  justified.  It  is  certain  that  since  the 
days  of  the  latter  no  scientist  has  so  deeply  influenced  man's  general  concep- 
tion of  life  as  Darwin  has  done;  it  is  his  theory  of  evolution  that  has  taken 
the  place  of  the  idealistic  theory  of  romanticism  and  made  the  common  de- 
scent the  connecting  link  in  existence  instead  of  ideas  and  archetypes.  In 
all  spheres  of  knowledge  the  development  from  earlier  to  later  stages  has 
been  the  one  clue  for  research;  history,  which  had  previously  sought  for 
"guiding  ideas,"  is  now  an  evolutionary  science,  just  as  is  philology,  and 
even  philosophy  has  at  least  one  school  that  has  followed  the  same  prin- 
ciple. Everyone  knows  the  important  role  played  by  the  idea  of  evolution 
in  naturalistic  literature.  The  influence  of  Darwinism  on  biology  will  be 
described  in  the  next  chapter.  Of  its  weaknesses  a  certain  number  have  al- 
ready been  referred  to  above;  it  shared  with  all  new  ideas  the  illusion  that 
it  could  do  too  much;  this  was  so  with  Darwin  himself,  modest  though  he 
personally  was,  and  still  more  so  with  his  admiring  successors.  We  shall 
now  proceed  to  describe  the  differences  of  opinion  caused  by  the  new  doctrine. 


CHAPTER    XII 


FOR     AND     AGAINST     DARWIN 


M 


Why  Dartvin  s  theory  prevailed 
'oDERN  CRITICS  have  often  asked  themselves  how  it  is  that  a  hypothe- 
sis like  Darwin's,  based  on  such  weak  foundations,  could  all  at 
once  win  over  to  its  side  the  greater  part  of  contemporary  scien- 
tific opinion.  If  the  defenders  of  the  theory  refer  with  this  end  in  view  to 
its  intrinsic  value,  it  may  be  answered  that  the  theory  has  long  ago  been 
rejected  in  its  most  vital  points  by  subsequent  research.  It  has  also  been 
pointed  out,  for  instance  by  Radl,  that  the  objections  made  against  the  the- 
ory on  its  first  appearance  very  largely  agree  with  those  which  far  later 
brought  about  its  fail.  The  factors  governing  the  victory  of  Darwinism  thus 
represent  a  problem  of  the  greatest  importance,  not  only  in  the  history  of 
biology,  but  also  in  that  of  culture  in  general  —  a  problem  that  would  re- 
quire far  more  exhaustive  treatment  than  can  be  given  to  it  here.  In  this 
work  we  can  only  endeavour  to  throw  light  on  some  of  the  circumstances 
that  appear  to  be  specially  remarkable  surrounding  this  important  episode, 
the  history  of  which  it  will  largely  be  the  duty  of  future  generations  to 
write. 

Darwinism  and  liberalism 
Darwin's  origin  of  species  contains  many  points  that  were  likely  both  to 
win  the  applause  of  and  to  give  ofTence  to  his  contemporaries.  A  factor  that 
without  doubt  very  largely  contributed  to  both  the  one  and  the  other  was 
the  book's  relation  to  the  political  movement  of  the  time,  to  which  refer- 
ence has  already  been  made.  From  the  beginning  Darwin's  theory  was  an 
obvious  ally  to  liberalism;  it  was  at  once  a  means  of  elevating  the  doctrine 
of  free  competition,  which  had  been  one  of  the  most  vital  corner-stones  of 
the  movement  of  progress,  to  the  rank  of  a  natural  law,  and  similarly  the 
leading  principle  of  liberalism,  progress,  was  confirmed  by  the  new  theory  — 
the  deeper  down  the  origin  of  human  culture  was  placed,  the  higher  were 
the  hopes  that  could  be  entertained  for  its  future  possibilities.  It  was  no 
wonder,  then,  that  the  liberal-minded  were  enthusiastic;  Darwinism  must 
be  true,  nothing  else  was  possible.  But  beside  this  there  was  a  good  deal 
more  in  it  that  could  attract  radical  cultured  views,  chiefly  its  strongly 
worded  polemic  against  the  doctrine  of  creation,  which  could  be  employed 
to  counteract  theological  obscurantism,  and  also  the  very  idea  of  a  material 

477 


478  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

connexion  in  existence,  a  principle  that  could  be  set  up  in  opposition  to 
the  theories  of  ideas  held  by  reactionary  romanticism.  The  deficiencies  in 
Darwin's  work  were  therefore  readily  overlooked  —  his  vague  starting- 
point,  his  uncritical  material,  his  weak  arguments  based  on  loose  assump- 
tions, his  belief  in  the  power  of  chance  and  of  finality  as  an  explanation  of 
nature.  As  a  matter  of  fact,  the  natural  explanations  of  the  preceding  ages 
failed  still  more  in  that  respect;  they  were  generally  based  on  the  wisdom 
of  the  Creator  and  the  benefit  of  man  as  the  cause  of  all  that  exists  and  takes 
place  —  that  is  to  say,  an  explanation  without  the  slightest  trace  of  scien- 
tific treatment.  Darwin's  theory,  then,  was  at  any  rate  an  immense  advance; 
its  weaknesses  could  be  overcome  by  continued  research,  its  vagueness  and 
casualness  removed  by  fresh  discoveries  and  replaced  by  firmly  established 
facts,  while  the  finality  in  nature  could  thus  be  made  synonymous  with 
natural  law.  Briefly,  no  one  was  prepared  to  doubt  the  possibilities  of  the 
theory's  future  development,  and  for  the  moment  it  entailed  a  freedom  from 
the  pressure  of  prejudice  which  there  had  previously  seemed  to  be  no  means 
of  avoiding. 

Defiance  of  the  conservatives 
While,  then,  liberal  tendencies  felt  themselves  closely  bound  up  in  Dar- 
winism, the  new  movement  was  for  that  very  reason  all  the  more  repugnant 
to  the  conservative  social  elements.  Those  who  looked  for  their  ideal  in 
the  past  and  in  tradition  must  have  been  appalled  to  see  the  good  old  times 
depicted  as  a  kind  of  half-way  station  along  the  road  from  the  ape  stage; 
and  that  free  competition  which  to  their  mind  only  led  to  all  manner  of  li- 
cence, was  that  to  be  the  true  creator  of  the  life  that  is  lived  today,  instead 
of  the  divine  reason  which  has  governed  the  world  and  preserved  law  and 
justice?  And,  again,  this  vague,  indeterminate  idea  of  evolution,  was  it  to 
be  substituted  for  those  firmly  established  and  eternal  ideas  that  governed 
the  creation  of  nature  and  its  forms?  Thus  reasoned  many,  and  Darwin's 
theory  was  therefore  challenged  from  pulpit  and  professorial  chair,  at  sci- 
entific gatherings,  in  journals  and  newspapers.  This  first  polemic  against 
Darwinism  has  its  own  peculiar  interest;  it  is  dazed  and  not  particularly 
keen-sighted,  it  clings  despairingly  to  the  old  ideas  and  as  yet  lacks  orienta- 
tion as  to  the  exact  position  adopted  by  its  opponents.  In  the  present  history 
it  is  only  possible  to  give  attention  to  some  few  of  the  more  representative 
scientific  contributions,  whereas  the  miscellaneous  mass  of  protests  from 
other  quarters  can  have  no  place  here. 

Owen  s  opposition 
The  highest  scientific  reputation  among  the  opponents  of  Darwin  was  un- 
doubtedly that  of  Richard  Owen.  It  was,  of  course,  impossible  for  the  lat- 
ter's  idealistic  morphology  to  be  reconciled  with  the  Darwinian  doctrines 
of  descent,  and  if  anyone  was  to  discover  and  demonstrate  the  weaknesses 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  479 

underlying  the  new  theory,  it  was  he.  Tlie  fact,  however,  that  his  influence 
was  not  so  great  as  his  scientific  reputation  might  have  warranted  was  mostly 
due  to  the  way  in  which  he  conducted  himself;  instead  of  openly  defending 
his  views  he  wrote  anonymously,  repeatedly  referring  to  "Professor  Owen" 
as  his  authority  in  opposition  to  Darwin.  This  gave  his  contribution  a  tinge 
of  lampoonery  that  detracted  from  the  effect  it  might  otherwise  have  had. 
The  article  (it  appeared  in  the  Edinburgh  Kevieiv  of  i860),  which  much  em- 
bittered Darwin,  is  chiefly  interesting  as  being  an  expression  for  the  sharp 
contrast  between  the  romantic  natural  philosophy  and  the  realistic  evolu- 
tional theory.  Owen  points  out  with  strong  emphasis  how  few  are  the  facts 
and  how  weak  the  proofs  that  form  the  basis  for  the  new  theory,  how  the 
problem  of  species-formation  must  still  be  considered  unsolved  in  spite  of 
the  theory  of  selection,  how  it  was  possible  to  assume  other  factors  govern- 
ing species-formation  besides  variation  and  natural  selection.  As  such  fac- 
tors he  suggests  parthenogenesis  and  alternation  of  generations;  he  believes 
it  possible  to  suppose  that  the  various  stages  in  such  a  cycle  —  polypus  and 
medusa,  or  sporocyst,  redia,  cercaria  —  might,  so  to  speak,  liberate  them- 
selves from  the  series  and  begin  to  give  rise  to  forms  similar  to  them- 
selves, with  the  result  that  the  whole  cycle  would  disintegrate  into  a  number 
of  widely  differing  life-forms.  He  even  adopts  Pouchet's  spontaneous-gener- 
ation experiments  in  his  support  against  Darwin:  if  the  Infusoria  spontan- 
eously generate  daily,  how  can  it  be  assumed  that  all  higher  beings  could 
have  been  evolved  in  one  single  series  originating  in  primitive  forms?  Owen's 
suggestions  in  regard  to  species-formation  are  certainly  not  very  happily  con- 
ceived from  a  modern  point  of  view,  and  indeed  they  are  only  presented  as 
experiments  with  ideas  in  order  to  prove  how  complicated  and  difficult  of 
solution  the  problem  of  species-formation  really  is,  but  the  worst  of  it  is 
that  Owen  brings  into  the  field  the  whole  of  the  thought-systems  of  the  old 
idealistic  natural  philosophy;  as  a  factor  that  actively  operates  in  the  crea- 
tion of  the  symmetrical  forms  of  the  higher  animals  he  adduces  a  "polar- 
izing force,"  the  true  essence  of  which  need  not  be  analysed  here,  as  the 
name  itself  explains  it.  Even  the  old  doctrine  of  "  the  ideal  type"  is  brought 
forward  for  the  same  purpose.  But  one  who  has  recourse  to  such  empty 
phrases  to  explain  the  origin  of  life-forms  has  no  right  to  accuse  Darwinism 
of  weak  argumentation  and  of  making  false  hypotheses.  A  controversy  such 
as  this  best  shows  what  an  immense  advance  Darwinism  nevertheless  in- 
volved at  the  time,  and  at  the  same  time  explains  why  it  is  that  even  the 
authorized  objections  of  the  old  school  must  die  away  unheard. 

One  gets  the  same  impression  from  the  criticism  of  Darwinism  offered 
by  Agassiz,  another  important  representative  of  the  old  biological  school. 
Jean  Louis  Rodolphe  Agassiz  was  born  in  1807  at  Motier  in  Switzerland,  of 
French  parents,  and  even  during  his  school-time  devoted  himself  to  natural 


480  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

science.  He  studied  at  several  German  universities,  his  teachers  including 
both  Schelling  and  Oken,  but  principally  Dollinger,  mentioned  above  as 
von  Baer's  master;  he  became  doctor  of  medicine  and  afterwards  spent  a 
couple  of  years  in  Paris  in  lively  discussion  with  both  Cuvier  and  Humboldt. 
His  chief  object  of  study  was  the  fishes,  both  recent  and  fossil;  a  large  work 
that  he  had  commenced  on  the  fishes  of  Europe  was  never  finished,  while 
another  on  fossil  fishes  proved  a  pioneering  work  in  its  own  sphere.  But 
besides  this,  glacial  research  proved  of  special  interest  to  this  many-sided 
scientist,  and  in  this  field  too  he  was  a  pioneer.  He  proved  that  the  glaciers 
had  in  earlier  times  been  far  more  extensive  in  his  native  country  than  they 
are  now,  and  during  a  journey  to  Scotland  he  found  that  large  glaciers  had  ex- 
isted there  too  in  past  ages.  From  this  he  drew  conclusions  regarding  the 
general  glacialization  of  Europe,  which  afterwards  led  to  that  highly  de- 
veloped research-work  on  the  glacial  period  which  has  been  especially  note- 
worthy in  Scandinavia.  During  the  years  1831-46  Agassiz  was  a  professor 
at  Neuchatel;  he  then  moved  to  America  and  became  professor  at  Harvard 
University.  There  he  did  splendid  work  as  both  a  zoologist  and  a  geologist, 
making  extensive  journeys  and  producing  works  on  the  animal  world  and 
the  zoology  of  America,  as  well  as  on  theoretical  problems.  He  died  in  1873. 
In  his  theoretical  writings  Agassiz  shows  himself  a  true  romantic  natu- 
ral philosopher,  as  might  be  expected  from  the  education  he  received.  The 
problem  of  species  engaged  him  a  great  deal  and  is  solved  by  him  in  a  mark- 
edly idealistic  direction.  In  such  circumstances  it  was  obvious  that  he  could 
not  hail  the  advent  of  Darwinism  with  any  great  enthusiasm.  In  his  polemics 
against  it  he  makes  a  great  point  of  its  weaknesses;  lack  of  observation  of 
the  real  transition  from  one  species  to  another,  lack  of  obedience  to  law  in 
its  theory  of  natural  selection,  the  weak  conclusions  drawn  from  similarity 
in  the  embryonic  stage  to  similarity  of  origin.  But  the  most  serious  mistake 
to  his  mind  is  that  the  new  theory  fails  to  realize  the  creative  idea  running 
through  all  animate  nature.  The  individuals  perish,  but  hand  over  to  their 
posterity,  generation  by  generation,  all  that  is  typical,  with  the  exclusion  of 
what  is  merely  individual;  therefore,  while  the  individuals  have  only  a  mate- 
rial existence,  species,  genera,  families,  and  so  on  upwards  exist  as  the 
thought-categories  of  the  Supreme  Intelligence,  and  as  such  possess  a  truly 
independent  and  immutable  existence.^  Here,  it  will  be  seen,  speaks  the  pure 
romantic  idealism,  whose  supporters,  thanks  to  their  intensive  professional 
insight,  have  no  difficulty  in  discovering  the  weaknesses  underlying  the  new 
biological    theory,    though    only    to    maintain    in    its    stead    their    own 

^  In  his  "Essay  on  Classification"  Agassiz,  speaking  of  rudimentary  organs,  maintains 
that  these  exist  not  for  any  purpose  of  function,  but  to  complete  the  design,  just  as  in  a  building 
certain  details  are  introduced  for  the  sake  of  symmetry,  without  any  idea  of  their  serving  a 
practical  purpose. 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  481 

Speculation,  equally  unworkable  in  form  as  in  contents  and  therefore  in- 
evitably doomed  to  failure. 

It  would  hardly  be  worth  while  to  carry  this  account  of  the  attacks 
against  Darwin  any  further.  We  might  still  mention  the  contribution  of 
S.  WiLBERFORCE,  Bishop  of  Oxfotd,  owing  to  the  sensation  it  created  at  the 
time.  Having  himself  studied  natural  science,  and  with  the  indefatigable 
Owen  as  prompter,  he  reviews  the  weaknesses  of  Darwinism  in  an  easy  and 
fluent  style,  though  somewhat  superficially,  but  at  the  end  of  his  treatise 
he  spoils  his  case  completely  by  sermonizing  on  the  subject  of  the  origin 
of  man,  bringing  forward  all  the  persons  of  the  Trinity  as  arguments  to 
prove  a  special  creation  in  the  image  of  God.  From  such  opponents  Darwin 
clearly  had  nothing  to  fear.  But  even  scientists  with  a  truly  modern  concep- 
tion adopted  from  the  outset  an  attitude  of  criticism  towards  this  theory  — 
KoLLiKER,  for  instance.  In  a  brief  examination,  substantiated  by  numerous 
facts,  Kolliker  submits  in  a  concise  and  determined  style  his  objections  to 
the  theory  of  selection,  at  the  same  time  acknowledging  the  great  service 
of  Darwin  in  having  sought  to  base  the  knowledge  of  the  origin  of  organ- 
isms upon  experiments  and  in  having  made  descent  the  foundation  thereof, 
so  that  the  life-forms  might  be  regarded  as  a  series  of  evolutionary  phenom- 
ena. He  expressly  declares  that  the  earlier  attempts  of  natural  philosophy  to 
construct  a  history  of  evolution  are  weak  in  comparison  with  Darwin's, 
and,  moreover,  he  appreciates  the  far-reaching  insight  and  the  splendid  con- 
scientiousness on  which  his  theory  is  founded.  As  its  weak  points  he  men- 
tions first  of  all  its  teleological  conception;  the  principle  of  finality  as  applied 
to  life -forms,  which  has  already  been  pointed  out  above;  further,  the  ab- 
sence of  transition  forms  between  the  species,  both  extant  and  fossil,  the 
lack  of  proof  that  characterizes  'the  entire  hypothesis  of  selection,  and 
finally  the  circumstance  that  nothing  is  known  of  unfertile  variety-hybrids, 
which  would  nevertheless  be  bound  to  appear  somewhere  if  the  varieties 
were  transitions  to  species.  Moreover,  Kolliker  holds  that  it  is  possible  to 
imagine  other  ways  of  evolution  than  Darwin's.  He  considers  that  the  idea 
that  all  species  have  been  created  as  they  are  is  not  worth  discussing,  but 
it  is  conceivable  either  that  all  organisms  have  arisen  each  out  of  its  own 
primary  form,  or  that  the  species  have  come  into  existence  through  one  pri- 
mary form  or  through  a  few.  The  latter  alternative  he  considers  to  be  more 
probable,  but  then  there  must  be  a  common  law  governing  formation,  ac- 
cording to  which  forms  of  one  kind  may  in  certain  circumstances  give  rise 
to  entirely  different  forms,  either  by  a  larval  form's  adopting  an  independ- 
ent course  of  development,  or  by  an  egg  or  embryo  of  a  lower  form's  giving 
rise  to  a  higher  type  of  life.  This  creation  theory  of  Kolliker's  is  merely  a 
concept  and  is,  moreover,  based  on  hypotheses  that  have  never  been  con- 
firmed. Of  real  value,  on  the  other  hand,  is  his  criticism  of  Darwm's  theory 


48x  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

which  is  founded  on  a  truly  exact,  and  not  on   a  natural-philosophical, 
basis. 

Huxley  versus  Kolliker 
This  criticism  of  Kolliker's  was  opposed  by  Huxley,  who  vehemently  de- 
nies that  there  is  any  teleological  explanation  at  all  in  Darwin,  whose  en- 
tire theory  is  based  rather  on  the  absence  of  any  creative  purpose  in  nature. 
And  in  proof  of  his  view  Huxley  cites  exactly  the  same  quotation  out  of 
the  Origin  of  Species  as  Kolliker  does  for  his  own  argument.  From  this  it  is 
obvious  that  the  two  antagonists  must  be  standing  in  some  essential  respect 
on  different  ground,  and  the  question  is  of  such  great  general  interest  that 
it  deserves  closer  examination.  Strictly  speaking,  Huxley  is  right,  in  so  far 
as  no  creative  design  in  the  romantic  natural-philosophical  sense  is  ever  re- 
ferred to  by  Darwin;  but  this  does  not  prevent  his  constant  assertion  as  to 
the  adaptability  of  life-forms  and  organs  to  certain  given  conditions  from 
implying  a  teleological  explanation  of  phenomena;  not  only  the  entire  the- 
ory of  sexual  selection,  but  also  most  of  the  doctrine  of  natural  selection 
actually  rests  on  this  assumption.  The  contrast  between  the  romantic  and 
the  Darwinian  teleology  is  best  explained  by  an  example.  It  is  asked:  Why 
has  a  cat  claws?  For  the  sake  of  the  creative  design,  say  the  romanticists, 
and  in  order  to  serve  the  purposes  of  the  cosmic  order.  For  its  own  sake, 
says  Darwin,  and  in  order  to  enable  it  to  survive  in  the  struggle  for  exist- 
ence. But  it  is  really  the  question  itself  that  is  absurd  —  as  absurd  as  the 
question:  Why  does  a  stone  fall?  or  Why  does  the  earth  revolve  round  the 
sun?  Biology  can  only  endeavour  to  find  out  the  conditions  under  which 
cat's  claws  are  developed  and  used,  but  never  anything  more;  those  who 
question  beyond  that  fail  to  fulfil  Bacon's  requirement  that  we  should  "ask 
nature  fair  questions."  But  Darwin  and  his  contemporaries  are  constantly 
putting  such  wrong  questions  to  nature.  This  is,  of  course,  due  to  the  fact 
that  they  were  unable  to  free  themselves  entirely  from  the  influence  of  ro- 
mantic philosophy,  which,  indeed,  they  desired  to  abandon  and  the  weak- 
nesses of  which  they  fully  realized,  but  its  grasp  of  the  problem  of  life  was 
really  too  firm  for  them  to  loosen.  Natural  philosophy  had,  indeed,  found 
in  its  plan  of  creation  an  explanation  for  everything,  and  to  resign  in  face 
of  the  causes  of  the  phenomena  of  life  would  have  meant,  to  the  new  direc- 
tion in  which  biology  was  moving,  almost  the  same  thing  as  a  declaration 
of  bankruptcy  in  face  of  its  opponents.  And  in  contrast  to  the  idealistic  plan 
of  creation  Darwin's  teleology  involves  possibilities  of  development,  in  so 
far  as  a  number  of  the  so-called  purposeful  adaptations  have  since,  mainly 
through  modern  researches  into  the  problem  of  heredity,  found  its  law-bound 
explanation,  while  other  phenomena  have  had  to  accept  that  resignation  in 
face  of  the  inexplicable,  which  is  the  hall-mark  of  exact  and  critical  science. 
Darwin's  theory  of  adaptation,  which  is  now  so  often  condemned  for  its 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  483 

credulity,  has  thus  in  reality  formed  a  necessary  transitional  stage,  which 
has  freed  biology  from  the  illusions  of  the  past  and  made  a  more  exact  re- 
search possible  in  the  future. 

Among  Darwin's  other  opponents  in  Germany  may  be  mentioned  Al- 
bert WiGAND  (i8ii-86),  professor  of  botany  at  Marburg,  a  pupil  of  Schlei- 
den,  and  well  known  as  a  capable  plant-anatomist  and  plant-physiologist, 
as  well  as  a  leading  expert  on  cryptogams.  He  was,  moreover,  deeply  re- 
ligious and  on  that  account  was  unable  to  accept  the  theory  of  spontaneous 
generation.  It  was  therefore  inevitable  that  Darwinism  should  have  been 
odious  to  him  from  the  start,  and  he  wrote  many  treatises  against  it.  Even- 
tually, after  ten  years  of  preliminary  work,  he  summarized  his  views  in  a 
work  comprising  nearly  thirteen  hundred  pages,  entitled  Beitrdge  :^ur  Metho- 
dik  der  Naturforschung.  He  here  shows  himself  to  be  a  keen-sighted  student 
of  nature  and  a  keen  critic  of  the  old  exact  school.  Cuvier  is  his  ideal  as  a 
scientist  and  he  definitely  associates  himself  with  him  in  his  opposition  to 
Geoffrey's  efforts  to  attain  natural-philosophical  unity.  He  has  a  keen  eye 
for  the  weaknesses  of  Darwinism  and  analyses  them  objectively  and  in  de- 
tail; he  especially  brings  out  the  weaknesses  underlying  the  theory  of  se- 
lection, and  in  contrast  to  the  lack  of  design  in  the  phenomena  of  variation 
and  selection,  as  presented  by  Darwin,  he  maintains  the  existence  of  a  defi- 
nite course  and  plan  in  evolution  —  a  plan  that  excludes  both  chance  and 
explanations  of  finality.  This  criticism  is,  indeed,  on  the  whole  justified, 
and  even  Wigand's  assertion  that  Darwinism  is  natural  philosophy  rather 
than  exact  research  is  quite  a  fair  judgment;  but  when  it  comes  to  trying 
to  justify  the  idea  of  conformity  to  law  urged  in  opposition  to  the  doctrine 
of  chance,  the  former  is  ascribed  to  a  personal  deity,  for  natural  science  can- 
not get  away  from  an  ultimate  cause  of  existence.  This,  of  course,  should 
not  be  used  as  grounds  for  a  natural-scientific  explanation,  but  the  doctrine 
of  the  creation  and  the  theory  of  the  immutability  of  the  species,  which 
Wigand  would  urge  in  opposition  to  Darwinism,  are  nevertheless  based 
upon  it.  In  doing  so,  however,  he  has  vitiated  the  effects  of  his  criticism; 
his  ideas  were  capable  of  satisfying  neither  the  natural  philosophers  of  the 
old  school  nor  the  exact  scientists,  and  he  himself  lived  just  long 
enough  to  see  Darwinism  reach  the  height  of  its  influence  upon  human 
culture. 

Even  the  aged  von  Baer  entered  the  lists  against  Darwinism,  complain- 
ing of  its  lack  of  conformity  to  natural  law;  he  sees  in  evolution  a  striving 
after  a  definite  goal  —  "  Zielstrebigkeit,''  as  he  calls  it  —  and  this,  indeed, 
explains  the  finality  in  existence,  but  presupposes  in  its  turn  a  common 
scheme  for  all  natural  phenomena,  which  is  only  conceivable  with  a  per- 
sonal creator  as  the  primary  cause.  The  high  respect  in  which  this  octoge- 
narian student  of  evolution  was  held,  exempted  him  from  harsh  criticism 


484  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

at  the  hands  of  the  younger  generation;  his  contribution  was  added  to  the 
records  in  silence. 

Darwinism  was  least  appreciated  in  France,  where  Cuvier's  pupils  held 
sway  in  the  realm  of  zoology  and  where  even  representatives  of  experimen- 
tal research  —  Bernard  and  others  —  had  little  sympathy  for  the  specula- 
tive and  hypothetical  elements  in  the  new  theory.  It  is  striking  that  Darwin 
was  not  elected  to  the  French  Academy  of  Science  until  after  he  had  pub- 
lished his  works  on  plant-physiology,  and  then  under  reference  only  to  them 
and  not  to  the  descent  theory.  And  when  this  theory  —  or  "  trans fortnisme,' ' 
as  it  was  called  in  French  —  eventually  found  acceptance  in  the  country  of 
Lamarck,  it  was  with  him  rather  than  with  Darwin  that  the  followers  of 
the  new  tendency  associated  themselves.  Of  the  earlier  critics  of  Darwinism 
in  France  the  first  name  is  that  of  Jean  Louis  Armand  de  Quatrefages  de 
Breau  (i8io-9x),  first  a  physician  and  finally  professor  of  anthropology  at 
Paris,  and  famous  as  a  leading  specialist  on  marine  fauna,  particularly  the 
Annelida,  but  foremost  as  an  anthropologist.  As  this  last  he  carried  out 
valuable  investigations  into  special  subjects,  all,  however,  governed  by  a 
firm  conviction  as  to  the  unity  of  the  human  race  and  its  independence  of 
other  life -forms.  He  wrote  a  number  of  treatises  against  Darwinism,  the 
chief  of  which  was  one  entitled  Charles  Darwin  et  ses  prkurseurs  fran^ais,  in 
which  he  begins  by  describing  several  transformistic  authors  of  French  na- 
tionality: de  Maillet,  Buffon,  Lamarck,  and  others.  In  regard  to  Darwin, 
Quatrefages  admits  that  there  is  a  struggle  for  existence,  but  does  not  be- 
lieve in  its  power  to  create  new  life-forms.  He  sharply  criticizes  Darwin's 
habit  of  adducing  the  probable  and  the  possible  —  purely  personal  convic- 
tion instead  of  facts  proved  on  conclusive  evidence  —  and  he  particularly 
points  out  that,  when  it  comes  to  the  question  of  the  life-phenomena  of 
past  ages,  Darwin  constantly  appeals  to  "the  unknown."  And  Quatrefages 
concludes  his  critical  examination  with  the  words:  "Let  us  not  dream  of 
what  may  be;  let  us  instead  assume  and  seek  what  is!"  Among  the  earlier 
critics  of  Darwinism  Quatrefages  is  worthy  of  respect  on  account  of  the  con- 
siderate and  objective  manner  in  which  he  passed  judgment  on  the  theory. 
Eventually,  however,  the  descent  theory  gained  ground  even  in  France, 
chiefly,  as  mentioned  above,  in  the  Lamarckian  form,  which  at  the  same  time 
became  known  in  other  countries  also,  and  which  will  be  described  later  on. 

Vast  quantites  of  polemical  writings  against  Darwin  and  his  theory 
appeared  during  the  period  immediately  after  he  first  attracted  public  at- 
tention; most  of  these  were  of  practically  no  scientific  value,  since  they  were 
based  on  religious  arguments,  which  were  the  most  usual,  or  else  on  quasi- 
scientific  or  other  grounds.  Of  the  really  objective  contributions  to  the  sub- 
ject it  would  be  possible  to  name  many  others  besides  those  referred  to  above, 
but  space  forbids  a  more  detailed  review  of  them.  At  the  same  time  there 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  485 

came  forward  in  defence  of  Darwinism  many  distinguished  scientists,  who 
made  weighty  contributions  to  the  discussion  and  assisted  in  the  rapid  ad- 
vance along  the  new  lines  laid  down  by  Darwin.  Even  of  these  it  is  possible 
only  to  name  a  few;  in  the  present  chapter  reference  will  be  made  to  the 
English  contributions  in  favour  of  Darwin,  while  one  or  two  separate  chap- 
ters will  be  devoted  to  the  development  of  Darwinism  in  Germany,  where 
it  acquired  an  essentially  novel  character. 

Darwin's  supporters 
Among  the  first  to  associate  themselves  with  Darwin  was  the  aged  Lyell. 
In  a  work  entitled  Geological  Evidence  ofi  the  Antiquity  of  Man,  published  in 
1863,  he  takes  up  the  question  of  the  origin  of  species  by  means  of  varia- 
tion. He  refers  briefly  to  Darwin's  theory  and  in  support  thereof  cites  a  num- 
ber of  facts,  especially  geological  and  palieontological;  of  these  he  bases 
his  argument  mainly  on  the  extinct  proboscideans  of  the  Tertiary  period, 
while  he  further  adduces  a  number  of  fossil  insects,  as  well  as  the  saurian 
bird  Archasopteryx.  In  regard  to  man,  whose  primitive  history  had  been 
the  real  subject  of  the  book,  sympathetic  reference  is  made  to  the  statements 
of,  inter  alia,  Huxley,  as  to  man's  anatomical  agreement  with  the  higher 
apes;  similarly,  mention  is  made  of  Darwin's  theory  of  the  origin  of  the 
intelligence  by  means  of  natural  selection,  and  the  work  concludes  with  a 
refutation  of  the  accusation  that  Darwinism  would  lead  to  materialism. 
Darwin  himself  highly  appreciated  the  support  thus  given  him  by  Lyell, 
and  the  influence  of  the  aged  geologist  certainly  contributed  much  towards 
bringing  the  new  doctrine  to  victory. 

Among  those  who,  besides  Darwin,  should  be  named  as  supporters  of 
the  theory  of  selection,  the  first  place  is  due  to  Alfred  Russell  Wallace. 
Born  in  1813,  he  was  originally  an  engineer  and  afterwards  a  schoolmaster, 
and  he  was  besides  interested  in  collecting  plants  and  insects.  In  1848,  in 
company  with  his  friend  Henry  Walter  Bates  (i82.5-9z),  he  made  a  voy- 
age to  Brazil  for  the  purpose  of  exploration  and  the  collection  of  scientific 
material.  After  a  year  the  two  friends  parted;  Bates  remained  in  Brazil, 
while  Wallace  returned  home  and  shortly  afterwards  made  a  journey  to  the 
East  Indian  archipelago,  where  he  remained  for  a  number  of  years,  continu- 
ing his  comparative  biological  studies  on  the  various  islands.  Upon  his  re- 
turn home  he  found  himself  already  a  famous  man  and  continued  his  bio- 
logical research-work,  partly  on  voyages  and  partly  in  his  own  country. 
He  never  received  any  permanent  appointment,  but  had  to  earn  a  living  as 
a  writer  and  lecturer.  In  his  old  age  he  was  assured  a  means  of  subsistence 
through  a  government  pension.  He  died  in  191 3,  over  ninety  years  old. 

Wallace' s  discoveries  in  animal  geography 
The  result  of  Wallace's  Indian  journey  proved  to  be  of  the  greatest  impor- 
tance; he  thereby  became  one  of  the  pioneers  of  modern  animal-geography. 


486  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

He  established  the  fact  that  the  western  half  of  the  archipelago  possesses 
an  essentially  Indian  animal  world,  whereas  the  eastern  half  has  an  equally- 
marked  Australian  fauna;  the  border-line  he  found  to  lie  in  the  narrow  but 
deep  sound  between  the  islands  Bali  and  Lombok,  and  northwards  from  there 
in  the  Macassar  Strait  between  Borneo  and  the  Celebes.  He  afterwards  com- 
piled, with  the  aid  of  the  results  gained  during  this  and  subsequent  voyages, 
an  animal  geographical  system,  in  which  the  globe  was  divided  into  sep- 
arate regions  based  on  the  distribution  of  animal  forms  both  in  recent  times 
and  in  preceding  periods.  This  animal  geographical  system,  which  is  univer- 
sally known  from  the  text-books  on  zoology,  is  a  contribution  of  lasting 
value  to  the  development  of  biology. 

But  in  the  course  of  his  studies  of  the  distribution  of  animal  life  in  the 
East  Indian  islands  Wallace  found  himself  faced  with  the  same  problems  as 
Darwin  in  the  Galapagos  Islands;  the  various  islands  and  island-groups  pos- 
sess their  peculiar  animal  species.  The  distribution  of  species  on  the  earth  is 
thus  governed  by  geological  conditions,  and  if  we  consider  the  animal  life 
of  earlier  periods  we  find  that,  instead  of  the  new  extant  forms,  there  were 
other  similar  forms  —  in  fact,  that,  as  he  says,  every  species  has  been  pre- 
ceded in  time  and  space  by  a  similar  species.  These  reflections  he  recorded 
in  a  treatise  which  he  sent  home  and  which  was  printed  in  1855.  The  ex- 
planation of  the  phenomenon  he  found  —  like  Darwin  —  when  meditating 
upon  Malthus's  theory  of  competition;  it  is  the  struggle  for  existence  that 
has  compelled  living  creatures  to  develop  themselves  in  order  not  to  perish 
in  the  struggle  against  other  species;  if  a  variety  has  been  equipped  with 
more  powerful  qualities  than  the  main  species,  it  drives  out  the  latter  and 
usurps  its  place.  This  theory  Wallace  expounded  in  a  report,  which  he  sent 
to  Darwin  for  perusal;  the  latter  was  struck  by  the  agreement  with  the 
ideas  that  he  himself  just  happened  to  be  working  out  and  found  the  situa- 
tion highly  embarrassing.  At  the  suggestion  of  some  friends  he  published 
Wallace's  treatise  together  with  a  report  of  his  own  results,  which  he  sub- 
mitted to  the  Linnean  Society  in  1858,  thus  giving  science  an  opportunity 
of  seeing  the  same  theory  presented  by  two  investigators  working  independ- 
ently. Much  surprise  has  been  expressed  at  the  incident,  which  has  often 
been  put  forward  as  a  proof  of  the  undeniable  truth  of  the  theory.  It  is  pos- 
sible to  find  an  explanation  of  the  phenomenon  by  making  a  comparison 
between  the  two  originators  of  the  theory;  they  were  both  self-taught  men 
with  essentially  systematic  interests,  but  without  any  anatomical  training; 
they  had  both  explored  an  island  region  and  received  their  impressions  there- 
from; both  had  consequently  been  confronted  with  the  problem  of  the  dis- 
tribution of  species,  and,  finally,  both  had  been  influenced  by  Malthus;  and 
though  the  fundamental  view-point  is  the  same  in  both  scientists,  yet  Wal- 
lace has  a  conception  of  the  problem  that  is  in  many  respects  peculiar  to 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  487 

himself.  He  manifestly  never  felt  so  deeply  moved  by  the  actual  doctrine  of 
the  creation  as  Darwin  had  been,  and,  further,  he  has  by  no  means  the  same 
interest  as  Darwin  in  domestic-animal  varieties,  with  which  he  himself  had 
never  experimented;  rather,  having  studied  in  the  richest  tropical  regions, 
he  had  gained  a  far  stronger  impression  of  the  wealth  of  life-forms  and  their 
adaptation  to  environment.  This  especially  comes  out  in  the  mimicry  theory 
that  he  and  his  friend  Bates  created. 

Theory  of  protective  resemblance 
After  a  ten  years'  sojourn  in  the  tropics  of  South  America  Bates  returned 
home  with  rich  collections  and  eventually  became  secretary  to  the  British 
Geographical  Society.  He  wrote  an  essay  in  which  he  propounded  the  idea 
of  protective  resemblance  in  the  animal  kingdom  —  an  idea  that  was  after- 
wards taken  up  and  further  developed  by  Wallace.  It  is  known  that  a  large 
number  of  animals  possess  external  characteristics  that  correspond  to  con- 
ditions in  the  natural  surroundings  in  which  they  live;  the  white  fur  of 
polar  animals,  the  sandy  yellow  of  desert  beasts,  the  likeness  of  many  in- 
sects to  the  bark  of  the  trees  on  which  they  live,  are  all  examples  of  this.  In 
the  more  abundant  plant-life  of  the  tropics  there  appear  still  more  remark- 
able instances  of  this  similarity,  especially  among  the  insects;  well-known 
examples  are  the  "wandering  leaves"  and  "wandering  sticks,"  which, 
owing  to  their  likeness  to  the  undergrowth,  often  elude  the  observation 
of  even  the  most  experienced  collectors.  Wallace  believes  that  all  these  forms 
have  arisen  through  the  circumstance  that  natural  selection  in  the  struggle 
for  existence  has  favoured  those  individuals  that,  owing  to  variations  in 
the  direction  of  greatest  likeness  to  their  surroundings,  have  been  better  pro- 
tected than  others  and  have  thereby  had  a  better  chance  to  propagate.  But 
Wallace  considers  that  even  the  obvious  exceptions  from  the  rule  which  quite 
often  occur  —  animals  with  strikingly  brilliant  colours  —  only  still  fur- 
ther confirm  the  law,  seeing  that  they  really  possess  some  other  character- 
istic which  acts  as  a  powerful  protection  against  their  enemies  and  which 
thus  converts  their  splendid  colours  into  a  kind  of  warning  signal  to  the 
latter;  as,  for  instance,  an  offensive  odour,  as  in  the  skunk  of  America,  the 
natterjack,  and  the  salamander,  as  well  as  a  large  number  of  insects,  in- 
cluding our  common  lady-bird,  with  its  magnificent  red-and-black  spotted 
wings;  or,  again,  a  hard  shell,  as  in  many  brilliantly  coloured  tortoises;  or 
poison,  as  in  many  of  the  vividly  marked  snakes  in  the  tropics.  The  most 
remarkable  application  of  this  law  Wallace  sees,  however,  in  the  mimicry 
or  disguise  whereby  certain  animals  protect  themselves  against  their  enemies 
by  resembling  other  more  dangerous  animals  in  their  outward  appearance; 
there  are  flies  that  in  form  and  manner  of  flying  resemble  bumble-bees,  butter- 
flies that  resemble  wasps;  and  this  disguise  is  demonstrated  still  more  in  the 
tropics,  where  non-poisonous  snakes  are  often  misleadingly  like  the  poisonous 


488  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

ones  and  many  insects  exhibit  similar  [congruities.  Even  this  protective 
resemblance  Wallace,  of  course,  derives  from  natural  selection.  Furthermore, 
he  points  out  in  this  connexion  the  females'  need  for  protection  during  the 
period  when  they  are  ministering  to  their  young  as  a  cause  of  their  less 
conspicuous  coloration,  as  in  the  birds,  whereas  the  cock  birds,  which  do 
not  require  this  protection,  have  developed  greater  splendour  of  colouring. 
Wallace  thus  explains  the  external  dissimilarity  of  the  sexes  without  having 
recourse  to  Darwin's  theory  of  sexual  selection,  which  he  rejects. 

The  whole  of  this  theory  of  protective  resemblance,  which  was  once 
cited  as  one  of  the  strongest  arguments  in  favour  of  Darwinism,  has  natu- 
rally been  discredited  concurrently  with  the  theory  of  selection  itself;  the 
mimicry  theory  in  particular  had  already  been  vehemently  attacked  by  sci- 
entists who  did  not  find  it  accord  with  their  observations  and  experiments; 
the  enemies  that  through  their  pursuit  of  prey  were  supposed  to  have  called 
for  a  protective  resemblance  have  in  many  places  been  found  to  be  non- 
existent, and  remarkable  instances  have  been  discovered  of  resemblances  of 
this  kind  in  animals  in  different  parts  of  the  world,  which  could  not  there- 
fore have  influenced  one  another's  appearance.  Further,  in  order  to  maintain 
the  theory  it  has  been  necessary  to  ascribe  to  a  great  many  animals  powers 
of  observation  and  distinction  as  weak  as  man  himself  possesses.  In  the  lat- 
ter respect  Wallace  was  extremely  credulous;  he  states,  inter  alia:  "The  atti- 
tudes of  some  insects  may  also  protect  them,  as  the  habit  of  turning  up  the 
tail  by  the  harmless  rove-beetles  (Staphylinidas)  no  doubt  leads  other  ani- 
mals besides  children  to  the  belief  that  they  can  sting."  This  comparison 
between  the  animal's  power  of  observation  in  nature  and  that  of  a  child  is 
certainly  very  naive.  But  Wallace  was  on  the  whole  more  of  an  imaginative 
than  critical  nature;  very  soon  he  had  astonished  the  world  by  becoming  a 
convinced  spiritualist,  although  he  was  a  free-thinker  in  religious  questions, 
and  in  later  years  he  became  entirely  engrossed  in  spiritual  seances  and  a 
number  of  similar  fantastic  ideas  of  spiritual  life  in  nature,  while  at  the  same 
time  he  expressed  his  utter  contempt  for  the  results  of  modern  heredity  re- 
search. He  thereby  placed  himself  definitely  on  the  side  of  natural-scientific 
development. 

A  personality  of  an  entirely  different  character  was  Darwin's  other  cham- 
pion in  England  —  Huxley,  one  of  the  most  famous  biologists  of  his  time. 
Thomas  Henry  Huxley  was  born  in  182.5  in  a  London  suburb,  the  son  of  a 
poor  schoolmaster.  After  two  years  at  school,  which  he  himself  described 
as  "a  pandemonium,"  he  had  from  the  age  of  ten  to  pursue  his  studies  by 
himself  and  he  did  so  with  such  success  that  seven  years  later  he  gained  an 
entry  into  the  medical  faculty  in  London.  Having  passed  his  examinations, 
he  became  a  surgeon  in  the  English  fleet  and  served  in  that  capacity  in  a 
vessel  that  was  exploring  the  channels  north  of  Australia.  In  these  tropical 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  489 

waters  there  existed  abundant  animal  life,  which  induced  the  young  doctor 
to  investigate  it.  Among  other  works  he  brought  out  a  book  on  the  medusre, 
which  brought  him  wide  recognition.  At  the  age  of  thirty  he  was  appointed 
professor  at  a  School  of  Mines  and  this  led  him  to  take  up  palasontological 
research,  but  he  further  had  an  opportunity  of  teaching  physiology  and  com- 
parative anatomy,  which  he  had  already  thoroughly  studied  during  his  stu- 
dent days.  Full  of  energy  and  initiative  as  he  was,  he  was  able  to  make 
practical  use  of  his  science  to  an  extent  that  few  have  equalled.  Not  only 
by  means  of  popular  lectures  and  text-books,  but  also  as  a  member  of  school 
committees  and  an  expert  on  fishery  questions,  he  laboured  to  expand  the 
knowledge  of  biology  and  to  increase  respect  for  its  methods  and  mode  of 
thought.  His  authority  ultimately  became  very  great  and  honours  of  all 
kinds  were  showered  upon  him  —  more,  in  fact,  than  he  cared  for.  After 
a  long  period  of  suffering  he  died  in  1895.  His  marble  statue  stands  by  the 
side  of  Darwin's  in  the  South  Kensington  Museum  in  London. 

Huxley' s  ivork  on  the  medusce 
Huxley  was  a  highly  gifted  scientist,  though  critical  rather  than  creative. 
His  first  work  on  the  anatomy  and  affinities  of  the  medusa;  was  that  of 
a  pioneer;  he  therein  demonstrated  the  connexion  between  hydroid  polypi  1 
and  hydromedusa;  and  combined  them  into  one  order,  the  Hydrozoa.  Of 
still  greater  value  was  his  idea  of  comparing  the  dermal  and  intestinal  layers 
of  these  animals  with  the  germinal  layers  in  the  embryonic  stages  of  the 
higher  animals;  out  of  this  comparison  eventually  arose  the  general  theory 
of  germinal  layers.  His  sea  voyage  likewise  produced  a  series  of  valuable 
studies  on  the  Tunicata.  He  also  made  important  contributions  in  the  sphere 
of  vertebrate  anatomy;  especially  well  known  are  his  com.parative  studies 
of  the  structure  of  the  cranium,  whereby  he  proved,  on  the  support  of  the 
preparatory  embryological  works  of  Rathke  and  others,  the  absurdity  of 
the  Oken-Goethe  theory  of  the  cranium's  being  composed  of  vertebra;,  while 
at  the  same  time  he  admitted  its  original  metameric  structure.  This  proved 
a  severe  blow  to  Owen's  archetype  theory;  from  that  moment  the  aged,  cap- 
tious anatomist  became  Huxley's  enemy,  all  the  more  so  as  the  latter  had 
already  rejected  the  idealistic  morphology.  When,  later  on,  old  Owen  de- 
clared that  the  human  brain  has  certain  parts  which  no  other  animal  can  be 
shown  to  possess  and  sought  on  these  grounds  to  claim  for  the  human  race 
a  special  position  as  towards  the  rest  of  the  animals,  Huxley  proved  in  a 
sharply  critical  way  that  the  anatomical  details  of  Owen's  account  were  en- 
tirely inaccurate,  and  this  nullified  all  the  latter's  efforts  to  isolate  man  from 
the  animals. 

Huxley  embraces  Darwinism 
Nevertheless,  in  his  youth  Huxley  was  an  upholder  of  the  immutability 
of  the  species,  and  an  opponent  of  Lamarck's  theories  of  evolution.  Upon 


490  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

the  advent  of  Darwin,  however,  he  was  one  of  the  first  to  be  convinced  and 
from  that  time  onwards  became  one  of  the  most  zealous  champions  of  Dar- 
winism —  its  general  agent,  as  he  himself  jokingly  remarked.  He  took  part 
in  the  earliest  controversy  on  The  Origin  of  Species,  contributing  a  paper  that 
proves  how  understanding  and  at  the  same  time  how  independent  was  his 
attitude  towards  Darwin's  theory  from  the  very  outset.  In  the  first  place, 
he  has  not  Darwin's  blind  faith  in  the  absolute  dominance  of  the  small 
variations  in  nature.  He  cites  as  an  example  of  sudden  changes  the  oft- 
quoted  ancon  or  otter  sheep  of  America,  whose  sudden  appearance  is  a 
well-known  fact,  and  further,  borrowing  from  Reaumur,  the  story  of  a  fam- 
ily that  had  a  child  with  an  excessive  number  of  fingers  and  toes,  which 
phenomenon  was  afterwards  inherited  by  its  descendants.  The  arising  of  the 
otter  sheep  is  an  obvious  mutation;  from  the  appearance  of  the  supernumer- 
ary fingers,  again,  conclusions  might  have  been  drawn  in  the  spirit  of  Mendel. 
This,  however,  was  not  done;  even  in  the  moderate  form  that  Huxley  gave  to 
his  divergences  from  the  true  selection-theory,  they  attracted  no  attention; 
small  indeed  would  the  variations  have  to  be  for  the  struggle  for  existence 
and  selection  to  have  any  material  effect  on  them,  and  what  interest  could  be 
awakened  by  the  story  of  the  inheritance  of  six  fingers?  On  the  basis  of  such 
exact  observations  of  detail  one  came  no  closer  to  the  theory  of  creation, 
which,  indeed,  was  the  main  idea  at  that  time.  Regret  has  often  been  ex- 
pressed that  Mendel's  observations  were  published  in  such  an  out-of-the- 
way  place  that  no  one  noticed  them;  it  is  more  than  likely  that  the  result 
would  have  been  the  same  wherever  they  had  appeared;  the  fact  is,  the 
time  was  not  yet  ripe  for  them.  —  However,  Huxley's  objections  to  the 
master's  theories  were  not  numerous,  nor  were  they  bitter;  he  took  far  greater 
pains  to  defend  what  good  he  found  in  them,  which,  indeed,  was  a  very 
great  deal.  And  in  contrast  to  Darwin  himself,  Huxley  was  a  born  controver- 
sialist, with  an  ever-wakeful  pugnacity,  a  never-failing  promptness  in  reply, 
an  extensive  knowledge  of  books,  and  a  rare  gift  of  putting  the  most  in- 
volved questions  in  a  fluent  and  easily  understood  style.  For  the  rest,  his 
polemics  are  always  courteous;  sceptic  as  he  is,  he  confronts  his  opponent 
with  a  supercilious,  but  not  always  a  friendly,  smile,  and  he  never  allows  his 
composure  to  be  ruffled,  nor  himself  to  be  reduced  to  silence.  He  particularly 
enjoyed  crossing  swords  with  men  of  the  Church,  and  on  that  battlefield 
there  were  certainly  to  be  found  opponents  en  masse  so  long  as  he  lived. 
Among  them  was  Gladstone,  the  great  Liberal  statesman,  who  was  also 
an  extremely  learned  and  highly  conservative  theologian.  At  one  period 
during  the  eighties  Huxley  entered  into  a  controversy  with  him  —  the  fore- 
most biologist  against  the  leading  statesman  in  England  at  that  time  — 
concerning  the  gospel  story  of  the  Gadarene  swine,  which  were  drowned 
after  the  Devil  had  entered  into  them.  Rather  more  urgent  problems  were 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  491 

dealt  with  in  his  dispute  with  another  famous  politician,  the  Duke  of  Argyle, 
who  in  a  work  entitled  The  Reign  of  Laiv  had  opposed  Darwinism's  lack  of  con- 
formity to  law  in  the  sense  given  to  it  by  idealistic  natural  philosophy.  But 
Huxley  sought  to  influence  the  contemporary  world  of  ideas  also  in  a  posi- 
tive way;  he  enunciated  the  same  social  ethics  that  Darwin  had  taught  and 
that  their  age  so  largely  embraced;  he  laboured  to  make  the  results  of  modern 
natural  science  the  basis  of  school  education  instead  of  the  traditional  classi- 
cal languages,  and  he  endeavoured  by  means  of  popular  writings  and  lectures 
to  bring  them  to  the  knowledge  of  the  general  public.  As  a  popular  scien- 
tific writer  he  is  unrivalled  for  the  clearness,  warmth,  and  honesty  of  his  style; 
he  never  expresses  a  view  that  he  cannot  defend  and  never  tries  to  disguise 
the  fact  that  the  capacity  of  science  for  explaining  phenomena  is  limited. 
The  same  honesty  he  displayed  also  as  a  specialist.  He  once  described  a  gelati- 
nous substance  taken  from  the  bottom  of  the  sea,  which  he  thought  was 
a  kind  of  undifferentiated,  but  living  plasm,  and  which  in  honour  of  Haeckel 
he  named  Bathybius  haeckelii;  when  it  was  later  discovered  that  the  substance 
was  an  inanimate  precipitation,  he  frankly  and  boldly  acknowledged  his 
mistake,  which  Haeckel  found  it  rather  difficult  to  admit.  But  Huxley  was 
also  interested  in  purely  philosophical  problems;  he  was  a  great  admirer  of 
David  Hume,  the  famous  sceptic  of  the  eighteenth  century,  Kant's  predeces- 
sor as  a  critic  of  knowledge,  and  Huxley  described  his  life  and  teaching  in 
a  monograph.  He  himself  represented  his  theoretical  standpoint  as  agnosti- 
cism, as  a  strict  insistence  upon  the  impossibility  of  knowing  anything  be- 
yond the  actual  observations  of  the  senses.  And  it  must  be  admitted  that  he 
succeeded  in  an  unusually  high  degree  in  keeping  free  from  the  materialistic 
dogmatism  to  which  the  opponents  of  the  traditional  ideals  of  thought  and 
religion  are  so  easily  addicted. 

Gray  on  Darwinism 
Among  the  professional  botanists,  also,  Darwin  at  once  found  valuable  sup- 
■  porters.  One  of  these  was  Asa  Gray  (1810-88),  professor  at  Harvard  Univer- 
sity and  well  known  as  a  leading  writer  on  systematic  botany  and  American 
flora.  Immediately  after  Darwin's  appearance  he  came  forward  on  his  behalf 
and  in  opposition  to  his  own  colleague  Agassiz;  the  contributions  he  wrote 
on  behalf  of  the  new  theory  in  the  course  of  a  number  of  years  he  collected 
in  a  special  book,  entitled  Darwiniana.  In  his  first  review  of  The  Origin  of 
Species  he  first  of  all  attacks  Agassiz's  idea  of  species  and  then  goes  on  to 
point  out  that,  even  though  Darwin  was  unable  to  prove  his  theory  of  de- 
scent, he  at  any  rate  made  an  origin  of  species  far  less  incredible  than  before. 
Gray  was  at  great  pains  to  prove  that  Darwinism  could  be  reconciled  to  the 
belief  in  a  personal  God,  and  he  likewise  sets  great  store  by  the  Darwinian 
theory  as  being  better  adapted  to  finding  an  explanation  of  the  finality  in  na- 
ture than  earlier  theories;  he  expressly  points  out  that  Darwin  rehabilitated 


492.  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

the  teleological  explanation  of  nature  —  that  is,  the  same  as  Kolliker 
maintained  and  Huxley  denied.  To  such  divergent  interpretations  could 
Darwin's  theory  give  rise. 

Darwin  had  also  found  a  convinced  supporter  and  a  lifelong  friend  in 
Joseph  Dalton  Hooker  (1817-1911),  a  keen  explorer  in  various  exotic  coun- 
tries, a  distinguished  plant-systematist,  and  finally  director  of  Kew  Gardens 
in  London.  Darwin  was  engaged  in  an  almost  constant  interchange  of  ideas 
with  him  during  the  many  years  he  w^orked  at  his  theory;  when  eventually 
The  Origin  of  Species  was  published.  Hooker  zealously  defended  the  new  the- 
ory of  descent,  both  in  articles  in  the  press  and  in  his  own  more  important 
works.  In  particular,  the  introduction  to  his  book  on  the  flora  of  Tasmania, 
which  was  published  in  the  year  after  Tbe  Origin  of  Species,  represents  a  defence 
of  these  doctrines,  based  partly  on  geographical  arguments  and  partly  on  evi- 
dence derived  from  classification,  with  special  reference  to  the  many  phaner- 
ogam genera  which  are  so  rich  in  species  and,  owing  to  their  numerous 
middle-forms,  are  so  difficult  to  classify  —  Rubus,  Rosa,  Salix,  and  others. 
Darwin's  later  researches  into  plant  physiology  were  also  supported  to  the 
utmost  by  Hooker;  in  fact,  of  all  the  champions  of  Darwinism  he  was,  on 
the  whole,  in  closest  personal  contact  with  its  founder. 

Development  of  Danvinism  in  England  and  Germany 
It  was  from  many  different  quarters,  then,  that  Darwin  won  support  for 
his  theory  of  descent;  in  fact,  as  has  often  been  emphasized  before,  it  be- 
came the  most  widely  cherished  scientific  idea  of  the  age.  In  these  circum- 
stances it  was  obvious  that  many  forces  were  destined  to  make  for  its  further 
development.  Towards  this  end,  however,  it  was  possible  to  follow  differ- 
ent methods;  of  these  there  were  really  two  that  immediately  came  into  use 
—  one  in  each  of  the  two  countries  that  came  to  be  the  principal  centres  of 
Darwinism;  in  Germany  recourse  was  had  to  the  method  which  was  only 
hinted  at  by  Darwin  himself,  of  seeking  fresh  proofs  of  the  descent  theory 
in  comparative  morphology  and  embryology,  while  in  England  his  support- 
ers followed  the  experimental  and  statistical  method,  in  which  Darwin  him- 
self had  expressed  the  greatest  confidence.  These  two  courses  will  be  described 
in  the  following.  In  this  connexion,  however,  we  must  first  mention  one 
thinker  who,  although  not  a  professional  biologist,  yet  sought  more  con- 
sistently than  most  people  to  apply  the  descent  theory,  in  the  form  that 
Darwin  had  given  it,  to  all  the  phenomena  of  life,  and  who  was  regarded 
by  his  contemporaries  as  the  philosopher  of  evolution  above  all  others. 

Herbert  Spencer  was  born  at  Derby  in  the  midlands,  in  the  year  1810, 
the  son  of  a  schoolmaster.  His  parents  were  both  Free  Church  people,  but 
belonged  to  different  sects,  and  this  lack  of  harmony  induced  feelings  of 
doubt  in  the  son  at  an  early  age;  in  political  radicalism,  on  the  other  hand, 
he  was  fully  in  accord  with  his  home  throughout  his  life.  He  received  a  good 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  493 

school  education  and  especially  distinguished  himself  in  the  exact  sciences, 
the  classical  languages  having  no  attraction  for  him.  He  chose  engineering 
as  his  profession,  distinguishing  himself  by  a  number  of  minor  inventions. 
His  restless  and  insatiable  desire  for  knowledge,  how^ever,  soon  induced  him 
to  abandon  that  career,  and  he  resolved  to  devote  himself  to  working  out  a 
general  scientific  system.  In  order  to  carry  out  his  purpose  he  studied  many 
different  sciences,  chiefly  those  of  an  exact  character,  and  during  that  period 
he  earned  a  livelihood  by  writing  for  newspapers  and  journals.  He  never 
received  any  public  appointment  and  he  consistently  declined  the  honours 
that  were  offered  him,  especially  towards  the  close  of  his  life,  from  many 
quarters.  In  a  constant  struggle  with  poverty  he  lived  in  solitude,  being 
also  during  the  latter  part  of  his  life  a  sufferer  from  a  severe  nervous  afflic- 
tion. He  was  ruthlessly  radical,  not  only  in  his  political  views,  but  even 
in  his  personal  behaviour;  he  always  gave  his  opinion  straight  out,  and  if 
a  conversation  bored  him,  he  put  stoppers  into  his  ears.  In  spite  of  his  ill 
health  he  lived  to  a  good  old  age.  When  he  died,  in  1903,  his  body  was 
cremated  without  any  funeral  ceremony. 

Spencer's  idea  of  evolution 
Herbert  Spencer  was  not  a  specialist  in  biology,  and  his  speculations  on 
biological  problems  have  not  advanced  that  science  to  any  very  great  ex- 
tent. He  nevertheless  deserves  a  place  in  the  history  of  biology  as  a  rare 
example  of  a  consummate  and  typical  representative  of  that  evolutional  mode 
of  thought  which  was  awakened  to  life  by  the  general  tendency  of  the  times 
in  the  middle  of  last  century  and  which  was  promoted  by  Darwinism.  He 
is  commonly  called  the  most  consistent  philosopher  of  evolution  which  that 
period  produced  —  evolution  forms  the  very  groundwork  of  his  system.  In 
its  essential  features  this  system  was  already  pretty  definite  before  the  ad- 
vent of  Darwin;  it  was  promulgated  in  a  number  of  small  articles  in  periodi- 
cals, often  characterized  by  masterly  penetration  and  lucidity,  afterwards 
brought  together  to  form  an  imposing  work  entitled  A  Systetn  of  Synthetic 
Philosophy,  which  was  the  fruits  of  thirty  years'  work  and  which  gives  "a 
broad,  often  too  broad,  development  of  what  is  recorded  in  the  short  trea- 
tises" (HofFding).  When  Darwin  produced  his  theory,  Spencer  associated 
himself  with  it,  although  he  interprets  it  after  his  own  mind,  and  he  became 
one  of  the  most  influential  promoters  of  the  new  doctrine  of  evolution. 
Otherwise  he  is  said  not  to  have  been  in  favour  of  extensive  studies;  he 
preferred  to  think  for  himself  and  was  very  jealous  of  his  independence. 
Nevertheless,  there  is  no  doubt  that  Comte  and  his  contemporary  English 
positivists  exerted  some  influence  upon  him,  and  he  himself  admits  that  he 
discussed  biological  problems  with  both  Huxley  and  Hooker. 


494  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

Latv  of  differentiation 
Of  Spencer's  shorter  articles  there  is  one  dated  1851,  "The  Development 
Hypothesis,"  in  which  he  clearly  and  definitely  dissociates  himself  from  a 
belief  in  the  immutability  of  species;  a  hypothesis  of  creation  is  unscientific 
because  it  is  incomprehensible,  and  the  probability  is  that  the  various  forms 
of  life  on  the  earth  have  been  modified  in  the  course  of  the  ages  by  the  in- 
fluence of  different  external  conditions  of  life.  In  a  couple  of  other  similarly 
pro-Darwin  essays,  "Progress,  its  Law  and  Cause"  and  "Genesis  of  Sci- 
ence," he  gives  a  more  general  presentation  of  his  evolutional  theory,  which 
was  afterwards  further  developed,  in  view  of  the  selection  theory,  into  his 
great  philosophical  work.  According  to  him,  the  function  of  philosophy  is 
to  combine  under  one  common  standpoint  the  results  achieved  by  all  other 
sciences:  physics,  chemistry,  and  biology,  as  also  psychology  and  sociology. 
This  unity  common  to  all  sciences  exists  in  evolution.  All  existence  is  evolu- 
tion; the  heavenly  bodies  are  undergoing  change,  the  earth  was  once  incan- 
descent and  has  since  then  gone  through  a  series  of  evolutional  forms,  and 
all  things  existing  on  it,  both  animate  and  inanimate,  are  doing  the  same; 
the  separate  plant  and  animal  individual  is  being  evolved,  just  as  species 
and  genera  and  humanity  are  being  evolved,  individual  for  individual  and 
generation  after  generation.  The  question  of  what  "evolution"  is,  Spencer 
has  in  such  circumstances  to  try  to  get  answered  as  exhaustively  as  possible. 
In  the  above-mentioned  treatise  on  the  law  of  progress  he  endeavours  to 
formulate  the  answer  from  a  biological  standpoint;  starting  from  the  evolu- 
tion theories  of  C.  F.  Wolff,  Goethe,  and  von  Baer,  he  finds  in  agreement 
with  them  that  the  development  of  the  individual  proceeds  from  the  homo- 
geneous to  the  heterogeneous;  out  of  the  egg,  which  is  uniform  throughout, 
both  in  structure  and  composition,  is  evolved  an  individual  possessing  vari- 
ous parts  and  organs,  which  are  the  more  differentiated  the  further  the  de- 
velopment proceeds.  This  law  Spencer  believes  holds  good  for  everything; 
the  earth  was  once  uniformly  incandescent,  but  after  having  cooled  off,  it 
acquired  an  increasingly  different  and  varying  surface;  all  living  creatures 
were  originally  primitive  and  homogeneous,  but  out  of  these  primal  forms 
there  has  since  been  developed  an  ever  greater  multiplicity  of  life -forms;  the 
life  of  the  human  society  offers  the  same  picture,  and  differences  in  language 
and  other  manifestations  of  intellectual  life  have  similarly  developed.  But 
whence  is  this  differentiation  produced?  Spencer  answers  this  question  with 
the  contention  that  every  cause  invariably  has  more  than  one  effect;  if  a 
candle  is  lighted,  it  is  one  simple  chemical  process,  but  it  produces  a  number 
of  different  effects  —  heat,  light,  chemical  products.  Thus  there  are  created 
on  the  earth  an  ever-increasing  number  of  phenomena.  The  whole  of  this 
discussion  on  causality  is,  of  course,  a  purely  metaphysical  problem;  against 
the  theory  of  evolution  on  which  it  is  based  it  may  be  remarked  from  a 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  495 

biological  point  of  view  that  Spencer  deliberately  threw  himself  into  the 
arms  of  the  Wolffian  epigenesis  theory.  If  the  standpoint  of  the  preformation 
theory  is  adopted,  then  the  whole  foundation  of  this  doctrine  of  evolution  is 
destroyed.  Now,  in  modern  times,  the  egg  is  certainly  not  regarded  as  non- 
differentiated;  rather,  with  its  numerous  hereditary  factors  and  the  orienta- 
tion given  it  from  the  very  beginning,  it  is  a  tremendously  complex  structure. 

Process  of  consolidation 
At  a  later  period  Spencer  tried  also  to  expand  his  evolution  theory.  He  sees 
in  it  a  process  of  consolidation;  the  egg-cell  absorbs  nutriment  from  sur- 
rounding tissues,  the  embryo  from  the  yolk  of  the  Qgg,  both  under  a  proc- 
ess of  increasing  consolidation.  In  the  same  way  the  celestial  bodies  have 
been  consolidated  out  of  nebulous  masses,  and  the  human  communities  out 
of  scattered  groups.  Further,  evolution  may  be  regarded  as  a  transition  from 
the  indefinite  to  the  definite,  as  indeed  is  demonstrated  in  the  life  of  individ- 
uals, species,  and  communities.  But,  above  all,  in  his  later  years  Spencer 
began  to  realize  that  evolution  does  not  always  advance;  it  can  also  show 
the  exact  opposite  phenomenon,  that  progression  and  retrogression  succeed 
one  another  in  evolution.  This  speculation  suffers  on  the  whole  from  the 
attempt  to  bring  all  phenomena  on  the  earth  without  exception  under  one 
common  definition,  which  in  the  circumstances  becomes  far  too  abstract: 
it  says  too  little  because  it  is  meant  to  embrace  too  much.  The  same  fault 
underlies  the  definition  of  life  that  is  given  in  the  biological  section  of  Spen- 
cer's system.  Various  characteristics  of  life  are  examined,  and  finally  the 
definitive  characteristic  is  formulated  thus:  "Life  is  a  continuous  adjustment 
of  internal  conditions  to  external  conditions."  The  higher  the  life,  the 
stronger  is  the  connexion  between  the  internal  and  the  external;  the  intel- 
lectual life  represents  the  highest  degree  of  relationship  between  internal  and 
external  changes.  His  detailed  application  of  this  theory  of  life  offers  little  in 
the  way  of  interest;  although  controlled  by  Huxley  and  Hooker,  it  corre- 
sponds but  little  to  modern  ideas.  As  an  instance  may  be  quoted  the  assertion 
that  life  precedes  organization  in  the  matter  in  which  it  develops,  whereas 
in  reality  life  and  organization  are  indissolubly  bound  up  in  one  another. 

Limitation  of  the  capacity  for  knotvledge 
A  LIKING  for  abstract  conclusions  has  often  been  held  to  constitute  Spen- 
cer's chief  weakness;  it  is  in  accord  with  the  above-mentioned  tendency  to 
bring  together  the  most  dissimilar  phenomena  in  existence  under  one  view- 
point. He  himself  has  defined  knowledge  as  the  bringing  of  every  separate 
phenomenon  within  the  compass  of  a  more  general  and  previously  known 
one  —  the  operation  of  muscle,  for  instance,  is  explained  if  one  has  a  chance 
of  comparing  it  with  the  already  known  lever-mechanism  —  and  he  con- 
tends that  in  consequence  hereof  the  ultimate  and  most  general  phenomena 
must  remain  incomprehensible  because  there  is  nothing  more  general  with 


496  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

which  to  compare  them.  He  repeatedly  and  with  almost  passionate  emphasis 
affirms  that  our  capacity  for  knowledge  is  limited:  what  matter,  force,  space, 
and  time  really  are  we  shall  never  know,  for  our  mind  cannot  grasp  them; 
we  can  only  investigate  the  phenomena  that  our  personal  experience  of  them 
educes.  But  for  that  reason  Spencer  also  gives  religion  the  right  to  hold  its 
own  views  on  this  "  unknowable."  Religious  problems,  however,  have  little 
interest  for  him.  He  is  all  the  more  occupied  with  social  questions,  and  it 
is  in  this  sphere  that  his  evolution  theory  finds  its  most  curious  expression. 
His  belief  in  the  progress  of  humanity  is  boundless  and  he  is  prepared  to 
apply  to  it  unreservedly  Darwin's  theory  of  natural  selection  —  that  is,  as 
he  himself  says,  that  the  fittest  shall  survive.  The  freedom  of  the  individual 
he  places  above  all  else:  "Every  man  is  free  to  do  that  which  he  wills,  pro- 
vided he  infringes  not  the  equal  freedom  of  any  other  man."  The  State  is 
a  survival  from  the  primitive  conditions  of  earlier  ages,  and  its  interference 
with  the  life  of  the  individual  is  purely  wrong  and  merely  hinders  the  opera- 
tion of  free  selection.  All  measures  adopted  by  the  Government  are  worse 
than  if  they  were  carried  out  by  individuals;  public  poor-relief  is  expensive 
and  badly  administered  compared  with  private  charity;  State  schools  are 
always  inferior  to  private  schools;  in  a  word,  the  State  should  gradually  be 
done  away  with,  but  for  the  present  it  is  necessary  to  maintain  a  police 
force  to  ensure  domestic  security,  and  a  military  force  to  protect  the  country 
from  invasion,  though  on  no  account  should  there  be  compulsory  military 
service.  So  much  the  higher,  then,  must  be  the  claims  laid  on  private  mo- 
rality, and,  in  fact,  Spencer  claims  much  from  it.  He  holds,  in  conformity 
with  his  belief  in  the  heredity  of  acquired  qualities,  that  the  intellectual 
capacity  of  the  individual  becomes  the  common  property  of  the  race;  the 
quality  of  the  intellect  corresponds  to  certain  structural  conditions  in  the 
brain;  if  the  former  is  perfected,  then  the  latter  develop,  are  inherited  by 
the  descendants,  and  thus  benefit  humanity.  The  aim  of  morality  is  to  create 
as  much  happiness  as  possible;  happiness,  however,  must  not  be  sought  in 
material  prosperity  —  the  more  so  as  the  latter  leads  to  dishonesty.  To  be 
allowed  to  contribute,  in  however  small  a  way,  towards  the  advancement 
of  general  evolution  should  be  the  highest  happiness  to  which  the  individ- 
ual can  attain.  Morality  thus  benefits  the  community  more  than  the  individ- 
ual, according  to  Spencer,  as  indeed  according  to  the  positivism  of  the  age 
as  a  whole.  Both  his  and  his  contemporaries'  limitation  in  this  sphere  lay 
in  an  insufficient  sense  of  the  purely  personal;  he  had  but  little  sympathy 
for  the  individual's  longing  for  personal  release  from  his  confined  and  trying 
environment  or  from  his  inner  qualms  of  conscience;  he  thought  that  one 
and  all  should  take  things  calmly  in  the  hope  for  better  times  to  come  — 
which,  indeed,  seemed  a  far  more  likely  prospect  for  the  people  of  those  days 
than  for  those  of  our  own. 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  497 

As  a  matter  of  fact,  Herbert  Spencer  himself  lived  to  see  the  future  of 
the  world  darkened.  The  march  of  militarism,  which  he  hated,  went  on 
apace  towards  the  close  of  the  century;  the  colonization  of  tropical  countries, 
of  which  he  also  disapproved,  was  carried  still  further  afield;  while  social- 
ism, with  its  State  production,  must  necessarily  have  been  equally  distaste- 
ful to  him.  And  even  philosophy  began  in  his  lifetime  to  strike  along  paths 
other  than  those  he  had  marked  out.  But  though  his  ideas  are  now  for  the 
most  part  out  of  date,  he  will  always  be  remembered  as  one  of  the  most  per- 
sistent, disinterested,  and  courageous  champions  of  the  theory  of  evolution. 


CHAPTER    XIII 

THE     DOCTRINE     OF     DESCENT     BASED     ON     MORPHOLOGICAL 
GROUNDS.    GEGENBAUR     AND     HIS    SCHOOL 

Leading  position  of  Germany  in  biological  research 

IN  HIS  Geschichte  der  btologischen  Theorten  Radl  declares  that  Darwinism  was 
born  in  England,  but  found  a  home  in  Germany.  The  statement  is  cer- 
tainly justified  in  so  far  as,  during  the  decades  immediately  succeeding 
the  first  appearance  of  the  descent  theory,  Germany  came  to  take  a  leadmg 
position  in  the  sphere  of  biological  research;  here  England  and  America 
rapidly  came  under  German  influence,  as  also  did  Italy,  while  France  which 
kept  itself  isolated,  nevertheless  could  not  entirely  avoid  being  influenced. 
There  were  undoubtedly  many  reasons  for  this:  on  the  one  hand,  the  great 
economic  and  technical  development  that  resulted  from  the  founding  of  the 
German  Empire,  which  in  many  ways  proved  beneficial  to  research,  and, 
on  the  other  hand,  the  splendid  manner  in  which  the  work  at  the  German 
universities  was  organized,  which  became  a  pattern  for  other  countries,  es- 
pecially as  a  result  of  the  careful  and  methodical  guidance  given  by  the 
teachers  to  their  pupils'  theoretical  studies,  practical  work,  and  scientific 
production.  And  especially  as  far  as  biology  in  Germany  is  concerned,  this 
organization  had  reached  a  very  high  standard  -  chiefly  in  the  sphere  of 
comparative  anatomy  -  even  before  the  appearance  of  Dar^vln.  Originally, 
of  course,  comparative  anatomy  had  been  based  on  idealistic  morphology, 
on  the  assumption  that  ideas  formed  the  existing  basis  for  the  various  forms 
of  life   but  we  have  already  seen  how  this  form  of  romantic  natural  philos- 
ophy was  gradually  supplanted  by  a  more  realistic  manner  of  viewing  lite. 
What  Dai-winism  gave  to  this  realistic  morphology  was,  as  we  know,  a 
hitherto  lacking  connexion  in  existence;  common  descent  took  the  place  ot 
the  common  ideal  types.  The  fact  that  it  was  the  representatives  of  compara- 
tive morphology  in  Germany  who  hailed  the  new  doctrine  with  such  deep 
enthusiasm  is  explained  by  the  insistent  demand  that  they  had  of  old  f e  t 
for  a  uniform  conception  of  nature,  a  heritage  from  the,  at  one  time  all- 
prevailing,  romantic  philosophy.  But  it  is  just  this  never  entirely  eradicated 
romantic  element  that  gives  to  German  Darwinism,  with  its  application  of 
the  descent  theory  to  comparative  anatomy,  a  character  of  its  own.  Again, 
the  general  cultural  situation  in  Germany  at  the  time  of  the  launching  ot  the 
new  doctrine  must  of  course  have  had  a  considerable  influence  on  the  form 

498 


<; 
n 
Z 
w 

o 
w 

o 

1-1 

< 
u 


Pi 

w 

h-1 
:0 

O 
> 

H 
P^ 
W 

m 
o 

Q 
P 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  499 

it  was  to  take.  This  is  essentially  bound  up  in  the  two  names  Gegenbaur  and 
Haeckel,  each  of  whom  in  his  own  way  represents  a  different  side  of  the  in- 
fluence of  Darwinism  upon  contemporary  culture. 

Carl  Gegenbaur  was  born  in  182.6  at  Wiirzburg,  of  an  ancient  and  well- 
to-do  family  closely  connected  with  the  Civil  Service.  After  being  at  school 
in  his  native  town  he  graduated  at  its  university  and  applied  himself,  at 
variance  with  his  family  traditions,  to  the  study  of  medicine,  with  a  view 
to  fulfilling  his  ambition  to  pursue  scientific  studies,  in  which  he  had  early 
shown  a  keen  interest.  With  his  natural  bent  for  science,  he  at  first  derived 
but  little  pleasure  from  his  country's  educational  system;  the  gymnasium 
in  Wiirzburg  was  run  by  Jesuits  and  was  conducted  in  the  Jesuitical  spirit; 
nor  were  things  much  better  at  the  University,  until  Kolliker  arrived  there 
with  Leydig  as  his  assistant.  From  that  time  onwards  biology  received  a 
powerful  stimulus,  which  was  still  further  increased  when,  a  couple  of  years 
later,  Virchow  began  his  activities  as  a  teacher  there.  Within  a  short  time 
these  men  made  of  Wiirzburg  a  nursery  for  biological  research,  and  amongst 
their  pupils  Gegenbaur  at  once  took  one  of  the  foremost  places.  In  1851  he 
wrote  a  dissertation  for  Kolliker  and  shortly  afterwards  accompanied  his 
master  on  his  research  expedition  to  the  Mediterranean  coast,  a  trip  that 
resulted  in  the  young  explorer's  being  ever  afterwards  attracted  to  compara- 
tive anatomy.  The  immediate  result  of  the  voyage  was  a  number  of  valuable 
investigations  into  marine  animals  of  various  kinds,  and  the  consequence  of 
these  was  a  summons  to  a  professorial  chair  at  Jena  in  1855.  At  this  little 
Protestant  university,  maintained  by  a  liberal-minded  Government,  Gegen- 
baur at  once  succeeded  very  well,  although  himself  a  Catholic;  he  had  had 
enough  of  the  conditions  prevailing  at  home,  where  the  hospitals  were  un- 
der ecclesiastical  administration  and  the  doctors  were  subject  to  clerical  con- 
trol. At  Jena  he  gathered  around  him  a  host  of  like-minded  friends  and 
pupils,  chief  among  them  being  Haeckel.  Here  he  worked  out  a  scientific 
system,  which  he  afterwards  applied  throughout  his  life,  and  here  too  he 
produced  his  finest  works.  In  iSyx,  however,  he  accepted  an  invitation  to 
Heidelberg,  where  larger  resources  were  placed  at  his  disposal  and  where 
he  afterwards  laboured  until  the  close  of  the  century,  when,  owing  to  in- 
creasing ill  health,  he  resigned.  He  died  in  1903,  having  been  paralysed  by 
repeated  strokes. 

Gegenbaur  was  a  forceful  personality,  a  friend  to  his  friends,  and  an 
enemy  to  his  enemies.  As  the  founder  of  a  school  he  is  worthy  of  mention 
with  J.  Miiller,  but  while  the  latter  taught  his  pupils  the  method  he  had 
invented  and  in  theoretical  questions  allowed  them  to  go  their  own  way, 
Gegenbaur  permitted  no  divergence  from  the  general  principles  he  had  once 
and  for  all  made  his  own.  Moreover,  he  succeeded  in  inspiring  his  disciples 
with  such  "boundless  admiration"  (Fiirbringer)  that  most  of  them  were 


500  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

prepared  for  the  rest  of  their  lives  to  swear  by  the  master's  word.  This 
influence  he  won  not  through  his  lectures,  for  they  were  not  very  perfect 
in  form,  but  through  the  keen  interest  he  showed  in  his  pupils'  work,  pro- 
vided that  it  followed  the  right  direction;  in  the  laboratory  he  was  a  friend 
and  comrade  to  his  pupils  and  followed  their  careers  in  after  life  with  never- 
flagging  interest.  But  he  could  never  endure  contradiction;  as  a  controver- 
sialist he  was  bitter  and  irreconcilable,  although  he  invariably  controlled 
his  language.  At  Jena  he  collaborated  loyally  with  Haeckel,  and  the  ex- 
change of  ideas  that  took  place  between  them  was  mutual.  After  he  removed 
to  Heidelberg,  however,  this  co-operation  ceased  and  even  their  friendship 
cooled  off,  as  Haeckel  devoted  himself  to  popular  agitation,  of  which  his 
friend  never  approved.  In  his  old  age  it  was  the  Hegelian  philosopher  Kuno 
Fischer  who  was  in  closest  contact  with  Gegenbaur;  he  described  the  latter 
as  a  deep  thinker,  which  in  its  way  characterizes  him  correctly. 

Gegenbaur's  first  works  came  into  being  during  his  visit  to  the  Medi- 
terranean and  comprise  studies  of  the  anatomy  and  evolution  of  various 
marine  animals;  in  particular,  medusa;  and  other  Coelenterata,  Ascidia,  and 
worms  were  investigated  by  him  during  this  period,  many  of  them  with 
important  results.  Soon,  however,  he  went  over  entirely  to  the  study  of  the 
Vertebrata.  One  of  his  earliest  works  in  this  field  is  an  essay  on  the  evolution 
of  the  egg,  published  in  1861;  in  this  he  shows  that  all  eggs  of  the  Verte- 
brata are  simple  cells;  hitherto  it  had  been  supposed  that  the  egg  of  the 
bird,  for  instance,  was  a  multicellular  organ,  whereas  the  granules  in  the 
yolk  were  held  to  be  independent  cells.  In  this  connexion  he  strongly  sup- 
ports Max  Schultze's  view  that  the  cell  need  not  necessarily  possess  a  mem- 
brane, but  that  the  plasm  and  the  nucleus  are  its  principal  com.ponents.  This 
investigation,  which  of  all  Gegenbaur's  writings  is  perhaps  of  the  great- 
est value  in  the  field  of  discovery,  was  followed  by  a  long  series  of  other 
works,  wherein  he  applies  to  different  organic  systems  in  the  Vertebrata  the 
comparative  method  which  he  worked  out  in  order  to  confirm  Darwin's  the- 
ory, and  the  main  principle  of  which  is  to  discover  by  means  of  anatomical 
comparisons  the  affinity  between  the  animal  forms  due  to  descent.  His  finest 
productions  on  this  subject,  taken  as  models  for  the  whole  generation  of 
research  students,  were  his  comparative  studies  of  the  skeleton,  which  were 
brought  together  in  the  work  Untersuchungen  Tur  vergleichenden  Anatomk  der 
Wirbeltiere.  Among  these  studies  the  most  notable  is  the  essay  entitled  "  Car- 
pus  und  Tarsus,"  in  which  he  compares  piece  by  piece  the  bones  of  the  hand 
and  foot  in  different  vertebrate  animals,  establishes  their  identity,  and  en- 
deavours to  reconstruct  the  form  of  extremity  at  one  time  possessed  by  the 
ancestors  of  the  Vertebrata.  This  primal  extremity  he  terms  in  a  subsequent 
treatise  "  archipterygium  " ;  he  holds  that  it  has  been  developed  out  of  the 
gill  apparatus  and  reconstructs  the  modifications  by  which  have  been  evolved 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  501 

therefrom  the  fins  of  the  fishes  on  the  one  hand,  and  the  motive  organs  of 
the  land-animals  on  the  other.  He  supplemented  this  investigation  with  an- 
other on  the  scapular  apparatus  and  the  pelvis,  in  which  the  bones  of  these 
parts  are  similarly  compared.  The  last  and  biggest  section  of  this  work  is 
called  "Das  Kopfskelett  der  Selaclner"  and  is  described  by  Gegenbaur's  dis- 
ciples as  the  climax  of  his  production.  In  it  he  examines  and  condemns  after 
the  style  of  Huxley  the  old  theory  of  the  skull's  being  composed  of  verte- 
bra:; instead  he  makes  the  cranium  of  the  sharks  the  archetype  from  which 
the  same  part  in  all  higher  vertebrates  must  have  been  derived;  it  comprises 
in  the  sharks  throughout  their  lives  a  cartilaginous  capsule  and  is  formed 
of  the  same  elements  also  in  the  higher  vertebrates,  while  the  latter's  de- 
finitive cranium  is  constructed  with  the  co-operation  of  a  number  of  covering 
bones,  originating  in  the  skin.  On  the  other  hand,  the  visceral  skeleton  of 
the  head  —  gill-arches  and  jaw-bone  —  is  compared  with  the  ribs,  so  that 
a  part  of  the  head,  at  any  rate,  possesses  a  segmented  character.  In  conjunc- 
tion with  these  skeletal  investigations  Gegenbaur  also  carried  out  a  number 
of  comparative  studies  in  the  sphere  of  the  anatomy  of  the  nerves  and  mus- 
culature and  the  organs  of  digestion.  The  entire  results  of  his  research  work 
he  collected  in  that  great  work  which  was  published  towards  the  close  of 
his  life,  Verglekhende  Anatomk  der  Wirbeltiere,  in  which  he  gives  the  most 
complete  expression  to  his  ideas  and  aims.  As  parts  of  this  work  he  added 
his  previously  published  text-books  Grundxtige  and  Grundriss  der  vergleicben- 
den  Anatomie,  which  present  his  views,  in  concise  form,  and  the  method  of 
presentation  and  the  contents  of  which  have  been  imitated  by  many  later 
authors.  In  these,  as  also  in  his  monographs,  Gegenbaur's  style  is  always 
heavy  and  sometimes  hard  to  understand,  which  his  admirers  held  to  in- 
dicate depth  of  mind;  nevertheless,  consistency  and  set  purpose  are  the  most 
conspicuous  features  in  his  scientific  writings  —  which  indeed  explain  their 
success  with  his  contemporaries. 

Gegenbaur  s  general  principles 
In  some  essays  written  late  in  life  Gegenbaur  sets  forth  the  principles 
on  which  he  considers  that  biological  research  should  be  carried  out.  To 
him,  comparative  morphology  is  the  essential  science,  not  to  say  the  only 
road  to  the  knowledge  of  life;  and  the  final  goal  of  this  knowledge  is  the 
determining  of  the  mutual  relationship  of  the  different  life-forms  by  dis- 
covering their  common  origin.  "The  ultimate  aim  is  phylogeny,"  he  says 
in  an  account  of  the  relation  of  anatomy  to  ontogeny.  After  the  fashion  of 
Darwin,  he  ascribes  the  actual  formation  of  species  to  natural  selection, 
though,  practically  speaking,  he  does  not  discuss  this  problem,  but  con- 
fines himself  to  tracing  the  individual  organs  back  to  common  archetypes, 
which  he  seeks  in  the  lower  organisms,  in  the  vertebrates  particularly  in 
the  sharks.  Investigations  in  homology  with  a  phylogenetical  purpose  are 


502.  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

thus  the  aim  of  his  researches;  the  form  and  modification  in  the  form  of 
the  organs  are  all  that  interests  him;  physiological  problems  are  thrust 
aside,  experimental  investigations  are  unnecessary;  histology  is  to  him  sim-- 
ply  microscopical  anatomy  and  he  fails  to  understand  its  efforts  to  discover 
the  phenomena  of  metabolism  in  the  elementary  parts  of  the  body.  Even 
embryology,  which  has  nevertheless  made  such  weighty  contributions  to 
the  theories  of  descent,  is  given  no  independent  position,  but  is  recommended 
to  adjust  itself  carefully  to  the  results  of  the  comparisons  between  the  out- 
grown organs.  But,  owing  to  the  fact  that  these  investigations  into  the  prob- 
lem of  origin  can,  of  course,  never  be  verified,  Gegenbaur's  research  work 
proves  in  reality  to  be  a  theoretical  speculation,  which  differs  from  that  of 
idealistic  natural  philosophy  only  in  appearance,  but  not  in  reality.  Gegen- 
baur's archipterygium  and  Owen's  archetype  are  practically  alike  fictitious, 
only  that  the  former  is  believed  to  have  existed  some  time  in  the  beginning 
of  the  ages,  whereas  the  latter  had  its  existence  located  in  the  ideal  world. 
But  Gegenbaur  and  his  school  are  the  last  people  to  attribute  unreality  to 
their  primal  types;  provided  one  could  once  get  the  evolutionary  series  in 
order  and  the  gaps  filled  up  with  suitably  reconstructed  forms,  it  could  be 
urged  that  the  primal  type  had  as  real  an  existence  as  if  it  had  actually  been 
dug  up  out  of  one  of  the  earliest  fossiliferous  deposits.  Here  is  undoubtedly 
demonstrated  an  intellectual  contact  with  the  romantic  natural  philosophy, 
and  Gegenbaur  himself  was  without  doubt  influenced  from  that  quarter;  that 
he  as  a  thinker  should  have  been  approved  by  the  surviving  representatives 
of  Hegelianism  was  in  this  respect  striking  enough,  and,  as  a  matter  of  fact, 
he  himself  has  clearly  expressed  his  sympathies  for  the  romantic  tendency 
—  Goethe's  morphological  schemes  found  in  him  a  warm  admirer;  the  for- 
mer's and  Oken's  theory  of  the  skull's  being  formed  of  vertebra  is  referred 
to  with  unreserved  acceptance,  in  spite  of  its  not  being  tenable  any  longer. 
The  worst  of  such  evolutional  constructions,  however,  is  that  they  are  never 
allowed  to  live  long  undisturbed,  owing  to  the  discovery  of  fresh  facts,  and 
Gegenbaur's  life's  work  has  to  a  great  extent  had  to  suffer  that  fate.  His 
archipterygium  theory  was  soon  supplanted  by  another,  which  derived  the 
extremities  from  a  lateral  fin  instead  of  from  the  gill-bones,  and  which  perhaps 
nowadays  has  most  supporters.  Besides,  palasontological  finds  in  recent  years 
have  proved  that  the  earliest  amphibious  types  had  seven  digital  bones  in- 
stead of  the  five  that  Gegenbaur  assumed.  Further,  it  has  been  shown  in  our 
own  day  that  the  earliest  fossil  fishes  possessed  a  cranium  of  bone,  where- 
fore the  theory  of  the  shark's  cartilaginous  cranium  as  a  primal  type  is  no 
longer  tenable.^  In  certain  other  cases,  too,  he  has  been  alternately  right 

^  For  further  reference  to  these  questions  see:  Braus,  "Die  Enttvkklung  der  Form  der  Ex- 
tranitdteri"  in  O.  Hertwig's  Handbuch  der  Engwkklungslehre  der  Wirbeltiere;  Hans  Steiner,  "Die 
Entwicklung  des  Vogelfiugelskelettes,"  in  Acta  Zoologica  (Stockholm,  1912.);  E.  STENSio,Triassic  Fishes 
from  Spitzbergen  (Vienna,  192.1);  and  the  literature  referred  to  in  those  works. 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  503 

and  wrong,  according  as  new  facts  have  come  to  life.  Thanks,  however,  to 
his  lirm  convictions  and  will-power,  Gegenbaur  succeeded  in  compelling  a 
whole  generation  to  follow  his  line  of  thought.  Research  on  the  subject  of 
origin  was  regarded  as  the  most  important  function  of  science,  and  thus, 
to  quote  his  foremost  and  most  independent  disciple,  Oscar  Hertwig,  hy- 
pothesis was  made  the  main  point  of  evolution  in  science.  And  it  must  be 
admitted  that  these  theoretical  speculations  on  the  problem  of  descent  have 
had  a  highly  stimulating  effect  upon  morphological  research;  a  number  of 
practical  discoveries  of  the  greatest  value  and  of  the  highest  significance  for 
the  development  of  biology  have  been  made  by  the  Gegenbaur  school.  Even 
to  this  very  day  comparative  anatomy  contains  problems  still  unsolved  and 
still  attracts  investigators  of  worth.  And  though  the  purely  speculative  prob- 
lems of  descent  do  not,  it  is  true,  predominate  to  such  an  extent  as  formerly, 
the  presupposed  common  origin  nevertheless  still  forms  the  basis  on  which 
rest  present-day  homological  investigations.  But  comparative  anatomy 
has  certainly  had  to  abandon  its  monopoly  of  biology  and  to  recognize  other 
biological  tendencies  and  methods  as  being  equally  justified  in  their 
existence. 

Furbringer  on  the  system  of  birds 
Of  Gegenbaur's  disciples  the,  majority  naturally  came  from  Germany,  but 
students  also  flocked  to  his  institute  from  Scandinavia,  England,  and  Russia. 
Chief  of  these  was  Max  Furbringer.  Born  in  1846,  he  eventually  joined 
Gegenbaur  as  a  pupil  at  Jena-and  accompanied  him  to  Heidelberg  as  pro- 
sector. Having  for  a  time  been  professor  at  Amsterdam  and  Jena,  he  succeeded 
his  master  at  Heidelberg  and  faithfully  preserved  the  latter's  traditions.  He 
carried  out  comparative  investigations  in  many  fields;  the  excretal  organs 
of  the  vertebrates  as  compared  with  those  of  the  Annelida,  and  the  evolution 
of  the  scapular  regions  are  two  of  his  best-known  contributions  to  compara- 
tive anatomy.  He  is  chiefly  to  be  remembered,  however,  for  his  Untersuch- 
ungen  ziif  Morphologie  und  Systematik  der  Vogel,  a  monumental  work  in  both 
size  and  content.  The  first  half  of  it  consists  of  a  comparative  study  on  the 
Gegenbaur  model  of  the  region  of  the  breast,  shoulder,  and  wing  through- 
out the  whole  order  of  birds.  To  this  is  added  a  general  systematic  section 
setting  forth  the  natural  bird-system  based  on  a  comprehensive  comparative 
investigation  of  representatives  of  all  the  bird  families.  This  system,  which 
is  now  universally  accepted,  has  entirely  re-formed  the  bird  class;  the  old 
orders  are  for  the  most  part  exploded  —  the  owls,  for  instance,  are  trans- 
ferred to  the  nightjars;  the  falcons  and  the  vultures  are  placed  next  to  the 
petrels,  herons,  and  storks  —  an  example  of  how  intensive  anatomical  in- 
vestigations may  give  to  the  family  relationships  an  entirely  different  value 
from  that  of  ancient  tradition.  One  of  Fiirbringer's  advantages  is  that  he 
avoids  the  fanciful  elements  in  the  descent  theories  in  which  his  age  other- 
wise abounds;  he  investigates  the  extant  birds,  but  produces  no  reconstructed 


504  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

middle-forms  and  archetypes,  letting  the  scientific  material  that  actually 
exists  speak  for  itself.  His  method  thus  acquires  a  soundness  that  has  given 
to  his  results  a  lasting  value.  He  died  in  1910. 

Hubrecht  on  phytogeny 
Gegenbaur  had  a  far  more  imaginative  disciple  in  the  person  of  the  Dutch- 
man A.  A.  W.  Hubrecht  (1853-1915),  a  professor  at  Utrecht.  In  his  younger 
days  he  was  occupied  mostly  with  the  invertebrates,  especially  the  worms, 
but  he  afterwards  devoted  himself  entirely  to  the  evolution  of  the  Mam- 
malia. In  this  field  he  made  valuable  contributions  by  collecting  material 
in  the  course  of  expeditions  in  tropical  countries  and  by  investigating,  with 
special  reference  to  their  embryonic  development,  a  large  number  of  rare  and 
little-known  animal  forms.  On  the  basis  of  this  material  he  speculates  deeply 
upon  the  origin  of  the  Vertebrata  from  lower  animal  forms,  producing  a 
number  of  theories , that  diverge  considerably  from  what  the  earlier  evolu- 
tionists regarded  as  indisputable  truth.  The  sharks,  for  instance,  he  places 
for  palasontological  reasons  in  an  isolated  position  in  the  system  —  that  is 
to  say,  in  direct  opposition  to  Gegenbaur's  view  —  one  of  many  proofs  of 
how  fresh  facts  in  this  sphere  have  produced  fresh  difficulties,  which  it  has 
not  been  possible  to  solve  with  uniform  results. 

A  complete  account  of  the  works  produced  by  the  pupils  of  Gegenbaur 
or  in  his  spirit  would  fill  a  volume;  even  in  modern  times  comparative  anat- 
omy is  largely  under  the  influence  of  his  method.  Pupils  had  flocked  to  his 
laboratory  from  all  parts  of  the  world.  In  the  following  chapter  will  also 
be  mentioned  some  pupils  of  Gegenbaur,  who  in  their  younger  days  followed 
in  his  footsteps,  but  in  later  years  struck  out  new  paths  of  their  own,  some- 
times with  brilliant  success. 

Even  the  man  who  was  in  closest  touch  with  Gegenbaur  in  his  best 
days  and  who  exercised  most  influence  on  him,  just  as  he  was  most  in- 
fluenced by  him,  went  his  ov/n  way  towards  the  end;  this  was  Haeckel,  a 
man  who  gave  to  Darwinism  a  peculiar  stamp,  extremely  characteristic  of 
the  age,  and  who  contributed  much  to  its  success,  though  perhaps  still  more 
to  bringing  it  into  discredit. 


CHAPTER    XIV 


HAECKEL    AND     MONISM 


ERNST  Heinrich  Haeckel  was  born  at  Potsdam  in  1834.  His  father  had 
taken  part  as  a  volunteer  in  the  Prussian  War  of  Independence  against 
Napoleon,  and  afterwards,  having  adopted  a  public  career,  he  ad- 
vanced to  the  rank  of  " Regierungsrat."  His  mother  was  the  daughter  of  a 
Civil  Servant,  who  had  been  dismissed  from  his  post  and  arrested  for  having 
opposed  the  French  conqueror.  His  parents'  home,  in  spite  of  its  bureau- 
cratic character,  had  nevertheless  preserved  the  liberal-minded  traditions  of 
earlier  times  and  the  literary  interests  acquired  in  the  days  of  greatness  of 
the  German  world  of  letters.  Young  Ernst  received  his  school  education  in 
a  provincial  gymnasium,  where,  as  he  himself  says,  mathematics  were  neg- 
lected for  philosophy  and  the  classical  languages.  Even  when  grown  up, 
he  still  enjoyed  reading  Homer  in  the  original  and  throughout  his  life  de- 
lighted in  interlarding  his  writings  with  Greek  terms.  His  greatest  pleasure, 
however,  he  found  in  nature,  both  in  reality  and  in  poetry;  he  was  a  keen 
botanist  and  at  the  same  time  read  Goethe's  works,  Humboldt's  travels, 
and  Schleiden's  popular  writings.  He  was  especially  interested  in  Schlei- 
den  and  was  very  anxious  to  go  to  Jena  in  order  to  be  trained  as  a  botanist 
under  him.  After  he  had  matriculated,  in  1851,  however,  his  father  insisted 
upon  his  going  to  Wiirzburg  to  study  medicine.  He  spent  two  years  there 
and,  in  spite  of  his  dislike  for  professional  studies,  devoted  himself  with 
interest  to  anatomy  and  histology  under  KoUiker  and  to  pathology  under 
Virchow.  He  then  spent  one  year  in  Berlin  studying  under  J.  Miiller,  whom 
he  regarded  as  his  true  master  and  who  inspired  him  with  a  love  for  marine 
research,  particularly  in  regard  to  the  lower  animals.  Having  been  for  some 
time  assistant  to  Virchow,  he  went  on  an  expedition  to  the  Mediterranean 
at  the  suggestion  of  Kolliker  and  Gegenbaur  and  collected  at  Messina  ma- 
terial for  his  first  important  work.  Die  Radiolarien,  which  resulted  in  his 
being  called,  upon  the  recommendation  of  Gegenbaur,  to  the  chair  of  zool- 
ogy at  Jena  in  i86i.  There  he  worked  until  his  resignation,  in  1909,  after 
which  he  lived  for  another  ten  years,  continuing  his  literary  work  until 
he  died,  in  1919. 

The  life  which  falls  within  these  dates  is  without  doubt  one  of  the  most 
remarkable  during  the  epoch  just  closed;  there  are  not  many  personalities 
who  have  so  powerfully  influenced  the  development  of  human  culture  — 

505 


5o6  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

and  that,  too,  in  many  different  spheres  —  as  Haeckel.  He  has  been  much 
disputed  —  now  praised  to  the  skies,  now  vilely  abused.  As  a  matter  of  fact, 
it  is  not  at  all  easy  to  grasp  the  true  value  of  his  life's  work.  No  important 
scientific  discovery  attaches  to  his  name,  and  the  ideas  he  promulgated  are 
largely  borrowed  from  others.  The  works  that  once  brought  him  fame  are 
now  hopelessly  out  of  date,  but  it  must  be  admitted  that  much  in  them  has 
now  been  incorporated  in  our  general  knowledge.  The  idea  of  evolution,  in 
the  form  given  to  it  by  Darwin,  found  in  Haeckel  its  most  devoted  cham- 
pion; his  personality  and  his  trend  of  thought  have  set  their  mark  on  the 
elaboration  of  this  theory,  especially  on  the  continent  of  Europe,  and  they 
are  therefore  worthy  of  closer  examination. 

Light  is  thrown  on  Haeckel 's  early  development  by  two  collections  of 
letters,  which  have  since  been  published,  the  one  addressed  to  his  parents 
in  his  student  days  at  Wiirzburg,  the  other  to  his  betrothed  during  his  Ital- 
ian journey.  This  development  is  highly  characteristic  of  the  generation  to 
which  he  belonged  and  therefore  explains  in  some  degree  how  it  was  that 
he  acquired  such  an  influence  over  his  age.  Young  Haeckel  at  Wiirzburg 
is  by  no  means  a  German  "corps"  student  of  the  ordinary  type;  on  the 
contrary,  he  was  a  very  nice  youth,  abhorring  duels  and  drinking-bouts, 
diligently  attending  lectures  and  exercises,  writing  tender  and  affectionate 
letters  to  his  parents,  regularly  attending  church,  and  comforting  his  lonely 
hours  with  pious  thoughts.  True,  he  could  cause  his  parents  anxiety  on  ac- 
count of  his  dislike  for  medicine  and  his  propensity  for  unpractical  dreaming, 
but,  on  the  other  hand,  he  was  always  ready,  with  a  somewhat  rhetorical 
and  precocious  eloquence,  to  confess  his  weaknesses  to  his  old  parents  and 
to  promise  to  make  them  happy  in  the  future.  The  most  striking  feature  of 
these  letters  is  their  Christian  piety,  which  contrasts  strongly  with  the 
hatred  that  Haeckel  felt  for  Christianity  in  later  years;  the  youth  expresses 
his  indignation  against  Karl  Vogt  and  other  "materialists"  of  the  time  in 
terms  that  were  afterwards  used  almost  word  for  word  against  himself.  It 
is,  of  course,  the  opinions  held  in  his  parents'  home  that  here  recur  —  the 
old-fashioned,  serious,  moral-religious  atmosphere  pervading  the  home  of 
a  Prussian  Civil  Servant,  with  its  literary  and  patriotic  traditions.  At  Wiirz- 
burg young  Haeckel  was  enraged  at  the  Catholic  propaganda,  which  was 
carried  on  at  that  time,  during  the  period  of  reaction  after  1848,  with  extreme 
ruthlessness,  and  at  the  same  time  as  his  father  was  deploring  the  unhappy 
political  situation.  In  the  letters  from  Italy  the  whole  aspect  is  altered;  that 
was  in  1859,  ^^^  Y^^^  ^^  ^^^  liberation  of  Italy.  Haeckel  is  full  of  enthusiasm 
over  Germany's  unification  and  raves  against  her  opponents,  vassal  princes 
and  Prussian  junkers,  who  were  serving  the  reactionary  politics  of  Austria. 
His  religious  attitude  is  now  something  quite  different;  Christianity  has  been 
superseded  by  a  worship  of  humanity  in  general,  combined  with  enthusiasm 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  507 

for  the  enlightened  minds  of  classical  antiquity  and  hatred  against  the 
ecclesiastical  reaction  —  a  very  common  trend  of  thought  at  that  time  — 
which  found  expression  in  many  quarters  in  literature,  as,  for  instance,  in 
the  works  of  Haeckel's  contemporary  fellow-countryman  Paul  Heyse.  His 
biographers  declare  that  Haeckel's  religious  change  of  front  took  place  in 
the  course  of  spiritual  struggles,  but  there  is  little  trace  of  them  in  his  letters; 
it  would  appear  more  likely  that  with  him,  as  with  countless  others,  reli- 
gious free-thinking  was  induced  by  political  independence  of  thought;  it 
w^as  difficult  in  those  days  to  reconcile  Christian  belief  and  political  liberal- 
mindedness,  owing  to  the  Church's  intimate  connexion  with  the  reactionary 
forces  in  society  and  her  obstinate  resistance  to  all  movements  of  reform. 
Through  his  free-thinking,  however,  Haeckel  lost  that  conviction  which 
had  kept  him  going  before,  and  he  felt  himself  beginning  to  doubt  the  possi- 
bility of  penetrating  any  deeper  into  the  essence  of  natural  phenomena. 

Haeckel  embraces  Danvinism 
That  guiding  line  for  his  thoughts  which  he  thus  lost  Haeckel  rediscovered 
when  he  made  the  acquaintance  of  Darwin's  theory.  In  Germany  as  in  Eng- 
land this  theory  had  been  received  with  mixed  feelings;  instances  of  this 
have  been  given  above.  Haeckel  at  once  became  an  ardent  supporter  of  the 
new  doctrine;  in  it  he  found  not  only  the  means  to  understand  existence, 
but  also  the  confirmation  of  the  progress  he  desired  to  find  in  it.  It  was 
mainly  through  his  promulgation  of  it  that  Darwinism  became  a  watch- 
word for  all  supporters  of  the  idea  of  a  liberal-minded  development  in  the 
sphere  of  social  and  cultural  life,  and  obviously  an  abomination  to  its  op- 
ponents, the  clerical  and  conservative  elements  in  the  community.  The  course 
of  social  development  in  Germany  took  an  unexpected  turn,  however;  the 
unification  of  the  country,  the  long-cherished  dream  of  the  free-minded,  was 
brought  to  reality  through  Bismarck,  but  in  such  a  manner  that  the  power 
of  the  princes  and  the  junkers  was  preserved.  It  was  not  thus  that  the  lib- 
erals had  imagined  things  would  turn  out;  their  opinion  now  became  divided; 
the  majority  of  them  sided  with  the  new  work  of  unification  and  its  leaders, 
while  a  smaller  group  still  insisted  upon  their  demand  for  liberal-minded 
social  reforms.  To  this  latter  group  belonged  some  of  the  leading  scientists 
in  Germany,  and  among  them  Haeckel,  although,  living  as  he  did  in  the 
small  town  of  Jena,  he  never  took  an  active  part  in  politics.  It  was  with 
all  the  greater  enthusiasm,  then,  that  he  devoted  himself  to  promoting  this 
radical  development  in  the  sphere  of  general  culture,  and  he  rapidly  gained 
a  following  of  people  with  similar  ideas  to  his  own,  who  took  up  the  strug- 
gle against  dogmatic  conservatism  in  both  the  social  and  the  religious  sphere, 
employing  the  evolution  theory  of  Darwinism  as  their  principal  weapon.  Of 
course  the  authorities  viewed  with  anything  but  friendly  eyes  this  natural- 
scientific  opposition,  with  its  social  tinge;  the  employment  of  these  hostile 


5o8  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

elements  in  the  government  service  was  opposed  with  all  their  power,  and 
many  of  the  radical  party  lived  for  the  rest  of  their  days  as  independent 
writers.  Haeckel  himself,  however,  was  protected  by  the  liberal-minded 
Weimar  Government  from  all  unpleasant  consequences  and  was  thus  en- 
abled, though  a  professor,  to  take  a  leading  part  in  the  struggle.  It  goes 
without  saying  that  the  natural-scientific  contents  of  this  doctrine  were  in- 
fluenced by  the  political  and  social  views  of  the  antagonists,  but,  on  the 
other  hand,  this  circumstance  contributed  towards  making  Darwinism  popu- 
ular  and  creating  a  widespread  interest  in  its  problems  and  arguments.  Before 
proceeding  to  describe  the  part  Haeckel  played  in  this  struggle,  however, 
we  must  take  a  glance  at  the  subject  of  research  that  he  made  his  own  and 
determine  how  far  his  general  scientific  conclusions  were  based  thereon. 

His  work  on  Kadiolaria 
Haeckel  began  as  a  microscopist;  when  he  was  at  Wiirzburg  his  father  gave 
him  a  microscope  and  he  could  not  find  words  to  express  his  delight  at  all 
that  he  saw  in  it.  In  fact,  both  the  papers  he  wrote  for  his  degree  were  on 
microscopical  subjects  —  his  dissertation  on  the  tissues  of  the  river  cray- 
fish, and  an  essay  on  the  pathological  changes  of  the  venous  system;  two 
school  essays,  the  former  worked  out  under  the  guidance  of  J.  Miiller,  the 
latter  under  that  of  Virchow  and  noteworthy  as  being  Haeckel's  only  spe- 
cialized investigation  in  the  sphere  of  the  vertebrates  —  both  papers  credit- 
able in  their  form  and  contents,  but  not  very  original.  His  appearance  as  an 
independent  investigator  is  marked  by  his  monumental  work  on  the  Radio- 
laria,  which  is  without  doubt  his  best.  It  is  dedicated  to  the  memory  of 
J.  Miiller  and  is  written  in  his  spirit;  he  was,  in  fact,  his  foremost  predecessor 
in  that  field.  It  contains  about  one  hundred  and  fifty  new  and  carefully  de- 
scribed and  illustrated  species,  as  well  as  abundant  material  derived  from 
observations  of  their  structure  and  mode  of  life.  It  makes  what  were  at  the 
time  valuable  contributions  to  the  problem  of  the  biology  of  single-celled 
animals,  and    moreover,  the  identity  established  by  Max  Schultze  of  the 
protoplasm  in  the  higher  animals  and  the  sarcode,  which  had  already  been 
described  by  Dujardin,  is  hereby  confirmed  with  fresh  proofs.  In  connexion 
therewith  several  cytological  observations  are  quoted  that  are  of  consider- 
able general  interest  —  on  the  phenomena  of  currents  and  the  manifestations 
of  assimilation  in  pseudopods  and  protoplasm,  and  also  on  the  power  of 
cells  to  absorb  solid  bodies.  Haeckel  has  observed  how  the  blood  corpuscles 
in  a  mollusc  absorb  indigo-particles  injected  into  the  blood,  but  he  did  not 
follow  up  this  important  fact  any  further,  it  being  left  to  MetschnikofF  a 
couple  of  decades  later  to  take  up  the  subject  and  make  it  the  basis  of  his 
theory  of  phagocytes.  In  regard  to  classification,  Haeckel  tries  to  found 
a  natural  system  based  on  affinity;  it  is  in  connexion  with  this  that  he  an- 
nounces for  the  first  time,  though  tentatively,  his  association  with  Darwin's 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  509 

theory  and  endeavours  to  find  a  primal  form  from  which  the  rest  of  the 
Radiolaria  could  be  derived.  On  the  whole,  however,  the  system  was  set 
up  in  the  traditional  way. 

Later  on  Haeckel  continued  the  work  on  the  Radiolaria,  adding  two 
new  parts  (1887-8),  and  in  the  special  section  of  these  he  describes  several 
hundred  new  species,  which  are  splendidly  illustrated.  The  complaint  has 
been  made  against  his  descriptions  that  they  keep  too  much  to  the  skeleton, 
and  against  the  illustrations  that  they  are  over-simplified,  but  on  the  whole 
both  text  and  illustrations  compare  creditably  with  the  former  volumes  of 
the  work.  The  general  section  of  the  new  work,  on  the  other  hand,  is  strongly 
characterized  by  the  natural-philosophical  speculations  which  Haeckel  had 
produced  in  the  mean  while,  and  to  which  we  shall  revert  later  on. 

His  work  on  sponges 
Another  field  that  Haeckel  made  the  subject  of  systematic  research  was  the 
sponges,  of  which  he  dealt  especially  with  the  Calcarea  in  his  monograph 
Die  Kalkschwdmme,  of  1871.  In  this  work  he  has  recorded  his  most  consist- 
ent attempt  to  create  a  Darwinistic  classificational  system  —  a  true  "nat- 
ural" system  based  on  descent,  instead  of  the  old  "artificial"  system.  The 
group  had  been  very  little  investigated  and  the  facts  contributed  by  Haeckel 
are  of  some  importance,  considering  the  age  when  they  were  published,  al- 
though they  have,  of  course,  undergone  a  good  deal  of  modification  as  a 
result  of  subsequent  research.  On  the  other  hand,  this  natural  system  has 
its  curious  features.  The  order  of  the  Calcarea  is  divided  into  families  ac- 
cording to  the  shape  of  the  canals  in  the  walls  of  the  sponge,  and  this  mode 
of  classification  has  been  retained  by  subsequent  naturalists.  The  division 
into  genera,  on  the  other  hand,  is  based  on  the  calcareous  spicules  of  the 
skeleton.  These  two  features,  the  canals  and  the  calcareous  skeleton,  are,  ac- 
cording to  Haeckel,  the  only  systematically  employable  elements,  for  their 
form  is  inherited,  whereas  the  artificial  system  has  taken  account  of  mouth 
formation  and  colony  or  solitary  life,  which  are  dependent  upon  "adapta- 
tion." No  evidence,  however,  is  offered  in  proof  of  these  statements,  and 
it  certainly  does  seem  decidedly  artificial  to  base  the  division  into  genera 
upon  one  single  character,  without  the  slightest  attempt  to  test  the  theory 
by  means  of  comparative  morphology.  Nevertheless,  the  system  has  its  pe- 
culiar interest  as  an  attempt  to  separate  entirely  from  the  Linnasan  system. 
The  terms  hitherto  employed  have  been  entirely  abolished;  instead  of  "  gen- 
era" he  uses  "generic  varieties,"  besides  which  there  are  differentiated  and 
nominated  "specific,  connective,  and  transitory  varieties"  or  "initial,  bind- 
ing, and  transitional  species."  One  must  admit  the  logical  consistency  of 
this  attempt  to  get  away  from  Linnasanism;  the  latter  rests  entirely  upon 
the  immutability  of  the  species,  and  if  it  is  once  denied,  it  is  necessary  really 
to  set  up  a  new  system  with  a  different  idea  of  species.  Haeckel's  attempt. 


5IO  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

however,  has  proved  unsuccessful  and  has  failed  to  gain  the  acceptance  of 
more  recent  systematists;  in  his  own  later  systematic  works  he  himself  uses 
the  old  traditional  terms  of  genus  and  species,  in  spite  of  all  the  assurances 
of  Darwinism. 

On  the  medusa 
A  THIRD  subject  in  which  Haeckel  worked  as  a  systematist  is  the  medusa; 
here,  too,  he  summarized  his  results  in  a  monograph  of  huge  dimensions, 
entitled  Das  System  der  Medusen  (1879),  containing  a  large  number  of  newly- 
described  forms  and  a  system  of  classification  that  in  part  is  of  some  value. 
In  particular,  the  two  main  groups  that  he  classifies  in  it,  the  Craspedota 
and  the  Acraspeda,  have  been  retained  by  later  systematists.  On  the  other 
hand,  it  has  been  found  upon  examination  that  some  of  the  diagnoses  of 
species  are  full  of  serious  mistakes,  which  is  explained  by  the  fact  that  Haeckel 
has  in  general  a  far  keener  eye  for  the  demarcation  of  the  large  groups  in  the 
system  than  for  genera  and  species;  careful  detailed  examination  was  never 
his  strong  point. 

There  is  still  another  group  of  life -forms  which  engaged  Haeckel 's  in- 
terest and  which  perhaps  appealed  more  to  him  than  any  other  —  namely, 
the  order  Monera.  To  this  order  he  refers  single-celled  organisms  without 
nucleus  —  that  is,  those  formed  of  only  a  homogeneous  mass.  He  has  de- 
scribed a  great  number  of  these  —  generally  amoeboid  organisms  —  many  of 
them  with  systematic  validity.  Nevertheless,  the  improved  microscopy  of 
modern  times  has  actually  discovered  in  the  majority  of  these  a  nuclear  sub- 
stance, either  in  the  form  of  a  single  nucleus  or  divided  into  minute  parti- 
cles, and  modern  biology,  which  has  learnt  by  experience  to  count  the 
nuclear  substance  among  the  essential  components  in  a  cell  capable  of  life, 
has  in  general  presupposed  the  existence  of  the  nucleus  even  in  cells  in  which, 
owing  to  its  minimal  dimensions  or  indistinct  cell-content,  it  has  not  been 
possible  to  confirm  its  existence.  Haeckel,  however,  stubbornly  held  to  his 
non-nuclear  Monera,  the  existence  of  which  he  regarded  as  an  essential  quali- 
fication of  that  spontaneous  generation  by  which  he  believed  life  to  have 
arisen,  and  which  he  looked  upon  as  "a  logical  postulate  for  philosophical 
natural  science."  This  brings  us  to  Haeckel's  natural-philosophical  specula- 
tions —  that  part  of  his  activities  which,  far  more  than  his  specialized  re- 
search-work, brought  him  both  fame  and  ill  fame. 

The  essentials  of  his  opinion 
As  has  already  been  mentioned,  Haeckel  declared  his  adherence  to  Darwinism 
in  his  work  on  the  Radiolaria.  At  a  scientific  congress  in  1863  he  expounded 
Darwin's  theory  in  a  manner  that  considerably  enhanced  its  success  in  Ger- 
many. The  lecture  really  comprised  a  brief  summary  of  the  Origin  of  Species  — 
of  the  doctrine  of  selection  and  the  struggle  for  existence.  In  its  essentials  the 
argumentation  is  Darwin's  own,  taken  from  the  theory  of  domestic  animals, 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  511 

from  animal  geography  and  paleontology;  but  striking  indeed  are  the  radi- 
cal conclusions  that  Haeckel  draws  in  regard  to  the  origin  of  man;  they  rep- 
resent what  eventually  became  one  of  his  chief  interests  and  immediately 
caused  a  great  sensation.  There  are  two  more  peculiarities  of  Haeckelian 
thought  that  come  out  clearly  in  this  lecture:  his  political  radicalism,  which 
induces  him  to  call  progress  "a  natural  law  which  no  human  power,  neither 
the  weapons  of  tyrants  nor  the  curses  of  priests,  can  ever  succeed  in  sup- 
pressing" —  the  words  were  uttered  just  at  the  moment  when  the  struggle 
between  Bismarck  and  his  liberal  opponents  waxed  hottest  —  and  his  pre- 
dilection for  the  romantic  natural  philosophy,  which  makes  him  praise 
Goethe,  GeofTroy  Saint-Hilaire,  and  Oken  as  "deep-thinking  men  possess- 
ing prophetic  inspiration,"  and  as  supporters  of  "philosophical  theories  of 
evolution"  foreshadowing  Darwin.  These  elements  —  Darwin's  theory  of 
evolution,  political  radicalism,  and  romantic  natural  philosophy  —  really 
impress  the  whole  of  Haeckel's  subsequent  pronouncements  with  their  char- 
acter, whether  they  concern  "general  morphology,"  "cosmic  riddles,"  or 
"artificial  forms  in  nature."  The  doctrine  of  natural  selection  forms  the 
groundwork,  which  he  never  takes  steps  to  reconstruct  or  add  to,  however 
great  the  progress  made  by  research.  His  political  radicalism  mostly  finds 
expression  in  a  violent  hatred  of  priests  and  Christianity,  but  also,  though 
not  so  apparent,  in  opposition  to  the  undue  interference  of  government  au- 
thorities. The  influence  of  romantic  natural  philosophy  comes  out  most 
clearly  in  his  utter  incapacity  to  grasp  the  relativity  and  limitations  of 
human  knowledge,  which  Herbert  Spencer  among  others  so  forcefully  and 
repeatedly  emphasized;  Haeckel's  way  of  constantly  trying  to  solve  the 
"riddles  of  the  universe"  is  far  more  reminiscent  of  Schelling  than  of  the 
contemporary  positivist  trend  of  thought,  just  as  his  overbearing  self-con- 
fidence and  his  abusive  polemics  are  more  representative  of  romanticism  than 
of  exact  research.  Thus  through  Haeckel's  influence  romantic  natural  philos- 
ophy experienced  a  revival  in  the  century  of  exact  science. 

His  Generelle  Morphologic 
Haeckel  struck  his  great  blow  for  "philosophical  scientific  research"  with 
his  Generelle  Morphologie  der  Organismen,  with  its  subtitle  Kritiscbe  Grundxiige 
der  mechanischen  Wissenschaft  von  den  entivickelten  Formen  der  Organismen,  be- 
griindet  durch  die  Desxendenztheorie ,  which  was  published  in  1866.  The  first 
part  of  the  work  was  dedicated  to  Gegenbaur,  the  friend  with  whom  he 
had  constantly  exchanged  ideas  and  who  had  inspired  much  of  its  contents. 
The  latter  part  of  the  book  is  dedicated  to  Darwin,  Goethe,  and  Lamarck, 
those  "scientific  thinkers  who  founded  the  theory  of  descent."  As  this  trio 
vras  afterwards  constantly  referred  to  by  Haeckel,  it  may  be  worth  while 
examining  the  combination  more  closely.  Lamarck  and  Darwin  may  both 
be  regarded  as  founders  of  the  theory  of  descent,  although  the  latter,  it  is 


5Ii  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

true,  positively  rejected  the  former's  explanation  of  nature  and  was  but  little 
concerned  with  its  materialistic  speculation.  But  the  idea  of  seeing  in  Goethe 
a  precursor  of  a  "  mechanical  science  of  the  organisms ' '  certainly  needs  some 
explanation.  The  great  poet  was  universally  looked  upon  by  his  age  as  an 
idealistic  natural  philosopher;  the  biologists  who  acclaimed  him  did  so  under 
that  assumption  and  he  himself  had  adduced  " geistige  Krdfte"  as  a  cause  of 
the  origin  of  and  modifications  in  the  life-forms,  and  otherwise  also  given 
utterance  to  markedly  spiritualistic  views.  Whence,  then,  Haeckel's  asser- 
tion to  the  contrary?  The  reason  is  no  doubt  to  be  found  partly  in  Haeckel's 
own  natural-philosophical  turn  of  mind,  which  could  never  be  induced  to 
take  the  idea  of  "mechanism"  in  existence  really  seriously,  and  partly  in 
the  position  Goethe  enjoyed  in  the  cultural  life  of  the  period  —  his  influ- 
ence as  a  poet  and  a  cultural  personality,  which  was  highly  admired  even 
in  Haeckel's  home  and  circle,  and  which  was  opposed  by  no  one  beyond 
the  extreme-orthodox  ecclesiastical  authorities,  who  found  free-thinking  and 
libertinism  in  his  poetry,  something  which  in  its  turn  increased  the  sym- 
pathy of  the  liberals  for  the  really  somewhat  conservative  poet-minister. 
And  the  liberal  opposition  became  once  and  for  all  one  of  the  leading  mo- 
tives in  Haeckel's  system  of  thought. 

The  very  choice  of  subject  and  the  consequent  title  of  the  work  —  Gen- 
eral Morphology  —  is  also  obviously  borrowed  direct  from  Goethe,  who,  in 
fact,  invented  the  word  in  question  and  from  whom  Haeckel  also  derived 
the  philosophical  conception  of  morphology  that  he  develops  in  the  book. 
For,  strictly  speaking,  Haeckel  was  no  professional  morphologist  in  the 
modern  sense.  He  had  till  then  worked  almost  exclusively  on  the  classifi- 
cation of  single-celled  animals;  and  in  the  comparative  anatomy  of  the  higher 
animals,  especially  the  Vertebrata,  he  practically  never  carried  out  any  spe- 
cial investigations,  at  least  none  of  which  the  results  have  been  published. 
That  he  nevertheless  based  his  theoretical  speculation  not  on  classification, 
as  Darwin  himself  did,  but  on  morphology,  was  no  doubt  due,  as  hinted 
above,  to  his  admiration  for  Goethe,  but  also,  of  course,  to  the  influence 
exerted  on  him  by  his  friend  Gegenbaur,  who  was  no  doubt  responsible  for 
the  best  contributions  of  facts  in  the  work.  But  a  speculatively  inclined 
student  who  concerns  himself  with  second-hand  knowledge  will,  of  course, 
easily  succumb  to  the  temptation  to  let  his  imagination  get  the  better  of 
his  critical  sense  —  a  fact  that  finds  strong  confirmation  in  Haeckel. 

His  ternary  division  of  nature 
The  General  Morphology  begins  with  a  chapter  on  the  relation  between  mor- 
phology and  other  sciences.  First  comes  an  assertion  that  every  natural  object 
possesses  three  qualities:  matter,  form,  and  energy  or  function.  In  connexion 
with  this  idea  natural  science  is  divided  into  three  disciplines:  chemistry, 
or  "  Stojflehre,"  morphology,  a.nd  physics,  or  '^  Kraftlehre."  Then  the  knowledge 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  513 

of  inorganic  nature  is  divided  into  mineralogy,  hydrology,  and  meteorology; 
and  biology  is  divided  into  xpology,  -protistology,  and  botany.  Thus  we  have 
here  four  threefold  groups,  all  extremely  ill-grounded.  One  is  tempted  to 
assume  that  it  is  really  Schelling's  romantic  ternary  mysticism  haunting 
him  here  —  though,  of  course,  indirectly  and  unconsciously.  The  division 
into  plants,  animals,  and  protista  is,  of  course,  entirely  useless,  nor  did  it 
ever  succeed;  instead  of  one  vague  line  of  demarcation  such  as  that  between 
plants  and  animals,  we  here  get  two.  Then  the  aims  and  means  of  morphol- 
ogy are  described;  the  aim  is  a  mechanically  causal  explanation  of  the  forms 
and  phenomena  of  life,  whereby  a  "monistic"  explanation  of  the  universe 
will  be  made  possible,  which  indeed,  it  is  declared,  is  already  so  in  the 
other  natural  sciences,  but  in  biology  is  for  the  time  being  replaced  by  a 
"vitalistic"  and  "dualistic"  view,  the  incorrigibility  of  which  is  depicted 
in  vivid  colours.  The  means  of  attaining  this  monistic  explanation  of  nature 
is  declared  to  be  by  "philosophical  thinking,"  by  the  aid  of  which,  facts 
should  be  capable  of  interpretation,  whereas  the  mere  observation  of  nat- 
ural phenomena  is  deeply  despised.  As  a  matter  of  fact,  this  philosophizing 
constitutes  Haeckel's  great  weakness,  which  gradually  induces  him  to  aban- 
don exact  research.  The  insistence  upon  interpreting  the  phenomena  of  life 
according  to  purely  mechanical  laws  is  in  itself  fully  justified;  physiology 
had  already  pursued  that  method  before  Haeckel's  time,  and  his  claim  that 
the  other  branches  of  biology  should  follow  its  example  was  quite  reason- 
able. But  Haeckel's  great  mistake  lay  in  his  refusal  to  realize  and  acknowl- 
edge the  limited  possibilities  of  the  mechanical  explanation  of  nature.  He 
certainly  admits  in  one  passage  (p.  105)  that  the  human  capacity  for  knowl- 
edge has  its  limits:  that  we  cannot  reach  the  ultimate  grounds  for  a  single 
phenomenon,  and  that  the  origin  of  a  crystal  down  to  its  ultimate  causes  is 
just  as  inexplicable  as  the  origin  of  an  organism.  But  he  does  not  stop  for  a 
moment  to  think  that  in  such  circumstances  natural  philosophy  should  en- 
deavour to  determine  these  limits  and  see  that  they  are  not  exceeded.  Shortly 
after  the  above  admission  he  confidently  asserts  that  no  essential  difference 
between  animate  and  inanimate  exists;  after  making  a  close  comparison  he 
comes  to  the  conclusion  that  the  crystal  and  the  living  cell  are  in  all  respects 
comparable,  as  to  their  physical  and  chemical  composition,  their  growth  and 
individuality.  The  restriction  that  should  follow  from  the  limitation  of  the 
human  capacity  for  knowledge  is  entirely  forgotten.  The  memory  of  it  cer- 
tainly reawakens  now  and  then,  but,  generally  speaking,  he  entertains  a 
blind  faith  in  the  power  of  "mechanical  causality"  to  explain  anything 
whatever. 

Mechanical  interpretation  of  nature 
What  Haeckel  chiefly  bases  his  conviction  upon  as  to  the  unlimited  possi- 
bilities of  the  mechanical  explanation  of  nature  is  Darwin's  theory.  His 


514  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

enthusiasm  for  it  knows  absolutely  no  bounds;  once  he  assures  us  outright 
that,  thanks  to  this  theory,  there  is  now  not  a  single  fact  in  organic  life 
that  cannot  be  explained,  although  many  are  still  unexplained.  This  en- 
thusiasm, indeed,  he  shared  with  the  whole  of  his  generation;  in  a  previous 
chapter  light  has  been  thrown  upon  the  hopes  that  the  selection  theory 
aroused  on  its  first  appearance;  the  fact  that  in  Haeckel  they  reached  such 
dizzy  heights  was  due,  of  course,  to  his  personal  temperament,  in  which 
enthusiasm,  a  naive  self-satisfaction,  and  a  blind  confidence  in  the  correct- 
ness of  his  own  ideas  had  been  the  predominant  features  since  his  youth. 
Otherwise,  he  desired  to  a  certain  extent  to  modify  the  selection  theory 
itself,  in  so  far  as  he  would  define  more  precisely  the  actual  term  "struggle 
for  existence."  He  urges  the  exclusion  of  all  conditions  belonging  to  sur- 
rounding nature;  the  competition  with  other  living  creatures  is  all  that 
should  be  considered  in  this  connexion.  He  further  maintains  the  existence 
of  a  competition  ivithin  the  individual,  between  its  various  parts  —  that  is, 
an  adaptation  of  the  theory  of  correlation  to  Darwinism,  which  was  later 
developed  in  certain  respects  by  others.  And,  finally,  Haeckel  insists,  far 
more  emphatically  than  Darwin,  upon  the  transformation  of  the  individual 
through  the  influence  of  environment  and  the  inheritance  of  the  modifica- 
tions thus  brought  about;  he  defines  evolution  as  a  co-operation  between  an 
"  innerer  Bildungstrieb"  —  heredity  —  and  an  " dusserer  Bildungstrieb"  —  the 
influence  of  environment.  These  expressions,  which  have  a  very  natural- 
philosophical  and  not  a  very  mechanical  sound,  he  borrowed,  as  he  himself 
admits,  from  Goethe's  Pfianzenmefamorpbose,  which  he  considers  represents 
Darwinism  in  mice,  and  which  to  his  mind  still  forms  the  basis  of  plant 
morphology  —  a  view  which  at  that  time  was  shared  by  only  a  few  sup- 
porters of  natural  philosophy,  but  which  has  been  repeated  on  Haeckel's 
authority  up  to  modern  times  by  literary  historians  and  other  non-profes- 
sionals. For  the  rest,  he  attributes  to  Darwinism  an  infinite  mass  of  new 
determinations,  with  their  attendant  terminology.  Haeckel  almost  surpasses 
Linnasus  in  his  mania  for  classifying  and  naming,  but  he  is  entirely  lack- 
ing in  the  incomparable  gift  for  form  that  the  great  systematist  possessed; 
most  of  his  categories  and  nomenclature  have  not  survived  their  originator, 
although  a  number  of  them  have  been  universally  adopted,  as  for  instance, 
the  terms  "ontogeny"  and  "phylogeny,"  the  former  denoting  the  indi- 
vidual's, the  latter  the  race's  development,  and  "  cecology,"  as  an  expression 
denoting  the  relation  of  living  beings  to  their  environment.  Utterly  absurd, 
on  the  other  hand  is  his  "  promorphological "  classification  of  the  life-forms 
according  to  a  symmetrical  plan  intended  still  further  to  confirm  the  alleged 
similarity  between  the  structure  of  crystals  and  organisms;  the  details  of 
this  system,  which,  as  a  matter  of  fact,  give  evidence  of  a  very  superficial 
knowledge  of  the  foundations  of  crystallography,  may  be  compared  with 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  515 

Oken's  wildest  flights  of  imagination;  infusorians,  pollen  granules,  corals, 
flower-spikes,  are  cited,  amongst  other  things,  as  examples  of  the  various 
supposed  crystal-symmetrical  forms.  Undoubtedly  more  successful  is  the  nat- 
ural system  that  he  afterwards  sets  up  for  the  organisms,  wherein  is  employed 
for  the  first  time  the  method,  so  frequently  used  since,  of  representing  by 
means  of  a  graphic  chart  in  the  form  of  a  genealogical  tree  the  mutual  agree- 
ment of  the  different  life-forms,  as  if  derived  from  an  assumed  common  origin. 
Haeckel  has  certainly  had  to  endure  a  good  deal  of  chaff  for  his  genealogical 
trees  and  they  will  not,  of  course,  bear  too  close  examination,  but  it  cannot 
be  denied  that  the  method  itself  has  proved  of  good  service  to  scientific 
works  aiming  at  a  natural  system;  we  need  only  mention  how  Fiirbringer 
employed  it  in  his  great  work  on  the  birds.  Here,  as  in  many  other  respects, 
Haeckel  has  had  a  rousing  and  stimulating  influence  on  subsequent  research. 

Haeckel  idenfifies  spirit  and  matter 
The  genealogical  tree  that  now,  as  henceforth,  interested  Haeckel  most  is, 
however,  that  of  man;  already  at  this  stage  he  sets  forth  the  ideas  concern- 
ing it  that  he  was  later  to  develop  still  further.  From  man  he  proceeds  to 
the  universe  and  God,  and  now  makes  the  entirely  unexpected  assertion  that 
"no  matter  can  be  conceived  without  spirit,  and  no  spirit  without  matter." 
It  is  hard  to  make  out  how  this  idea  is  to  be  reconciled  with  his  earlier  as- 
surance that  every  natural  phenomenon,  both  animate  and  inanimate,  can 
and  is  to  be  explained  mechanically;  ever  since  the  days  of  Galileo,  indeed, 
all  spirits  have  been  outlawed  from  mechanics.  Haeckel,  nevertheless,  makes 
use  of  his  spirit-matter  to  decree  unity  between  God  and  nature  —  a  unity 
which  denotes  true  monism  and  which  admits  of  a  true  divine  worship.  It 
is  again  from  Goethe,  of  course,  that  these  pantheistic  reveries  are  borrowed, 
so  that  in  this  first  philosophical  work  of  Haeckel's,  romantic  idealism  has 
the  last  word. 

Generelle  Morpbologie,  which  in  Haeckel's  own  views  is  his  principal 
speculative  work,  had  but  little  success;  only  one  edition  was  published. 
Darwin,  it  is  true,  was  delighted,  although  he  complained  mildly  of  the 
vehement  style  in  which  the  book  was  written,  but  the  German  biologists 
were  enraged  at  the  natural-philosophical  daring,  the  dilettante  treatment 
of  detail,  and  the  scurrilous  language.  After  some  years  of  silence,  however, 
Haeckel  resumed  his  natural-philosophical  activities,  this  time  in  a  more 
popular  form,  with  the  result  that  he  was  extremely  successful  with  both 
his  series  of  lectures  Naturliche  Schopjungsgeschichte  (1868)  and  his  Anthropo- 
genie  oder  Entivicklungsgeschichte  des  Menscben  (1874);  ^^^  former  work  espe- 
cially became  extraordinarily  popular,  being  translated  into  many  languages, 
and  it  really  represents  perhaps  the  chief  source  of  the  world's  knowledge 
of  Darwinism.  It  reproduces  the  ideas  and  the  arguments  from  Generelle  Aior- 
phologie,  but  in  an  easier  style  and  excluding  his  extensive  speculations  on 


5l6  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

symmetry.  He  gives  instead  a  special  account  of  the  descent  of  man,  which 
Haeckel  regarded  all  along  as  the  centre  point  of  the  theory  of  evolution 
and  of  all  science  in  general.  This  problem  likewise  represents,  as  the  title 
indicates,  the  subject  of  his  Ant hrofo genie,  a  work  of  far  greater  significance 
than  the  History  of  the  Creation  and  certainly  the  one  in  which  Haeckel  has 
set  forth  h'is  most  brilliant  and  most  important  ideas  —  those  of  his  that 
most  deeply  affected  the  development  of  biology.  The  intention  of  the  work 
is  to  give  a  comprehensive  idea  of  the  origin  of  man,  based  on  the  evidence 
of  morphology,  embryology,  and  palaeontology.  Haeckel  definitely  takes  as 
his  starting-point  his  well-known  "biogenetical  principle":  that  the  on- 
togeny not  only  of  man,  but  also  of  every  living  creature  is  a  recapitulation 
of  its  phylogeny;  "the  development  of  the  embryo  is  an  abstract  of  the  his- 
tory of  the  genus."  This  idea  in  itself  is  not  new;  as  we  have  seen,  it  had 
already  been  propounded  by  Meckel,  and  Darwin  gave  it  an  important  place, 
although  it  was  formulated  in  summary  fashion,  in  his  Origin  of  Species.  It 
was  then  taken  up  and  further  elaborated  by  Fritz  Muller  (1811-97),  one 
of  the  more  peculiar  representatives  of  biology  during  last  century. 

Fritz  Muller  on  the  development  of  crayfish 
Born  in  Germany,  Fritz  Muller  had  studied  medicine  —  among  other  things, 
biology  under  J.  Muller  —  but  afterwards  went  out  to  Brazil,  where  he  re- 
mained for  the  rest  of  his  life  in  various  occupations  and  with  varying  for- 
tunes. Having  from  the  very  beginning  been  entirely  won  over  to  Darwin's 
theory,  he  resolved  to  prove  it  by  applying  it  in  detail  to  a  suitable  animal 
group,  for  which  purpose  he  chose  Crustacea,  which  in  his  adopted  country 
exist  in  a  multitude  of  forms.  He  paid  special  attention  to  the  different  types 
of  development  to  be  found  in  closer  related  forms  within  this  class:  the 
river  crayfish  creeps  out  of  the  e§,g  like  its  parents;  the  crabs  have  one  or 
two  larval  forms,  while  the  prawn  has  many  —  a  nauplius  stage  similar  to 
the  larvas  of  the  lowest  Crustacea  described  under  that  name,  a  7j)ea  stage, 
like  that  of  the  crabs,  and  a  my  sis  stage,  like  the  perfected  form  of  the  schiz- 
opod  crayfish.  Various  other  Crustacea  likewise  possess  peculiar  metamor- 
phoses, especially  the  strangely  formed  parasite  crayfish,  whose  early  stages 
resemble  those  of  the  independently  living  Crustacea.  All  these  facts,  espe- 
cially the  fact  that  the  larvas  of  certain  higher  Crustacea  resemble  the  fully 
grown  individuals  of  lower  Crustacea,  convinced  Fritz  Muller  that  the  evo- 
lution of  the  individual  is  a  "historical  document,"  which  is  sometimes 
effaced,  owing  to  the  development's  striking  into  a  more  and  more  direct 
path  from  the  tgg  to  the  fully  grown  creature,  and  which  is  sometimes 
"counterfeited,  owing  to  the  struggle  for  existence  that  the  independently 
existing  larva;  have  to  maintain."  A  case  such  as  that  of  the  prawn  he  re- 
gards as  typical;  the  prawn's  ancestors  in  past  ages  possessed  the  form  that 
its  larva;  now  possess,  and  that,  too,  in  the  same  sequence  as  that  in  which 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  517 

the  larva:  now  succeed  one  another,  whereas  the  history  of  the  river  crayfish 
has  been  obliterated  and  that  of  a  number  of  other  Crustacea  has  received 
fresh  contributions  in  respect  of  form. 

This  theory,  which  Fritz  Miiller  expounded  in  1S64  in  a  paper  entitled 
Fur  Darwin,  aroused  Haeckel's  ardent  enthusiasm.  To  him  it  became  a  "prin- 
ciple for  the  origin  of  life,"  the  main  support  of  the  theory  of  descent  and 
a  particularly  weighty  argument  in  the  controversy  over  the  struggle  for 
man's  "natural  creation."  It  was  then  chiefly  to  human  evolution  that  he 
sought  to  apply  the  theory  and  in  his  Anthrofo genie,  as  also  previously  in 
his  Naturliche  Schopfungs geschichte ,  he  works  out  the  embryonic  development 
of  man  from  the  es,g  to  birth  with  a  view  to  collecting  proofs  of  the  condi- 
tions governing  man's  descent  and  affinity.  Haeckel  was  never  a  specialist 
in  embryology  and  its  points  of  detail  were  of  no  interest  to  him  in  them- 
selves, but  only  in  so  far  as  they  could  serve  as  evidence  to  prove  the  descent 
of  man.  His  ideas  of  embryology  could  in  such  circumstances  only  be  one- 
sided and  deficient;  the  professional  embryologists  offered  serious  objections 
to  them,  which  he  either  affected  to  overlook  or  else  answered  with  per- 
sonal abuse.  Complaints  were  made  especially  against  his  illustrations, 
which,  contrary  to  usual  practice,  he  hardly  ever  borrowed  from  mono- 
graphs on  the  subject,  but  drew  himself.  Being  designed  exclusively  to  prove 
one  single  assertion,  his  illustrations  were  naturally  extremely  schematic  and 
without  a  trace  of  scientific  value,  sometimes  indeed  so  far  divergent  from 
the  actual  facts  as  to  cause  him  to  be  accused  of  deliberate  falsification  — • 
an  accusation  that  a  knowledge  of  his  character  would  have  at  once  refuted.' 

Haeckel's  theory  of  germinal  layers  and  gastrcea 
Two  specially  remarkable  details  in  Haeckel's  doctrine  of  the  biogenetical 
principle  are  the  theory  of  the  germinal  layers  and  the  gastrasa  theory.  We 
have  previously  described  the  investigations  into  the  embryonic  germinal 
layers  carried  out  by  Pander,  von  Baer,  Remak,  and  others,  and  also  how 
Huxley  compared  dermal  and  intestinal  layers  in  the  medusa:  with  the  ger- 
minal layers  in  higher  animals.  Besides  these  facts  Haeckel  had  for  material 
on  which  to  work  his  own  researches  into  the  Calcarea,  the  embryonal  de- 
velopment of  which  he  had  studied.  On  all  this  he  now  bases  the  theory  of 
the  origin  of  the  animals,  and  especially  that  of  man;  since  man  originates 
from  a  single  cell,  the  ^gg,  then  in  the  beginning  of  time  the  original  form 
out  of  which  the  human  race  has  evolved  must  also  have  been  a  unicellular 
animal.  Out  of  the  egg-cell  there  is  developed  by  segmentation  a  cell-group; 

^  It  is  nevertheless  difficult  to  understand  such  an  action  as  this :  allowing  in  his  Naturliche 
Schopfungsgeschichte  (ed.  i,  p.  241)  the  same  cliche,  reproduced  three  times,  to  represent  an  egg  of 
a  man,  an  ape,  and  a  dog.  This  absurdity  was  removed  from  subsequent  editions,  albeit  only 
after  Haeckel  had  rewarded  with  abuse  those  who  pointed  out  the  fact;  and  the  incident  was  for 
ever  afterwards  a  theme  on  which  his  enemies  constantly  harped. 


5l8  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

this  stage  the  primal  forms  of  the  higher  animals  and  man  have  also  passed 
through,  and  during  that  period  they  have  resembled  such  cell-colonies,  as, 
for  instance,  the  Vol  vox.  Out  of  the  simple  cell-mass  there  evolves  in  the 
sponges,  by  means  of  invagination,  a  stage  of  development  v^ith  double 
walls,  a  gastrula,  which  corresponds  to  the  simplest  form  of  an  animal  pos- 
sessing an  intestinal  canal;  the  original  form  of  the  higher  animals  must 
likewise  have  passed  through  this  stage.  This  original  form  common  to  all 
higher  animals  is  called  gastrasa.  From  each  of  the  walls  of  the  gastrula 
there  splits  off  through  segmentation  a  fresh  layer;  these  two  secondary 
layers  combine  and  form  the  mesoderm,  which  gives  rise  to  the  muscula- 
ture and  various  other  organs  in  the  higher  animals.  This  process  has  also 
taken  place  at  some  time  or  other  in  the  primal  form  of  the  higher  animals, 
and  therefore  all  these  three  layers  and  their  derivatives  are  homologous 
throughout  the  entire  animal  kingdom. 

Importance  of  Haeckel's  bio  genet  ical  principle 
This  evolutional  theory  is  undeniably  Haeckel's  most  brilliant  and  most 
important  contribution  to  the  history  of  biology.  O.  Hertwig  was  right  in 
saying  that  for  fifty  years  biological  literature  was  under  the  influence  of 
this  idea;  the  abundant  facts  that  were  amassed  on  the  subject  of  embryology 
during  this  period  were  mostly  intended  to  confirm  the  biogenetical  principle 
or  the  "recapitulation"  theory,  as  it  has  also  been  called,  and  biologist;, 
strained  every  effort  to  apply  it  to  every  detail  in  the  development  of  th; 
embryo.  And  the  application  was  "strained"  in  the  fullest  sense  of  the  word. 
Haeckel  knew  from  the  outset  that  the  gastrula  stage  of  the  mammals  is  not 
formed  through  invagination,  as  the  theory  claimed,  but  through  delamina- 
tion,  or  splitting  off;  he  consoled  himself,  however,  with  the  thought  that 
in  the  lancet-fish  invagination  generally  takes  place,  and  from  this  primi- 
tive animal  he  derives  the  Mammalia,  with  the  assertion  that  their  gastrula 
form  is  due  to  later  adaptation  —  to  the  "falsification"  of  documents,  of 
which  Fritz  Miiller  had  spoken.  He  also  explains  a  number  of  other  facts 
of  a  similar  kind  according  to  the  same  method.  Matters  became  still  worse 
w^hen  the  embryologist  His  came  forward  with  an  attempt  to  explain  the  en- 
tire cause  of  embryonic  development  on  purely  mechanical  grounds.  Haeckel 
was  furious  and  replied  with  a  shower  of  abuse,  quite  forgetting  all  his 
own  utterances,  in  which  he  insisted  upon  a  mechanical  explanation  of  na- 
ture. In  reality  this  mechanical,  or,  in  other  words,  physiological,  side  of 
embryonic  development  is  of  very  great  importance,  though  Haeckel  quite 
overlooked  the  fact  in  his  anxiety  to  explain  natural  creation;  later  on,  how- 
ever, it  received  all  the  greater  attention.  But,  even  apart  from  this,  time  has 
dealt  hardly  with  Haeckel's  ontogenetical  theories.  The  gastrula  forma- 
tion by  means  of  invagination  has  proved  far  less  general  than  Haeckel 
believed  —  inter  alia,  it  is  lacking  in  most  of  the  Coelenterata  —  and  the 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  519 

far-fetched  homologization  of  the  germinal  layers  has  been  considerably  re- 
stricted, the  same  organs  in  a  number  of  different  animal  forms  having  been 
found  to  possess  an  entirely  different  origin.  In  particular,  the  mesodermal 
formation  has  now  been  resolved  into  a  number  of  different  processes.  In 
fact,  the  entire  " biogenetical  principle"  is  nowadays  severely  challenged, 
even  as  a  hypothesis;  in  the  vegetable  kingdom  it  has  received  no  confirma- 
tion, which  is  indeed  strange  for  a  theory  proposed  to  hold  good  as  a  gen- 
eral explanation  of  life,  but  even  those  zoologists  who  in  general  give  any 
support  at  all  to  the  recapitulation  theory  do  so  with  considerable  reserva- 
tions, called  for  by  the  results  of  modern  hereditary  research  and  experi- 
mental biology.  Nowadays  one  does  not  compare  without  question,  as  they 
did  in  Haeckel's  time,  the  ideas  of  similarity  and  affinity ;  similarity  can 
demonstrably  arise  through  the  influence  of  very  different  factors,  and  it  is 
preferred  to  follow  His  in  seeking  for  the  mechanical  conditions  governing 
the  development  of  form  instead  of  seeing  therein  resemblances  to  the  ani- 
mal life  of  past  ages.  But  this  should  not  involve  our  depreciating  Haeckel's 
influence  on  the  development  of  embryology;  it  was  his  theory  which  evoked 
that  interest  in  those  phenomena  that  brought  about  the  immense  revival 
of  this  form  of  research,  lasting  up  to  the  present  day.  In  this  connexion  we 
may  remember  von  Baer's  words  that  "inaccurate  but  definitely  pronounced 
general  results  have,  through  the  corrections  which  they  call  for  and  the 
keener  observation  of  all  the  circumstances  which  they  induce,  almost  in- 
variably proved  more  profitable  than  cautious  reserve."  It  is  just  herein  that 
Haeckel  has  benefited  his  science  most;  here  he  has  made  his  most  important 
and  historically  most  yaluable  contribution.  But  with  it  he  gave  all  that 
he  had  to  give;  the  years  that  he  lived  afterwards  produced  nothing  to  in- 
crease his  reputation,  but  detracted  much  from  it. 

His  ivork  on  ' '  peri  genes  is 
For  as  early  as  in  his  Antbropogeny  Haeckel  displays  his  increasing  weakness 
for  vague  and  profitless  speculations.  Talk  of  a  mechanical  explanation  of 
nature  is  certainly  kept  up,  but  it  becomes  more  and  more  empty  w^ords, 
while  the  spiritual  qualities  of  matter  appear  increasingly  in  the  foreground; 
energy  and  soul  are  now  consistently  identified,  and  are  generally  denoted 
by  the  term  "energy,"  in  a  manner  which  testifies  to  his  absolute  contempt 
for  the  simplest  grounds  of  physics.  And  this  fault  is  still  more  intensified 
in  a  treatise  published  in  1875  entitled  Die  Ferigenesis  der  Plastidule,  the  nat- 
ural-philosophical confusion  pervading  which  it  is  truly  difficult  to  repro- 
duce in  a  summary.  The  title  itself  is  supposed  to  mean  "  the  wave-production 
of  life-particles"  and  this  is  intended  to  explain  the  same  phenomena  as 
those  upon  which  Darwin  tries  to  throw  light  by  means  of  his  pangenesis 
theory  —  that  is,  heredity  and  adaptation.  The  pangenesis  theory  fails  to 
satisfy  Haeckel,  who  instead  endeavours  to  explain  heredity  by  an  analysis 


52.0  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

of  the  molecules,  or  plastidules,  as  he  calls  them,  of  living  matter.  Life  is 
due  to  their  atomic  structure,  and  "  jedes  Atom  besitxt  eine  inhdrente  Summe  von 
Kraft  und  ist  in  diesem  Sinne  beseelt."  Energy  and  soul  are  thus  identified  anew, 
and  this  having  been  done,  all  difficulties  disappear.  Haeckel  now  explain^ 
reproduction,  as  always,  with  the  old  definition:  growth  over  and  above  the 
individual;  heredity  is  a  transmission  of  the  motion  of  the  plastidules,  and 
adaptation  a  change  in  this  motion.  This  certainly  sounds  somewhat  me- 
chanical, but  some  pages  further  on  we  suddenly  find  a  new  definition: 
"Die  Erblichkeit  ist  das  Geddchtnis  der  Plastidule,  die  Variabilitdt  ist  die 
Fassungskraft  der  Plastidule."  And  yet  still  later  we  are  told  that  "das  Ge- 
ddchtnis"' is  a  transmitted  motion.  It  would,  of  course,  be  superfluous  to  judge 
these  fancies  according  to  scientific  standards ;  Haeckel  himself  admits  that 
he  got  the  idea  of  "the  memory  oi"  the  atoms"  from  Goethe's  famous  ro- 
mance Die  Wahlverivandtschaften,  and  indeed  the  whole  plastidule  theory 
sounds  like  a  romance;  in  producing  it  Haeckel  had  abandoned  himself  en- 
tirely to  romantic  natural  philosophy  and  there  he  remained  for  the  rest  of 
his  life.  The  phenomenon  might  seem  to  have  only  a  psychological  interest 
and  might  be  passed  over  with  a  reference  to  Haeckel's  esthetic  turn  of 
mind  —  he  was,  in  fact,  something  of  an  artist,  a  gifted  dilettante  in  water- 
colour  painting  and  an  admirer  of  beauty  both  in  art  and  in  nature  —  but 
it  might  also  be  pointed  out  that  a  pioneer  in  science  may  be  considered 
justified  in  entertaining  some  strange  thoughts  on  general  problems  —  this 
has  been  acknowledged  throughout  the  ages.  Yet  this  does  not  explain  how 
it  was  that  this  speculative  side  of  Haeckel's  activities  should  have  proved 
capable  of  creating  such  an  extraordinary  sensation  among  his  contempo- 
raries —  that  people  should  have  been  so  loud  in  their  praises  and  in  their 
abuse.  This  point  demands  an  explanation  by  itself,  wherefore  we  must  cast 
a  glance  at  the  political  and  social  conditions  of  the  time. 

Political  radicalism  of  the  Haeckelians 
In  Germany  the  seventies  were  a  somewhat  restless  decade;  the  recent  vic- 
tories had  certainly  confirmed  Bismarck  in  his  power,  but  he  nevertheless 
had  opponents  in  two  directions:  the  Catholics,  whose  ultramontane  politics 
were  regarded  as  a  menace  to  the  unity  of  the  Empire,  and  the  interna- 
tional labour  movement,  which  had  recently  found  expression  in  the  com- 
munal riot  in  Paris,  that  had  so  scared  the  world,  and  not  least  Germany, 
where  some  attempts  against  the  lives  of  distinguished  people  were  placed 
to  its  account.  In  such  circumstances  the  liberal-minded  apprehended  a  fur- 
ther reign  of  terror,  and  the  friends  of  domestic  peace  still  further  social 
upheavals.  And  Darwinism  in  particular,  which  indeed  had  from  the  begin- 
ning been  strikingly  characterized  as  a  theory  of  progress,  through  Haeckel's 
boisterous  attacks  on  the  authorities  of  State  and  Church  and  through  his 
dogmatic  description  of  the  contrast  between  the  doctrine  of  creation  and 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  5x1 

the  theory  of  evolution,  had  been  suspected  by  the  conservatives  and  looked 
upon  as  a  socially  dangerous  hypothesis,  the  truth  of  which,  moreover, 
could  be  disputed  on  the  grounds  of  the  plastidule  theory  and  similar  ideas 
contained  in  it.  The  exchange  of  ideas  on  Darwinism  became  in  these  cir- 
cumstances more  and  more  lively;  round  Haeckel  there  gathered  a  crowd 
of  young  naturalists  who  preached  the  new  doctrine  with  enthusiasm. 
Among  them  may  be  named  A.  Brehm,  the  author  of  the  universally  known 
work  Animal  Life,  F.  von  Hellwald,  known  as  a  geographical  writer, 
G.  Jager,  famous  for  his  curious  hygienic  theory,  and  others.  Since  the  uni- 
versities were  mostly  closed  to  them,  they  carried  on  their  agitation  by  means 
of  popular  lectures  and  polemical  writings,  in  which  they  expounded  their 
views,  willingly  associating  their  natural-scientific  radicalism  with  a  po- 
litical radicalism,  and  with  this  party  the  old  radicals  Vogt  and  Biichner 
associated  themselves.  But  the  new  theory  claimed  also  politically  con- 
servative adherents,  as,  for  instance,  Du  Bois-Reymond;  he  had,  it  is  true, 
embraced  Darwinism  with  enthusiasm  and  had  declared  that  its  appearance 
had  freed  biology  from  all  explanations  of  the  vexed  problems  of  final- 
ity, but  at  the  same  time  he  had  expressed  disapproval  of  "Haeckelism." 
In  his  above-mentioned  lecture  on  the  limitations  of  our  knowledge  of 
nature  he  had  uttered  a  warning  against  belief  in  a  possibility  of  definitely 
solving  the  riddles  of  nature  and  life.  Haeckel,  who,  it  will  be  remembered, 
had  nevertheless  himself  admitted  the  limitation  of  man's  capacity  for 
knowledge,  became  enraged  at  the  word  "  ignorabimus,''  in  which  he  scented 
political  reaction.  The  foreword  to  his  Anthropogenie  is  directed  against  it 
and  treats  the  expression  entirely  politically.  The  situation  became  still  more 
tense  some  years  later,  when  the  Prussian  Government  was  engaged  in  draft- 
ing a  new  educational  law,  the  provisions  of  w^hich  were  bound  to  affect  the 
future  of  science  in  Germany.  Then  Haeckel  came  forward  at  a  scientific 
meeting  at  Munich  in  1877  with  an  address  on  the  relation  of  the  evolution 
theory  to  science  in  general.  In  it  he  presented  his  old  theories,  including 
the  plastidule  hypothesis,  and  expressed  the  assurance  in  connexion  with 
them  that  biology,  as  conceived  evolutionally,  is  not  an  exact,  but  a  his- 
torical and  philosophical,  science,  and  as  such  aimed  at  uniting  natural- 
scientific  research  with  the  psychical  sciences  and  thus  forming  the  basis 
for  a  uniform  view  of  life,  which  would  gradually  reconstruct  the  whole 
of  human  existence  on  general  humanitarian  lines,  and  which  should  there- 
fore constitute  the  foundations  of  all  education. 

Virchow  opposes  Haeckel 
This  proposal  was  opposed  by  Virchow  in  a  speech  in  which  he  points  out 
all  that  is  hypothetical  and  unproved  in  Darwinism,  and  on  these  grounds 
he  uttered  a  warning  against  incorporating  it  in  a  scheme  of  school  educa- 
tion, for  such  a  program  should  only  concern  itself  with  indisputable  proofs. 


52.1  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

Virchow's  speech  was  greeted  with  cheers  by  the  conservatives;  as  a  matter 
of  fact,  its  criticism  of  Haeckel's  fantastic  ideas  was  justified,  but  its  peda- 
gogical program  was  of  doubtful  value;  it  might  reasonably  be  asked  what 
would  be  left  if  all  hypothesis  were  banned  in  the  schools  —  every  explana- 
tion of  nature  is  fundamentally  hypothetical,  and  much  of  the  results  of 
historical  research  rests,  of  course,  upon  disputed  facts.  And  even  more  un- 
acceptable sounds  his  passing  reference  to  the  spiritual  affinity  of  Darwinism 
to  socialism  —  a  denunciation  which  at  that  time  was  equivalent  to  an  ac- 
cusation of  high  treason.  Shortly  after^vards  the  Prussian  Minister  of  Edu- 
cation sent  round  a  circular  strictly  forbidding  the  schoolmasters  in  the 
country  to  have  anything  to  do  with  Darwinism,  and  in  the  new  educational 
law  biology  was  entirely  excluded  from  the  curriculum  for  the  highest 
classes  in  the  schools,  with  a  view  to  protecting  schoolchildren  from  the 
dangers  of  the  new  doctrines.  Haeckel  replied  to  Virchow's  speech  in  a  pam- 
phlet, Freie  Wissenschaft  und  freie  Lehre,  in  which  he  again  formulates  the 
antithesis  "Creation  —  Evolution,"  brings  forward  "certain  proofs"  of  the 
correctness  of  the  theory  of  descent,  declares  that  cell-psychology  can  be 
traced  to  Virchow's  own  ideas,  and  finally  urges  the  freedom  of  education 
and  Darwinism's  independence  of  the  political  questions  of  the  day.  His  reply 
was  hailed  with  enthusiasm  by  the  free-thinkers  and  it  is  easy  to  realize 
the  eagerness  with  which  the  friends  of  the  freedom  of  thought  and  word 
must  have  gathered  around  him  in  spite  of  his  many  delusions,  when  such 
measures  as  the  school  regulations  mentioned  above  were  adopted  by  the 
opposite  party.  All  the  more  so  as  the  outcome  proved  Haeckel's  justifica- 
tion; Darwinism  might  be  prohibited  in  the  schools,  but  the  idea  of  evolution 
and  its  method  penetrated  everywhere,  in  historical  research  and  linguistic 
studies,  and  even  in  the  scientific  treatment  of  religious  documents  and  reli- 
gious history.  And  to  this  result  Haeckel  has  undeniably  contributed  more 
than  most;  everything  of  value  in  his  utterances  has  become  permanent, 
while  his  blunders  have  been  forgotten,  as  they  deserve. 

Victory  of  Darivinism 
During  the  eighties  the  dispute  as  to  the  justification  of  Darwinism  died 
down;  Haeckel  himself  spent  most  of  this  period  in  studying  the  Radiolaria, 
and  his  partisans  likewise  began  to  pursue  other  activities.  Instead,  that 
decade  was  to  witness  the  undisputed  domination  of  comparative  morphol- 
ogy in  biological  research  and  training;  it  was  at  a  time  when  Gegenbaur's 
and  Haeckel's  ideas  universally  prevailed  without  opposition  and  were  ap- 
plied to  various  groups  of  the  animal  kingdom.  But  the  results  were  in  no 
wise  what  Haeckel  had  anticipated.  Instead  of  simple  and  easily  compre- 
hended proofs  of  the  indisputable  validity  of  Darwinism,  the  younger  gen- 
eration of  scientific  students  found  masses  of  involved  facts,  which  only 
contributed  to  confuse  the  biogenetical  principle,  the  gastrasa  theory,  and 


MODERNBIOLOGY  5 13 

the  other  "natural  hiws."  This  was  not  at  all  what  Haeckel  had  expected. 
Self-confident  by  nature  and  spoiled  by  the  successes  of  his  earlier  years,  he 
was  lost  amongst  all  these  developments;  intensive  study  of  detail  had  never 
been  his  strong  point,  and  the  minute  methods  and  detailed  observations 
of  the  young  morphologists  aroused  his  keen  opposition.  In  a  letter  dating 
from  this  period  he  expresses  the  opinion  that  modern  morphologists  in 
general,  and  " Querschnittler  und  Anilhifdrber''  in  particular,  possess  far  less 
"logical  schooling"  than  the  systematists  of  the  old  school.  And,  as  always, 
special  research  was  followed  by  a  waning  interest  in  theoretical  specula- 
tions; instead  of  paying  attention  to  Haeckel's  watchword  —  either  crea- 
tion or  evolution  —  students  preferred  to  leave  the  theories  to  their  fate 
and  to  go  over  to  practice.  When,  then,  even  Haeckel's  favourite  idea  of 
man's  origin  from  the  higher  apes  and  his  affinity  to  the  gorilla  and  the 
chimpanzee  began  to  be  doubted  by  scientific  students,  who  found  man  to 
be  in  anatomical  respects  highly  isolated  and  traced  him  back  direct  to 
lower  mammal  forms,  it  is  not  to  be  wondered  at  that  the  old  master  lost 
patience.  He  was  no  longer  capable  of  controlling  developments,  or  of  obey- 
ing them;  to  withdraw  from  the  struggle,  which  would  have  been  the  wisest 
thing  for  him  to  do,  was  more  than  his  unbounded  energies  could  endure  — 
perhaps  also  he  was  too  vain  to  do  so  —  and  so  he  continued  the  struggle 
on  behalf  of  his  natural  philosophy,  becoming,  as  the  years  went  on,  more 
and  more  isolated  from  his  old  friends  and  disciples  in  the  world  of  science. 
In  compensation  he  gained  from  another  quarter  a  new  and  grateful  public. 
The  old  political  radicalism  had  died  out  towards  the  close  of  the  century; 
most  of  the  liberal  party  ceased  altogether  from  offering  opposition;  instead 
the  struggle  was  taken  up  with  increasing  success  against  the  government 
authority  by  the  socialistic  labour  movement,  which,  violently  persecuted 
by  Bismarck,  sometimes  counteracted,  sometimes  favoured  by  his  successors, 
waxed  stronger  and  stronger,  until  in  the  revolution  of  November  191 8  it 
destroyed  the  old  social  order.  With  youthful  idealism  its  members  embraced 
the  modern  natural  science;  they  too  were  enemies  of  the  conservative  State 
Church,  which  was  friendly  to  the  Government  and  which  condemned  them 
to  show  humble  obedience  to  superiority.  There  was  all  the  more  reason, 
then,  for  their  being  drawn  together  by  a  natural-scientific  explanation  of 
the  world  which  made  progress  the  aim  of  life.  To  them  Haeckel's  monism 
was  a  welcome  ally;  that  its  cosmic  view  was  over-simplified  and  falsely 
depicted  it  was  not  in  their  power  to  control,  owing  to  their  lack  of  special 
studies,  but  its  founder's  ardent  belief  in  natural  science  and  intense  hatred 
of  the  State  Church,  combined  with  his  oppositional  attitude  in  politics, 
sounded  irresistibly  attractive.  It  is  against  this  background  that  Haeckel's 
later  scientific  activity  must  be  viewed  in  order  that  its  influence  may  be 
understood  aright. 


5X4  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

Haeckel' s  Weltratsel 
In  the  nineties  Haeckel  returned  to  natural  philosophy;  he  published  one 
or  two  papers  on  monism  and  an  important  work  on  "systematic  phy- 
logeny,"  comprising  a  genealogical  tree  for  all  living  beings  —  that  is,  a 
detailed  application  of  his  earlier,  and  even  then  somewhat  out-of-date, 
theorifes.  In  1899  he  published  his  famous  work  Die  Weltratsel,  which  was 
intended  to  be  a  summary  of  his  ideas  and  at  the  same  time  a  farewell  to 
his  activities;  being  a  child  of  the  nineteenth  century,  he  wished  to  con- 
clude his  work  with  its  exit  —  a  promise  that  unfortunately  he  failed  to 
keep.  The  Kiddle  of  the  Universe  had  extraordinary  success;  in  Germany  the 
book  was  sold  by  the  hundred  thousand  and  in  England  by  tens  of  thou- 
sands; special  emphasis  has  been  laid  on  the  fact  of  its  widespread  distribu- 
tion among  the  working-classes,  and  in  Japan  it  is  said  to  have  been  used 
as  a  school  text-book.  Nevertheless,  from  a  scientific  point  of  view  it  must 
be  regarded  as  utterly  valueless.  Its  biological  section  is  a  rehash  of  the  his- 
tory of  the  creation;  anthropogeny,  and  the  monograph  on  the  plastidule, 
as  little  attention  as  possible  being  paid  to  the  immense  progress  made  by 
scientific  research  since  then.  As  a  matter  of  fact,  biology  takes  up  only  one- 
quarter  of  the  volume;  the  rest  is  devoted  to  psychology,  cosmology,  and 
theology.  The  cosmological  section  gives  evidence  of  the  author's  hopelessly 
confused  ideas  on  the  simplest  facts  of  physics  and  chemistry;  final  judgment 
has  been  passed  on  it  in  a  widely  distributed  polemical  paper,  which  has 
never  been  challenged  by  trustworthy  authorities,  written  by  the  Russian 
physicist  Chwolson,  to  whom  we  refer  those  who  desire  to  gain  an  insight 
into  Haeckel's  standing  in  regard  to  the  exact  sciences.  The  philosophical 
section  of  the  book  has  been  no  less  severely  criticized  by  specialists  on  the 
subject;  philosophers  of  different  schools  have  pointed  out  its  utter  lack  of 
clarity  in  point  of  theoretical  knowledge  and  logic,  its  incapacity  to  define 
even  the  simplest  ideas.  In  passing,  it  may  be  mentioned  that  this  time  "mon- 
ism" is  based  mostly  on  Spinoza,  the  great  dogmatist  and  repudiator  of  evo- 
lution, whose  purely  metaphysical  idea  of  substance  is  at  once  placed  on 
a  par  with  the  "matter"  of  physics.  True,  the  real  character  of  substance 
is  said  to  be  inexplicable,  but,  notwithstanding  this,  everything  between 
heaven  and  earth  is  explained  with  its  aid.  If  we  add  to  this  Haeckel's  total 
lack  of  historical  sense  and  critical  judgment  —  his  views  on  events  and 
persons  are  derived  from  the  simplest  vocabulary  of  contemporary  political 
and  cultural  radicalism  —  the  final  impression  of  The  Kiddle  of  the  Universe 
will  be  an  utterly  depressing  one.  The  cause  of  the  book's  popularity  is 
obviously  to  be  found  in  the  political  and  social  sphere.  Its  very  introduction 
points  in  that  direction,  the  progress  in  the  scientific  world  being  there  con- 
trasted with  a  dark  picture  of  the  political  situation  of  the  time:  government, 
administration,  courts  of  justice,  and  education  are  depicted  as  appallingly 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  5x5 

behind  the  times,  and,  above  all,  the  Church  is,  of  course,  represented  as 
the  centre  of  all  kinds  of  obscurity,  superstition,  and  tyranny.  From  all 
quarters,  both  radical  and  conservative,  the  signal  to  open  hostilities  was 
eagerly  awaited.  Some  years  after  the  appearance  of  The  Kiddle  of  the  Utiiverse 
there  was  founded  the  Monist  League,  a  widely  ramified  association  formed 
for  the  purpose  of  working  for  the  ideas  to  which  Haeckel  gave  expression 
in  this  book  and  in  a  sequel  to  it.  Die  Lebenswunder.  Since  then  it  has  laboured, 
by  means  of  meetings,  lectures,  and  papers,  and  in  some  circles  by  devotional 
exercises,  with  a  view  to  taking  the  place  of  the  ecclesiastical  cult.  Haeckel's 
colleagues,  however,  for  the  most  part  kept  aloof  from  the  league;  only  a 
few  scientists  of  importance  have  joined  it.  From  the  side  of  the  conserva- 
tives violent  attacks  were  made  on  the  league;  in  the  Prussian  Diet  Reincke, 
the  professor  of  botany,  made  a  strong  stand  against  it,  characterizing  it  as 
a  menace  to  society  and  subversive  of  morals.  This  started  the  battle  in  ear- 
nest. To  counteract  the  Monist  League  there  was  founded  the  Keplerbund, 
so-called  after  the  great  astronomer.  The  very  name,  however,  proved  fatal; 
Kepler,  it  is  true,  was  at  the  same  time  a  great  naturalist  and  a  devout  Chris- 
tian, but  all  the  same  he  was  so  saturated  with  the  grossest  superstitions  of 
his  time  that  he  cannot  by  any  stretch  of  the  imagination  be  held  up  as  the 
ideal  seeker  after  truth  in  modern  times.  And  the  Keplerbund  failed  no  less 
than  the  Monist  League  to  attract  scientists  of  any  weight;  the  latter  kept 
more  strictly  than  ever  outside  the  struggle  and  showed  on  the  whole  — 
the  biologists,  at  any  rate  —  their  sympathy  for  Haeckel,  whose  work,  in 
spite  of  all  his  mistakes,  nevertheless  seemed  to  them  to  represent  a  struggle 
for  enlightenment  and  liberty  of  doctrine  against  the  constant  menace  of 
the  powers  of  reaction. 

And  Haeckel  certainly  did  maintain  the  radically  liberal-minded  stand- 
point of  his  youth  undisturbed  through  all  these  changes  —  which  it  was 
all  the  more  easy  for  him  to  do  as  he  had  never  taken  part  in  practical  poli- 
tics and  therefore  had  not  to  solve  any  political  or  social  problems  of  detail. 
But  the  shock  caused  him  by  the  Great  War  proved  all  the  greater  on  that 
account;  the  idea  that  the  fellow-countrymen  of  Darwin  should  have  sided 
with  the  enemies  of  Germany  drove  him  to  despair.  A  few  more  works  came 
from  his  pen,  among  them  one  entitled  Funf^igjahre  Stammesgeschichte,  with 
which  he  celebrated  the  fifty  years'  jubilee  oiGenerelle  Morpbologie,  and  which 
testifies  to  his  having  learnt  nothing  and  forgotten  nothing.  His  final  work, 
Krisfall-Seelen,  is  sufficiently  characterized  by  its  title.  It  came  out  in  1917;  two 
years  later  he  died,  his  death  being  hastened  by  an  accident,  which  de)ivered 
him  from  the  infirmities  of  old  age  and  the  misery  of  those  unhappy  years. 

Hartjnann  on  Haeckel 
The  well-known  philosopher  Eduard  von  Hartmann,  in  an  otherwise  sym- 
pathetic character-sketch  of  Haeckel,  describes  the  latter's  "monism"  thus: 


5  26  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

"He  is  an  ontological  pluralist  in  that  he  conceives  nature  to  be  a  multi- 
plicity of  separate  substances  (atoms),  a  metaphysical  dualist  in  so  far  as 
he  assumes  in  every  substance  two  combined  metaphysical  principles  (en- 
ergy and  matter);  a  phenomenal  dualist  in  that  he  assumes  two  distinct 
spheres  of  phenomena  (external  mechanical  happening,  and  internal  sensa- 
tion and  will),  a  hylozoist  because  he  ascribes  to  all  matter  the  possession 
of  life  and  soul;  further,  he  is  a  philosopher  of  identity,  a  cosmonomistic 
monist,  and  a  materialist."  Thus  the  Haeckelian  monism,  if  closely  looked 
into,  will  be  found  to  contain  a  little  of  everything.  It  may  therefore  be 
worth  pointing  out  in  this  connexion  that  even  more  deeply  elaborated  mo- 
nistic systems  have  appeared  in  our  own  day.  As  a  matter  of  fact,  monism  as 
a  philosophical  view  of  life  is  a  comparatively  ancient  doctrine;  the  neo- 
Platonists,  who  ascribed  true  existence  only  to  ideas,  were  undeniably 
monists,  as  was  also  Spinoza,  and  so,  too,  Schelling  and  his  successors,  in- 
cluding both  Goethe  and  Hegel.  Monism  based  on  natural-scientific  grounds, 
however,  has  undoubtedly  become  an  especially  widespread  conception  in 
modern  times.  As  one  of  its  leading  representatives  may  be  mentioned  Ernst 
Mach  (i 838-191 6),  professor  originally  of  physics  and  then  of  philosophy 
at  Vienna.  As  a  physicist  he  applied  himself,  inter  alia,  to  mental-physio- 
logical studies  after  the  pattern  of  Helmholtz,  but  he  also  studied  Kant's 
writings  and  was  led  through  them  into  the  sphere  of  the  theory  of  knowl- 
edge. He  thereupon  felt  himself  called  upon  .to  create  a  method  of  scientific 
thinking,  not  as  a  philosopher,  for  he  was  unwilling  to  call  himself  that, 
but  as  a  student  of  science.  He  will  have  nothing  to  do  with  transcendent 
spheres  of  thought.  Through  the  analysis  of  different  sense-impressions  he 
came  to  the  conclusion  that  everything  is  phenomenal;  nothing  exists  in 
itself;  the  outer  world  consists  of  a  series  of  phenomena,  and  the  ego,  the 
personality,  likewise  of  a  series  of  phenomena,  which  we  call  perceptions; 
the  phenomena  stand  in  a  relation  to  one  another,  which  is  expressed  by 
the  functional  terms  of  mathematics:  one  change  brings  about  another;  the 
phenomena  inside  and  outside  the  personality  are  mutually  interdependent. 
Mach  denies  the  principiant  contrast  between  appearance  and  reality;  the 
most  fantastic  dream  is  just  as  much  a  phenomenon  as  a  real  event;  he  like- 
wise denies  the  contrast  between  ego  and  non-ego,  for  both  are  a  series  of 
mutually  interdependent  phenomena.  The  manner  in  which  Mach  explains 
on  these  postulates  such  phenomena  as  will  and  thought  has  been  much  dis- 
cussed by  philosophers  who  have  made  a  special  study  of  the  subject,  and 
has  often  been  characterized  as  lacking  in  seriousness:  by  Hoffding,  for  in- 
stance, who  points  out  that  the  elements  common  to  physics  and  physiology 
are  in  Mach  indefinite  and  mystical,  like  a  shapeless  nebula.  Now,  Mach, 
as  already  mentioned,  claims  to  be  only  a  natural  scientist  and  to  try  to 
solve  only  natural-scientific  thought-problems.  But  even  as  such  he  exposes 


MODERNBIOLOGY  5x7 

himself  to  the  same  criticism;  his  biological  reasoning  must  thus  be  regarded 
as  out  of  date  even  for  his  age,  and  partly  also  somewhat  ingenuous;  he 
argues  about  evolution  and  heredity  without  taking  into  account  the  re- 
sults of  contemporary  research,  he  believes  in  much  of  the  old,  childish  ani- 
mal-psychology in  the  spirit  of  the  earlier  Darwinism,  and  he  speculates, 
like  Haeckel,  upon  the  possibility  of  explaining  the  origin  of  the  sense- 
organs  by  means  of  the  theory  of  selection.  Strangely  enough,  he  also  de- 
fends the  teleological  explanation  of  nature,  as  far  as  biology  is  concerned  — 
though  as  a  provisional  explanation  only,  until  a  true  causal  explanation 
is  forthcoming.  His  references  to  all  that  teleology  has  achieved  in  arousing 
interest  in  problems  and  collecting  facts  with  which  to  solve  them  may  not 
be  devoid  of  truth,  but  he  certainly  overlooks  the  confusion  it  has  caused 
by  inducing  vitalistic  explanations  of  nature;  such,  in  fact,  were  revived 
under  the  influence  of  Mach,  as  we  shall  see  later.  Finally,  with  regard  to 
his  monism,  it  possesses,  in  spite  of  his  own  assurances,  more  philosophical 
than  scientific  interest;  the  practical  scientist  should  at  any  rate  be  allowed 
to  treat  things  as  really  existing  and  the  changes  that  take  place  in  them  as 
having  been  causally  effected. 

Another  monistic  theory  was  set  up  by  Richard  Avenarius  (1843-96), 
professor  of  philosophy  at  Zurich.  He,  too,  elaborated  a  kind  of  theory  of 
function,  but  in  contrast  to  Mach  he  gives  to  its  elements  a  material  nature. 
His  theory,  which  suffers  from  having  been  presented  in  very  difficult  lan- 
guage, has  had  less  influence  than  Mach's. 

Natural-philosophical  theories  of  this  kind  may  offer  some  interest  as 
thought-experiments  and  besides  may  have  their  ideal  value,  if  they  give 
expression  to  the  conception  of  life  of  a  consummate  personality.  Exact 
scientific  research,  on  the  other  hand,  carves  out  paths  of  its  own,  its  prog- 
ress sometimes  hindered,  sometimes  furthered  by  the  different  conceptions 
of  the  world,  according  to  how  they  deal  with  existing  facts.  Pasteur,  for 
instance,  in  the  controversy  over  spontaneous  generation,  undoubtedly  de- 
rived advantage  from  his  Catholic  dogmatism  as  against  those  who  saw  in 
spontaneous  generation  a  "philosophical  necessity."  And  his  very  example 
shows,  too,  how  in  the  long  run  the  practical  utility  of  observations  is  the 
most  conclusive  criterion  of  their  value.  Those  facts  will  last  which  con- 
tribute, however  indirectly,  towards  extending  man's  dominion  over  na- 
ture, whereas  the  "  theories  of  life,"  after  surviving  for  a  time,  find  a  haven 
in  the  archives  of  cultural  history,  provided  they  are  found  worthy  to  be 
preserved  there. 


CHAPTER    XV 

MORPHOLOGICAL     SPECIALIZED     RESEARCH     UNDER 
THE     INFLUENCE     OF     DARWINISM 


1.      Anatomy  and  Embryology 

Development  of  anatomy 

THERE  IS  NO  DOUBT  that  the  power  of  Darwinism  reached  its  zenith 
in  the  seventies  and  eighties.  By  then  the  opponents  of  the  earlier 
school  had  for  the  most  part  said  their  last  word,  and  the  younger 
generation  of  scientists  who  had  embraced  the  new  doctrine  as  yet  found 
no  difficulties  in  its  application.  Rather,  efforts  were  made,  by  means  of 
exhaustive  investigations  in  every  possible  field,  to  collect  fresh  proof  for 
it.  These  endeavours  resulted  in  an  extraordinarily  abundant  and  many-sided 
production,  chiefly  in  the  sphere  of  morphology,  with  its  various  special 
subjects,  though  also  in  those  of  geography  and  oecology,  as  well  as  in  the 
purely  systematic  sphere.  In  this  chapter  we  shall  give  a  comprehensive  re- 
view of  this  specialized  morphological  research -work,  which  was  as  many- 
sided  as  it  was  rich  in  results. 

Anatomy  developed  as  the  outcome  of  a  number  of  investigations,  the 
results  of  which  were  recorded  in  numerous  memoirs.  To  give  an  account 
of  all  the  valuable  facts  that  were  brought  to  light  in  the  course  of  this 
ceaseless  work  would  be  impracticable  within  a  reasonable  compass;  a  mere 
list  of  the  anatomical  works  that  were  published  during  that  period  would 
run  into  hundreds  of  pages.  In  the  field  of  the  invertebrates  especially,  in- 
numerable new  and  important  anatomical  discoveries  were  made;  hitherto 
unknown,  or  at  least  neglected,  animal  forms  were  now  studied  and  often 
produced  undreamt-of  ideas  for  the  furtherance  of  comparative  research. 
Chastognatha  and  Enteropneusta,  Tunicata  and  Brachiopoda  may  be  men- 
tioned as  examples  of  such  forms,  which,  though  insignificant  in  their  ap- 
pearance and  scope,  are  nevertheless  interesting  for  their  structure  and 
development.  But  the  Vertebrata  also  continued  to  provide  valuable  con- 
tributions to  comparative  anatomy,  which,  for  the  very  reason  of  its  mor- 
phogenetical  aims,  found  every  animal  form,  however  insignificant,  worth 
while  investigating  and  examining  for  the  circumstances  of  its  origin  and 
evolution.  But,  on  the  other  hand,  by  reason  of  the  aims  they  had  in  view, 

518 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  5^9 

these  investigations  ultimately  became  somewhat  monotonous,  with  the  re- 
sult that  this  line  of  research  finally  became  quite  unmodern  and  the  interest 
began  to  turn  in  other  directions.  Among  the  investigators  who  compiled 
the  results  of  this  work  may  be  mentioned  Robert  Wiedersheim  (1848-1913), 
a  disciple  of  Leydig  and  professor  at  Freiburg,  well  known  for  his  compre- 
hensive work  on  the  anatomy  of  the  Vertebrata  as  well  as  his  studies  of 
special  subjects,  particularly  of  the  bone-structure  of  the  Batrachia,  and  the 
Swiss,  Arnold  Lang  (1855-1916),  a  disciple  of  Haeckel  and  professor  at 
Zurich,  who  wrote  a  widely  referred-to  work  on  the  anatomy  of  the  in- 
vertebrates and  a  number  of  monographs  on  various  groups  among  the 
worms, 

Etnbryology 
That  branch  of  morphology,  however,  that  was  specially  developed  under 
the  influence  of  the  descent  theory  was  embryology.  The  biogenetical  prin- 
ciple and  its  related  subjects,  the  theories  of  germinal  layers  and  the  gastrasa, 
were  applied  to  different  spheres  and  gave  rise  to  ideas  in  many  directions, 
besides  which  the  new  microtechnics  offered  a  means  for  detailed  discover- 
ies of  hitherto  undreamt-of  results.  Embryology,  therefore,  proves  to  have 
been  the  most  productive  of  the  morphogenetical  specialized  spheres  and 
attracted  to  it  the  most  eminent  biologists  of  the  time. 

Among  these  representatives  of  phylogenetical  embryology  only  a  few 
of  the  more  important  can  be  mentioned  here.  Alexander  Kowalewsky 
(1844-1901),  an  academician  of  St.  Petersburg,  worked  in  the  spirit  of 
Haeckel,  encouraged  by  his  commendation;  his  detailed  investigations  into 
the  development  of  ascidians  and  salpa;  covered  an  immense  amount  of  de- 
tail and  the  same  is  true  of  his  work  on  the  development  of  the  lancet-fish, 
with  the  result  that  even  the  ontogeny  of  this  much-discussed  animal  be- 
came known.  Kowalewsky  was  a  firm  supporter  of  the  theory  of  the  ger- 
minal layers  and  developed  it  by  making  contributions  of  his  own  in  the 
theoretical  sphere. 

The  same  line  of  research  was  also  followed  by  the  two  brothers  Hert- 
wig,  and  it  led  them  both  to  make  discoveries  of  fundamental  importance 
and  to  produce  theoretical  ideas  of  a  very  different  nature  from  those  from 
which  they  had  started.  Oscar  Hertwig  was  born  in  1849  and  Richard 
Hertwig  in  1850,  the  sons  of  a  merchant  at  Friedberg  in  Hesse.  They  both 
studied  at  Jena  under  Haeckel  and  became  lecturers  there  and  finally  pro- 
fessors, Oscar  of  anatomy  at  Berlin,  Richard  of  zoology  at  Munich.  Both 
carried  on,  each  in  his  own  subject,  extensive  and  important  activities  as 
teachers  and  investigators.  At  Jena  they  worked  together  in  the  sphere  of 
evolution  in  the  manner  of  Haeckel  and  published  a  series  of  papers  entitled 
Studien  x.ur  Blattertbeone,  which  dealt  especially  with  the  problem  of  the  mid- 
dle germinal  layers.  Here  they  expounded  their  famous  "coelom"  theory, 


530  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

which  was  intended  to  be  a  universal  answer  to  the  question:  "How  does 
the  two-layered  embryo  develop  into  a  higher  organization?"  The  theory 
takes  as  its  starting-point  the  two  primary  germinal  layers,  the  ectoderm 
and  the  entoderm,  between  which  there  arises  at  an  early  stage  an  originally 
structureless  layer  formed  by  immigrating  cells,  which  is  here  termed  "mes- 
enchyme." The  animals  are  now  divided,  in  respect  of  their  development, 
into  two  groups,  dependent  upon  whether  the  mesenchyme  participates  in 
the  formation  of  tissue  or  not.  The  former  takes  place  chiefly  in  the  coral 
animals,  the  flat-worms  and  the  molluscs,  in  which  the  muscular  and  nerv- 
ous systems  are  formed  out  of  the  mesenchyme,  whereas  in  most  other  ani- 
mal types,  chiefly  the  Articulata  and  the  Vertebrata,  the  said  tissues  are  of 
purely  epithelial  origin  and  are  formed  out  of  a  dual  evagination  of  the 
entoderm,  the  inner  cavity  of  which  gives  rise  to  the  body  cavity,  or  the 
coelom.  The  theory  was  afterwards  applied,  after  a  series  of  special  investi- 
gations, to  the  organic  formation  of  different  animal  forms  and  won  general 
acceptance  at  the  time.  It  is  true,  His  declined  to  accept  it,  but  did  not  suc- 
ceed in  substituting  any  better  explanation.  Later  research,  however,  has 
found  this  theory  to  be  far  too  schematical;  students  have  given  up  referring 
the  various  organs  to  the  three  germinal  layers  and  now  instead  seek  their 
origin,  each  separately,  in  so-called  primitive  rudiments.  Furthermore,  the 
formation  of  the  coelom  through  simple  invagination  has  been  found  upon 
closer  investigation  to  be  far  less  frequent  than  the  two  brothers  imagined. 
Their  theory  has  nevertheless  played  its  important  part  and  has  called  forth 
abundant  special  research-work  of  value  for  all  time.  In  the  following  pages 
we  shall  repeatedly  find  their  names  mentioned  in  connexion  with  valuable 
contributions  to  the  advancement  of  biology.  Among  their  pupils  may  be 
cited  the  scientific  collaborators  Eugen  Korschelt  (born  in  1858,  professor 
at  Marburg)  and  Karl  Heider  (born  in  1856,  latterly  professor  at  Berlin), 
who  together  published  an  exhaustive  summary  of  the  knowledge  of  their 
time  regarding  the  evolution  of  the  invertebrates.  Moreover,  both  have  dis- 
tinguished themselves  as  specialists,  particularly  in  the  sphere  of  experimen- 
tal research. 

During  this  period  England  was  also  the  scene  of  valuable  embryologi- 
cal  research-work.  Among  her  representatives  may  be  mentioned  Edwin 
Ray  Lankester  (born  1847),  a  professor  at  the  British  Museum  and  author 
of  a  number  of  papers  on  evolution,  dealing  especially  with  the  fishes  and 
the  Articulata.  He  especially  took  up  for  study  and  further  elaborated  the 
coelom  theory  and  has  brought  it  to  the  highest  point  it  has  yet  reached, 
having  sought  to  base  on  it  the  classification  of  the  animal  kingdom.  A 
very  distinguished  name  in  the  sphere  of  evolution  has  been  won  by  Francis 
Maitland  Balfour,  who  was  born  in  1851  and  died,  as  the  result  of  an 
accident,  in  i88i,  the  younger  brother  of  the  famous  statesman  Lord  Balfour. 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  531 

During  his  short  life  he  found  time  to  carry  out  a  number  of  extremely 
important  works  on  evokition,  including  a  study  of  the  evolution  of  the 
sharks  and  a  Treatise  of  Comparative  Embryology,  giving  an  account  of  the  evo- 
lution of  the  Q.gg  and  the  embryo  throughout  the  animal  kingdom,  a  work 
that  was  of  unrivalled  importance  at  the  time;  an  application  of  modern 
genetical  embryology  to  the  whole  animal  kingdom  and  at  the  same  time 
a  powerful  defence  of  the  Darwinian  morphology  in  its  classical  form.  Bal- 
four, in  fact,  definitely  maintains  that  phylogeny  is  the  goal  of  evolution, 
while  at  the  same  time  in  certain  details,  as,  for  instance,  in  the  theory  of 
extremity-formation  previously  mentioned,  he  adopts  a  dissentient  attitude 
towards  the  contemporary  Gegenbaur  school. 

Even  by  then  the  morphogenetical  embryology  had  met  with  decided 
opposition  on  the  part  of  the  naturalists  who  desired  to  substitute  for  phy- 
logenetical  conclusions  the  study  of  function  in  those  organs  whose  evolu- 
tion was  under  investigation,  and  thus  to  give  evolution  a  more  or  less 
physiological  direction.  To  this  group  belongs  the  afore-mentioned  Wil- 
HELM  His  (1831-1904),  who  was  born  at  Basel,  became  professor  of  anatomy 
there,  but  was  afterwards  summoned  to  Leipzig,  where  he  worked  until  his 
death.  Famous  both  as  an  anatomist  and  as  an  embryologist,  he  paved  the 
way  for  a  new  line  of  research,  particularly  in  the  field  of  embryology.  First 
of  all  he  expected  to  see  in  the  evolution  of  the  embryo  a  physiological 
process,  the  course  of  which  should  be  so  studied  that  each  later  stage  of 
development  must  necessarily  proceed  from  the  immediately  preceding  one. 
The  changes  whereby  the  simple  egg-cells  are  formed  into  complex  organisms 
are,  to  his  mind,  purely  mechanical;  as  the  result  of  a  series  of  flexions, 
fold-formations,  and  accretions  the  embryo  arises  out  of  the  originally 
lamellate  germinal  layers,  and  its  folds  are  in  their  turn  produced  entirely 
from  variformed  growth.  Every  organ  possesses  its  given  rudiments  in  the 
germinal  layers  and  these  layers  thus  consist  of  a  quantity  of  "  organbildende 
Keimbex.irke" ;  they  are  therefore  not  indifferent,  as  C.  F.  Wolff  and,  after 
him,  Haeckel  declared.  In  connexion  herewith  His  sharply  criticizes  the 
biogenetical  principle;  embryos  of  different  animal  forms  are  as  easily  dis- 
tinguishable from  one  another  as  the  fully  developed  animals;  Haeckel 's 
proofs  to  the  contrary,  both  verbal  and  pictorial,  are  examined  and  found 
to  be  untenable,  and  finally  the  question  is  put:  "If  we  possessed  a  complete 
genealogical  tree,  would  our  own  or  any  other  extant  organic  form  be  fully 
explained  thereby?"  In  reply  His  declares  that  if  in  a  case  of  near-sightedness 
it  is  possible  to  establish  the  fact  that  the  individual  in  question  has  inherited 
the  defect,  little  will  have  been  gained  therefrom  as  regards  our  knowledge 
of  the  character  of  that  defect;  rather,  the  eye's  capacity  for  accommodation 
and  other  concomitant  circumstances  must  be  investigated  for  this  purpose; 
in  the  same  way,  the  physiological  side  of  embryonic  development  is  more 


53X  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

important  than  any  phylogenetical  speculation.  The  whole  of  this  way  of 
thinking  won  but  little  acceptance  in  his  own  time,  when  research  was  being 
directed  along  phylogenetical  lines;  in  the  eyes  of  posterity,  on  the  other 
hand.  His  stands  out  as  precursor  of  the  mechanical  method  of  evolution, 
which  has  since  won  so  many  adherents  and  which  will  be  dealt  with  in 
the  following  pages. 

His,  however,  was  by  no  means  alone,  even  in  his  own  age,  in  his  con- 
ception of  evolution.  There  were  others  who  also  opposed  the  one-sided  phy- 
logenetical line  of  research;  among  them  may  be  mentioned  Alexander 
WiLHELM  GoETTE  (1840-19x1).  He  was  born  at  St.  Petersburg  of  Baltic  ori- 
gin, studied  at  Dorpat  and  at  Gottingen,  and  finally  became  professor  at 
the  German  university  in  Strassburg,  where  he  worked  for  the  greater  part 
of  his  life.  As  an  embryologist  he  was  influenced  from  the  beginning  by  his 
fellow-countryman  von  Baer.  In  his  principal  work.  Die  Entwkkelungsge- 
schichte  der  Unke,  he  seeks  to  make  the  evolution  of  Bombinator  igneus  the  basis 
of  a. purely  mechanical  theory  of  evolution,  freed  from  both  Haeckel's  "  jorm- 
bildende  Krdffe"  and  Gegenbaur's  phylogenetical  constructions.  Starting  from 
the  old,  but  at  the  time  commonly  accepted,  delusion  that  the  nucleus  of 
the  egg  is  dissolved  before  fertilization,  he  declares  that  the  egg  is  an  "un- 
organized, inanimate  mass,"  wherein  are  formed  by  purely  mechanical  forces 
—  osmotic  currents  and  resultant  pressure-changes  —  the  first  divisional  fur- 
rows, and  together  with  them  fresh  nuclei  as  centres  for  the  development 
of  the  new  cells.  Thus  is  explained  the  origin  of  life  out  of  lifeless  substance. 
Similar  mechanical  explanations  are  then  invented  for  the  formation  of  the 
germinal  courses  and  organs.  In  a  later  work  Goette  deals  in  the  same  method 
with  the  stages  of  development  in  certain  worm-forms.  The  interest  attaching 
to  these  investigations  lies  in  the  mechanical  conception  of  the  embryonic 
development,  which  is  not  only  maintained  theoretically,  but  is  also  in 
many  respects  successfully  applied.  Unfortunately,  Goette  was  so  delighted 
with  his  theory  that  he  let  all  criticism  go  by  the  board;  his  false  concep- 
tion of  the  nature  of  the  egg  he  still  maintained  long  after  it  had  been  proved 
untenable;  his  detailed  research  was  extremely  arbitrary  and  was  severely 
criticized  by  Gegenbaur.  His  theory  has  nevertheless  not  been  without  its 
effect;  his  disciple  Roux  especially,  doubtless  under  his  influence,  formu- 
lated a  mechanistic  conception  of  embryonic  and  organic  development  that 
received  widespread  support. 

Another  opponent  of  the  universally  current  embryological  conception 
was  NicoLAus  Kleinenberg,  born  in  i84x  at  Mittau,  a  disciple  of  Haeckel's, 
and  eventually  professor  at  Palermo,  where  he  died  in  1897.  Of  his  literary 
production,  which  was  small  in  extent  but  original  in  character,  may  be 
mentioned  his  monographs  on  the  evolution  of  the  fresh-water  polypus,  in 
which  the  ontogeny  of  this  primitive  animal  is  elucidated  for  the  first  time. 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  533 

In  a  subsequent  work  on  the  course  of  development  of  an  annelid  he  has 
propounded  a  curious  theory  of  its  embryonic  evolution  in  strong  opposition 
to  Haeckel's  gastrxa.  theory  and  the  coelom  doctrine  of  the  Hertwigs.  He 
starts  with  the  sentence:  "  Es  gibt  kein  tnittleres  Keiinblatt,"  and  adduces  a 
number  of  examples  of  how  various  organs  that  had  been  supposed  to  be 
mesodermal,  originate  directly  or  indirectly  from  the  ectoderm  or  entoderm. 
At  the  same  time  he  maintains  that  the  form  of  one  organ  depends  upon  its 
function  and  not  upon  its  origin;  "A  comprehensive  tissue-system  is  pos- 
sible only  on  a  physiological  basis."  These  views  were  at  the  time  at  which 
they  were  expressed  (1886)  so  utterly  opposed  to  those  of  his  age  that  they 
scarcely  caused  any  sensation;  their  time  came  later,  in  connexion  with  the 
altered  view  of  evolution  that  has  become  prevalent  in  our  day,  which  will 
be  described  in  a  subsequent  chapter. 


z.     Cytology 

Development  of  microscopical  cell-research 
Microscopical  cell-research  is  undoubtedly  the  branch  of  biology  that  re- 
ceived the  greatest  stimulus  during  the  last  decade  of  the  past  century,  and 
that  has  seen  the  most  important  results  and  in  many  ways  set  its  mark 
upon  the  whole  of  biology  in  general.  Its  highly  perfected  methodics,  with 
its  minute  technical  preparation  of  material  for  investigation,  carefully 
adapted  to  suit  each  particular  case,  and  its  careful  microscopical  study  of 
the  smallest  details,  employing  the  highest  possible  magnifications,  became 
a  characteristic  feature  of  the  research  work  of  that  period.  The  purely  tech- 
nical side  of  biology  thereby  received  an  entirely  new  character;  whereas 
formerly  skill  in  dissection  was  the  most  essential  qualification  of  the  biolo- 
gist, this  ability  now  became  to  a  certain  extent  superfluous,  thanks  to  the 
development  of  the  technique  of  microtomy.  On  the  other  hand,  the  student 
of  cells,  if  he  desires  to  create  something  new  and  to  work  independently, 
must  acquire  a  chemical  knowledge  of  the  means  of  fixing  the  tissues,  as 
well  as  a  colour  technique  for  the  purpose  of  their  further  treatment.  It  was, 
of  course,  possible  for  the  whole  of  this  method  of  research  to  degenerate 
into  a  mere  unintelligent  dexterity,  as  biologists  of  the  old  school  in  par- 
ticular called  it,  but  it  has  also  made  possible  more  than  any  other  method 
the  obtaining  of  results  that  have  entirely  transformed  our  conception  of 
the  phenomena  of  life. 

We  left  cell  research  at  the  point  to  which  Max  Schultze  had  brought         v 
it  —  the  knowledge  of  the  cell  as  a  limited  quantity  of  protoplasm  with 
concomitant  nucleus.  Schultze  is  also  remarkable  inasmuch  as  in  his  cell 
studies  he  was  still  working  without  a  microtome;  he  brought  cytology  to 


534  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

the  farthest  point  possible  with  the  old  methods.  During  the  period  imme- 
diately succeeding  his  death,  cell  research  made  rapid  strides  in  regard  both 
to  the  value  of  the  discoveries  made  and  to  the  number  of  workers  engaged 
in  it.  Limitations  of  space  make  it  impossible  to  do  justice  to  all  the  truly- 
distinguished  minds  that  during  this  period  laboured  for  an  increased  knowl- 
edge of  the  life  and  structure  of  the  cell.  Some  of  the  most  prominent  cytolo- 
gists  will  be  mentioned  here,  after  which  a  description  will  be  given  of  the 
most  important  discoveries  in  their  field  of  research;  the  fact  that  their  activi- 
ties and  the  rivalry  to  achieve  the  most  important  results  were  contempo- 
raneous would  indeed  render  it  extremely  difficult  to  retain  here  the  bio- 
graphical method  of  presentation  of  the  subject  that  we  have  followed 
hitherto. 

Its  representatives 
In  the  sphere  of  plant  cytology  Eduard  Strasburger  takes  the  first  place. 
He  was  born  in  1844  of  German  parents  at  Warsaw,  received  his  school  edu- 
cation there,  and  studied  partly  in  Paris  and  partly  at  German  academies, 
first  at  Bonn  and  then  at  Jena,  where  Haeckel  won  him  over  to  Darwinism 
and  even  procured  him  a  professorship.  He  afterwards  became  professor  at 
Bonn,  where  he  worked  until  his  death,  in  1911.  Equally  distinguished  as 
a  research-worker  and  a  teacher,  he  attracted  to  his  institute  a  large  num- 
ber of  pupils  from  all  countries;  he  was  a  leading  writer  of  text-books,  and 
his  scientific  production  included,  besides  his  epoch-making  cell-studies,  a 
number  of  branches  of  vegetable  anatomy. 

Among  students  of  animal  cytology  the  above-mentioned  brothers  Hert- 
wig  take  high  rank;  besides  them  there  is  Walther  Flemming  (1843-1905), 
professor  first  at  Prague,  then  at  Kiel,  distinguished  not  only  as  an  observer, 
Ijut  also  as  a  technician  and  teacher.  Further,  Hermann  Fol  (i845-9x);  a 
native  of  Geneva  and  the  son  of  wealthy  parents,  he  studied  in  Berlin  and 
became  professor  in  his  native  town  and  a  scientist  of  high  repute.  Being 
specially  interested  in  marine  research,  he  equipped  at  his  own  expense  a 
vessel  for  the  purpose;  in  the  course  of  a  voyage,  he,  together  with  the  ves- 
sel and  the  crew,  disappeared  and  were  never  heard  of  again.  Otto  Butschli 
(1848-1910),  after  having  studied  chemistry  and  mineralogy,  devoted  him- 
self to  zoology  and  became  professor  at  Heidelberg.  It  is  possible  that  his 
earlier  occupying  himself  with  inorganic  elements  and  processes  induced  in 
him  that  liking  for  comparison  between  organic  and  inorganic  structures 
which  characterized  his  later  research  work.  Besides  these  names  should  be 
mentioned  that  of  the  Belgian  Edouard  van  Beneden  (1845-1910);  the  son 
of  a  highly  reputed  zoologist,  who  was  especially  known  as  an  expert  on 
parasitology,  he  applied  himself  to  the  study  of  medicine  and  eventually 
became  a  professor  at  Liege,  famous  as  a  many-sided  investigator  and  pub- 
lisher of  the  well-known  journal  Archives  de  biologie.  Finally,  reference  should 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  535 

be  made  to  Theodor  Boveri  (1861-1915),  a  disciple  of  the  brothers  Hertwig 
and  professor  at  Wiirzburg,  as  well  as  the  two  Heidenhains  —  Rudolf 
(1834-97),  a  pupil  of  Ludwig  and  professor  of  physiology  at  Breslau,  but 
active  also  as  a  cytologist,  and  his  son  Martin,  born  in  1862.  and  professor 
at  Tubingen,  who  devoted  himself  exclusively  to  cell  research.  All  the  above 
have  advanced  their  science  by  making  valuable  discoveries  and  important 
technical  improvements. 

Strasburger  on  the  formation  and  division  of  cells 
In  1875  "^^^  published  the  first  edition  of  Strasburger's  pioneer  work  Zell- 
bildung  und  Zellteilung,  a  third  completely  revised  edition  came  out  in  1880. 
The  main  problem  that  occupied  cytological  research  during  this  period  was 
that  of  the  origin  of  the  cellular  nucleus.  As  we  have  seen,  Nageli  had  al- 
ready observed  the  division  of  the  nucleus,  but  neither  his  own  nor  other 
similarly  extensive  observations  were  able  to  possess  general  application. 
Even  in  the  first  edition  of  his  said  work  Strasburger  makes  the  nucleus  of 
the  egg-cell  in  the  plants  he  investigated  dissolve  upon  fertilization  and  its 
mass  disperse  into  the  plasm  of  the  cell;  in  the  latter  are  then  formed  a 
number  of  concretions,  which  give  rise  to  fresh  nuclei.  In  the  third  edition, 
on  the  other  hand,  it  is  asserted  that  examples  of  independent  cell-formation 
can  no  longer  be  cited  from  the  vegetable  kingdom;  fresh  nuclei  invariably 
arise  through  the  division  of  older  ones.  This  established  one  more  of  the 
principles  of  modern  cytology.  Even  before  this  students  had  begun  to  ob- 
serve the  curious  phenomena  attending  nuclear  division  in  the  majority  of 
cells,  but  apart  from  these  scattered  observations,  it  was  Strasburger  who, 
as  far  as  the  vegetable  kingdom  is  concerned,  elucidated  this  process,  which, 
though  complicated,  is  now  widely  known  and  is  set  forth  in  all  text-books. 
This  process  —  indirect  nuclear  division,  also  called  "mitosis"  or  "kary- 
okinesis"  —  is  as  follows:  the  nucleus,  having  lost  its  membrane,  concen- 
trates its  colourable  contents  around  its  middle  plane,  after  which  the  latter 
divides  itself  and  the  two  halves  go  each  its  own  way  and  thereupon  again 
concentrate  into  two  daughter-nuclei.  The  main  principles  of  this  process 
were  already  elucidated  in  the  above-mentioned  first  edition  of  Strasburger's 
book,  and  in  the  third  a  number  of  further  details  are  given.  In  the  field  of 
zoology  Biitschli,  O.  Hertwig,  and  Flemming  during  the  same  decade  made 
their  decisive  contributions  to  our  knowledge  of  nuclear  division,  and,  be- 
sides, certain  isolated  details  were  discovered  by  Fol,  van  Beneden,  and 
others.  As  a  result  of  this  research  work  the  elements  composing  the  nucleus 
were  also  investigated;  filament  substance  and  nucleolus,  nuclear  juice,  and 
nuclear  membrane  were  the  constituents  that  were  distinguished  to  begin 
with.  Of  these  the  first-mentioned  was,  owing  to  the  part  it  plays  in  the 
nuclear  divisions,  the  object  of  greatest  attention,  and  especially  on  this 
subject  Flemming's  studies  of  the  cells  of  amphibious  larva;  were  conclusive. 


536  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

It  was  he  who  ascertained  after  detailed  study  the  process  of  nuclear 
division  and  actually  gave  to  its  various  phenomena  the  names  that  have 
been  in  use  since  then;  owing  to  its  strong  colourability  he  called  the  fila- 
ment substance  "chromatin"  and  non-colourable  substance,  which  also  ap- 
pears upon  division,  "achromatin";  the  names  of  the  different  phases  of 
division  —  spirem,  aster,  metakinesis,  dyaster,  and  dispirem  —  were  also 
invented  by  him.  He  also  proved  the  conversion  of  the  chromatin  from  a 
network  into  a  convoluted  filament  and  further  into  a  number  of  bent  staves, 
and  proved  that  the  actual  division  consists  in  these  latter's  splitting  along 
their  length.  These  chromatin  staves  were  afterwards  called  by  Waldeyer 
"chromosomes"  and  have,  as  is  well  known,  come  to  play  a  decisive  part 
in  modern  heredity-research.  The  processes  of  the  fusiform  achromatin  fila- 
ments during  division  were  also  studied  by  Flemming;  it  was  not  until  later 
that  the  minute  central  body,  the  centrosome,  which  is  of  such  vital  impor- 
tance for  their  transformation,  was  investigated,  primarily  by  Flemming  and 
Boveri,  who  together  with  van  Beneden  discovered  its  division  in  cell- 
reproduction.  Boveri's  studies  of  the  centrosomes  especially  were  very  in- 
tensive and  have  proved  to  be  of  fundamental  importance.  This  formation 
has  been  characterized  by  him  as  the  cell's  dynamic  centre,  which  facilitates 
the  nuclear  and  cellular  division.  He  also  discovered  that  the  centre  of  the 
spermatozoon  is  formed  thereby. 

While  the  nucleus  has  been  found  in  the  difi'erent  forms  of  life  to  repre- 
sent the  conservative  element  —  the  chromosomes  are,  as  is  well  known, 
equally  numerous  and  similarly  formed  in  all  cells  in  the  same  individual  — 
the  protoplasm  of  the  cell  and  its  many  and  various  derivatives  have  ofi'ered 
fresh  problems,  owing  to  their  wealth  of  form,  which  has  proved  all  the 
greater,  the  more  these  formations  have  been  investigated.  The  actual  basic 
substance,  which  still  has  to  bear  the  clumsy  and  illogical  name  of  pro- 
toplasm, has  been  investigated  by  a  vast  number  of  students  and  has  called 
forth  many  attempts  at  an  interpretation  of  its  essence.  These  attempts  have 
for  the  most  part  concentrated  upon  three  diff"erent  theories  based  on  obser- 
vation, which  have  been  named  after  their  founders:  Biitschli's  froth  theory, 
Flemming's  filament  theory,  and  Altmann's  granule  theory;  to  say  nothing 
of  the  purely  speculative  attempts  to  discover  the  fundamental  substance  of 
life.  The  chief  difficulty  that  revealed  itself  in  these  explanations  and  that 
brought  out  their  mutual  contradictions  is  actually  caused  by  the  incon- 
stancy which  the  living  protoplasm  always  displays  and  which  is  a  neces- 
sary consequence  of  its  role  as  bearer  of  all  the  metabolism  in  the  cells  and 
the  organisms  composed  of  them.  Even  the  nucleus  displays  phenomena  of 
substance-renewal  and  it  has  been  found  that  the  vital  manifestations  of 
the  cell  ultimately  receive  their  impulses  from  that  quarter,  but  it  is  in  any 
case  in  the  plasma  substance  that  these  manifestations  of  life  are  essentially 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  537 

expressed.  And  they  are  as  much  of  a  chemical  as  of  a  physical  nature;  the 
physical  phenomena  —  movement  of  various  kinds  —  are  invariably  in- 
duced and  brought  about  by  chemical  reactions  and  in  their  turn  produce 
new  reactions. 

Plasma  ttoeories 
BiJTscHLi's  froth  theory  is  an  essentially  physical  attempt  to  explain  the 
structure  of  protoplasm.  He  certainly  repeatedly  points  out  the  chemical 
reactionary  phenomena  of  the  cell,  but  he  pays  little  attention  to  them. 
Taking  as  his  basis  the  strongly  vacuolized  substance  of  the  lowest  pro- 
tozoa, especially  of  the  amoeba;,  with  the  current-phenomena  visible  therein, 
he  conceives  the  living  protoplasm  as  a  fluid  mass  identical  in  its  structure 
with  the  emulsion  that  is  obtained  when  oil  and  soda-solution  are  shaken 
together.  This  purely  mechanical  emulsion-theory  he  afterwards  elaborated 
after  making  a  series  of  experiments  of  a  very  ingenious  character.  Through 
the  mixture  of  variously  composed  liquids  both  he  and  a  whole  school  of 
investigators  after  him  succeeded  in  imitating  in  a  surprisingly  natural  way 
a  great  many  of  the  most  complicated  movements  and  structures  of  the  liv- 
ing cell-substance.  It  cannot,  of  course,  be  denied  that  the  mechanical  phe- 
nomena which  were  found  in  these  experiments  to  cause  the  movements  in 
the  given  substratum  may  also  be  capable  of  asserting  their  influence  upon 
the  plasma  movements,  but  as  a  reproduction  of  the  phenomena  of  life  these 
experiments  possess  the  fundamental  fault  of  entirely  disregarding  the  chem- 
ical reaction  that  is  incessantly  going  on  in  living  substance;  the  mobile 
oil-emulsion  remains  chemically  what  it  was,  whereas  a  creeping  amoeba 
is  continually  changing  its  chemical  composition,  so  that  movement  and 
chemical  reaction  are  indissolubly  dependent  upon  each  other.  In  connex- 
ion herewith  we  find  also  the  belief,  which  has  proved  unsatisfactory  from 
the  very  beginning,  that  the  fundamental  substance  of  life  is  fluid  —  a  the- 
ory that  has  been  considerably  revised  by  modern  colloid  chemistry,  of  which 
we  shall  have  more  to  say  presently. 

Flemming's  plasma  theory  undeniably  takes  more  account  of  chemical 
conditions.  According  to  this  theory,  protoplasm  consists  of  a  network  of 
fibres  embedded  in  a  homogeneous  substance.  These  structures  he  found  par- 
ticularly in  the  cellular  mass  in  various  tissue-elements:  in  egg-cells  and  in 
cartilaginous  and  glandular  cells  in  higher  animals.  He  believes  the  phenom- 
ena of  metabolism  in  the  cell  to  be  accompanied  by  changes  in  the  filament 
mass  and  in  the  basic  substance,  which  should  be  examined  in  detail  in 
different  subjects.  The  threads  may  sometimes  be  dissolved  into  canals  and 
vacuoles  and  thereby  convey  the  assimilation  products  not  only  to  different 
places  within  the  cell,  but  also  between  various  cells,  for  these  latter  are 
in  most  cases  demonstrably  connected  with  one  another  by  bridges  of  fila- 
ments. Thus  the  cells  become  the  structural  elements  in  the  body,  though 


538  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

also  elements  incorporated  in  one  and  the  same  vital  unit;  their  independence 
need  not  be  over-stressed. 

In  opposition  to  these  two  theories,  which  belong  to  the  eighties, 
there  appeared  somewhat  later  the  granule  theory  of  Altmann.  Richard 
Altmann  (1851-1901),  professor  at  Leipzig,  devoted  his  attention  chiefly 
to  the  fundamental  substance  in  which  the  above-described  network  of 
plasm  lies  embedded,  and  with  the  aid  of  suitable  colouring-matter  he  found 
in  it  a  mass  of  grainlike  formations  —  the  Latin  gramda  —  of  different  kinds 
in  different  cells.  In  these  he  sees  the  true  substance  of  the  cell;  he  even  finds 
that  the  threadlike  structures  which  can  be  produced- by  Flemming's  method 
are  composed  of  similar  granular  formations.  Indeed,  many  of  his  observa- 
tions have  been  confirmed;  in  the  glandular  cells  especially,  the  forthcoming 
secretion  first  appears  in  the  form  of  homogeneous  granules,  which  gradu- 
ally increase  in  size  and  assume  the  form  of  drops.  In  most  other  cells,  too, 
such  granular  structures  appear  as  expressions  of  the  cell's  change  of  sub- 
stance; as  in  nerve-  and  muscle-cells,  of  which  we  shall  have  more  to  say 
later.  Altmann,  however,  sees  far  more  than  this  in  these  granule  formations; 
he  calls  them  bioblasts  and  considers  them  to  be  the  true  elementary  organ- 
isms of  which  cells  and  tissues  are  composed,  just  as  bacterial  colonies  are 
composed  of  various  bacteria.  He  even  believes  these  protoplasmic  granules 
to  be  of  equal  value  to  micro-organisms  and  would  make  this  his  contri- 
bution towards  the  solution  of  the  riddle  of  life,  a  contribution  that  he 
further  supplements  by  finding  a  resemblance  between  bioblast  and  crystal; 
these  two  are  in  fact  compared,  though  hypothetically.  These  fantastic  ideas 
have  naturally  been  given  but  little  support;  Altmann  is  on  firmer  ground, 
however,  when  he  emphatically  states  that  the  living  substance  must  be 
solid  and  not  liquid  —  an  assertion  that  he  bases  upon  his  granule  theory 
in  opposition  to  Biitschli's  above-mentioned  experiments  and  speculations. 

These  granular  structures  of  the  cell-substance  have,  as  a  matter  of  fact, 
been  studied  by  numerous  later  investigators,  who  have  given  them  innu- 
merable names:  "mitochondria,"  "chondriosomes,"  etc.  They  are  brought 
to  light  by  the  use  of  special  colouring-methods,  but  in  favourable  circum- 
stances they  may  also  be  visible  in  the  living  subject,  which  justifies  the 
assumption  that  they  are  not  pure  artificial  products.  The  same,  indeed,  is 
true  of  the  other  two  plasmic  structures:  the  fibre  and  the  froth  structures. 
M.  Heidenhain  rightly  points  out  the  possibility  of  all  three  structural  forms' 
existing  in  one  and  the  same  cell.  But  this  would  also  go  to  show  that  none 
of  the  structural  theories  is  capable  of  forming  the  basis  for  a  uniform  con- 
ception of  what  living  matter  is  really  composed  of.  Heidenhain  therefore 
holds  that  the  common  structure  of  the  living  plasm  must  be  sought  beyond 
what  is  microscopically  visible  —  that  it  consists  in  a  system  of  minute 
particles  that  possess  the  qualities  of  life,  principally  that  of  multiplication 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  539 

by  fission,  and  that  build  up  those  structures  of  which  the  cell  is  composed. 
These  ultra-microscopical  particles,  which  therefore  cannot  be  observed, 
but  the  assumption  of  which  he  considers  to  be  an  incontrovertible  neces- 
sity, he  calls  "plasomes."  It  is  not  worth  while  going  further  into  his  spec- 
ulations; it  will  at  once  be  realized  that  we  here  have  a  name  for  Haeckel's 
plastidules,  Darwin's  gemmules,  and  innumerable  similar  ideas  —  unknown 
quantities  that  can  be  used  neither  for  the  purposes  of  observation  nor  for 
theoretical  calculation  and  that  are  therefore  automatically  eliminated  from 
the  problem  of  life.  True,  ultra-microscopical  technics  have  since  given  us 
some  insight  into  the  composition  of  the  living  substance  over  and  above 
w^hat  the  microscope  has  been  able  to  provide,  but  no  one  has  succeeded  in 
isolating  any  vital  unit  in  this  way,  and  up  till  now  the  cell,  with  all  its 
complications,  remains  the  smallest  form  under  which  the  living  substance 
has  been  found  to  exist  by  itself  and  independently  of  other  living  entities. 
Of  undoubtedly  greater  value  have  been  those  facts  in  regard  to  the  composi- 
tion of  the  cell  that  have  been  contributed  by  modern  chemical  research, 
which  will  be  discussed  later. 

While,  then,  the  fundamental  substance  of  the  cell  has  remained  in  its 
innermost  essence  undiscovered,  careful  and  extensive  studies  have  been  de- 
voted to  the  mass  of  cell  products  of  which  the  bodily  tissues  are  built  up. 
Of  the  pioneer  research-work  in  this  field  may  be  mentioned  the  investi- 
gations of  the  elder  Heidenhain  into  the  glandular  secretion  in  man  and  the 
higher  animals,  as  a  result  of  which  light  has  been  thrown  for  the  first  time 
especially  upon  the  microscopical  structure  of  the  salivary  glands  and  the 
relation  between  the  composition  of  their  cells  and  the  nature  of  their  se- 
cretion. In  his  footsteps  followed  Flemming,  Altmann,  the  younger  Heiden- 
hain, and  many  other  cytologists,  who  observed  and  compared  the  different 
phenomena  in  the  epithelial  cells,  both  the  secreting  and  the  resorbing,  in 
the  various  organs  of  the  body  and  the  cells  covering  the  surface  of  the  body. 
In  this  sphere  the  study  of  the  origin  and  development  of  the  granular  forma- 
tions has  been  most  intensive. 

Nerve  investigations 
One  field  of  inquiry  that  has  especially  occupied  the  attention  of  modern 
cytology  is  the  nervous  system.  Its  highly  complicated  structure  long  re- 
sisted all  attempts  at  an  explanation,  until  methods  were  discovered  whereby 
it  is  possible  to  colour  only  certain  special  elements,  which  can  thus  be  ex- 
amined in  their  entire  length.  These  "elective"  methods  include  impreg- 
nation with  metallic  salts,  which  has  been  applied  in  various  forms  by  the 
Italian  Camillo  Golgi  (1844-19x6),  professor  at  Pavia,  the  Spaniard  San- 
tiago Ramon  y  Cajal,  born  in  1851,  professor  at  Madrid  and  an  unusally 
thorough  expert  in  the  elements  of  the  nervous  system  throughout  the  ani- 
mal kingdom,  the  author  of  a  number  of  papers  on  the  subject,  as  well  as 


540  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

the  monumental  work  Histologic  du  sysfeme  nerveux,  and  the  Hungarian  Stefan 
Apathy  (1863-1913),  professor  at  Koloszvar.  Another  method  that  was  pro- 
ductive in  this  respect  has  been  the  incravital  methylene  blue-dyeing  method, 
which  was  discovered  by  Paul  Ehrlich  (1851-1915),  disciple  of  Koch  and 
principal  of  the  laboratory  of  hygiene  at  Frankfurt  am  Main,  and  which 
has  been  further  applied  especially  by  A.  Bethe,  professor  at  Strassburg. 
Others  who  have  studied  the  nervous  system  include  the  aged  Kolliker,  the 
Frenchman  Louis  Antoine  Ranvier  (1835-1911),  professor  at  Paris  and 
active  worker  in  many  branches  of  cytology,  and  also  Gustaf  Retzius  (1841- 
1919),  son  of  the  above-mentioned  anthropologist  and  early  in  life  an  assid- 
uous worker  in  this  sphere.  Neurological  research  has  to  a  certain  extent 
sought  to  ascertain  the  structure  of  the  actual  nerve-cells  and  their  internal 
modifications  during  different  stages  of  activity;  as  expressions  for  the  phys- 
iological condition  in  the  protoplasm  of  these  cells  have  been  characterized 
the  granular  formations  amassed  in  stages  of  rest  and  disappearing  upon 
irritation,  which  are  called  tigroid  substance,  owing  to  their  appearance, 
or  "Nissl's  granules"  after  their  discoverer,  Friedrich  Nissl,  hospital  doc- 
tor at  Frankfurt  am  Main  (died  1919).  Still  greater  interest,  however,  has 
been  devoted  to  the  problem  of  the  connexion  between  the  nerve  elements, 
which  indeed  is  of  vast  importance  also  from  the  physiological  point  of 
view.  In  this  field  there  have  been  two  mutually  opposed  theories.  Even 
His  had  observed  that  there  grow  out  from  the  embryonic  nerve-cells  threads, 
which  become  longer  and  longer.  Later  on,  Kolliker,  Cajal,  and  Retzius, 
among  others,  held  the  view  that  these  threads  give  rise  to  the  nervous 
fibrillar  and  that  the  nervous  system  is  thus  formed  of  a  number  of  mutually 
independent  elements,  consisting  of  a  cell  with  its  concomitant  nerve-thread 
and  connected  with  its  neighbours  only  by  contact.  In  opposition  to  this 
view.  Apathy  in  particular  has  maintained  that  the  nerve-thread  is  formed 
of  a  whole  series  of  cells  and  that  its  ramifications  extend  not  only  up  to, 
but  also  into,  the  plasm  in  the  ganglion-cells.  The  conflict  between  these 
two  lines  of  thought  was  at  one  time  quite  lively,  but  apparently  died  down 
without  either  party's  being  able  to  claim  a  decisive  victory. 

Muscle  investigations 
Besides  the  nervous  system,  the  musculature  early  attracted  the  attention 
of  the  cytologists,  especially  the  cross-striated  musculature,  the  complex 
structure  of  which  had  long  withstood  all  attempts  to  interpret  it.  William 
Bowman  (1816-91),  professor  of  physiology  in  London,  was  the  first  to 
make  any  weighty  contribution  towards  the  solution  of  the  problem.  In  a 
treatise  printed  in  1840  he  describes  how  the  muscle  is  composed  of  fibrillar, 
surrounded  by  a  substance  that  he  calls  sarcolemma,  and  how  the  fibrillar 
are  divided  crosswise  into  laminx  of  various  degrees  of  density.  During  the 
time  that  has  elapsed  since  then,  muscular  histology  has  had  many  students. 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  541 

The  most  important  progress  is  coupled  with  the  names  of  Alexander  Rol- 
LETT  (1834-1903)  and  Theodor  Wilhelm  Engelmann  (1843-1909),  both 
professors  of  physiology,  the  former  at  Graz  and  the  latter  first  at  Utrecht 
and  afterwards  in  Berlin.  Both  of  them  have  done  service  in  ascertaining 
the  regular  sequence  of  the  cross-stripes  in  the  muscles.  Rollett  is  responsi- 
ble for  these  formations'  being  denoted,  as  they  still  are,  by  letters.  Engel- 
mann, a  disciple  of  Gegenbaur  and  a  distinguished  investigator  in  many  fields 
of  research,  made  a  special  study  of  the  physical  qualities  of  muscle  —  the 
condition  of  the  various  elements  in  normal  and  polarized  light,  upon  con- 
traction and  relaxation.  These  results  led  to  a  one-sided  physical  view  of 
muscular  action,  which  was  still  further  advanced  by  Helmholtz's  and  other 
physiologists'  investigations  into  the  mechanics  of  muscular  action.  On  the 
other  hand,  Emil  Holmgren  (i866-i9ix),  professor  of  histology  at  Stock- 
holm, Sweden,  held  a  more  morphological  conception  of  the  muscular 
process;  by  careful  experimental  and  microscopical  studies  of  the  granular 
formations  which,  thanks  mostly  to  G.  Retzius,  were  already  known,  which 
are  situated  between  the  cross-sections  of  the  various  fibrills,  he  discovered 
that  the  granules  are  the  organs  which  bring  about  the  change  of  substance 
in  the  muscle  during  action;  his  views  were  accepted  and  elaborated  by 
AuGusTE  Prenant,  professor  at  Paris  and  well  known  as  an  unusually  many- 
sided  cytologist  and  author  of  that  both  extensive  and  intensive  work  en- 
titled Traite  de  cytologie.  We  can  deal  only  briefly  with  the  various  categories 
of  supporting  tissue  —  connective  tissue,  cartilage,  bone.  In  this  field  of  re- 
search a  number  of  investigations,  important  from  the  point  of  view  of  prin- 
ciple and  masterly  in  their  technique,  have  been  carried  out  by,  inter  alia, 
Ranvier,  Flemming,  Studnicka,  and  the  Dane  F.  C.  C.  Hansen;  these  have 
discovered  especially  the  origin  of  the  categories  of  supporting  tissues  and 
their  transitions  into  one  another.^ 

Discovery  of  fertilisation 
Undoubtedly  the  greatest  service  to  biology  that  has  been  performed  by 
modern  cell-research,  however,  is  its  having  given  us  our  present  knowledge 
of  the  course  and  significance  of  fertilization  —  a  discovery  worthy  to  be 
placed  by  the  side  of  the  explanation  of  the  circulation  of  the  blood  in  the 
seventeenth  century.  If,  however,  we  compare  the  course  of  these  two  great 
achievements  in  the  field  of  research,  we  get  a  striking  impression  of  the  con- 
trast that  exists  between  scientific  activities  nowadays  and  those  of  a  couple 
of  centuries  ago.  On  the  one  hand,  Harvey,  who  spent  twenty  years  or  so 
quietly  and  peacefully  examining  the  idea  that  had  been  kindled  in  him  in 
his  youth,  and  who  afterwards  submits  it  to  the  world  in  its  perfect  and 

^  Accounts  of  the  development  of  cell  research  in  more  modern  times  will  be  found  in 
Prenant's  above-mentioned  work,  in  M.  Heidenhain's  Plasma  und  Zelk,  and  in  other  histological 
text-books,  to  which  the  reader  is  referred. 


5  42.  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

consummate  form.  On  the  other  hand,  a  number  of  scientists  of  today, 
some  of  them  admittedly  of  the  highest  rank,  working  all  at  the  same  time 
in  mutual  rivalry  at  the  problem  of  fertilization,  expound  their  results 
practically  every  year,  often  in  a  half-finished  state  and  sadly  in  need  of 
emendation,  and  then  disputing  each  other's  claim  to  the  honour  of  hav- 
ing produced  the  various  details  of  the  discovery,  each  one  seeking  to  inter- 
pret according  to  his  own  lights  statements  that  are  often  found  to  have 
been  originally  formulated  as  mere  assumptions  and  suggestions.  The  account 
of  how  our  knowledge  of  the  origin  of  individual  life  was  finally  acquired 
can  therefore  hardly  be  so  attractive  a  task  as  that  of  describing  Harvey's 
lifework. 

That  science  had  so  long  to  wait  before  the  phenomena  of  fertilization 
were  fully  elucidated  is,  of  course,  primarily  due  to  the  fact  that  the  knowl- 
edge of  its  basis,  the  cell,  was  for  so  long  incomplete.  And  in  particular  the 
idea  as  to  the  nature  of  the  nucleus  of  the  cell  was,  as  O.  Hertwig  so  weightily 
observes,  still  extremely  vague  as  late  as  in  the  seventies;  a  cystic,  homogene- 
ous formation  was  seen  in  the  middle  of  the  cell,  and  no  really  clear  idea  was 
obtained  as  to  its  meaning.  It  was  supposed  to  have  been  observed  that  on 
certain  occasions  this  formation  disappeared  and  that  this  was  particularly 
so  within  the  egg-cell;  moreover,  it  was  postulated  by  Haeckel's  biogeneti- 
cal  principle,  according  to  which  every  living  being  arises  out  of  an  entirely 
undifferentiated  mass  of  plasm.  It  was  thought  to  be  probable  that  sperma- 
tozoa, one  or  several,  penetrate  the  egg  upon  fertilization,  but  the  part  they 
played  in  the  process  was  utterly  vague;  on  the  whole,  it  was  deemed  suffi- 
cient to  assume  some  kind  of  chemical  or  physical  influence  upon  the  egg- 
cell,  whereby  its  stages  of  segmentation,  which  had  already  been  studied, 
were  produced.  Indeed,  the  phenomena  of  nuclear  division,  referred  to  above, 
had  been  partially  investigated  in  the  case  of  egg-cells;  Fol  particularly  had 
observed  radial  phenomena  accompanying  division,  and  Biitschli  the  actual 
nuclear  pole,  but  no  one  had  as  yet  gained  any  clear  idea  of  the  process. 

In  1875  O.  Hertwig  spent  some  months  by  the  Mediterranean  Sea  and 
there  discovered  an  object  particularly  suitable  for  studies  in  fertilization 
and  egg-development  in  the  sea-urchin,  whose  eggs  are  transparent,  occur 
in  large  numbers,  and  are  rapidly  developed.  The  results  he  obtained  from 
his  investigations  of  this  material  he  recorded  in  a  dissertation  written  for 
the  purpose  of  obtaining  a  lectureship  at  Jena.  Among  the  theses  that  ac- 
companied the  paper,  according  to  the  German  custom,  the  first  runs  as 
follows :  ' '  Die  Befruchtung  beruht  auj  der  Verschmelzung  von  geschlectlkh  differen- 
Xierten  Zellkernen."  This  statement,  upon  which  further  light  is  thrown  in  the 
paper  itself,  really  contains  the  essence  of  our  modern  theory  of  fertilization. 
There  is  indeed  still  another  of  these  theses  that  is  of  importance:  the  as- 
sertion that  the  egg  does  not  pass  through  any  ' '  monera ' '  stage  —  a  statement 


MODERNBIOLOGY  5  43 

directly  conflicting  with  the  master's  (Haeckel's)  theory.  Otherwise  this 
work  is  in  many  parts  somewhat  incomplete;  thus,  the  so-called  pro- 
nucleus in  the  egg  is  supposed  to  be  developed  out  of  the  germinal  spot  in 
the  ovarial  egg,  while  the  rest  of  the  germinal  vesicle  is  assumed  to  have 
disappeared  —  this  being  stated  to  apply  to  the  entire  animal  kingdom.  No 
polar  bodies  have  been  observed,  nor  has  it  been  possible  to  prove  the  pene- 
tration of  the  spermatozoa  into  the  egg.  On  the  other  hand,  what  is  described 
and  illustrated  is  how  two  nuclei  in  the  egg  gradually  approach  one  another 
and  coalesce,  one  of  which  comes  from  the  extreme  part  of  the  egg-cell  and 
is  therefore  characterized  as  the  nucleus  of  the  male  sexual  product.  As  a 
matter  of  fact,  Biitschli  and  others  had  previously  observed  two  nuclei  unite 
in  the  fertilized  egg,  but  had  not  utilized  their  discovery  for  the  purpose  of 
a  general  interpretation;  simultaneously  with  O.  Hertwig,  van  Beneden  had 
published  an  account  of  certain  fertilization-phenomena  in  the  egg  of  the 
Mammalia  and  had  therein  expressed  the  view  that,  of  the  two  nuclei  which 
he  also  had  observed  in  the  newly-fertilized  egg,  one  is  of  male  and  the 
other  of  female  origin,  but  he  made  this  statement  under  reserve  as  being 
only  a  hypothesis,  "which  may  be  accepted  or  rejected."  The  principle 
that  fertilization  consists  in  the  union  of  the  male  and  the  female  nuclei  was 
thus  without  any  doubt  first  set  forth  by  Oscar  Hertwig;  he  was  the  first  to 
realize  the  significance  of  the  phenomena  and  he  therefore  deserves  all  the 
honour  for  it. 

Our  knowledge  of  fertilization  thus  made  slow  progress,  with  the  col- 
laboration of  different  investigators.  Fol  was  the  first  who  actually  saw 
(1879)  the  spermatozoon  penetrate  the  egg,  thereby  establishing  what 
O.  Hertwig  had  already  concluded,  that  one  single  male  cell  performs  the 
act  of  fertilization.  The  latter  scientist  followed  up  his  studies  of  fertiliza- 
tion and  gradually  succeeded  in  arriving  at  a  clearer  view  of  the  subject;  in 
a  work  on  the  fertilization  of  the  worms  he  gives  an  account  particularly  of 
the  expulsion  of  the  polar  bodies;  these  bodies,  which  have  already  been 
described  by  Sven  Loven  —  and  possibly  still  earlier  by  the  aged  Carus  — 
were  now  found  to  arise  through  indirect  nuclear  division,  but  were  still 
regarded  by  Hertwig  as  one  of  the  more  incidental  phenomena  of  fertiliza- 
tion. It  was  not  until  later  that  he  discovered  them  in  his  first  subject  of 
investigation,  the  egg  of  the  sea-urchin.  The  next  great  step  towards  a  solu- 
tion of  the  riddle  of  fertilization  was  taken  by  Flemming,  who  in  1879 
established  the  longitudinal  cleavage  of  the  chromosomes  in  indirect  cell- 
division,  which  was  afterwards  confirmed  by  Retzius  and  Strasburger.  In 
1887  van  Beneden  published  the  results  of  investigation  into  the  fertiliza- 
tion of  the  lumbrical  ascarid  worm  of  the  horse,  Ascaris  megalocephala,  well 
known  on  account  of  its  few  but  large  chromosomes.  In  this  animal  he  found, 
and  afterwards  established  in  other  quarters  also,  the  important  fact  that 


544  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

every  animal  has  an  equal  number  of  chromosomes  in  each  cell.  In  connexion 
therewith  he  discovered  the  reduction  in  the  number  of  chromosomes  in  the 
sexual  cells:  that  upon  the  latter's  maturation-division  the  number  of  chro- 
mosomes in  both  the  male  and  the  female  elements  are  reduced  to  half  of 
the  normal  number,  which  is  again  restored  upon  fertilization,  when  the 
male  and  female  chromosomes  are  united.  Somewhat  later  Karl  Rabl  (1853- 
1917),  professor  at  Leipzig,  detected  the  individuality  of  chromosomes:  that 
in  a  cell  every  chromosome  originates  from  a  given  chromosome,  like  itself 
in  form  and  size,  in  the  mother  cell.  And  finally,  in  1901,  the  American 
W.  S.  Sutton  discovered  the  so-called  accessory  chromosome,  which  at  the 
nuclear  division  assumes  a  place  for  itself.  All  these  facts  have  played  a  de- 
cisive part  in  modern  heredity-research  and  will  be  further  developed  later 
on  in  this  work. 

As  a  result  of  these  investigations  into  fertilization,^  very  briefly  re- 
ferred to  above,  our  knowledge  of  the  phenomena  of  life  was  so  considerably 
enhanced  that  it  is  difficult  to  overestimate  its  value;  this  not  least  because 
the  same  fertilization-phenomena  were  established  in  the  vegetable  at  the 
same  time  as  in  the  animal  kingdom:  the  union  of  male  and  female  nucleus, 
the  reduction  of  the  chromatin,  and  the  individuality  of  the  chromosomes; 
all  these  processes  take  place  with  a  certain  number  of  modifications,  but 
on  the  same  principle  in  every  multicellular  organism.  Life  has  thereby  been 
given  a  uniformity  far  more  demonstrable  and  real  than  the  hypothetical 
common  descent  of  Darwinism.  Even  in  the  lowest  unicellular  organisms, 
whether  they  belong  to  the  animal  or  the  vegetable  kingdom,  a  similarity 
in  their  evolution  has  been  definitely  established.  We  shall  now  proceed  to 
discuss  these  forms. 


3 .   Microbiology 

The  Darwinists  of  the  earlier  school,  chiefly  Haeckel,  largely  interested 
themselves,  as  we  have  seen,  in  the  very  lowest  animal  forms;  it  was  expected 
that  they  would  produce  fresh  ideas  in  regard  to  the  origin  of  life  upon  the 
earth,  discoveries  that  would  fill  the  gap  between  living  and  lifeless  sub- 
stance and  would  thus  make  the  great  evolutional  series  in  the  universe 
entirely  uniform.  These  expectations,  however,  whether  associated  with 
Huxley's  bathybius  slime  or  with  Haeckel's  Monera,  have  not  been  fulfilled; 
bathybius  turned  out  to  be  a  lifeless  calcareous  deposit,  and  in  the  Monera 
have  been  found  nuclei  and  other  organic  details  giving  evidence  of  ordinary 

^  In  an  article  entitled  "  Dokumente  xur  Geschkhte  der  Zeugungshhre"  (in  Archiv  fur  micro- 
scopische  Anatomic,  Bd.  90),  O.  Hertwig  has  given  a  comprehensive  account  of  the  history  of 
fertilization-research  up  to  the  year  1917. 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  545 

cell-Structure.  Indeed,  the  cellular  structure  of  these  lowest  organisms  has 
proved  to  be  highly  complex,  in  many  of  them  competing  with  the  funda- 
mental elements  in  the  highest  organisms.  Thus  there  remains  nothing  to 
be  done  beyond  widening,  by  strenuous  intensive  research,  our  knowledge 
of  these  beings,  whose  vital  manifestations  have  in  many  respects  proved 
of  service  in  answering  questions  of  the  greatest  theoretical  interest,  not  to 
speak  of  the  important  practical  problems  that  have  been  solved  through 
an  extended  knowledge  of  the  subject. 

Protozoa 
Of  the  unicellular  organisms,  the  Protozoa  have,  as  we  know,  been  longest 
known;  the  earlier  progress  made  in  this  field  of  research  has  been  described 
in  a  previous  chapter.  Of  those  who  have  worked  at  the  subject  at  a  later 
period  the  most  conspicuous  and  successful  investigators  and  distinguished 
teachers  were  Biitschli  and  Richard  Hertwig.  The  Protozoa  have  proved  to 
possess  a  wealth  of  different  forms  and  structures,  both  in  protoplasm  and 
nuclei,  which  has  provided  the  science  of  general  cytology  with  an  invalu- 
able material  for  purposes  of  comparison.  Biitschli's  investigations  into  their 
plasma  and  the  changes  that  take  place  therein  in  different  stages  have  al- 
ready been  mentioned  above.  Earlier  naturalists  were  inclined  to  see  in  the 
Protozoa  radically  undifferentiated  plasm,  but  this  assumption  has  been  ut- 
terly disproved  by  experience;  on  the  contrary,  the  higher  unicellular  ani- 
mals possess  a  great  number  of  plasmic  formations  of  a  markedly  organic 
character  —  cilia  and  flagella,  vacuoles  and  muscular  fibrillas.  And  their 
vital  manifestations  have  after  careful  investigation  been  proved  to  exist  in 
undreamt-of  numbers;  their  irritability  and  way  of  reacting  to  different 
impressions  offer  an  important  field  for  experimental  biology  to  investigate. 
The  nuclei  of  the  Protozoa  have  been  of  special  interest  owing  to  their 
immense  wealth  of  form,  to  which  the  higher  animal  cells  have  not  attained, 
and  owing  to  their  correspondingly  numerous  functions.  It  is  in  this  sphere 
that  R.  Hertwig  has  made  his  most  important  contribution  to  the  advance- 
ment of  biology.  To  start  with,  he  has  demonstrated  that  the  nucleus  in  the 
Protozoa  contains  the  same  constituents  as  the  cell-nucleus  in  general  — 
chromatin,  linin,  and  nuclear  body.  Moreover,  the  chromatin  substance  is 
in  many  cases  found  to  be  divided  up  in  the  cellular  plasm  in  the  form  of 
granules  or  a  network,  and  sometimes  the  nucleus  is  entirely  incorporated 
in  this  latter  —  a  phenomenon  that  is  reminiscent  of  bacterial  chromatin's 
being  invariably  distributed  over  the  cellular  body,  and  that  at  the  same 
time  explains  part  of  Haeckel's  Monera.  Upon  the  presence  of  the  nucleus 
depends  the  Protozoa's  capacity  for  assimilation;  a  fragment  of  such  a  cell 
without  the  nucleus  would  perish  for  lack  of  metabolism.  Of  still  greater 
importance  is  the  condition  of  the  nucleus  in  the  propagation  of  Protozoa; 
since  this  generally  takes  place  through  division,  the  process  is  started  by 


546  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

the  nucleus,  which  then  displays  a  number  of  different  phenomena  in  differ- 
ent forms:  on  the  one  hand,  direct  division  through  interlacing;  on  the  other 
hand,  a  regular  mitosis,  with  a  division  of  the  centrosome  and  spindle- 
formation;  and,  between  the  extremes,  a  number  of  transition  forms.  After 
the  division  the  nucleus  and  plasma  grow  at  different  speeds  until  a  certain 
ratio  of  bulk  arises  between  them;  then  a  fresh  division  takes  place.  This 
"nucleus-plasma  relation,"  as  R.  Hertwig  calls  it,  is  thus  a  decisive  factor 
in  reproduction  and  not,  as  formerly  supposed,  a  growth  beyond  the  nor- 
mal standard,  for  this  can  vary  considerably  even  in  the  same  species.  Still 
more  remarkable  are  the  phenomena  that  R.  Hertwig  discovered  upon  the 
conjugation  of  the  Protozoa  —  in  the  fusion  of  two  individuals  which  pre- 
cedes division  in  certain  circumstances.  In  many  Protozoa  there  exists,  besides 
the  ordinary  large  nucleus,  a  small  nucleus,  called  the  micronucleus,  which, 
previous  to  conjugation,  divides  itself  twice;  three  of  the  divided  nuclei  per- 
ish, while  the  fourth  unites  with  the  corresponding  nucleus  in  the  conju- 
gating neighbouring  cell,  whereupon  out  of  the  unifying  product  fresh  nuclei 
are  formed  in  the  cells,  whose  large  nuclei  meanwhile  disintegrate.  In  the 
three  disappearing  divided  nuclei  R.  Hertwig  has  seen  the  equivalent  of  the 
polar  bodies  in  the  eggs  of  higher  animals,  while  the  likewise  moribund 
large  nucleus  has  been  held  to  correspond  to  the  body  in  a  higher  animal, 
which  dies,  whereas  the  sexual  cells,  here  equivalent  to  the  conjugated 
small  nuclei,  reproduce  the  life-form.  Whether  or  not  these  comparisons 
may  perhaps  have  been  carried  too  far,  the  future  must  decide;  it  is  certain 
that  through  them  a  number  of  vital  phenomena  of  general  interest  have 
been  viewed  in  an  entirely  new  light,  and  the  uniformity  of  the  fundamental 
phenomena  of  life  has  received  further  confirmation. 

Bacteriology 
Of  even  greater  importance,  however,  has  been  the  progress  made  in  the 
sphere  of  bacteriology;  it  was  during  this  period  that  light  was  thrown 
upon  the  part  played  by  bacteria  as  producers  of  disease  and  that  their  bi- 
ology was  discovered.  Theories  had  long  been  in  circulation  that  minute 
living  "seeds  of  disease"  were  the  causes  particularly  of  the  great  plagues; 
such  a  hypothesis  had  been  set  up  during  the  Renaissance  by  the  Italian 
physician  Girolamo  Fracastoro  (1483-1533);  Linnsus,  it  will  be  remem- 
bered, had  embraced  similar  ideas;  these  theories  had  been  encouraged  by 
the  discovery  of  yeast-fungi  in  the  eigh teen-thirties;  Henle  had  been  spe- 
cially interested  in  "parasites"  as  producers  of  disease,  and  as  a  proof  of  his 
assumption  of  such  a  cause  of  disease  he  had  formulated  the  principle :  con- 
stant existence,  isolation  from  foreign  interference,  reproduction  of  the  form 
of  disease  by  means  of  the  isolated  parasite.  These  conditions,  however, 
were  found  to  be  difficult  to  fulfil;  even  Pasteur,  who  was  nevertheless  the 
founder  of  modern  bacteriology,  had  not  succeeded  in  finding  a  means  of 


MODERNBIOLOGY  5  47 

safely  isolating  the  micro-organisms  that  were  to  be  examined  and  thus 
obtaining  pure  cultures  of  them.  He  had  certainly  adhered  to  the  idea  of 
constancy  of  species  in  the  micro-organisms,  but  other  investigators  of  the 
highest  reputation  had  maintained  in  contrast  thereto  the  "pleomorphism" 
of  these  beings  —  that  one  form  could  pass  unrestrictedly  into  others  of  an 
entirely  different  nature;  this  had  been  the  view  of  Lister,  the  famous  in- 
ventor of  the  antiseptic  bandage,  as  also  of  the  well-known  botanist  Nageli, 
for  reasons  which  will  be  mentioned  later  on.  It  was  in  these  circumstances 
that  Koch  made  his  important  contribution  to  the  development  of  bacteri- 
ology. 

Heinrich  Hermann  Robert  Koch  was  born  in  1843,  the  son  of  a  miner 
in  the  Harz  mountains;  he  studied  at  Gottingen  under  Henle  and  became 
a  district  doctor  in  a  provincial  town  in  Posen.  In  that  district  there  was  a 
serious  outbreak  of  anthrax  among  the  cattle,  and  the  young  doctor  was 
thus  faced  with  the  problem  of  this  disease.  At  an  early  date  a  French 
physician,  Casimir  Joseph  Davaine  (i8ii-8i),  a  practitioner  in  Paris,  had 
discovered  small  stick-shaped  formations  in  the  blood  of  animals  affected 
with  anthrax  and  through  experiments  had  found  them  to  be  producers  of 
the  disease,  but  had  not  succeeded  in  ascertaining  their  course  of  evolution 
and  method  of  distribution.  Koch  took  up  the  problem  for  fresh  treatment; 
after  victoriously  struggling  against  the  difficulties  that  a  provincial  doctor 
always  experiences  when  he  proposes  to  carry  out  experimental  research- 
work,  he  succeeded  in  elucidating  the  entire  evolutional  history  of  the 
anthrax  microbe;  how,  when  introduced  into  the  blood  of  an  animal,  it  prop- 
agates by  repeated  division  on  a  vast  scale,  and  then,  when  the  animal  has 
died,  these  microbes  are  converted  in  favourable  circumstances  into  spores 
possessing  great  powers  of  resistance  to  external  influences  and  the  ability, 
after  migrating  into  a  fresh  animal  host,  to  start  the  process  of  evolution 
all  over  again.  Koch's  genius  in  these  experiments  lay  in  the  simple  and  yet 
extremely  effective  technique  that  he  worked  out;  indeed,  it  was  in  this 
sphere  that  he  afterwards  won  his  greatest  successes.  The  anthrax  microbe 
was  at  first  cultivated  in  a  damp  chamber  in  serum,  but  Koch  soon  invented 
the  method  of  planting  bacteria  on  a  gelatin  solution;  on  this  substratum, 
which  could  be  made  solid  or  liquid  at  will  by  a  slight  alteration  of  tem- 
perature, it  was  easy  to  isolate  the  bacteria  and  produce  absolutely  pure 
cultures.  The  method,  which  in  its  simplicity  is  one  of  the  most  brilliant 
inventions  of  modern  times,  has  been  the  foundation  on  which  the  whole  of 
present-day  microbe-research  has  since  then  developed.  But,  in  addition  to 
this,  Koch  introduced  the  aniline-dye  method  into  the  study  of  bacteria,  a 
method  which  since  that  time  has  been  perfected  in  many  ways  and  one  where- 
by innumerable,  otherwise  invisible  micro-organisms  have  been  discovered 
and  described;  and,  furthermore,  he  invented  the  microscopical  illuminating 


548  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

apparatus,  constructed  to  his  order  by  the  physicist  Abbe,  of  Jena  —  nowa- 
days an  indispensable  aid  to  all  who  work  with  strong  magnifications. 

Koch's  first  discoveries  won  him  immediate  fame;  he  was  elected  a  mem- 
ber of  the  Kaiserliches  Gesundheitsamt  in  Berlin,  whose  leading  force  he 
at  once  became,  and  had  munificent  sums  placed  at  his  disposal.  During  the 
period  that  followed,  he  was  responsible  for  two  great  achievements  —  the 
discovery  of  the  tubercular  bacillus  and  the  cholera  microbe.  In  the  case 
of  the  former  he  tried  to  produce  a  specific  cure  in  tuberculin,  but,  as  is  well 
known,  without  success.  Extremely  valuable,  on  the  other  hand,  was  his 
reform  of  the  technics  of  disinfection :  the  abolition  of  the  earlier  ineffective 
means  of  disinfection,  such  as  fumigating  with  sulphur,  and  spraying  with 
carbolic,  and  the  substitution  of  new  experimentally  tested  and  therefore 
effective  methods. 

Koch' s  pupils 
Koch's  activities  included  also  the  training  of  a  host  of  pupils;  from  all 
countries  there  flocked  to  his  laboratory  students,  who  have  since  diffused 
his  methods  everywhere.  Among  these  may  be  named  F.  J.  S.  Loffler  (born 
in  1851),  the  discoverer  of  the  microbes  of  diphtheria  and  swine-fever,  and 
Emil  Behring  (1854-1917),  professor  at  Marburg,  the  founder  of  serum 
therapy.  In  his  later  years  Koch  himself  was  the  accepted  authority  on 
everything  concerning  problems  of  infection,  and  he  undertook  many  voy- 
ages, especially  to  the  tropics,  with  a  view  to  investigate  infectious  diseases 
existing  there  and  to  try  to  find  a  cure  for  them.  Of  a  despotic  disposition 
and  spoiled  by  his  early  successes,  during  his  last  years  he  did  not  always 
take  into  account  the  most  recent  discoveries,  nor  who  had  made  them, 
which  sometimes  resulted  in  disputes  that  proved  of  little  benefit  for  the 
advancement  of  science.  He  laboured,  however,  up  to  the  last,  in  spite  of 
impaired  health;  he  died  in  1910  of  paralysis  of  the  heart. 

While  thus  the  disease-producing  micro-organisms  were  giving  rise  to 
an  entirely  new  branch  of  research,  the  yeast-fungi,  which  were  allied  to 
them,  likewise  became  the  object  of  close  study.  The  pioneer  in  this  field, 
next  to  Pasteur,  was  the  Dane  Emil  Kristian  Hansen  (1841-1909).  Born  of 
a  working-class  family,  he  became  at  first  a  secondary-school  teacher,  ma- 
triculated when  he  was  near  the  age  of  thirty,  and  afterwards  applied  himself 
to  the  study  of  chemistry  and  biology.  When  the  famous  Karlsberg  laboratory 
was  instituted  by  the  brewer  Jacobsen,  of  Copenhagen,  Hansen  became  its 
leading  force,  and,  in  compliance  with  the  wishes  of  the  founder,  devoted 
himself  entirely  to  the  study  of  the  fermenting  process.  In  this  sphere  he 
created  what  has  ever  since  been  the  accepted  technology  of  the  subject; 
in  particular,  he  perfected  the  pure  cultivation  of  the  yeast-fungi  by  an  in- 
genious method  of  isolating  a  single  specimen  of  these  organisms,  which 
occur  in  masses  and  are  only  visible  under  the  strongest  magnifications;  by 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  549 

allowing  this  specimen  to  reproduce  itself  there  came  into  being  a  "pure 
line"  of  yeast-fungi,  possessing  fully  controllable  characters.  This  technique 
of  yeast-cultivation  has  entirely  reformed  the  brewing  industry  and  the 
manufacture  of  yeast.  Moreover,  Hansen  has  added  much  of  value  to  our 
knowledge  of  the  enzvmes,  which  play  an  active  part  in  fermentation  phe- 
nomena, and  a  number  of  other  kindred  manifestations.  A  new  conception 
of  the  process  of  fermentation  has  been  produced  by  Eduard  Buchner  (1860- 
1917),  professor  of  chemistry  at  Berlin.  He  has  proved  that  the  alcoholic 
fermentation  of  sugar  is  not,  as  was  hitherto  believed,  caused  directly  by 
vital  action  on  the  part  of  the  yeast-fungi,  but  that  these  organisms  produce 
a  chemical  ferment  which  brings  about  the  yeasting  and  which  can  be  iso- 
lated and  made  to  function  even  in  the  absence  of  the  fungi.  As  a  result  of 
this  discovery  the  classical  fermentation-theory  set  up  by  Pasteur  has  been 
considerably  modified  and  has  been  transferred  from  the  sphere  of  biology 
to  that  of  chemistry.  A  number  of  other  phenomena  in  the  same  category  will 
be  discussed  later  on  in  this  work. 

Of  far  later  date  than  the  knowledge  of  bacteria  and  yeast-fungi  is  our 
knowledge  of  another  group  of  organisms,  which  are  usually  referred  to 
the  animal  kingdom  and  which  have  been  found  to  resemble  bacteria  in 
being  producers  of  disease  —  namely,  the  Sporozoa.  Even  Meckel  was  aware 
that  the  well-known  disease  "ague,"  or  malaria,  was  accompanied  by  a 
peculiar  darkening  of  the  blood  corpuscles  and  of  certain  other  tissue  ele- 
ments in  the  infected  subjects.  But  the  disease  itself  was  considered  to  be 
"miasmatic"  —  that  is,  due  to  poisonous  vapours  emanating  from  the  hu- 
mid districts  in  which  it  occurs.  Then  the  French  army  surgeon  Alphonse 
Laveran  (1845-19x0,  while  serving  in  Algeria  in  1880,  discovered  that  the 
said  pigmentation  is  caused  by  a  parasite  which  occurs  under  various  forms, 
but  which,  owing  to  its  mobility,  he  thought  belonged  to  the  animal  king- 
dom. His  accurate  description  of  the  newly-discovered  producer  of  disease 
was  worthy  of  the  closest  attention,  but  it  threw  no  light  on  the  causes 
of  its  distribution.  This  point  was  definitely  answered  by  the  Englishman 
Sir  Ronald  Ross,  who  was  born  in  1857  in  India,  where  he  was  serving  as 
an  army  surgeon,  and  who  was  afterwards  elected  to  a  professorial  chair  at  an 
institute  of  tropical  diseases  at  Liverpool.  He  discovered  the  alternation  of 
generation  in  the  malarial  plasmodium:  how,  after  developing  in  the  human 
blood,  it  is  absorbed  by  blood-sucking  mosquitoes,  is  conveyed  from  the 
mosquito's  intestinal  canal  into  its  salivary  glands,  and  thence  passes  into 
the  blood  of  human  beings,  who  thus  become  likewise  infected.  An  impor- 
tant contribution  to  the  problem  of  malaria  has  been  made  by  the  Italian 
Giovanni  Baptista  Grassi  (1854-19x5),  professor  of  zoology  at  Rome,  who 
made  his  name  especially  on  account  of  the  effective  measures  of  protection 
he  adopted  against  malaria  in  his  own  country,  which  was  so   terribly 


550  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

ravaged  by  that  disease;  by  excluding  the  mosquitoes  from  human  dwellings 
and  eradicating  their  larvae,  he  has  succeeded  in  making  inhabitable  dis- 
tricts that  were  formerly  dangerous  to  live  in,  and,  further,  his  exhaustive 
studies  of  the  biology  of  the  malarial  mosquito  have  made  it  possible  for 
other  countries  also  to  take  energetic  measures  for  its  extermination. 

A  number  of  other  parasites  have  latterly  been  discovered  and  described, 
as,  for  example,  the  Flagellata,  which  produce  in  tropical  Africa  the  fatal 
sleeping-sickness,  which  is  transmitted  from  one  person  to  another  by  the 
tick;  and,  further,  the  producer  of  the  cattle-plague,  also  an  African  disease, 
transmitted  by  the  tsetse-fly,  which  had  made  cattle-breeding  impossible  in 
extensive  districts.  These  parasites  were  specially  studied  by  Koch  and  his 
pupils. 

To  the  beginning  of  our  century  belongs  the  discovery  of  Spirockate 
pallida,  the  carrier  of  syphilitic  infections,  one  of  the  most  dangerous  ene- 
mies of  man.  It  was  discovered  by  Fritz  Schaudinn,  who  has  thereby  en- 
sured for  himself  a  place  in  the  cultural  history  of  the  world.  Born  in  1871 
in  East  Prussia,  he  studied  at  Berlin,  and  after  taking  his  doctor's  degree 
he  was  given  an  appointment  at  the  Gesundheitsamt.  Labouring  under  con- 
stant difficulties  and  in  frequent  dispute  with  the  old  despotic  Koch  and  other 
bureaucrats  in  the  Civil  Service,  who  neither  would  nor  could  appreciate  the 
value  of  his  ideas,  he  worked  his  way  up  to  a  brilliant  reputation  as  a  micro- 
biologist. It  was  not  until  shortly  before  his  death  that  he  received  the  per- 
manent post  worthy  of  him  as  head  of  a  research  institute  at  Hamburg.  He 
made  valuable  contributions  to  our  knowledge  of  the  life  of  the  malarial 
parasite;  by  means  of  experiments  upon  himself  he  studied  the  dangerous 
Amceba  histolytica,  the  producer  of  a  serious  form  of  intestinal  catarrh  —  an 
experiment  that  cost  him  his  life.  He  also  published  the  valuable  results  of 
his  researches  into  the  reproduction  of  the  Foraminifera  and  Heliozoa.  The 
above-mentioned  discovery  of  Spirochate  pallida  he  made  in  the  year  before 
he  died.  Moreover,  he  had  a  number  of  distinguished  pupils,  as,  for  instance, 
M.  Hartmann,  born  in  1876,  who  took  up  for  further  study  his  theoretical 
research-work  on  the  Protozoa,  and  S.  Prowazek  (1875-1916),  who  con- 
tinued his  work  on  the  disease-producing  Sporozoa. 


4.  Vegetable  Morphology 

Development  from  romanticism  to  exact  investigation 
It  is  necessary  to  take  a  brief  glance  at  the  method  of  morphological  re- 
search as  applied  in  the  sphere  of  botany,  especially  in  view  of  the  part 
played  by  plants  as  a  basis  for  modern  evolutional  theories.  For  this  pur- 
pose we  must  go  back  to  the  period  before  the  appearance  of  Darwinism, 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  551 

when  romantic  idealism  still  prevailed  in  biological  research-work.  At  that 
time  Goethe's  spiral  visions  and  metamorphosis  theory  were  still  playing 
their  part  as  foundations  on  which  various  naturalists  based  their  concep- 
tions of  the  form  and  growth  of  plants  and  the  position  and  development 
of  their  leaves.  These  imaginings  produced  appalling  confusion  in  ideas  and 
theories.  "It  is  remarkable,"  says  Sachs  in  his  Geschkhte  der  Botanik,  "that 
as  soon  as  there  was  any  mention  of  the  metamorphosis  of  plants,  even 
gifted  and  clever  men  gave  way  to  nonsensical  gibberish."  But  even  clear- 
thinking  investigators  sought  to  solve  these  problems  from  a  purely  ideal 
point  of  view;  the  position  of  the  leaves  of  the  plants  was  created  by  an 
idea  which  expressed  itself  in  mathematically  formulated  relations  between 
the  leaves.  Karl  Friedrich  Schimper  (1803-67),  for  the  greater  part  of  his 
life  a  private  scholar,  was  one  of  these  speculative  plant-morphologists;  he 
expressed  the  "spiral  tendency"  in  the  position  of  the  leaves  by  means  of 
a  serial  fraction.  His  ideas  were  further  developed  by  Alexander  Braun 
(1805-77),  who  studied  at  Munich,  among  others  under  Schelling,  and 
finally  became  professor  of  botany  at  Berlin  and  a  distinguished  teacher. 
Among  his  disciples  was  Haeckel,  who  highly  admired  him  and  was  largely 
influenced  by  him  in  the  romantic  direction.  Braun,  who  was  otherwise  a 
specialist  of  some  merit,  recorded  his  morphological  speculations  in  a  trea- 
tise iJber  die  Verjiingung  in  der  Nafur,  a  curious  blend  of  exact  knowledge  and 
romantic  imaginative  thought.  The  work  contains  a  number  of,  for  the  time, 
excellent  studies  of  lower  plants,  especially  unicellular  Algas,  the  growth 
and  reproduction  of  which  are  carefully  described.  Upon  these  observations, 
as  well  as  some  studies  of  the  position  of  the  leaves  in  buds  and  flowers  and 
on  the  stem  of  higher  plants,  is  based  a  "living  view  of  nature,"  which 
tries  to  find  in  nature  "  nicht  bloss  die  Wirkung  toter  Krafte,  sondern  den  Aus- 
druck  lebendiger  Tat.''  This  conception  of  nature  is  based  on  "rejuvenation" 
as  the  driving  force  in  life,  whereby  the  old  is  constantly  being  converted 
into  a  new:  the  child's  "old"  milk-teeth  into  new  ones,  the  "old"  pupa 
of  the  butterfly  larvns  into  a  new  butterfly,  to  say  nothing  of  the  spring's 
rejuvenation  of  leaves  and  herbs,  which,  of  course,  gave  rise  to  the  whole 
of  this  speculation.  "The  spirit  that  develops  in  man  is  not  outwardly  united 
to  nature,  for  its  appearance  is  already  indicated  in  the  lower  stages  of  nat- 
ural life,  especially  in  the  animal  kingdom;  rather  the  spiritual  life  is  the 
purest  representation  of  the  same  basis  of  life  as  that  which  in  previous  stages 
confronted  us  as  natural  life."  This,  of  course,  is  pure  natural  philosophy; 
it  is  no  wonder,  then,  that  Goethe's  metamorphosis  doctrine  finds  its  appli- 
cation here,  both  in  ascending  and  descending  metamorphosis  and  in  the 
spiral  arrangement  of  the  leaves,  which  on  the  model  of  Schimper  is  expressed 
in  mathematical  formulas.  It  is  strange  to  note  how  exact  observations  are 
mixed  up  with  this  fantastic  terminology,  especially  when  it  is  applied  to 


55X  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

the  then  newly-discovered  cytological  details.  "  Alle  Verjungungen  im  Zellen- 
leben  sind  mit  einer  mehr  oder  minder  tiej  eingreifenden  Entbildung  der  bereits  be- 
festigten  und  der  Fortbildung  understrebenden  Telle  der  Zelle  verbunden.''  By  this 
'^  Entbildung"  is  meant  simply  the  dissolution  of  the  cell  membranes  upon 
the  segmenting  of  the  cells,  which,  of  course,  represents  the  "Verjungungs" 
phenomenon.  These  same  principles  are  also  applied  to  vegetable  geography, 
and  the  system  becomes  merely  a  link  in  this  magnificent  unity  whereby 
"the  whole  of  nature's  course  of  development  from  the  first  manifestations 
of  life  through  an  infinite  number  of  rejuvenations  gradually  rises  to  the 
emerging  of  man."  All  this  speculation  is  interesting  as  being  an  intermedi- 
ate link  between  the  old  natural  philosophy  in  the  spirit  of  Goethe  and 
the  new  philosophy  of  Haeckel,  who  differs  from  his  master  only  in  his 
materialistic  tone,  though  but  little  in  fact.  Haeckel's  symmetry  ideas  in 
particular  are  certainly  in  imitation  of  Braun. 

Exact  research,  however,  must  eventually  come  into  its  own  even  in 
vegetable  morphology.  The  scientist  who  has  contributed  more  than  anyone 
else  towards  producing  an  exact  conception  of  the  forms  and  development 
of  plant  life  is  Nageli,  though  even  he  was  in  close  contact  with  the  old 
idealistic  philosophy.  Carl  Wilhelm  Nageli  was  born  in  1817  near  Zurich, 
where  his  father  was  a  physician,  and  it  was  intended  that  he  should  be 
trained  for  the  same  profession  at  the  college  in  his  native  town.  His  at- 
tendance at  the  lectures  of  the  aged  Oken,  however,  induced  him  to  take 
up  a  more  speculative  career,  which  he  was  finally  permitted  to  do.  He 
studied  botany  at  Geneva  under  de  Candolle  and  wrote  as  his  dissertation 
a  work  on  vegetable  classification;  he  then  went  to  Berlin  and  spent  a  couple 
of  years  studying  Hegel's  philosophy,  which,  according  to  his  own  state- 
ment, did  not  attract  him  very  much,  and  he  finally  spent  some  time  working 
at  Jena  under  Schleiden.  He  was  a  friend  of  Kolliker  and  accompanied  the 
latter  on  a  trip  to  Italy,  afterwards  becoming  professor,  first  at  Freiburg, 
then  at  Zurich,  and  ultimately  at  Munich,  where  he  spent  the  rest  of  his 
life  in  work  of  an  unusually  many-sided  and  productive  character.  Since  his 
childhood  his  health  had  been  poor,  but  he  worked  with  indomitable  en- 
ergy up  to  the  last  ten  years  of  his  life,  when  sickness  compelled  him  to 
abandon  his  activities.  He  died  in  1891.  Ill  health  brought  with  it  an 
irritable  temper,  which  made  it  difficult  to  associate  with  him,  either  as 
a  teacher  or  as  a  man  of  science;  indeed,  his  personal  pupils  were  few  in 
number,  but  the  influence  exercised  by  his  writings  was  all  the  greater.  In- 
deed, he  must  without  doubt  be  counted  among  the  foremost  botanists  of 
the  century,  and  that,  too,  in  many  different  spheres,  being  at  the  same  time 
anatomist  and  cytologist,  morphologist  and  systematist;  moreover,  his  natu- 
ral-philosophical speculations  have  proved  of  deep  significance. 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  553 

Ndgeli' s  cytological  investigations 
Nageli  was  certainly  greatest  as  a  cytologist;  his  studies  of  the  dividing 
of  the  pollen-grains  and  of  the  unicellular  Algas  have  already  been  men- 
tioned as  epoch-making  in  their  sphere,  and  through  them  he  became  one 
of  the  pioneers  of  modern  cytology.  We  may  also  include  in  this  category 
his  studies  of  the  sexual  reproduction  of  the  cryptogams,  a  problem  that  has 
largely  been  elucidated  by  him.  Nevertheless,  his  cell  research  had  its  weak- 
nesses; the  fact  that  he  long  maintains  the  old  belief  in  independent  cell- 
formation  is  of  less  importance  in  this  respect  than  the  influence  which  he 
permitted  his  theoretical  speculations  to  exercise  on  the  observations  that 
had  already  been  made.  In  the  field  of  vegetable  anatomy  a  series  of  essays 
that  he  wrote  on  the  growth  of  the  stem  and  root  forms  the  basis  of  our 
present-day  knowledge  of  the  subject.  As  a  systematist  he  was  especially 
occupied  in  studying  genera  that  possess  abundant  forms,  but  are  difficult 
to  elucidate,  chiefly  Hieracium,  the  numerous  and  mutually  overlapping  mi- 
crospecies  of  which  he  sought  to  explain  by  means  of  both  natural  observa- 
tions and  horticultural  experiments.  His  experiences  in  studying  this  difficult 
genus  led  him  to  speculate  upon  the  term  "species,"^  which  formed  the 
basis  of  his  evolutional  theories.  As  a  plant-physiologist  he  distinguished 
himself  chiefly  in  his  investigations  into  the  growth  of  starch  granules, 
whereby  he  laid  the  foundation  of  our  knowledge  of  that  curiously  organized 
structure  in  these  elements  of  stored  nutrition,  which,  as  far  as  their  chemi- 
cal composition  is  concerned,  are  comparatively  simple.  Even  in  this  line 
of  research,  however,  he  became  involved  in  theoretical  speculations  of  that 
abstract  kind  which  had  interested  him  since  his  youth. 

In  a  treatise  Uber  die  Aufgabe  der  Naturgeschichte,  dated  1844,  Nageli  has 
given  an  account  of  the  theoretical  standpoint  from  which  he  started.  He 
lays  down  as  the  aims  of  natural  research,  firstly  the  discovery  of  fresh  facts, 
and  secondly  the  creation  of  new  laws  of  thought.  His  interest  in  these 
latter  are  clearly  reminiscent  of  his  studies  in  the  Hegelian  school,  referred 
to  above.  True,  he  indignantly  repudiates  the  accusations  of  Hegelianism 
that  were  directed  against  him,  but  the  likeness  is  nevertheless  unmistakable 
and  gives  his  speculations  a  character  all  its  own,  which  is  strongly  diver- 
gent from,  for  instance,  Haeckel's;  while  the  latter  speculates  upon  forms  of 
symmetry,  the  psychic  qualities  of  matter,  and  other  ideas  reminiscent  of 
Schelling,  Nageli  is  ever  seeking  to  create  fixed  categories  of  thought,  pref- 
erably with  reference  to  mathematical  deductions.  Above  all,  he  strives  to 
create  "absolute  ideas,"  in  which  the  various  phenomena  are  to  be  defined. 
All  life  is  movement,  and  so  all  biology  must  be  evolution,  and  from  the 

'  In  contrast  to  Lamarck,  Darwin,  and  even  Haeckel,  Nageli  speaks  in  every  way  depreciat- 
ingly of  Linnaeus  and  his  work  for  the  advancement  of  classification.  As  is  well  known,  these 
views,  which  have  but  little  justification,  have  since  recurred  in  many  German  botanists. 


554  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

evolution  of  the  individual  it  is  possible  to  conclude  that  of  the  species. 
The  species  is  a  summary  of  all  similar  individuals  and,  as  such,  an  absolute 
idea;  similarly,  there  are  many  circles,  ellipses,  and  other  geometrical  figures, 
but  their  ideas  are  essentially  different  —  and  in  the  same  way  the  species 
have  no  intertransitional  forms.  "Die  absolute  Verschiedenbeit  der  Arten  scheint 
mir  durch  die  Erjahrung  hinldngliclj  bestdtigt,  und  allgemein  genug  angenommen, 
um  auch  ihrerseits  die  Absolut  he  it  der  Begrijfe  ■zii  bestdtigeti."  And  like  the  species 
the  higher  systematical  categories  also  possess  their  absoluteness;  the  vege- 
table and  the  animal  kingdoms  have  no  transitions,  for  "  dieser  Annahme  ivider- 
spricht  schon  die  Absolutheit  der  Begriffe. ' '  If  this  is  not  Hegelianism,  it  is  at  any 
rate  very  near  it. 

His  micella  theory 
The  ideas  expounded  in  this  work  of  his  early  years  proved  in  many  respects 
to  have  a  decisive  influence  on  Nageli's  future  development.  In  his  work  on 
starch  granules  he  presents  his  once  famous  micella  theory,  which  again 
shows  his  tendency  to  transfer  the  deductions  of  geometry  to  biology.  Ac- 
cording to  this  theory  the  cells  and  their  derivatives  are  composed  of  parti- 
cles called  "micellas,"  which  are  supposed  to  be  composed  of  a  number  of 
molecules,  possess  a  regular  crystalline  form,  and  in  a  dry  state  keep  close 
to  one  another,  owing  to  their  mutual  attraction;  in  certain  circumstances, 
however,  the  micellas  attract  water,  which  penetrates  in  between  them  and 
surrounds  each  one  of  them,  and  through  this  action  arises  tissue.  This  the- 
ory, which  was  irreconcilable  with  the  findings  of  physics  and  consequently 
had  to  be  abandoned  even  during  the  lifetime  of  its  originator,  shows  how 
he  strove  to  compare  animate  and  inanimate  matter;  in  actual  fact  he  denies 
any  principial  difference  between  them.  In  consequence  he  believed  also  in 
spontaneous  generation,  stubbornly  maintaining  that  doctrine  throughout 
his  life;  he  certainly  recognized  Pasteur's  experiments,  but  he  considered  that 
they  did  not  demonstrate  the  impossibility  of  spontaneous  generation,  and 
to  his  mind  spontaneous  generation  is  ' '  nicht  eine  Frage  der  Erjahrung  und  des 
Experiments,  sondern  eine  aus  dem  GesetT^e  der  Erhaltung  von  Kraft  und  Stoff  fol- 
gende  Tatsache."  In  his  youth  he  believed  in  the  spontaneous  generation  of 
unicellular  sponges  and  believed  that  it  could  be  demonstrated  by  experi- 
ment; when  he  did  not  succeed,  he  assumed  the  spontaneous  generation  of 
very  primitive  unicellular  creatures,  and  in  his  old  age  he  continued  his  re- 
treat, inasmuch  as  he  assumed  as  products  of  spontaneous  generation  a  kind 
of  extremely  primitive  life-units,  whereof  countless  numbers  go  to  form  one 
cell,  and  which  he  termed  "  probia."  But  he  was  undeniably  more  consistent 
than  Haeckel  in  not  moving  spontaneous  generation  back  to  the  beginning 
of  the  world,  holding  that  it  could  just  as  well  take  place  now  as  then, 
"for  the  difficulty  of  letting  a  cell  arise  out  of  formless  chemical  substance 
is  not  a  jot  greater  for  primeval  times  than  for  modern  times."  We  must 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  555 

also  take  in  conjunction  with  this  theory  his  positive  assertion,  previously 
referred  to,  as  to  the  pleomorphism  of  micro-organisms;  it  cannot,  of  course, 
be  denied  that  the  absence  of  any  species-characters  in  them  was  a  feature 
of  primitive  organization,  which  would  make  them  closely  akin  to  lifeless 
matter. 

His  descent  theory 
Nageli's  descent  theory  is  also  in  line  with  his  theory  of  spontaneous  genera- 
tion; since  spontaneous  generation  goes  on  incessantly,  it  is  possible  to  sup- 
pose that  the  most  highly  developed  organisms  are  really  the  oldest,  while 
the  primitive  organisms  have  been  evolved  later.  His  descent  theory  has  thus 
acquired  a  decidedly  polyphyletic  character,  and,  strictly  speaking,  it  does 
not  presuppose  any  transition  from  one  species  to  another.  The  most  inter- 
esting feature  in  Nageli's  phylogenetical  speculation  —  recorded  in  an  essay 
on  the  genesis  of  the  natural-historical  species  (1865)  and  in  a  large  work, 
Mecbanisch-pbysiologische  Theorie  der  Abstamtnungslehre  (1884)  —  is  his  criti- 
cism of  Darwin's  theory  of  selection.  In  the  course  of  his  experiments  on 
the  Hieracium  he  had  discovered  that  the  external  conditions  of  life  which 
cause  the  struggle  for  existence  do  not  alter  the  life-types;  species  that  are 
placed  in  new  conditions  of  life  do  not  assume  any  similarity  to  kindred 
species  previously  brought  under  these  conditions.  Natural  selection,  there- 
fore, cannot  possess  any  form-building  power;  it  does  exist,  but  has  only  an 
extenuative  effect  on  middle  forms.  Instead,  evolution  takes  place  out  of  the 
inner  being  of  the  organisms  in  virtue  of  an  internal  force,  which  Nageli 
most  frequently  terms  "  Vervollkommmtgskraft,"  and  once,  in  imitation  of 
Blumenbach,  "  Nisus  formativus,"  a  force  by  means  of  which  the  development 
is  led  in  a  certain  direction,  not,  as  Darwin  holds,  to  variations  in  every 
possible  direction.  This  force,  however,  is  by  no  means  a  special  life-force; 
on  the  contrary,  it  is  compared  with  the  inertia  in  inorganic  nature;  just 
as  a  rolling  globe  goes  on  until  it  meets  an  obstacle,  so  organic  evolution  — 
it,  too,  being  a  movement  —  advances  until  an  obstacle  comes  in  the  way. 
These  obstacles  can  be  either  the  struggle  for  existence,  or  else  direct  ma- 
terial influence  due  to  irritation;  according  to  Nageli  the  ruminants  have 
got  horns  as  a  result  of  striking  their  foreheads  against  one  another  —  an 
explanation  in  the  spirit  of  Lamarck. 

His  heredity  theory 
In  connexion  with  his  doctrine  of  descent  Nageli  propounds  a  heredity  the- 
ory of  his  own.  At  variance  with  Haeckel's  view  on  the  undifferentiated 
character  of  the  egg-cell  he  definitely  maintains  that  the  egg-cell  is  as  com- 
plicated as  the  creature  which  is  to  be  evolved  therefrom;  the  qualities  of 
the  coming  individual  are  all  united  in  the  egg-cell.  But  because  this  latter 
and  the  sperm  cell,  in  spite  of  their  difference  in  size,  have  an  equally  large 
share  in  the  qualities  of  the  new  individual,   these  qualities  cannot  be 


556  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

allocated  to  the  whole  protoplasm  of  the  egg;  there  must  be  a  certain  part 
of  them  that  is  particularly  responsible  for  the  specific  qualities.  This  con- 
stituent of  the  cell  Nageli  calls  idioplasma;  he  believes  that  through  segmen- 
tation it  is  imparted  to  every  fresh  cell  and  gives  the  latter  its  character; 
it  is  through  it  that  every  organism  is  such  as  it  is  and  not  otherwise.  The 
idioplasma  is,  according  to  Nageli,  a  solid  body,  not  semi-fluid  like  the  rest 
of  the  cellular  mass,  and  it  has,  of  course,  its  peculiar  composition  of  micella, 
the  shape  and  size  of  which  give  rise  to  the  most  subtle  calculations.  All 
evolution  consists  in  changes  in  the  micellas  of  the  idioplasma,  and  these 
changes  go  on  incessantly,  although  they  are  not  at  once  perceptible,  for 
the  energy  amassed  through  these  changes  is  released  intermittently,  and 
therefore  the  alterations  in  species  likewise  take  place,  not  gradually,  but 
suddenly. 

From  the  structure  of  the  idioplasma  Nageli  gradually  passes  to  atomic 
structure  in  general,  and  he  here  becomes  involved  in  speculations  as  to  the 
atoms'  being  composed  of  still  smaller  particles,  which  are  called  " amera"; 
of  these  latter  the  simple  chemical  basic  elements  are  composed,  and  Nageli 
builds  up  a  kind  of  phylogeny  for  these  elements,  according  to  which  the 
heavy  metals  must  have  originated  first,  and  afterwards  the  other  elements 
in  succession.  Further,  he  speculates  upon  the  form  of  the  atoms,  upon  ethe- 
real atoms,  ethereal  heat,  upon  the  impossibility  of  entropy,  and  various 
similar  subjects,  which  contemporary  physics  and  chemistry  had  naturally 
passed  over  in  silence. 

His  influence 
Nageli's  mechanical-physiological  theory  was  his  last  work,  so  that  he 
concluded  his  life's  activities,  in  spite  of  his  expressed  intention  to  deal  with 
natural  phenomena  on  a  mathematically  exact  basis,  in  a  mass  of  thought- 
constructions  of  just  as  impractical  a  nature  as  those  of  the  master  of  his 
youth,  Hegel.  His  influence,  however,  has  been  of  deep  significance,  not  only 
on  account  of  the  immense  number  of  important  facts  that  he  established, 
but  also  in  the  purely  theoretical  sphere.  He  was  the  first  unreservedly  to 
venture  to  reject  the  doctrine  of  natural  selection  as  the  sole  cause  of  the 
evolution  of  life  and  to  demand  that  it  be  replaced  by  another  theory  capable 
of  producing  a  more  convincing  confirmation  by  way  of  observation  and 
experiment.  The  "  Vervollkommungskraff"  on  which  he  would  base  his  ex- 
planation of  the  origin  of  species  was  really  nothing  but  a  word,  but  behind 
it  there  lay  at  any  rate  an  insight  into  the  fact  that  evolution  is  a  quality 
in  life  itself,  not  a  movement  that  is  thrust  upon  living  creatures  from  out- 
side. And  in  connexion  therewith  Nageli  points  out  that  life  need  not 
necessarily  evolve  as  a  result  of  minute  imperceptible  variations,  but  the 
changes  might  just  as  well  take  place  suddenly  and  on  a  larger  scale  —  an 
idea  which  is  certainly  not  very  strongly  brought  out  in  him,  but  which 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  557 

nevertheless  afterwards  survived;  de  Vries  especially  inherited  it  through 
his  theory  of  mutation,  but,  above  all,  Nageli's  idioplasma  theory  was  an 
idea  that  was  utilized  by  subsequent  investigators  with  much  profit.  Here, 
again,  he  really  only  invented  a  word,  but  the  idea  of  a  special  substance's 
being  the  bearer  of  the  cell's  hereditary  qualities  received  remarkable  con- 
firmation in  the  above-described  discovery  of  the  role  played  by  chromatin 
in  cell-division  and  its  importance  for  the  vital  processes  of  the  cell  in  gen- 
eral. What  prevented  Nageli  himself  from  drawing  from  his  speculation 
conclusions  of  practical  value  was  undoubtedly  his  belief  in  ' '  absolute  ideas ' ' 
and  the  derivation  of  facts  from  them  —  a  belief  that  he  never  really  suc- 
ceeded in  eradicating.  Herein,  too,  we  must  obviously  seek  the  cause  of  his 
attitude  towards  Mendel,  violently  criticized  at  a  later  date.  The  latter  had 
reported  to  him  the  results  of  his  epoch-making  experiments  and  received 
in  reply  an  inquiry  as  to  whether  the  formulas  he  had  set  up  were  not  "em- 
pirical rather  than  rational."  In  these  words  is  clearly  shown  the  weakness 
of  Nageli's  abstract-speculative  method:  he  could  not  grasp  Mendel's  incon- 
trovertible results  based  on  fact,  since  they  did  not  agree  with  his  own  the- 
ories, and  the  correspondence,  which  went  on  for  some  time,  though  in 
courteous  terms,  produced  no  result.  With  all  his  weaknesses  Nageli  never- 
theless stands  out  as  one  of  the  foremost  biologists  of  his  time,  and  his 
ideas  had  an  influence  long  after  his  death. 

Among  Nageli's  pupils  the  first  that  deserves  mention  is  his  fellow- 
countryman,  Simon  Schwendener  (1819-1919),  for  a  long  time  an  assistant 
to  his  master  and  finally  professor  at  Berlin.  Of  his  works  should  be  men- 
tioned one  entitled  Dasmechanische  Prin^ip  im  anatomischen  Bau  der  M.onokotylen. 
In  this  he  describes  the  mechanical  functions  of  the  cells  and  tissue  elements 
and  shows  how  the  structure  of  the  plant  closely  follows  the  general  laws 
of  mechanics  governing  its  sustaining  power  and  strength.  In  doing  so,  how- 
ever, he  sometimes  interprets  the  structure  and  functions  of  plants  from 
a  too  narrowly  mechanical  point  of  view.  Thus,  for  instance,  he  sets  up  a 
mechanical  theory  in  regard  to  the  position  of  the  leaves,  wherein  he  exam- 
ines the  above-mentioned  idealistic  spiral  theory  and  finds  that  the  leaves' 
spiral  position  is  caused  by  conditions  of  mechanical  stress  and  is  altered 
if  the  stress  alters.  In  spite  of  its  one-sidedness,  however,  this  work  contrib- 
uted in  its  own  sphere  towards  overcoming  the  romantic  belief  in  an  idea's 
being  the  cause  of  a  natural  phenomenon  and  substituting  a  mechanical  ex- 
planation. Schwendener's  works  in  the  sphere  of  lichenology,  however, 
caused  a  still  greater  sensation  than  the  above  investigation.  Hitherto  the 
lichens  had  formed  a  class  in  the  vegetable  kingdom  by  the  side  of  Algas 
and  Fungi.  Schwendener  now  declared,  as  the  result  of  a  series  of  micro- 
scopical investigations,  that  the  lichens  are  really  a  kind  of  double  organ- 
isms, consisting  of  fungous  hyphas,  in  which  cells  of  Algas  lie  embedded 


558  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

and  which  jointly  contribute  to  the  existence  of  the  whole,  the  Fungi  by 
forming  the  substratum,  the  Algx  by  assimilating  carbonic  acid  with  their 
chlorophyll.  This  discovery,  which  upon  publication  aroused  the  keen  op- 
position of  the  lichen-systematists,  has  gradually  received  confirmation  and 
is  now  universally  accepted  as  correct. 

Among  those  who,  as  far  as  the  vegetable  kingdom  is  concerned,  paved 
the  way  for  a  uniform  conception  of  its  vital  manifestations,  must  also  be 
mentioned  Wilhelm  Hofmeister  (182.4-77).  Born  in  Leipzig,  he  was  edu- 
cated with  a  view  to  taking  up  a  commercial  career  and  became  a  music- 
seller  in  his  native  town,  but  he  spent  his  spare  time  studying  botany,  and 
eventually  became  a  professor,  first  at  Heidelberg  and  then  at  Tubingen.  His 
great  achievement  is  his  comparative  investigations  into  the  reproduction 
of  plants,  which  he  carried  out  while  he  was  still  a  music-dealer  and  which 
resulted  in  his  being  appointed  professor.  He  closely  studied  the  phanero- 
gams, as  well  as  vascular  cryptogams  and  mosses,  especially  observing  their 
formation,  development,  and  combination  of  the  sexual  products,  and  he 
established  in  all  these  phenomena  a  bond  of  agreement  that  made  possible 
in  all  essential  respects  the  adoption  of  a  uniform  conception  of  sexual  re- 
production throughout  the  vegetable  kingdom  —  an  achievement  that  is 
all  the  more  remarkable,  seeing  that  his  knowledge  of  the  cell  was  not  in 
advance  of  the  stage  at  which  his  own  period  had  arrived.  Hofmeister's 
work  on  the  reproduction  of  plants  was  followed  up  by  several  later  natu- 
ralists. Among  these  may  be  mentioned  Nathanael  Pringsheim  (1813-94), 
at  one  time  professor  at  Jena  and  then  a  private  scholar  in  Berlin.  He  found 
out  the  method  of  reproduction  of  the  Algas  and  published  several  valuable 
works  on  plant  physiology.  Also,  Heinrich  Anton  de  Bary  (1831-80), 
professor  at  Strassburg,  who  discovered  the  sexual  reproduction  of  the  Fungi 
and  the  alternation  of  generation  in  the  rust  fungi,  and  also  solved  a 
large  number  of  important  problems  in  the  sphere  of  mycology  and 
bacteriology. 

Considerations  of  space  forbid  our  continuing  the  account  of  the  develop- 
ment of  plant  morphology  up  to  modern  times;  in  fact,  all  the  details  will 
be  found  in  the  text-books  on  the  subject.  We  shall  therefore  proceed  to 
another  branch  of  biological  research,  which  has  also  played  an  important 
part  in  modern  times. 


5.   Geographical  Biology 

In  the  foregoing,  Humboldt  and  Wallace  have  been  named  as  founders,  in  the 
modern  sense,  of  vegetable  and  animal  geography.  Like  all  other  branches 
of  biology,  these  fields  of  research  have  in  our  day  become  highly  specialized. 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  559 

while  fresh  fields  have  been  opened  up  for  the  employment  of  their  methods 
on  an  extensive  scale.   Among  these  novel  spheres  we  note  not  only  new 
land-areas  —  it  was  not  until  our  own  period  that  the  entire  globe  can 
be  said  to  have  been  explored  and  described  —  but  also  to  a  still  greater 
degree  the  oceans,  the  deeper  areas  of  which  have  only  recently  been  known 
as  regards  their  physical  character  and  conditions  of  life.  Our  knowledge  of 
them  has  been  gained  partly  through  the  work  carried  out  at  the  zoological 
marine  stations,  of  which  the  most  famous  in  recent  times  has  been  that 
founded  by  Anton  Dohrn  (i 840-1 909)  at  Naples,  and  partly  as  the  result 
of  oceanographic  expeditions  specially  equipped  for  the  purpose,  among 
which  may  be  recalled  in  particular  the  important  English  Challenger  expedi- 
tion (i 872.-6)  and  the  German  Valdivia  expedition  (1898-9),  not  to  mention 
the  results  obtained  by  polar  expeditions  equipped  by  a  number  of  countries, 
both  large  and  small.  It  is  through  these  voyages  of  exploration  that  the 
life-forms  of  the  ocean  first  became  known  —  the  life  in  the  vast  depths, 
whose  denizens  live  in  constant  darkness  and  under  high  pressure  and  of- 
ten assume  amazing  forms;  the  actual  inhabitants  of  the  vast  ocean-expanses, 
the  so-called  plankton  fauna  and  flora,  with  their  often  transparent  and  frag- 
ile forms,  which  are  constantly  swimming  in  the  water,  forms  of  widely 
differing  systematic  groups;  and,  lastly,  the  life  that  moves  around  the  coasts. 
Innumerable  workers  have  devoted  themselves  to  this  branch  of  study,  which 
has  often  been  carried  out  under  the  leadership  of  committees,  national  and 
international,  with  the  consequence  that  the  work  and  its  results  have  to 
a  certain  extent  acquired  an  impersonal  character.  The  pioneer  in  this  field 
is  Karl  August  Mobius  (1815-1908),  professor  first  at  Kiel  and  then  in 
Berlin.  By  his  great  work  Die  Fauna  der  Kieler  Bticht  (1865)  he  has  created 
the  modern  system  and  methodics  of  oecology.  By  way  of  introduction  he 
describes  the  topography  of  the  estuary  that  he  investigated,  various  sec- 
tions of  it  being  surveyed  and  characterized  in  regard  to  position,  depth, 
and  their  plant  and  animal  life.  He  then  presents  in  systematical  order  the 
creatures  that  inhabit  each  locality.  Others  have  continued  along  the  path 
thus  beaten  by  Mobius.  Among  them  may  be  named  Victor  Hensen  (1835- 
1914),  who  was  professor  of  physiology  at  Kiel  and  in  that  capacity  studied 
the  structure  of  the  auditory  organ,  but  afterwards  he  devoted  himself  en- 
tirely to  marine  research,  chiefly  with  the  idea  of  improving  the  fishing 
industry.  He  made  a  special  study  of  plankton  life,  with  particular  refer- 
ence to  its  microscopical  forms.  In  order  to  advance  the  study  of  these  crea- 
tures, which  are  of  importance  as  food  for  fish,  he  worked  out  a  statistical 
method  of  his  own.  Of  others  who  laboured  in  this  sphere,  to  some  extent 
practically  important,  may  be  cited  the  Dane  C.  G.  J.  Petersen  (born  in 
i860),  who  investigated  animal  life  in  the  sounds  and  bays  of  Denmark  on 
a  method  of  his  own,  and  J.  Schmidt  (born  in  1877),  who  after  lengthy  and 


560  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

difficult  exploration  succeeded  in  elucidating  the  reproductive  process  of  the 
eel  —  a  problem  that  many  before  him  had  tried  to  solve  in  vain. 

Touching  the  continental  life -forms,  the  classification  into  large  geo- 
graphical regions  already  drawn  up  has  on  the  whole  been  retained,  and 
both  plant  and  animal  geographists  have  for  the  most  part  devoted  them- 
selves to  the  study  of  conditions  within  smaller  areas  belonging  to  these  re- 
gions. Among  investigators  of  this  category  in  the  sphere  of  animal  life  may 
be  mentioned  the  explorer  Karl  Semper  (1831-93),  professor  at  Wiirzburg, 
who  studied  the  problem  of  the  life-conditions  of  animals  from  various  points 
of  view. 

Plant  geography:  its  floristk  and  fnorphological  courses 
In  the  field  of  plant  geography,  research  has  taken  especially  two  courses, 
a  systematical,  which  is  ultimately  based  on  Linnxus's  observations  and 
theories  in  connexion  with  the  distribution  of  the  plant  species,  and  a  mor- 
phological, which  has  its  origin  in  Humboldt's  theories  on  the  morpho- 
logical association  of  different  vegetable  types  with  different  countries  and 
forms  of  landscape.  These  two  tendencies  have  exerted  a  mutual  influence 
and  have,  each  in  its  own  way,  been  influenced  by  the  doctrine  of  descent 
and  its  attempt  to  explain  the  origin  of  species  out  of  conditions  of  geo- 
graphical distribution.  And  at  the  same  time  valuable  results  were  gained 
by  the  comparison  between  the  distribution  of  existent  plant-forms  and  that 
of  the  corresponding  genera  and  species  of  earlier  geological  periods.  All 
representatives  of  modern  plant-geography  have  been  compelled  more  or  less 
to  take  these  conditions  into  consideration.  It  is  still  possible,  however,  to 
trace  two  main  tendencies  in  this  sphere,  which  nevertheless  incessantly 
touch  and  cross  one  another.  The  first  of  these,  the  systematic  or  floristic, 
which  rests  upon  the  systematic  entities,  treats  of  the  distribution  of  the 
species  within  larger  or  smaller  areas  and  their  variations  in  different  parts 
of  one  area  under  the  influence  of  certain  factors.  It  endeavours  to  find  out 
the  causes  of  the  changes  in  the  character  of  species  in  certain  localities  and 
countries  and  for  this  purpose  studies  the  migrations  of  species,  such  as  oc- 
cur through  the  distribution  of  land  and  sea  in  recent  times  and  through 
the  changes  that  have  taken  place  in  the  distribution  in  earlier  ages,  in  so 
far  as  it  has  been  possible  to  trace  these  shiftings  of  the  world's  surface. 
Further,  it  examines  the  distribution  of  extinct  and  fossilized  species,  from 
which  those  of  our  own  time  may  possibly  have  originated.  Special  interest 
has  been  devoted  to  the  immigration  of  plants  in  those  parts  of  Europe  that 
were  once  visited  by  the  glacial  period,  as  well  as  those  vegetable  remains 
in  the  mountain  ranges  of  the  polar  regions  that  give  evidence  of  a  previous 
warmer  climate  there. 

^    Morphological  or  oecological  plant-geography  does  not  investigate  the 
nature  of  the  flora,  but  of  the  vegetation.  It  works,  not  with  species,  but 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  561 

with  plant  communities,  by  which  is  meant  plants  of  very  different  systemati- 
cal categories  that,  on  account  of  a  uniformity  in  the  alimental  conditions, 
have  adapted  themselves  to  living  together  within  a  certain  area.  The  aim 
of  this  tendency  is  to  analyse  such  plant-associations  and  to  ascertain  their 
relations  to  the  climate,  the  soil,  and  other  environmental  conditions.  Both 
these  tendencies  have  made  considerable  progress  up  to  recent  times  and  can 
claim  a  number  of  distinguished  representatives,  of  whom  it  is  possible  only 
to  name  a  few.  The  two  previously  mentioned  English  botanists  Brown  and 
Hooker  made  valuable  observations  as  to  the  distribution  of  plants,  espe- 
cially in  extra-European  countries.  The  Swiss  Oswald  Heer  (1809-83)  made 
a  special  study  of  the  conditions  of  the  flora  of  the  glacial  period  and  also 
of  earlier  geological  strata.  There  followed  in  his  tracks  the  Swede  Alfred 
Nathorst  (i850-i91x),  who  did  very  creditable  work  in  investigating  the 
fossil  vegetable  world  of  the  polar  countries.  Adolf  Engler  (born  in 
1844),  professor  at  Berlin  and  founder  of  an  important  school  of  plant 
geography,  has  endeavoured,  by  studying  the  recent  and  fossil  vegetable 
world,  to  gain  some  insight  into  the  evolution  and  changes  of  the  flora,  espe- 
cially in  the  temperate  countries.  August  Heinrich  Grisebach  (1814-79), 
professor  at  Gottingen,  sought  to  carry  out  an  investigation  into  the  influ- 
ence of  climate  on  the  vegetation  and  a  classification,  on  a  climatic  basis, 
of  the  flora  in  certain  areas.  The  Dane  Eugen  Warming  (1841-19x4)  per- 
formed a  considerable  service  to  science  by  his  study  of  plant-associations, 
which  he  classified  and  analysed  in  respect  of  plant  forms  and  conditions 
of  life.  By  this  work  he  made  a  contribution  to  oecological  plant-geography 
of  fundamental  importance.  Andreas  Franz  Wilhelm  Schimper(i856-i9oi), 
professor  at  Basel,  made  long  voyages  for  the  purpose  of  studying  tropical 
vegetation,  and  from  climatological  and  modern  physiological  points  of  view 
he  worked  out  the  vegetation  of  the  entire  globe  in  his  Vjianxengeogra-phie 
auf  fhysiologischer  Grundlage  (1898).  His  geographical  and  oecological  classi- 
fications have  exerted  great  influence  upon  subsequent  development. 


CHAPTER   XVI 

NEO-D  ARWINISM     AND     N  E  O  -  L  A  M  A  R  C  K  I  SM 

Decline  of  Darwinism 

TOWARDS  THE  CLOSE  of  the  nineteenth  century  the  influence  of  Darwin- 
ism began  noticeably  to  wane.  The  signs  of  this  are  many:  partly 
internal,  in  that  the  actual  theory,  as  had  so  often  happened  before 
and  indeed  always  will  happen  with  dominating  views,  becomes  split  up  into 
a  number  of  mutually  conflicting  tendencies  in  different  directions,  and  partly 
external,  in  phenomena  manifested  in  the  general  cultural  situation.  The  op- 
timistic belief  in  progress  as  a  law  governing  nature  and  human  life,  which 
prevailed  in  the  middle  of  the  century  and  formed  the  basis  of  the  success 
of  Darwinism,  had  some  decades  after  been  essentially  disturbed.  The  un- 
limited progress  that  was  to  follow  upon  political  and  economic  freedom 
had  proved  to  be  somewhat  relative;  democracy,  which  had  been  introduced 
in  many  countries,  had  led  to  disappointments,  out  of  which  much  capital 
had  been  made  by  its  political  opponents,  while  free  competition  had  called 
forth,  not  a  friendly  and  stimulating  rivalry  with  a  universally  acknowledged 
precedence  for  the  best,  but  an  inimical  and  severe  struggle  between  rival  en- 
terprises, social  classes,  and  nations,  wherein  people  sought  rather  to  do  one 
another  the  greatest  possible  injury.  It  was  quite  natural  that  the  confidence 
in  liberalism  that  had  but  recently  been  so  strong  should  in  such  circum- 
stances begin  to  waver;  the  belief  that  progress  goes  on  by  itself  began  to 
be  regarded  as  a  matter  of  course;  instead  men  of  courage  were  required  to 
remove  the  increasing  difficulties.  So  there  arose  a  long  line  of  opponents 
to  liberalism,  from  the  strange  romanticist  Carlyle,  with  his  demand  for 
hero-worship,  to  Nietzsche,  with  his  paradoxical  "superman"  ideal;  both 
deserve  mention  as  men  who  made  violent  attacks  on  Darwin  and  his  theory. 
Their  successes  in  the  sphere  of  literature  may  thus  be  registered  as  defeats 
for  Darwinism,  and  they  were  by  no  means  the  only  ones  of  their  kind;  on 
the  contrary,  there  appeared  in  th  nineties  a  literary  tendency  that  was 
wholly  intended  to  be  a  contrast  to  the  naturalistic  literature  of  the  pre- 
ceding decade  based  on  natural  science.  And  while  the  popularity  of  Dar- 
winism among  the  general  public  thus  began  to  wane,  its  champions  among 
the  scientists  had  to  defend  themselves  against  the  obstacles  that  the  re- 
sults of  fresh  research  placed  in  the  way  of  the  old  theory. 

As  we  know,  both  Darwin  and  Haeckel  had  based  their  doctrines  of 

561 


MENDEL 

From  Grtgor  Johaim  Moidel :  Leben,  Werk  und  Wirkmig  by  Dr.  Hugo  litis, 
published  by  Verlag  von  Julius  Springer,  Berlin 


RICHARD     OWEN 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  563 

descent  partly  on  the  theory  of  variability  and  natural  selection  brought 
about  by  the  struggle  for  existence  among  the  variations,  and  partly  on  the 
assumption  of  the  direct  influence  of  environment  upon  the  individual,  and 
the  inheritance  of  the  changes  thus  brought  about  —  that  is,  a  Lamarckian 
conception.  Here  at  once,  in  this  double  explanation,  lay  the  seeds  of  dis- 
sension: one  could  with  prejudice  emphasize  the  idea  of  selection,  or  with 
equal  prejudice  maintain  the  influence  of  environment.  And  this  was  ex- 
actly what  happened;  the  period  immediately  preceding  and  around  the  turn 
of  the  century  witnessed  the  birth  of  the  two  evolutional  schools  of  thought 
called  neo-Darwinism  and  neo-Lamarckism,  whose  advocates  sought  to  con- 
vince the  biologists  of  the  absolute  validity  of  their  own  views.  Out  of  these 
two  main  directions  there  further  originated  a  number  of  special  attempts  to 
explain  the  causes  of  evolution,  so  that  the  situation  in  which  the  doctrine 
of  descent  eventually  found  itself  was  somewhat  chaotic.  We  shall  here  de- 
scribe some  features  of  this  internal  dissolution  of  Darwinism. 

In  Germany  the  theory  of  selection  found  a  highly  gifted  and  power- 
ful advocate  in  the  person  of  August  Weismann  (1834-1914).  He  studied 
medicine,  being  a  pupil  of  Leuckart,  who  inspired  him  with  an  interest  for 
biology.  After  working  for  some  years  as  a  practitioner  he  was  invited,  on 
account  of  a  useful  treatise  on  the  evolution  of  flies,  which  he  had  written 
in  the  mean  while,  to  be  professor  at  Freiburg,  where  he  laboured  until  his 
death.  His  special  subject  was  the  evolution  of  the  lower  animals;  in  this 
field  he  particularly  distinguished  himself  in  his  studies  of  the  reproduction 
of  the  Daphniidas,  as  a  result  of  which  he  elucidated  the  peculiar  egg-de- 
velopment in  these  crustaceans  and  the  no  less  curious  "cyclic  reproduction" 
that  characterizes  them.  An  ophthalmic  disease,  however,  soon  precluded 
him  from  using  the  microscope  and  compelled  him  to  apply  himself  partly 
to  experimental  and  partly  to  purely  speculative  activities.  One  result  of 
this  was  his  strange  theory  of  evolution,  which  placed  him  among  the  very 
foremost  of  Darwin's  successors. 

Weismann's  theory  of  descent  and  heredity  is  based,  firstly,  on  his 
above-mentioned  special  investigations,  and  secondly  on  Nageli's  idioplasma 
theory,  referred  to  above.  Nageli  had  sought  for  a  material  substructure  for 
the  inherited  dispositions,  out  of  which  are  developed  in  every  individual 
certain  given  qualities,  and  he  believed  he  had  discovered  it  in  his  hypothe- 
sis of  the  idioplasma,  which,  existing  equally  in  the  egg  and  in  the  sperm, 
through  their  union  forms  in  the  new  individual  the  basic  material  for  its 
special  qualities.  Weismann,  who  as  a  result  of  his  studies  and  his  own  re- 
search work  had  acquired  a  deep  insight  into  contemporary  cytological 
knowledge,  came  for  that  very  reason,  when  he  was  forced  to  devote  him- 
self to  purely  theoretical  speculations,  to  take  up  the  question  of  cell-struc- 
ture as  a  basis  for  the  evolutional  theory  that  Darwin  and  his  school  had 


5  64  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

promulgated.  In  a  series  of  lectures  and  monographs  dating  from  the  eighties 
he  endeavours  to  find  out  what  it  is  that  produces  heredity  in  a  biological 
sense;  how,  he  asks,  are  we  to  account  for  the  characteristic  in  organisms 
of  transmitting  to  their  offspring  their  own  essential  being,  for  the  fact  that 
from  the  eagle's  egg  is  invariably  hatched  an  eagle,  and,  moreover,  one  of 
the  same  species  as  its  parents?  In  imitation  of  Haeckel  he  starts  from  the 
unicellular  animals  and  finds  that  in  these  the  mutual  resemblance  of  the 
different  generations  is  due  to  the  individuals'  propagating  by  division;  to 
the  fact  that  every  infusorian  is  a  segment  of  a  previous  one,  that  there  thus 
exists  in  them  a  "  Continuitat  des  Individuums ."  And  the  same  is  true  of  the 
multicellular  animals  in  virtue  of  sexual  reproduction;  for  the  individual's 
life  the  sexual  cells  are  without  significance,  but  they  preserve  the  continuity 
of  the  species  through  the  ages;  out  of  them  arises  in  certain  given  circum- 
stances a  new  individual  of  the  same  kind  as  the  old. 

Weismann  s  germinal--plasf7t  theory 
From  this  it  may  be  concluded  that  there  exists  a  special  "germinal  plasm" 
which  corresponds  to  the  individual  series  in  unicellular  animals  and  which, 
like  them,  preserves  the  species  by  repeated  dividing,  whereas  the  corporeal 
plasm  of  the  individual  gradually  falls  into  decay.  Originally  the  differen- 
tiation of  sexual  and  corporeal  cells  had  been  due  to  a  division  of  labour 
in  the  simplest  cell-colonies,  such  as  we  still  see  in  the  primitive  colony- 
forming  animals;  for  the  sexual  cells  that  perform  the  function  of  reproduc- 
tion contain  both  germinal  and  corporeal  plasm,  which  separate  when,  in 
the  earliest  embryonic  stage,  the  rudimentary  cells  of  the  sexual  organs  sepa- 
rate from  the  rest  of  the  cells.  Out  of  the  germinal  plasm,  therefore,  arises 
the  long  series  of  analogous  individuals,  and  these  resemble  one  another  for 
the  very  reason  that  their  form  is  governed  by  the  character  of  the  germinal 
plasm,  which  is  determined  once  and  for  all;  if  changes  appear  in  the  exter- 
nal bodily  form,  they  correspond  to  and  are  induced  by  changes  in  the  ger- 
minal plasm.  These  changes  are  brought  about  by  fertilization,  in  which 
the  germinal  plasm  of  two  different  individuals  is  united;  through  this  "am- 
phimixis," as  Weismann  calls  it,  is  formed  a  new  germinal  plasm,  with  both 
the  parents'  qualities,  which  accordingly  appear  also  in  the  offspring.  But 
if  the  qualities  of  the  individual  are  thus  due  entirely  to  the  germinal  plasm, 
there  can  be  no  possibility  of  influencing  the  individual  series  from  out- 
side; the  organs  of  the  individual  that  are  formed  of  corporeal  plasm  can 
be  influenced  by  practice,  in  so  far  as  the  germinal  plasm  has  created  possibili- 
ties therefor,  but  changes  of  this  kind  exercise  no  influence  upon  the  germinal 
plasm.  Consequently,  Lamarck's  theory  that  the  character  of  the  species  is 
created  by  the  habits  of  the  individual  is  untenable. 

This  denial  of  the  heredity  of  acquired  characters  became  one  of  the 
corner-stones  of  Weismann's  biological  theory  and  he  sought  in  many  and 


MODERNBIOLOGY  5  65 

various  ways  to  procure  proofs  for  his  argument.  He  bred  large  quantities 
of  rats,  whose  tails  he  cut  off  at  birth,  but  he  never  succeeded  in  finding  a 
rat  born  tailless,  nor  did  other  malformations  brought  about  by  outward 
interference  ever  reproduce  themselves.  He  therefore  felt  fully  justified  in 
maintaining  his  standpoint  that  all  changes  in  the  outward  appearance  of 
the  individual  compared  with  other  individuals  are  due  to  changes  in  the 
germinal  plasm;  that  every  so-called  acquired  character  is  really  produced 
by  a  change  in  the  germinal  plasm,  whereby  the  body  becomes  capable  of 
adapting  itself  to  the  different  external  conditions  of  life.  But  how,  then, 
have  the  various  life-forms  arisen  in  the  course  of  ages?  By  means  of  natural 
selection,  answers  Weismann,  and  by  that  means  alone.  The  variations  that 
are  brought  about  especially  through  the  amphimixis  of  sexual  reproduction, 
but  also  through  other  changes  in  the  germinal  plasm,  are  advanced  or  re- 
tarded by  natural  selection  and  thus  give  rise  to  new  forms,  whose  germinal 
plasm  is  better  adapted  to  the  conditions  of  existence  than  that  of  the  old 
forms.  Natural  selection  is  thus  the  cause  of  the  evolution  of  animate  beings, 
Weismann  rejecting  Nageli's  assumption  of  internal  causes  of  evolution  in- 
herent in  the  organisms  themselves,  for  such  a  theory  "cannot  explain  the 
finality  of  the  organisms.  And  yet  this  is  the  very  riddle  that  the  organic 
world  gives  us  to  solve."  Numberless  instances  are  quoted  of  this  adaptabil- 
ity, this  connexion  between  form  and  function,  and  every  instance  is  likewise 
made  to  serve  as  evidence  of  the  creative  power  of  natural  selection. 

' '  The  continuity  of  the  germinal  plasm ' '  and  ' '  the  omnipotence  of  natu- 
ral selection"  are  two  phrases  in  which  Weismann's  theory  of  life  used  to 
be  summed  up.  As  a  result  of  the  former  of  these  ideas  —  that  of  the  germinal 
plasm  as  the  preserver  of  heredity  —  Weismann  has  reached  by  way  of  specu- 
lation conclusions  to  a  certain  extent  foreshadowing  those  that  modern 
heredity-research  has  since  arrived  at  by  means  of  exact  observation.  His 
subsequent  attempts  to  expand  this  theory  gave  him  similarly  happy  in- 
spirations, as  when  he  localizes  the  germinal  plasm  —  that  is,  the  preserver 
of  heredity  —  in  the  chromosomes  of  the  sexual  cells.  "The  idea  in  itself 
was  sound,"  says  Johannsen  in  this  connexion.  Even  Weismann,  however, 
succumbed  to  the  danger  of  basing  his  conception  of  a  phenomenon  on  mere 
speculation;  in  his  continued  efforts  to  extend  his  germinal-plasm  theory 
downwards  he  works  out  a  highly  complicated  plan  to  show  the  structural 
nature  of  living  substance;  every  one  of  its  minutest  entities  consists  of  a 
mass  of  chemical  molecules;  they  are  termed  "biophores,"  and  he  assures 
us  that  they  are  not  hypothetical:  "They  must  exist,  for  the  phenomena  of 
life  must  be  bound  to  an  entity  of  matter."  Of  biophores  are  composed  the 
determinants:  those  units  in  the  germinal  plasm  that  govern  the  various 
qualities  in  the  smallest  parts  of  the  individual;  the  determinants  in  their 
turn  build  up  the  ids,  which  form  larger  groups  of  qualities,  and  these  again 


566  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

the  chromosomes,  which  unite  in  themselves  all  hereditary  qualities.  With 
these  we  have  at  last  arrived  at  something  that  can  be  observed;  in  fact,  the 
foregoing  has  been  pure  imagination,  of  the  kind  that  the  biologists  of 
the  past  century  had  such  difficulty  in  avoiding  when  they  had  to  explain 
the  phenomena  of  life.  Darwin  and  Haeckel  were  content  each  with  one 
hypothetical  unit  of  life;  it  can  hardly  be  said  that  Weismann  would  have 
done  any  special  service  to  biology  by  burdening  it  with  three  of  them. 

Theory  of  germinal  selection 
However,  the  germinal-plasm  theory  and  its  conclusions,  both  the  ingen- 
ious and  the  false,  only  served  Weismann  as  a  means  for  proving  the  doc- 
trine that  gradually  came  to  mean  for  him  the  very  corner-stone  of  biology: 
the  doctrine  of  the  omnipotence  of  natural  selection.  The  championship  of 
this  theory,  and  the  fight  against  that  of  the  inheritance  of  acquired  char- 
acters eventually  became  his  chief  aim  in  life;  all  that  could  serve  his  pur- 
pose he  took  to  be  good,  while  all  that  militated  against  it  was  rejected. 
He  went  through  many  a  hard  struggle  on  behalf  of  his  favourite  theory; 
in  the  nineties  he  was  especially  attacked  by  Herbert  Spencer,  who  main- 
tained the  doctrine  of  the  transmission  of  acquired  characters,  chiefly  for 
social  reasons;  it  was,  in  fact,  the  precondition  of  human  progress.  But  from 
many  other  quarters  also  there  arose  the  cry  of  "the  impotence  of  natural 
selection,"  and  this  cry  was  again  taken  up  after  the  turn  of  the  century. 
Weismann's  defence  was  often  somewhat  laboured;  against  Spencer  he  de- 
fended himself  mostly  on  the  old  argument  about  the  intelligence  of  the 
workers  among  the  bees,  which  cannot  be  transmitted  by  inheritance,  since 
they  are  sterile,  and  which  therefore  cannot  be  directly  "acquired"  either. 
It  was  more  difficult  to  answer  the  question  as  to  how  that  finality  arose 
that  shows  itself  in  occasional  encroachments  upon  an  organism;  how,  for 
instance,  a  fracture  heals  in  certain  definite  ways;  the  fracture  certainly  can- 
not be  traced  to  natural  selection.  Here  Weismann  found  support  in  a  theory 
that  was  produced  by  the  afterwards  famous  experimental  biologist  Roux, 
who  in  his  youth  published  a  work  entitled  Der  Kampfder  Teile  im  Organismus. 
Here  an  attempt  is  made  to  explain  what  Roux  calls  ' '  functional  adaptation 
within  the  organism:  that  every  organ,  even  every  cell,  possesses  its  given 
structure,  which  changes  if  the  conditions  of  the  organ's  function  are  changed, 
so  that  in  normal  circumstances  the  life  of  the  body  runs  its  even  course; 
if  this  is  disturbed  by  interference  from  outside,  cells  and  tissues  adapt  them- 
selves as  required  to  repair  the  damage.  This  fact  Roux  considers  to  be  due 
to  a  "struggle  for  existence"  between  the  cells  in  the  body  and  even  between 
the  molecules  in  every  cell,  each  of  which  strives  to  force  its  way  forward 
at  the  expense  of  its  neighbours,  an  effort  that  is  controlled  by  the  general 
requirements  of  the  body,  the  weakest  elements  being  thrust  aside  and  de- 
stroyed. This  theory,  to  which  we  shall  revert  in  another  connexion,  at 


MODERNBIOLOGY  5  67 

once  won  Weismann's  keen  approval,  but  it  met  with  opposition  from  other 
quarters;  as,  for  instance,  from  O.  Hertwig,  who  held  that  upon  the  first 
division  of  the  egg  it  should  be  possible  to  see  something  of  this  struggle 
between  the  cells,  but  that,  on  the  contrary,  the  first  easily  observable  em- 
bryonic cells  show  no  inclination  whatever  for  mutual  strife,  but  rather 
each  one  has  its  carefully  defined  form  and  place.  Weismann,  however, 
adopted  the  idea  of  natural  selection  within  the  organism  and  combined  it 
with  his  germinal-plasm  theory.  In  a  work  entitled  Uber  Germinalselektion 
he  declares  that  between  the  various  parts  of  the  body  and  their  "deter- 
minants" in  the  germinal  plasm  there  exists  reciprocal  action;  if,  now, 
an  organ  is  not  used,  its  determinants  are  weakened  and  annihilated  by 
the  struggle  within  the  organism,  and  the  organ  disappears  in  succeeding 
generations;  in  this  way,  for  instance,  the  posterior  extremities  of  the  whale 
have  been  lost.  But,  all  the  same,  Weismann  comes  in  this  way,  although 
indirectly,  to  accept  the  inheritance  of  acquired  characters,  which  indicates 
that  the  theory  of  selection  finds  it  difficult  to  do  without  this  auxiliary 
hypothesis.  We  shall  here  leave  the  omnipotence  of  natural  selection  and 
pass  on  to  its  diametrical  opposite,  neo-Lamarckism. 

Lamarck's  theory  of  the  direct  influence  of  habits  of  life  upon  the  bodily 
structure  of  the  individual  and  its  offspring  gained  strong  support  towards 
the  close  of  the  century,  especially  in  France.  When  the  supporters  of  Cuvier 
finally  left  the  arena,  it  was  to  Lamarck  that  people  turned  for  a  basis  for 
their  biological  ideas.  When  the  belief  in  the  constancy  of  species  had  to 
give  way  to  the  theory  of  evolution,  the  form  that  this  was  to  take  was 
readily  sought  from  a  fellow-countryman,  and,  moreover,  an  older  man  than 
Darwin;  thus  "transformism,"  as  it  was  here  called,  could  also  claim  to  be 
an  originally  French  science.  Lamarck's  theory  found  an  eloquent  supporter 
in  Alfred  Giard.  Born  in  1846,  he  studied  at  the  Ecole  Normale  in  Paris 
and  eventually  became  professor  of  zoology  at  the  Sorbonne  and  head  of  the 
marine  laboratory  at  Wimereux,  near  Boulogne;  he  held  that  post  with  suc- 
cess until  his  death,  in  1908,  being  especially  known  for  his  profound  studies 
of  a  number  of  marine  animal  forms.  Under  the  characteristic  title  Contro- 
verses  transjormistes  he  collected  some  years  before  his  death  a  series  of  con- 
tributions to  the  problem  of  descent,  in  which  he  examined  and  further 
developed  Lamarck's  doctrines.  According  to  Giard,  evolution  proceeds  un- 
der the  influence  of  two  categories  of  factors;  namely,  the  primary,  which 
directly  influence  the  individual  and  indirectly  its  offspring,  and  among 
which  are  mentioned  light,  temperature,  food,  and  relations  to  other  beings 
—  that  is  to  say,  the  struggle  for  existence  —  and  the  secondary,  which 
include  everything  that  is  adapted  to  remove  less  suitable  forms  of  life  — 
that  is  to  say,  natural  selection.  Giard  now  takes  upon  himself  to  prove  the 
existence  of  the  primary  factors,  and  he  adduces  quite  a  number  of  proofs. 


568  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

Among  the  positive  proofs  he  includes  a  number  of  experiments  carried  out 
by  the  physiologist  Brown-Sequard,  who  believed  that  by  interfering  with 
the  nervous  system  in  guinea-pigs  he  had  induced  epilepsy  in  their  young; 
these  experiments,  however,  have  been  found  by  other  investigators  either 
to  have  miscarried  or  to  have  been  misinterpreted.  Giard  has  better  success 
when,  in  a  controversy  with  Weismann,  he  declares  that  the  secondary  fac- 
tors alone  cannot  explain  the  origin  of  the  forms  of  life;  he  points  out  a 
number  of  phenomena  that  cannot  be  explained  by  selection  alone.  On  the 
other  hand,  he  does  not  deny  the  existence  of  selection,  as  already  mentioned 
above;  he  only  considers  its  importance  to  be  "secondary." 

0.  Hertwig  against  natural  selection 
A  FAR  more  severe  judgment  than  that  of  Giard  and  several  other  Lamarckists 
—  for  example,  the  famous  American  paleontologist  E.  D.  Cope  (1840- 
57)  —  is  passed  upon  the  theory  of  selection  by  Oscar  Hertwig,  who  de- 
voted the  latter  part  of  his  life  particularly  to  attacking  the  common  belief 
in  it.  In  fact,  in  his  great  work  of  1916,  referred  to  above.  Das  Werden  der 
Organismen,  he  finally  settles  his  account  with  that  theory  and  at  the  same 
time  gives  a  summary  of  the  natural  philosophy  which  he  had  produced  in 
the  course  of  a  long  life  that  had  been  unusually  rich  in  experience.  Being 
mainly  a  cytologist,  Hertwig  attaches  decisive  importance  to  the  cell  and 
its  structure  as  the  groundwork  for  all  speculation  upon  evolution.  To  him 
the  cell  is  the  elementary  organism  and  he  vehemently  sets  his  face  against 
all  theories  of  biophores,  plastidules,  and  such  lower  vital  entities.  Every 
form  of  life  has  its  peculiar  cell-structure :  there  are  in  nature  as  many  ' '  species 
cells"  as  species;  it  is  the  character  of  the  species  cell  that  causes  every  form 
of  life  to  be  what  it  is  and  produces  descendants  of  the  same  kind.  Evolution 
is  regulated  in  each  separate  case  by  the  character  of  the  species  cell,  and 
those  phenomena  that  coincide  therewith  are  described  as  the  "  biogenetical 
law  of  cause,"  which  precludes  the  possibility  of  any  such  biogenetical  prin- 
ciple as  that  which  Haeckel  conceived;  in  its  embryonic  development  a  mam- 
mal certainly  does  not  pass  through  a  series  of  stages  identical  with  the 
lower  animals,  but  rather  the  egg  of  every  mammal  species  is  just  as  fully 
specialized  as  the  animal  itself,  and  similarly  with  the  embryonic  stages.  The 
tgg  contains  within  itself  all  the  characters  of  the  organism  as  rudiments; 
Hertwig,  following  Nageli,  terms  the  bearer  of  the  rudiment  within  the 
cell  "idioplasma,"  but  he  is  generally  content  to  speak  of  the  rudiments  of 
the  species  cell.  Towards  the  question  of  heredity  he  adopts  a  decidedly 
morphological  attitude  and  insists  that  the  material  basis  of  the  relative 
phenomena  must  be  observed  and  explored,  thereby  opposing  Johannsen's 
physiological  view  of  the  phenomena  of  heredity.  He  most  emphatically 
maintains  the  heredity  of  acquired  characters  —  that  is  to  say,  the  metab- 
olistic  influence  of  environment  upon  the  hereditary  dispositions.  In  support 


MODERNBIOLOGY  5  69 

of  this  assertion  he  cites  a  number  of  experiments,  which,  however, 
have  been  interpreted  differently  by  modern  heredity-research,  such  as,  for 
instance,  Kammerer's  experiments  with  colour  changes  in  the  salamander, 
and  Tower's  experiments  in  connexion  with  the  evolution  of  the  beetle.  If 
Hertwig's  views  on  this  point  approach  those  of  Lamarck,  he  refuses  all 
the  more  definitely  to  have  anything  to  do  with  Darwin's  theory  of  selection. 
He  brings  out  the  latter's  weaknesses  in  a  strong  light;  he  especially  points 
out  how  much  of  the  theory  is  borrowed  from  human  conditions  and  is, 
moreover,  utterly  misinterpreted.  The  breeder  who  selects  suitable  variations 
creates  nothing  new  thereby,  but  only  chooses  what  suits  him,  and  this  pro- 
cedure has  no  counterpart  in  nature  —  the  struggle  for  existence  does  not 
destroy  creatures;  the  masses  that  die  do  so  from  quite  different  causes.  To 
declare  that  selection  favours  certain  variations  postulates  mere  chance  as 
an  operative  cause,  but  chance  is  no  natural-scientific  explanation.  And  he 
views  with  equal  disfavour  the  above-mentioned  theory  of  the  struggle  of 
the  parts  within  the  organism;  this,  too,  is  found  to  rest  upon  utterly  false 
conclusions. 

Once  again  Oscar  Hertwig  attacks  the  theory  of  the  struggle  for  exist- 
ence and  natural  selection,  in  his  polemical  paper  Zur  Abwehr  des  ethischen, 
des  so'^ialen,  des  politischen  Danvinismus,  wherein  the  old  student  of  evolu- 
tion sharply  criticizes  the  outgrowths  that  Darwinism  had  induced  in  the 
sphere  of  social  life.  The  fact  is  that  a  number  of  writers,  partly  biolo- 
gists with  a  deficient  social  grounding,  partly  newspaper-men  and  political 
authors  of  various  kinds,  had  made  use  of  the  theory  of  the  struggle  for 
existence  and  of  selection  to  proclaim  a  new  social  theory,  on  the  one  hand 
rejecting  activities  based  on  Christian  charity  and  strivings  after  social 
equality,  and  on  the  other  hand  extolling  war,  social  want,  and  ruthless 
competition  as  phenomena  destined  to  thin  out  the  weaker  and  less  hardy 
human  beings,  and  thereby  to  further  human  progress.  Against  these  asser- 
tions Hertwig  maintains  that  natural  phenomena  cannot  be  made  the  stand- 
ards of  human  culture;  justice  and  morality  have  their  origin  exclusively 
in  human  community  life;  in  nature  no  such  principles  exist;  the  beast  of 
prey  that  tears  its  victim  to  pieces  acts  neither  justly  nor  unjustly,  but  ac- 
cording to  its  nature.  To  make  a  merciless  struggle  for  existence  the  basis 
of  social  life  would  therefore  be  equivalent  to  destroying  all  that  the  cul- 
tural efforts  of  the  past  have  built  up.  War  and  economic  misery  are  of  no 
constructive  value;  on  the  contrary  they  ruthlessly  destroy  both  the  capable 
and  the  incapable.  Thus  in  the  very  bitterest  days  of  the  Great  War  Hertwig 
dares  to  hope  for  a  peaceful  settlement  between  the  nations.  That,  however, 
he  did  not  live  to  see;  when  he  died,  in  i9xx,  the  unhappy  consequences  of 
the  war  —  unhappy  for  the  whole  of  humanity  and  most  of  all  for  his  own 
fatherland  —  had  been  brought  out  in  all  their  frightful  clearness,  and  his 


570  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

distress  at  these  misfortunes  is  said  to  have  broken  the  aged  patriot  and 
philanthropist  and  to  have  appreciably  shortened  his  life. 

Eimer's  "orthogenesis"  theory 
We  shall  mention  in  the  following  some  further  tests  of  the  descent  theory, 
though  more  as  proofs  of  the  increasing  difficulties  with  which  the  successors 
of  Darwin  had  to  contend  than  for  any  actual  value  that  the  results  possessed. 
Theodor  Eimer  (1843-98),  a  fellow-countryman  and  disciple  of  Kolliker's 
and  eventually  professor  at  Tubingen,  endeavoured  to  solve  the  difficulty  of 
the  descent  theory  chiefly  along  the  lines  laid  down  by  Nageli.  He  rejects 
Darwin's  theory  of  variation  in  all  possible  directions  as  the  basis  of  selec- 
tion; the  development  of  the  organic  forms  must  rather,  he  holds,  depend 
upon  a  force  operating  in  a  definite  direction,  a  force  induced  and  modified 
by  outward  influence,  such  as  light,  air,  heat,  nourishment,  and  thus  one 
that  provides  selection  with  the  material  for  changes  which  it  influences. 
This  definitely  directed  evolution  he  terms  "orthogenesis"  and  he  seeks 
to  prove  that  it  is  indispensable  for  the  building  up  of  species;  selection 
alone  cannot  produce  anything  new,  but  rather  it  is  this  inner  force,  law- 
bound,  yet  aff"ected  by  external  influences,  that  is  the  true  origin  of  life- 
forms.  In  proof  of  this  he  cites  a  large  number  of  observations  dealing  with 
the  colour  changes  in  butterflies,  as  well  as  the  development  of  the  skeleton 
of  vertebrates,  which  attracted  great  attention  at  the  time  and  brought  their 
originator  a  large  following,  but  which  are  now  no  longer  up  to  date. 

Semon  s  " mneme"  theory 
Richard  Semon  (i 859-1919),  a  pupil  of  Haeckel  and  at  one  time  a  professor 
at  Jena,  pursued  another  line  of  thought.  His  theory  of  evolution  is  also 
based  entirely  on  the  belief  in  the  transmission  of  acquired  characters,  but 
he  endeavours  to  give  this  theory  a  direction  more  suited  to  the  time  by 
submitting  it  in  a  new  form.  To  his  mind,  the  weakness  underlying  previous 
theories  of  this  kind  had  been  due  to  lack  of  clearness  in  the  term  "char- 
acter"; instead  of  transmission  of  acquired  characters  it  should  be  called 
transmission  of  acquired  reactions.  For  the  hereditary  transmission  depends 
upon  the  nature  of  the  germinal  plasm,  and  this  reacts  under  natural  laws 
to  the  influence  of  the  general  condition  of  the  body.  The  power  of  living 
substance  to  react,  its  "  Rei^barkeit,"  is  the  primary  cause  of  evolution.  Even 
if  the  external  influence  upon  it  is  transitory,  there  nevertheless  remains  an 
impression,  which  becomes  a  decisive  factor  in  its  future  development.  This 
impression  is  termed  "  Engramm."  And  the  altered  construction  of  the  new 
generations'  form,  upon  which  natural  selection  has  an  extenuating  influence, 
is  due  to  the  co-operation  between  the  outwardly  induced  Engramm  of  the 
body  and  that  o  the  germinal  plasm.  This  influence  of  the  corporeal  sub- 
stance upon  the  germinal  plasm  is  called  "somatic  induction,"  and  the  as- 
sumed power  of  the  living  substance  to  preserve  external  impressions,  upon 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  571 

which  the  whole  theory  rests,  is  called  "  fnneme.''  Semon  adduces  a  mass  of 
arguments  to  prove  his  theory  of  the  transmission  of  external  influence,  but 
all  of  them  have  since  been  rejected  or  given  a  fresh  interpretation  by  the 
representatives  of  experimental  heredity-research.  The  purely  evolutional 
proofs  are  borrowed  partly  from  palaeontology  —  for  example,  the  process 
of  stunted  growth  in  the  toes  of  certain  animal  forms  —  and  partly  from 
embryology  — •  the  skin  of  the  human  sole  is  even  in  the  embryonic  stage 
thicker  than  that  on  other  parts  of  the  body  —  but  as  these  proofs  cannot 
possibly  be  tested  as  regards  the  evolution  that  has  actually  taken  place, 
they  cannot  be  considered  binding  according  to  exact  methods.  The  experi- 
mental proofs,  however,  will  be  more  closely  dealt  with  later  on;  as  a  matter 
of  fact,  they  recur  quite  regularly  in  all  Lamarckists  and  are  adduced  by  them 
as  being  positive,  whereas  other  investigators  have  pointed  out  fallacies 
either  in  the  experiments  themselves  or  in  their  interpretations. 

Vauly  s  Lamar ckism 
We  must  mention  only  in  passing  one  more  line  of  thought  based  on  La- 
marck, represented,  inter  alia,  by  August  Pauly  (1850-1914),  professor  at 
Munich,  who  seeks  the  cause  of  evolution  in  a  conscious  psychic  striving 
towards  a  certain  goal  on  the  part  of  the  organism  and  all  its  elements. 
This  theory  can  hardly  come  within  the  scope  of  natural  science;  it  has 
crossed  the  border  of  metaphysics,  but  is  worth  mentioning  as  a  further  ex- 
ample of  the  desperate  expedients  that  the  speculation  on  the  problem  of 
origin  was  finally  compelled  to  adopt.  In  support  of  his  views  Pauly  further 
cites  the  traditional  examples  of  the  inheritance  of  acquired  characters. 

The  struggle  between  the  champions  and  the  opponents  of  the  theory 
of  the  inheritance  of  acquired  characters  is  to  some  extent  reminiscent  of 
that  between  Pasteur  and  Pouchet  regarding  spontaneous  generation  — 
people  could  not  agree  upon  the  interpretation  of  the  experiments  and  a 
theoretical  standpoint  based  on  them.  And  in  this  case,  too,  it  would  seem 
as  if  the  practical  consequences  must  eventually  determine  the  value  of  the 
theory;  neither  animal-breeders  nor  horticulturalists  have  really  succeeded 
in  applying  the  theory  of  the  transmission  of  acquired  characters,  those  of 
them  who  believed  in  it  having  really  remained  at  the  same  grossly  empiri- 
cal standpoint  as  their  colleagues  had  adopted  long  before  Darwin's  time, 
while  modern  racial  research,  working  on  the  Mendelian  method,  has  at- 
tained results  of  an  entirely  different  practical  value  and  has,  in  fact,  com- 
pletely revolutionized  the  methods  of  racial  breeding. 

Plate  s  Darwinism 
While  both  the  theory  of  selection  and  Lamarckism  thus  had  their  sup- 
porters, who  carried  the  conclusions  of  their  several  lines  of  thought  to  ex- 
treme limits,  the  middle  course  pursued  by  Darwin  himself  has  also  been 
xoUowed  by  scientists  of  repute  up  to  modern  times.  As  one  of  these  may  be 


572.  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

mentioned  Ludwig  Plate  (born  in  i86i),  Haeckel's  disciple  and  successor 
at  Jena.  After  having  applied  his  theoretical  ideas  to  a  number  of  special 
investigations,  both  morphological  and  experimental,  he  summarized  his 
main  arguments  in  an  extensive  work,  Selektionsprinxif  und  Probleme  der  Art- 
bildung,  which  may  be  said  to  contain  all  that  can  be  adduced  in  modern 
times  in  defence  of  the  old  Darwinism.  And  as  its  champion  Plate  has  done 
a  great  service,  thanks  to  his  wealth  of  knowledge,  his  strong  convictions, 
and  his  honesty.  From  the  imperious  disposition  of  his  master,  Haeckel, 
he  kept  entirely  free;  he  refused  to  employ  the  theory  of  selection  to  explain 
the  fundamental  qualities  of  the  living  substance:  assimilation,  growth,  res- 
piration, etc.,  or  indeed  to  explain  variability  or  heredity;  its  sole  function, 
to  his  mind,  is  "to  explain  the  origin  of  the  teleological  organizations,  in 
so  far  as  they  are  not  elementary  qualities  nor  can  be  placed  in  the  category 
of  Lamarckian  factors."  Darwin's  greatest  service,  in  his  opinion,  lies  in 
the  fact  that  "he  sought  to  explain  organic  finality  out  of  natural  forces, 
to  the  exclusion  of  any  metaphysical  principle  operating  with  conscious  in- 
telligence." Finality  is  thus  the  principal  quality  of  organic  life;  adaptations 
are  expressly  declared  to  represent  a  main  difference  between  animate  and 
inanimate  bodies.  In  his  anxiety  to  defend  the  theory  of  selection,  Plate 
has,  obviously  without  realizing  it,  hereby  come  perilously  near  Johannes 
Miiller's  old  doctrine  of  finality  and  a  far  cry  from  Haeckel,  who  was  at 
one  time  prepared  to  characterize  rudimentary  organs  as  being  the  opposite 
to  profitable^  and  the  knowledge  of  them  as  "dysteleology."  Plate,  how- 
ever, examines  all  the  different  kinds  of  finality  —  phenomena  of  correla- 
tion, mechanical  equiponderant  apparatus,  embryonic  structures,  instincts, 
protective  resemblance,  and  a  good  deal  more  —  all  this  in  order  to  find 
proofs  of  the  operation  of  natural  selection.  But  if  the  theory  of  selection 
is  thus  to  stand  or  fall  by  the  question  of  finality  in  nature,  the  result  will, 
of  course,  be  that  the  function  of  selection  automatically  lapses  if  a  different 
view  of  natural  phenomena  is  advanced.  And,  as  has  already  been  pointed 
out,  ever  since  the  days  of  Democritus  of  old,  research  has  constantly  aimed 
at  seeking  the  existence  of  law-bound  necessity  in  nature  without  any  ex- 
planations of  purpose.  But  then,  as  Johannsen  says,  finality  in  an  organism 
becomes  merely  an  expression  for  the  fact  that  "organisms  must  be  systems 
in  dynamic  equipoise,"  that  finality  in  general  is  self-evident  in  the  very 
fact  of  organization.  From  this  standpoint  one  does  not,  of  course,  explain 
by  external  causes  the  origin  of  functional  adaptation  in  the  organisms, 

^  Haeckel  has  made  a  special  point  of  the  human  appendix  as  a  proof  of  nature's  lack  of 
finality;  it  serves  no  purpose,  but  produces  only  dangerous  inflammations  —  an  extremely  in- 
genuous argument.  A  healthy  appendix,  of  course,  plays  its  part  in  the  renewal  of  substance, 
and  the  danger  of  sometimes  becoming  inflamed  is  one  to  which  any  section  of  the  intestine 
whatever  is  exposed. 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  573 

which  differentiates  them  from  inanimate  natural  objects;  on  the  contrary, 
this  becomes  part  of  the  problem  of  life  itself,  but  instead  we  get  rid  of  the 
anthropomorphistically  childish  speculations  upon  teleological  and  non- 
teleological  forms  of  organizations  in  nature,  which  actually  imply  a  con- 
fession that  we  cannot  grasp  the  idea  of  nature's  being  law-bound. 

In  such  circumstances  it  is  of  no  particular  interest  to  follow  Plate  in 
his  attempts  to  meet  all  conceivable  objections  to  the  theory  of  selection. 
Among  other  things  he  honestly  admits  that  it  has  never  been  possible 
actually  to  observe  selection,  but  he  consoles  himself  with  the  numerous 
indirect  arguments  that  could  be  quoted  in  its  defence.  Furthermore,  he 
emphatically  maintains  that,  besides  selection,  environment  co-operates  in 
renewing  the  organisms  and  their  descendants;  he  thus  rejects  Weismann's 
theory  of  the  omnipotence  of  selection,  as  well  as  Elmer's  and  other  neo- 
Lamarckists'  denial  of  its  metabolistic  power.  He  also  tried  to  adopt  an 
attitude,  consistent  with  his  own  point  of  view,  towards  the  results  of 
experimental  heredity-research,  dealing  with  them  in  a  monographic  Verer- 
bungslehre. 

With  this  we  can  leave  the  doctrine  of  descent  in  the  old  Darwanistic 
sense.  Modern  heredity-research  has  introduced  quite  a  different  and  essen- 
tially experimental  treatment  of  the  problems  of  evolution,  and  the  old 
morphological  speculation  upon  the  origin  of  species  and  genera  has  pro- 
portionately lost  ground  —  as  it  has  always  happened  in  the  history  of  the 
exact  sciences  that  speculation  must  give  way  to  facts.  The  old  doctrine  of 
descent  actually  possessed  the  weakness  of  insisting  upon  external  grounds 
of  explanation  for  the  phenomena  of  life;  selection  as  well  as  direct  outward 
influence  were  to  explain  phenomena  that  must  really  be  an  expression  for 
manifestations  of  life  itself.  Nevertheless  there  appears  here  also  an  increas- 
ing self-deliberation  based  on  a  progressive  knowledge  of  facts;  there  is  a 
vast  difference  between  Haeckel's  belief  in  the  power  of  Darwinism  to  ex- 
plain anything  whatsoever  and  Plate's  modest  limitation  of  the  function  of 
selection  to  a  mere  explanation  of  the  teleological  arrangements  of  living 
creatures,  "in  so  far  as  they  are  not  elementary  qualities."  Indeed,  why  not 
let  them  all  be  elementary  qualities?  One  can  trace  here  the  human  age-old 
tendency  to  look  for  outward  causes  for  everything;  formerly  one  sought  in 
the  phenomena  of  life  manifestations  of  a  divine  creator;  when  this  was  no 
longer  perceivable,  one  had  to  look  for  a  material  creative  power  —  it  was 
difficult  to  realize  that  evolution  is  a  part  of  life  itself.  We  shall  revert  below 
to  the  problems  of  evolution  in  the  form  in  which  modern  heredity-research 
has  presented  them. 


CHAPTER    XVII 


EXPERIMENTAL     BIOLOGY 


I. 


Experimental  Morphology 


THE  HISTORY  OF  BIOLOGY  might  really  close  with  the  establishing  of 
the  dissolution  of  Darwinism.  This  theory  undeniably  constitutes 
a  construction  of  thought  of  its  own,  and  the  ideas  and  methods 
of  research  that  have  succeeded  it  are  still  in  the  developing  stage,  and  their 
possibilities  of  development  can  at  best  be  only  guessed  at.  A  summary 
glance  at  these  conquests  of  the  newest  biology  is  nevertheless  defensible 
as  a  further  justification  for  the  defeat  of  the  old  ideas  and  in  view  of  the 
intrinsic  interest  that  the  new  discoveries  possess.  The  author,  who  himself 
laboured  exclusively  in  the  sphere  of  the  old  morphology  and  who  accord- 
ingly does  not  feel  justified  in  competing  with  the  many  splendid  presen- 
tations of  the  development  of  experimental  biology  that  already  exist, 
proposes  to  make  only  very  brief  reference  to  the  results  of  modern  research 
and  give  a  short  account  of  the  theoretical  reflections  to  which  they  have 
given  and  may  give  rise. 

In  a  lecture  given  in  1900  in  celebration  of  the  birth  of  the  twentieth 
century,  Oscar  Hertwig  gave  a  summary  of  the  history  of  biology  during 
the  past  century.  In  it  he  sharply  criticized  physiology,  which,  in  his  view, 
had  created  a  brilliant  experimental  technique  and  had  discovered  a  number 
of  facts  concerning  the  chemical  and  physical  processes  of  the  organisms, 
but,  on  the  other  hand,  had  neglected  all  other  vital  phenomena,  with  the 
result  that  a  whole  category  of  the  most  important  physiological  problems 
—  namely,  fertilization  and  embryonic  development  —  had  fallen  entirely 
into  the  hands  of  the  morphologists  and  been  dealt  with  by  anatomists, 
zoologists,  and  botanists.  While  the  professional  physiologists  had  thus  re- 
verted to  "an  empty  mechanism"  and  imagined  that  the  explanation  of  life 
was  only  a  chemico-physical  problem,  the  morphologists  discovered  the 
structural  conditions  in  the  fundamental  elements  of  the  body  that  are  char- 
acteristic of  the  phenomena  of  life  and  thereby  extended  the  knowledge  of 
life  in  a  sphere  in  which  the  methods  of  chemistry  and  physics  have  no  part. 
This  accusation  against  the  old  classical  physiology  has  certainly  been  to 
some  extent  justified  and  is  indeed  confirmed  by  a  statement  made  by  one  of 

574 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  575 

its  representatives  already  quoted  above;  owing  to  this  exclusiveness  physi- 
ology came  to  be  an  antithesis  to  morphology,  which  proved  disastrous, 
not  least  because  the  experimental  method  and  the  physiological  point  of 
view  no  longer  served  the  purposes  of  morphology,  which  in  consequence 
reverted  to  narrow  phylogenetical  speculations.  Botany  was  the  first  to  free 
itself  from  this  narrowness  of  view;  indeed,  there  appeared  at  quite  an  early 
stage  students  of  this  subject  who  were  capable  of  not  only  realizing  but 
also  solving  physiological  problems. 

Julius  Sachs  was  born  in  1831  at  Breslau,  of  poor  parents.  His  studies 
at  school  were  embittered  by  privation  and  could  be  continued  only  thanks 
to  the  kindness  shown  him  by  the  aged  Purkinje,  whose  sons  were  his  school- 
fellows. In  their  home  he  found  help  and  encouragement,  especially  in  his 
interest  in  botany,  which  he  displayed  at  an  early  age.  When  Purkinje  moved 
to  Prague,  young  Sachs's  prospects  looked  gloomy,  especially  as  he  was  now 
an  orphan,  but  fortunately  he  was  not  forgotten  by  his  old  benefactor;  he 
was  allowed  to  go  to  Prague  after  him  and  to  work  in  his  institute  as  an 
assistant  and  draughtsman,  while  he  completed  his  studies.  Having  received 
his  degree,  he  was  given  a  post  as  teacher  of  botany  at  the  Saxon  academy 
of  forestry  at  Tharand,  afterwards  obtaining  a  similar  situation  at  Bonn  and 
finally  being  called  in  1868  to  Wiirzburg,  where  he  laboured  for  nearly  thirty 
years,  gaining  a  brilliant  reputation  both  as  an  investigator  and  as  a  teacher. 
In  his  best  days  Wiirzburg  was  an  international  centre  for  botanical  re- 
search. Towards  the  close  of  his  life  his  powers  waned,  and  at  the  same  time 
he  lost  his  ability  to  follow  the  development  of  evolution;  his  self-conceit 
had  always  found  it  difficult  to  keep  within  reasonable  bounds,  and  in  his 
old  age  he  simply  could  not  endure  any  other  opinion  than  his  own.  This 
eventually  resulted  in  isolation,  which  embittered  his  existence.  He  died  in 

1897. 

Sachs  was  one  of  those  who  was  early  won  over  to  Darwinism,  and 
throughout  his  life  he  viewed  biology  from  the  angle  of  the  doctrine  of 
descent.  This  was  in  fact  the  reason  why  in  his  otherwise  praiseworthy 
Geschichte  der  Botanik  he  speaks  so  contemptuously  of  Linnasus,  who  to  him 
was  conspicuous  only  as  a  narrow-minded  apostle  of  the  constancy  of  species. 
But  Nageli  has  also  exercised  a  great  influence  upon  Sachs,  who,  for  instance, 
associates  himself  with  a  view  that  there  are  internal  causes  of  form-develop- 
ment in  living  creatures,  and  he  also  embraced  the  theory  of  protoplasm's 
being  composed  of  solid  particles  capable  of  absorbing  water  in  their  inter- 
vening spaces.  In  regard  to  heredity,  Sachs  holds  views  most  closely  reminis- 
cent of  Weismann's  germinal-plasm  theory. 

Sachs  creates  experimental  plant-biology 
Sachs,  however,  is  best  known  as  the  creator  of  experimental  plant-biology. 
This  science  had  really  made  but  little  progress  since  the  days  of  Saussure, 


576  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

for  both  the  botanists  of  the  romantic  school  and  their  immediate  successors 
had  mostly  applied  themselves  to  morphology.  Sachs,  on  the  other  hand, 
conscientiously  devoted  himself  from  the  beginning  to  the  problem  of  plant 
physiology  and  the  means  of  exploring  it.  Among  his  earliest  works  may 
be  mentioned  his  investigations  into  the  physiological  part  played  by  the 
chlorophyll  granules,  which  he  elucidated  in  its  most  essential  features:  he 
established  the  fact  that  starch  formation  is  the  first  product  of  carbonic-acid 
assimilation,  and,  further,  that  sunlight  plays  the  decisive  part  in  this  proc- 
ess. He  investigated  the  different  parts  of  the  solar  spectrum  with  the  view 
to  discovering  their  influence  upon  the  alimentation  of  plants.  Again,  the 
continued  metabolism  and  conveyance  of  nutrient  substances  within  the 
plant  has  been  worked  out  by  him  in  all  essential  features.  He  studied  all 
the  vital  processes  in  the  vegetable  kingdom  with  a  view  to  ascertaining 
their  intensity,  which  he  expressed  in  graphic  form.  It  was  mainly,  however, 
the  movements  of  flowers  that  he  systematically  investigated;  he  established 
the  dependence  of  the  direction  of  growth  upon  the  law  of  gravity  and  in- 
vented a  rotating  apparatus  by  means  of  which  this  growth  can  be  studied 
under  abnormal  conditions.  He  is  responsible  for  the  method  of  investiga- 
tion and  thorough  exploration  of  all  that  goes  by  the  name  of  tropisms  — 
at  least  as  far  as  the  vegetable  kingdom  is  concerned.  As  a  basis  for  all  these 
phenomena  he  mentions  irritability,  a  quality  which  he  believes  originates 
only  in  the  living  plasm  and  which  he  carefully  analyses  in  respect  of  its 
various  manifestations  —  an  investigation  that  has  been  of  immense  theo- 
retical importance  for  subsequent  research.  Finally,  it  may  be  mentioned 
that  Sachs  was  the  finest  text-book  writer  of  his  time.  Through  his  manuals 
the  facts  that  he  discovered  and  the  ideas  that  he  defended  have  spread 
far  beyond  the  circle  of  his  personal  pupils. 

Among  these  pupils  Wilhelm  Pfeffer  (1845-1910)  is  worthy  of  spe- 
cial mention.  When  still  quite  young  he  became  a  professor,  first  at  Tubingen 
and  afterwards  at  Leipzig,  where  he  subsequently  laboured  as  a  brilliant 
teacher  and  investigator.  He  made  a  special  study  of  the  phenomena  of 
growth  in  plants  and  the  influence  exerted  upon  them  by  both  external  and 
internal  factors.  He  investigated  a  number  of  external  influences  and  made 
valuable  contributions  to  our  knowledge  of  them,  at  the  same  time  consid- 
erably  improving  the  technique  employed  for  their  study.  However,  he 
emphatically  declares  that  external  influences  do  not  act  directly  in  a  de- 
velopmental way,  but  only  cause  a  change  of  activity  in  the  plant  itself. 
He  sees  in  the  study  of  this  reciprocal  action  between  external  influences 
and  internal  manifestations  of  life  the  very  aim  of  biology,  and  ''  dkjormative 
Determinierung  der  Zellen  und  der  Organe ' '  becomes  the  object  of  his  close  analy- 
sis. In  this  study  very  careful  attention  is  paid  to  all  co-operating  factors, 
so  far  as  they  can  be  calculated,  and  unwarranted  attempts  at  simplification 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  577 

are  rejected;  it  is  thus  definitely  declared  that  cell-division  is  a  physiological 
process  and  not  merely  a  question  of  increased  superficial  distention  within 
the  cell,  as  mechanistically  inclined  investigators  have  tried  to  explain  the 
phenomenon.  Generally  speaking,  clear  traces  of  PfefTer's  influence  as  re- 
gards the  presentation  of  problems  and  general  points  of  view  are  also  to 
be  found  in  experimental  zoology,  a  fact,  indeed,  that  some  of  its  exponents 
have  openly  acknowledged.  His  labours  have  proved  of  still  greater  impor- 
tance to  botanical  specialized  research-work;  he  is  generally  acknowledged 
as  one  of  the  leading  personalities  in  botany  in  modern  times. 

Another  eminent  pupil  of  Sachs  was  Karl  Eberhard  Goebel  (born  in 
1855),  "^^°  ^^^^  ^^  ^^^  '-^'^^  ^^  assistant  at  Wiirzburg  and  has  since  worked 
as  a  professor  at  several  universities,  latterly  at  Munich.  He  is  an  investi- 
gator of  many  parts,  being  a  plant-geographist  with  a  wide  experience  of 
the  tropics,  a  morphologist,  and  a  physiologist.  As  a  morphologist  he  has 
always  maintained  the  dependence  of  form  upon  function;  morphology 
should  no  longer  be  kept  separate  from  physiology,  as  formerly.  He  employed 
the  old  word  "metamorphosis"  to  denote  organic  development,  but  not 
in  the  old  idealistic  sense;  by  it  he  would  express  the  idea  that  a  change  in 
function  produces  a  change  in  form.  "Our  idea  of  metamorphosis  is  thus  in 
the  first  instance  ontogenetical,  and  thereby  experimentally  conceivable  and 
demonstrable,"  he  says.  According  to  him,  no  "indifferent  rudiments" 
exist,  for  every  rudiment  has  its  peculiar  qualities,  which  determine  its  de- 
velopment, and  this  can  suffer  change  only  as  the  result  of  definite  changes 
in  the  vital  manifestations.  "If  we  call  a  leaf-rudiment  at  any  stage  'in- 
different,' it  really  means  nothing  but  a  denial  of  the  causal  connexion  of 
evolutional  phenomena."  These  changes  in  the  conditions  of  life  can  be  pro- 
duced experimentally,  and  extremely  important  experiences  in  regard  to  the 
organic  construction  of  plants  can  be  gained  thereby.  Space  forbids  our  going 
closely  into  Goebel's  experimental  studies  in  " Or gano graphic,''  as  he  calls 
the  study  of  the  relation  between  an  organic  form  and  function.  He  has 
hereby  performed  a  great  service  in  furthering  the  investigation  of  plant 
evolution  and  the  mechanical  process  in  evolution  in  general. 

Even  apart  from  Sachs's  school  there  have  been  many  important  stu- 
dents of  plant  biology  who  have  produced  valuable  results;  a  couple  of  them 
may  be  mentioned  here.  Julius  Wiesner  (i 838-191 6),  professor  at  Vienna, 
has  carried  out  useful  experiments  in  the  sphere  of  technical  botany,  espe- 
cially in  regard  to  the  effect  of  light  upon  the  vegetable  world,  which  he 
studied  in  different  localities  and  under  different  experimental  conditions. 
Hans  Karl  Albert  Winkler  (born  in  1877),  professor  at  Hamburg,  brought 
to  light  the  curious  graft-hybrid  phenomena:  as  a  result  of  grafting  related 
plant-species  their  tissues  can  be  made  to  grow  through  one  another  in  dif- 
ferent ways. 


578  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

In  zoology  the  experimental  method  has  made  slow  but  sure  progress. 
Strictly  speaking,  its  development  has  gone  hand  in  hand  with  the  new  con- 
ception of  the  fundamental  problems  of  biology  that  has  gradually  usurped 
the  place  of  the  old  phylogenetical  idea,  dating  from  the  zenith  of  Darwin- 
ism. It  may  be  said  that  the  new  principle  had  already  been  enunciated  by 
Kleinenberg  in  his  above-quoted  saying  that  an  organ's  form  depends  upon 
its  function  and  not  upon  its  origin.  Almost  at  the  same  time  as  this  utter- 
ance was  made,  August  Rauber  (i84z-i9I7),  professor  of  anatomy  at  Dorpat, 
sought  to  discover  the  conditions  and  laws  governing  the  first  construc- 
tion of  form  in  the  vertebrate  embryo.  In  opposition  to  the  contemporary 
belief  in  the  independence  of  the  individual  cells  he  maintains  that  the  whole 
governs  the  parts  and  not  vice  versa;  the  egg-cell  determines  the  directions 
of  cleavage  by  its  division  of  matter,  growth  is  the  primary  and  cleavage 
the  secondary.  Division  into  many  cells  facilitates  the  metabolism  of  sub- 
stance and  renders  possible  greater  strength  in  the  organism  and,  by  special- 
izing the  elements,  a  far  more  extensive  division  of  labour,  but  even  when 
this  division  of  labour  is  at  its  maximum,  the  organism  remains  a  whole, 
the  parts  of  which  are  developed  under  the  influence  of  the  whole.  Through 
his  efforts  to  find  out  in  detail  the  conditions  governing  the  various  phases 
of  development,  Rauber  became,  along  with  His,  Goette,  and  Kleinenberg, 
a  precursor  of  the  later  school  of  evolutional  physiology. 

As  its  founder  is  named  by  universal  accord  Wilhelm  Roux  (1850-1914). 
He  was  born  at  Jena,  where  his  father  was  a  fencing-master.  He  studied 
first  under  Haeckel  and  then,  at  Strassburg,  under  Goette,  and  also  in  Berlin. 
He  became  professor,  first  at  Innsbruck,  then  at  Halle,  where  he  worked 
during  the  period  1895-19x1.  He  laboured  with  never-failing  energy  and 
powers  of  endurance,  in  speeches  and  in  writing,  as  a  teacher  and  an  agita- 
tor, on  behalf  of  the  method  of  research  and  the  line  of  investigation  that 
he  originated.  As  a  research -worker  he  has  already  been  outdistanced  by 
younger  minds,  but  he  will  always  be  regarded  as  a  pioneer.  However,  the 
same  line  of  thought  has  been  followed  from  other  quarters  as  well  —  as, 
for  instance,  by  the  disciples  of  the  above-mentioned  plant-physiologists, 
Sachs  and  Pfeffer,  whose  ideas  were  really  in  many  respects  in  accord  with 
those  of  zoological  evolutional  mechanics. 

Roux  was  a  pupil  of  both  Haeckel  and  Goette;  his  works,  in  fact,  bear 
traces  of  the  influence  of  both,  not  only  in  his  early  days,  but  even  at  a  far 
later  age:  even  into  the  nineties  phylogeny  still  represented  the  aim  of  his 
research  work,  and  the  struggle  for  existence  and  selection  appear  to  him 
the  most  vital  forces  of  life.  But  he  would  achieve  this  aim,  not  like  Haeckel 
through  a  mere  comparison  between  more  primitive  and  more  developed 
forms,  but  through  investigating  the  mechanical  process  in  ontogenetical  ev- 
olution, such  as  through  the  program  that  Goette  had  in  mind.  As  a  matter 


MODERNBIOLOGY  5  79 

of  fact,  Roux  also  has  points  of  contact  with  Weismann,  whose  theory 
of  the  continuity  of  the  germinal  plasm  he  embraces;  he  consequently  re- 
jects the  theory  of  the  heredity  of  acquired  characters.  He  resembles  Weis- 
mann, too,  in  the  fact  that  he  likes  discussing  hypothetical  entities  of  life, 
whereof  he  enumerates  a  whole  series,  which,  however,  it  is  not  worth 
while  dilating  upon  here.  For  these  very  reasons  he  was  on  bad  terms  with 
O.  Hertwig,  who,  as  we  have  seen,  entertained  quite  different  views,  just 
as,  on  the  other  hand,  he  was  at  variance  with  Haeckel  and  other  original 
Darwinists  on  account  of  his  mechanical  theory  of  evolution. 

Creation  of  evolutional  mechanics 
The  theoretical  speculations  upon  descent  are,  however,  a  less  essential  side 
of  Roux's  research  work.  He  will  mostly  be  remembered  as  the  creator  of 
experimental  embryology;  whether  the  theories  that  he  based  upon  his  ex- 
periments are  eventually  accepted  or  rejected,  there  is  no  doubt  at  any  rate 
about  the  fact  that  he  created  a  special  method  of  research,  which  has  proved 
productive  and  was  largely  employed  by  his  contemporaries.  But  he  also 
exercised  considerable  influence  upon  the  theoretical  conception  of  biology 
itself;  he  has  directed  research  to  a  series  of  problems  which  many,  following 
his  precedent,  have  taken  up  for  treatment  and  which  have  largely  guided 
modern  biological  research.  He  himself  defined  as  the  aim  of  the  new  science 
that  he  desired  to  found  the  elucidation  of  the  "true  causes  of  formation" 
to  which  all  living  creatures  and  every  single  individual  must  attribute 
their  origin  —  a  subject  in  which  the  earlier  "descriptive  natural  science," 
to  his  mind,  failed  to  show  any  interest.  These  causes  of  "form-building 
forces,"  whereby  the  individual  organism  receives  step  by  step  the  form  that 
characterizes  it,  must,  in  his  opinion,  be  studied  primarily  by  way  of  ex- 
periment; if  a  process  of  development  is  altered  by  different  kinds  of  inter- 
ference, it  is  possible  by  combining  the  results  to  discover  the  cause  of  the 
process;  thus  is  created  a  "causal-analytical  form  of  research,"  such  as  chem- 
istry and  physics  had  already  realized  in  many  instances. 

Natural  selection  ivithin  the  organism 
As  previously  mentioned,  Roux  began  his  activities  with  a  theory  of  func- 
tional adaptation  produced  by  means  of  natural  selection  within  the  organ- 
ism. This  theory  he  sought  to  apply  to  the  organs  of  various  vertebrate 
animals;  he  measured  a  large  number  of  muscles  in  man  and  tried  to  deter- 
mine to  what  extent  their  dimensions  are  dependent  upon  one  another;  he 
studied  the  caudal  fin  of  the  dolphin  from  a  mechanical  point  of  view  and 
sought  to  determine  the  lines  and  curves  in  which  these  tissues  are  arranged 
in  order  mechanically  to  sustain  the  function  of  the  whole.  After  a  short 
time,  however,  he  went  over  entirely  to  embryology,  and  in  this  field  pro- 
pounded the  question  to  what  extent  and  how  far  back  in  evolution  certain  or- 
gans and  tissues  are  predestined  to  assume  their  prospective  form  and  function. 


580  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

and  whether  this  predestination  can  be  affected  by  different  influences. 
This  problem,  in  fact,  is  the  old  antithesis  of  preformation  and  epigenesis 
formulated  in  a  different  way,  and  the  discussion  of  the  problem  has  to  a 
great  extent  been  carried  on  in  the  new  form  brought  about  by  the  employ- 
ment of  the  methods  of  experimental  embryology.  Roux  himself,  starting 
from  the  theory  of  the  continuity  of  the  germinal  plasm,  which  was  in- 
fluenced by  Weismann  and  Sachs,  maintained  the  idea  of  a  very  early  deter- 
mination of  the  various  parts  of  the  embryo;  in  his  view,  the  first  cleavage 
plane  of  the  germinal  egg  establishes  the  median  plane  in  the  individual, 
the  cleavage  furrow  is  determined  by  the  line  of  penetration  of  the  sperm, 
and  the  front  part  of  the  future  animal  is  already  determined  before  the  fer- 
tilization of  the  egg  through  the  amassing  of  cytoplasm  in  that  quarter. 
Each  successive  cleavage  delimits  a  prospective  part  of  the  embryo;  be- 
cause in  karyokinesis  the  substance  becomes  not  equally  apportioned  to  the 
daughter-nuclei,  these  latter  acquire  different  values,  so  that,  as  he  says,  the 
whole  process  of  development  becomes  a  piece  of  mosaic  work.  In  proof  of 
his  theory  Roux  carried  out  a  series  of  experiments,  which  excited  universal 
admiration  at  the  time;  he  treated  a  newly-fertilized  frog's  egg  in  such  a 
way  that  with  a  heated  needle  he  burnt  away  one  of  the  two  first-formed 
blastomeres;  then  there  developed  at  first  a  half-embryo,  which  afterwards  re- 
generated in  the  usual  manner  of  the  Amphibia.  Roux  performed  many  other 
experiments  with  the  same  purpose  in  view,  and  though  his  technique  was 
simple  as  compared  with  that  which  his  successors  afterwards  elaborated, 
it  was  nevertheless  he  who  first  systematized  this  kind  of  research  work. 
Roux,  however,  was  at  once  subjected  to  sharp  criticism;  O.  Hertwig 
in  particular,  who  from  the  very  beginning  had  been  an  opponent  of 
the  Weismann  heredity-theory  and  its  founders,  at  once  attacked  the 
"mosaic"  theory,  maintaining  that  the  different  parts  of  the  egg  are 
by  no  means  predetermined,  but  that,  on  the  contrary,  the  egg's  mass 
is  equipotential-isotopic,  as  he  calls  it.  Moreover,  Hertwig,  who  in- 
variably opposed  narrow  mechanistic  tendencies  in  biology,  strongly  ob- 
jected to  the  actual  term  "developmental  mechanics,"  which  appeared  to 
him  to  imply  an  inadmissible  schematizing  of  the  phenomena  of  life.  And, 
finally,  he  considered  Roux's  experiments  to  be  inaccurate;  he  imitated  them 
and  found  that  the  halved  egg  gave  rise,  not  to  a  half-embryo,  but  to  a 
whole  embryo  of  small  size.  Hertwig  found  immediate  support  in  Driesch, 
an  observer  who  will  be  mentioned  further  in  another  connexion.  He  halved 
newly-segmented  eggs  of  the  sea-urchin  and  obtained  from  each  half  one 
larva  half  the  size  of  the  normal.  On  the  basis  of  these  and  other  experiments 
he  propounded  a  special  theory  of  evolution,  according  to  which  each  part 
of  the  egg  has,  on  the  one  hand,  a  "prospective  value,"  and,  on  the  other 
hand,  a  "prospective  potentiality";  the  meaning  of  these  terms  will  best 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  581 

be  explained  by  an  example:  the  half-egg  of  the  sea-urchin  has  the  pro- 
spective value  of  forming  half  a  larva,  but  the  potentiality  to  form  a  whole 
larva;  the  former  is  thus  the  determination  of  the  part  that  holds  good  in 
normal  cases,  the  latter  the  power  of  every  part  to  compensate  for  another 
if  necessary.  On  the  other  hand,  Roux  found  support  in  the  American  Wilson. 
He  isolated  cleavage  cells  from  the  egg  of  a  mollusc  and  found  that  they 
became  what  they  would  have  become  in  their  normal  connexion,  and  noth- 
ing more.  And  later  Boveri  discovered  that  the  sea-urchin's  eggs  investigated 
by  Driesch  actually  possess  a  differentiation  that  from  the  beginning  deter- 
mines the  succeeding  developmental  orientation.  The  fact  is,  the  disputants 
have  gradually  had  to  reconcile  their  views;  Roux  had  to  abandon  his  theory 
of  the  different-shaped  cleavage  of  the  nuclei,  while  Driesch  had  to  give  up 
his  theory  of  the  absolutely  uniform  character  of  the  sea-urchin's  egg.  On 
the  whole,  these  experimental  discoveries  were  too  generalized;  what  was 
discovered  in  the  case  of  one  animal's  egg  was  applied  without  question  to 
the  entire  animal  kingdom,  whereas  in  actual  fact  a  vast  number  of  different 
conditions  prevail.  In  the  main,  however,  it  seems  as  if  subsequent  research 
has  obtained  results  that  would  indicate  generally  that  a  very  early  special- 
ization and  localization  of  the  rudiments  take  place  in  the  embryo.  The 
investigations  that  have  been  carried  out  especially  by  Hans  Spemann,  one 
of  the  foremost  champions  of  experimental  morphology  at  the  present  time, 
give  some  evidence  of  this.  Born  in  1869  at  Stuttgart,  he  studied  at  Heidel- 
berg, Munich,  and  Wiirzburg,  and  has  been  a  professor  at  Rostock  and 
at  the  Kaiser  Wilhelm  Institute  in  Berlin;  he  is  now  working  at  Freiburg. 
An  extremely  clever  experimenter,  he  has  specially  taken  upon  himself  to 
prove  the  determination  of  different  sections  of  the  embryo  by  transferring 
parts  of  the  body  of  a  batrachian  embryo  from  one  place  to  another  and 
then  studying  the  successive  development.  As  a  general  result  he  records  that 
the  main  organs  of  the  amphibian  embryo  are  definitely  determined  during 
the  process  of  gastrula  formation;  at  an  earlier  period,  in  the  blastula  stage, 
normally  formed  twins  can  be  produced  by  means  of  dividing  off  with  thread; 
at  the  beginning  of  the  gastrula  stage  the  forward  end  can  still  be  doubled 
by  means  of  binding,  but  after  that  the  possibility  of  regulation  decreases, 
and  disappears  altogether  when  the  gastrula  is  completely  formed.  We  must 
here  pass  over  the  details  of  the  minutely  planned  and  carefully  carried-out 
experiments  by  which  these  statements  are  proved,  as  also  the  particulars 
of  the  various  attempts  he  made  to  get  mechanical  influences  to  operate  — 
pressure,  binding  up,  and  such  means,  whereby  different  observers  have 
sought  to  trace  out  the  forces  operating  inside  the  egg  and  to  discover  the 
details  of  which  they  are  composed. 

Besides  these  purely  mechanical  experiments  others  have,  of  course,  been 
carried  out,  such  as  those  in  which  eggs  and  embryos  have  been  subjected 


58x  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

to  the  influence  of  electricity,  light,  heat,  chemical  compounds;  of  these 
the  last  in  particular  have  produced  results  of  great  interest.  Among  such 
may  be  quoted  the  experiments  of  Curt  Herbst  (born  in  1866),  Biitschli's 
successor  at  Heidelberg.  He  placed  sea-urchins'  eggs  in  various  saline  solu- 
tions; in  lime-free  sea-water  the  eggs  disintegrate  into  their  first  cleavage 
cells,  w^hich  give  rise  to  dwarf  larvas;  the  addition  of  lithium  salt  produces 
quite  abnormally  developed  larvas;  treatment  with  sulphate-free  sea-water 
also  causes  peculiar  malformations  in  various  parts  of  the  egg.  Undoubtedly 
the  most  remarkable  of  these  chemical  experiments  in  evolution  are,  how- 
ever, those  concerned  with  the  initial  development  of  the  egg.  In  this  field 
Jacques  Loeb  not  only  has  taken  the  initiative,  but  has  also  proved  a  leader. 
Born  in  Germany  of  Jewish  parents  in  1859,  he  studied  medicine  in  his  na- 
tive country,  becoming  a  doctor  and  assistant  lecturer  in  physiology  at 
Wiirzburg,  but  he  soon  migrated  to  America,  where  he  held  a  number  of 
professorships,  the  last  one  being  at  the  Rockefeller  Institute  in  New  York.^ 
Already,  in  the  eighties,  R.  Hertwig  had  observed  that  unfertilized  sea- 
urchins'  eggs,  if  treated  with  a  weak  solution  of  strychnine,  surround  them- 
selves with  a  membrane  similar  to  that  which  appears  after  fertilization, 
before  the  cleavage  begins.  Similar  observations  were  made  later  by  Morgan, 
the  well-known  student  of  heredity.  Loeb  took  up  this  problem  for  system- 
atic revision  and  achieved  results  that  at  once  attracted  great  attention  and 
in  some  directions  produced  very  far-reaching  conclusions  and  awakened 
high  expectations.  After  performing  a  series  of  experiments  he  worked  out 
a  method  of  bringing  the  sea-urchin's  eggs  to  the  larval  stage  without  ferti- 
lization. This  method  is  somewhat  complicated;  first  of  all,  the  eggs  are 
subjected  to  the  influence  of  a  weak  organic  acid,  which  induces  the  forma-  , 
tion  of  membrane,  after  which  they  are  placed  for  a  carefully  fixed  period 
in  sea-water,  the  salinity  of  which  has  been  increased  to  one  and  one-half 
times  the  normal  and  which  besides  has  been  mixed  with  soda,  and  finally 
in  normal  sea-water,  in  which  the  development  takes  place.  Several  other 
simpler  methods  have  also  produced  results,  but  they  have  been  few  and 
indefinite.  The  above  method,  however,  subject  to  careful  regulation,  works 
safely,  although,  contrary  to  Loeb's  statements,  the  larv^  thus  formed  are 
by  no  means  invariably  quite  typical.  On  account  of  this,  Loeb  has  tried  to 
ascertain  the  chemical  compounds  that  induce  development  and  has  come 
to  the  conclusion  that  the  membrane  formation  is  caused  by  the  fat-dis- 
solving capacity  of  the  influencing  acid,  and  that  the  spermatozoon,  which 
upon  penetrating  the  egg  has  the  same  effect,  must  produce  a  similar  sub- 
stance. The  "hypertonic"  sea-water  then  used  "corrects"  this  effect  and 
thereby  contributes  to  the  actual  segmentation.  Thus  the  multiplication  of 

^   Loeb  died  in  1924. 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  583 

cells  would  be  reduced  to  a  relatively  simple  sequence  of  chemical  processes. 
There  can  be  no  doubt,  however,  that  Loeb  has  simplified  overmuch.  Other 
investigators  have,  in  fact,  produced  the  same  developmental  phenomena 
by  entirely  different  methods.  Among  those  who  have  worked  in  this  field 
may  be  mentioned,  apart  from  Loeb's  own  pupils,  Yves  Delage  (1854-1910), 
professor  at  Paris,  who  worked  out  his  own  method  of  developing  the  sea- 
urchin's  egg,  and  A.  Bataillon,  professor  at  Dijon,  who  acquired  a  name 
especially  as  a  result  of  his  experiments  with  the  frog's  egg;  by  simply 
pricking  the  egg  with  a  needle  dipped  in  serum,  he  caused  the  frog's  eggs 
to  develop  into  larvas  —  a  method  that  "activates"  the  egg  in  an  entirely 
different  way  from  Loeb's.  Here  we  obviously  have  a  metabolistic  process 
within  the  very  mass  of  the  egg,  set  free  by  mechanical  irritation  —  as  a 
matter  of  fact,  the  dose  of  serum  has  latterly  proved  to  be  superfluous  — 
although  the  adipose  splitting  can  in  this  case  also  be  established;  it  is  here 
induced  by  the  egg's  own  vital  manifestations  and  not  by  any  solvent  in- 
troduced from  outside.  Loeb's  theories,  to  which  we  shall  revert,  are  gov- 
erned entirely  by  his  lack  of  interest  in  morphological  phenomena  and  by 
his  consequent  passion  for  schematizing  the  complex  vital  process.  Strictly 
speaking,  most  other  evolutional  physiologists  of  the  new  direction,  from 
however  mechanical  a  point  of  view  they  may  otherwise  have  regarded 
evolution,  have  nevertheless  divided  its  mechanical  phenomena  into  those 
having  a  purely  external  origin  and  those  that  result  from  specific  internal 
causes.  Among  the  former  are  counted  the  universally  observable  influences 
of  heat,  electricity,  chemical  reagents;  among  the  latter,  the  various  organ- 
isms' peculiar  ways  of  reacting  to  them,  as  well  as  to  purely  mechanical  inter- 
ferences, with  their  normal  existence.  In  the  course  of  studying  these  hetero- 
geneous phenomena  of  reaction  many  of  the  experimental  observers  of  our 
own  time  have  produced  and  are  still  producing  a  great  number  of  detailed  re- 
sults of  immense  interest,  achieved  by  the  employment  of  exquisitely  delicate 
methods.  For  the  details  of  this  field  of  inquiry  —  still  by  no  means  ex- 
hausted —  we  must  refer  the  reader  to  technical  literature  on  the  subject;  a 
number  of  general  points  of  view  that  have  arisen  in  the  course  of  the  work 
carried  out  in  connexion  with  these  subjects  will  be  discussed  later  on.  We 
shall  instead  pass  on  to  another  form  of  experimental  research  —  a  field  that 
is  without  doubt  of  the  greatest  interest  to  humanity  at  the  present  time. 


■L.   Experimental  Heredity-research 

Earlier  ideas  on  heredity 
"Inheritance"  and  "heredity"  are  terms  that  originally  belonged  to  the 
judiciary  and  have  been  borrowed  from  it  to  acquire  a  natural  meaning. 


584  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

Just  as  the  right  of  a  child  to  take  over  his  parents'  property  is  called  in- 
heritance, so  the  word  is  used  to  denote  the  fact,  which  has  been  known  of 
old,  that  children  resemble  their  parents  in  body  and  soul;  facial  features 
and  figure  are  said  to  "be  hereditary ' '  from  father  and  mother  to  son  and 
daughter.  It  can  be  no  matter  for  surprise  that  from  the  beginning  the  mean- 
ing of  heredity  in  the  biological  sense  has  been  considered  to  be  this:  the 
direct  transmission  of  qualities  from  parents  to  children  —  that,  in  fact, 
has  been  the  idea  up  to  recent  times  and  it  has  not  been  until  the  details 
of  this  transmission  came  to  be  studied  that  a  deeper  insight  has  been  gained 
into  the  true  facts,  and  an  entirely  new  conception  has  taken  the  place  of 
the  old  theory  of  transmission.  It  is  through  this  research  work  that  the 
problems  of  evolution  have  for  the  first  time  been  dealt  with  on  an  entirely 
exact  basis;  the  same  mathematical  exactness  that  formerly  only  experi- 
mental physiology  was  capable  of  achieving  now  characterizes  the  methods 
and  results  of  heredity  research. 

Exact  heredity-research  has  received  contributions  from  various  quar- 
ters. Investigators  with  a  Darwinistic  training  have  made  weighty  contri- 
butions to  it,  but  besides  these,  others  —  and,  in  fact,  the  most  valuable 
of  all  —  have  come  from  circles  that  have  had  nothing  whatever  to  do 
with  Darwinism.  In  a  previous  section  have  been  mentioned  the  investiga- 
tions into  the  hybridization  of  plants  that  were  carried  out  in  the  eighteenth 
century  by  Koelreuter.  His  experiments  were  taken  up  by  many  other  stu- 
dents, among  the  most  highly  reputed  of  whom  may  be  named  Karl  Fried- 
rich  Gartner  (1772.-1850),  a  medical  practitioner  by  profession,  whose 
elaborate  experiments  with  plant  hybrids  brought  him  a  great  reputation 
and  were  especially  taken  advantage  of  by  Darwin.  The  experiments  carried 
out  by  the  Frenchman  Louis  Leveque  de  Vilmorin  (18x6-60)  were  of  a 
different  type.  De  Vilmorin  belonged  to  a  family  that  for  generations  had 
carried  on  trade  in  grain  and  seed-cultivation;  he  himself  was  particularly 
interested  in  sugar-beet,  which  he  cultivated  with  a  view  to  increasing  its 
percentage  of  sugar.  In  this  he  started  from  the  principle  that  the  offspring 
of  each  individual  should  always  be  kept  separate;  he  collected  the  seeds 
of  beets  with  a  high  sugar-content  and  sowed  them  separately,  with  the 
result  that  he  obtained  cultures  of  a  very  valuable  quality;  in  doing  so  he 
discovered  that  individuals  that  look  alike  might  have  entirely  different 
characters,  and  he  thus  came  to  hold  the  view  that  the  power  of  inheriting 
characters  might  in  itself  vary  and  give  rise  to  heterogeneous  offspring. 
Through  these  results  de  Vilmorin  became  a  pioneer  of  modern  heredity- 
research,  and  his  theses,  based,  as  they  are,  upon  exact  observations,  possess 
quite  a  different  value  from  his  contemporaries'  "philosophical"  specula- 
tions on  heredity,  numerous  traces  of  which  are  to  be  found,  inter  alia,  in 
belles-lettres  of  a  naturalistic  type. 


MODERNS  lOLOGY  585 

The  problem  of  heredity  was  dealt  with  from  an  entirely  dilTerent 
point  of  view  by  Francis  Galton  (i82.i-i9ii).  He  was  a  cousin  of  Darwin's 
and  his  life  reminds  one  of  the  latter's.  The  son  of  wealthy  parents,  he 
studied  medicine,  but  never  graduated,  for  as  soon  as  he  had  inherited  his 
father's  fortune,  he  went  on  voyages,  first  to  Eygpt  and  then  to  south-west 
Africa,  where  he  made  valuable  geographical  discoveries.  After  his  return 
to  England  he  applied  himself  for  some  years  to  meteorology,  but  eventually 
devoted  his  life  entirely  to  heredity  research.  He  began  by  seeking  to  prove 
experimentally  Darwin's  pangenesis  theory,  which,  it  will  be  remembered, 
assumes  that  particles  from  all  the  organs  of  the  body  are  transmitted 
through  the  sexual  products  from  generation  to  generation  and  bring  about 
the  offspring's  resemblance  to  the  parents.  Galton  injected  blood  from  a 
foreign  rabbit  into  a  pair  of  grey  ones,  in  the  hope  that  their  progeny  would 
thereby  become  dappled,  which  would  have  been  a  proof  of  the  pangenesis 
theory;  but  his  expectations  were  not  fulfilled,  the  young  of  the  grey  rabbits 
turning  out  grey.  In  virtue  of  this  experience  Galton  produced  a  heredity 
theory  of  his  own:  all  the  organic  units  existing  in  a  fertilized  egg  he  terms 
"stirp,"  and  he  believes  that  the  majority  of  these  are  used  for  purposes  of 
organic  structure,  but  that  a  number  of  them  are  left  over,  and  these  give 
rise  to  the  sexual  cells,  the  qualities  of  which  are  thus  not  influenced  by 
the  conditions  of  life  of  the  individual.  He  gave  expression  to  this  opposi- 
tion to  the  doctrine  of  the  heredity  of  acquired  characters  as  early  as  in 
1875  —  ^^^^  ^^'  before  Weismann  —  but  after  that  he  passed  on  to  quite 
different  developmental  problems.  From  the  very  beginning  the  evolution 
of  man  had  been  a  subject  of  special  interest  to  him;  he  is  extremely  fond 
of  demonstrating  physiological  phenomena  with  the  aid  of  social  and  politi- 
cal comparisons.  The  fact  that  brothers  and  sisters  are  often  so  unlike  one 
another  is  explained  by  a  reference  to  an  electoral  body,  where  a  very  slight 
difference  of  opinion  can  often  give  rise  to  an  entirely  different  result  when 
it  comes  to  the  vote;  in  the  same  way,  a  slight  change  in  the  hereditary  sub- 
stance can  produce  a  complete  change  in  the  appearance  of  the  individual. 

Galton  s  statistical  method 
In  a  later  work.  Natural  Inheritance,  Galton  has  presented  the  statistical 
heredity-theory  that  has  made  his  name  famous;  his  stirp  theory  is  here 
abandoned  and  the  transmission  of  acquired  characters  is  no  longer  denied 
so  absolutely  as  it  had  been  before.  Instead,  basing  his  arguments  on  an 
exhaustive  research-material,  he  tries  to  find  out  the  variational  direction 
in  a  large  number  of  human  qualities.  The  most  highly  valued  of  his  investi- 
gations have  been  those  into  the  question  of  height;  the  height  of  a  number 
of  parents  was  compared  with  that  of  their  grown-up  children  arranged  in 
series  from  the  shortest  to  the  tallest;  there  is  thus  obtained  an  average 
height,   which   is   possessed    by    the    majority,   while  the   less   numerous 


586  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

extremes  of  abnormally  short  and  tall  persons  group  themselves  in  either  di- 
rection from  the  middle.  Now,  Galton  finds  as  a  result  of  his  heredity  research 
a  variation  towards  the  mean  value,  the  children  of  the  tallest  groups  of 
parents  having  become  tall,  but  not  so  tall  as  the  parents;  those  of  the  short- 
est parents,  on  the  other  hand,  having  become  short,  but  not  quite  so  short 
as  the  parents  themselves.  From  this  Galton  infers  that  there  is  a  heredity 
variability  in  a  certain  direction,  which  natural  selection,  of  course,  influ- 
ences. This  result,  seeing  that  it  first  came  to  light  when  Darwinism  was  at 
the  height  of  its  popularity,  was  bound  to  win  many  supporters,  as  also  did 
Galton's  principle  that  it  is  necessary  to  deal  statistically  with  as  large  a 
number  of  cases  as  possible,  seeing  that  law-bound  necessity  in  isolated  cases 
is  effaced  by  incidental  circumstances.  This  principle  was  bound  to  attract  a 
generation  that  preferred  to  regard  humanity  collectively  and  placed  but  little 
value  on  what  was  purely  individual.  Later,  however,  it  has  been  found  that 
this  collectivism  actually  constituted  Galton's  most  serious  weakness;  it  is 
practically  an  impossibility  to  draw  conclusions  regarding  the  individual  case 
from  statistical  mass-calculations,  and  if  it  is  attempted,  it  leads  to  absurd  re- 
sults. On  the  other  hand,  Galton's  service  lies  in  the  fact  that  he  introduced 
exact  measurements  and  mathematical  calculations  into  the  theory  of  evolu- 
tion; his  method  of  expressing  the  details  of  development  graphically  by 
means  of  curves  has  since  been  applied  with  great  success  by  students  who 
were  able  to  isolate  well-defined  phenomena  and  to  follow  them  up  through 
different  generations.  For  Galton's  chief  weakness  was  really  this,  that  he 
believed  that  he  could  deal  with  practically  anything  statistically;  he  never 
realized  that  an  object  which  is  to  be  examined  must  first  have  its  true  essence 
determined.  Thus,  in  his  above-mentioned  work  he  tried  to  determine  statisti- 
cally the  laws  governing  "marriage  selection"  —  inter  alia,  whether  persons 
of  different  dispositions  feel  attracted  to  their  likes  or  vice  versa.  From  one  of 
his  tables  it  appears  that  46%  of  married  men  are  ill-tempered;  of  these,  again, 
2.7.%  have  had  good  and  X4%  bad-tempered  wives. ^  Statistics  of  this  sort 
seem  far  more  suited  to  a  comic  paper.  The  fact  that  Galton  seriously  tried 
to  solve  such  a  problem  testifies  to  his  extraordinarily  dilettante  mind,  which 
cannot  be  excused  by  the  fact  that  even  at  a  later  period  an  occasional  stu- 
dent of  heredity  has  sought  to  ascertain  the  existence  and  transmission  of 
equally  vague  and  indefinite  human  qualities.  As  a  matter  of  fact,  Galton 
applied  his  method  not  only  to  human  beings;  he  also  experimented  in  hor- 
ticulture, dealing  with  the  results  thus  obtained  by  the  same  statistical 
method.  He  bequeathed  his  fortune  to  an  institute  for  heredity  research  in 
London,  which  afterwards  worked  in  accordance  with  the  principles  that 
he  had  laid  down.  Galton  had  human  welfare  very  much  at  heart;  he  wanted 

^  See  "Appendix  D"  in  chat  work. 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  587 

to  create  a  better  human  race  and  desired  that  all  research  work  should  serve 
that  object;  he  gave  to  the  science  that  he  placed  highest  of  all  the  name 
of  "eugenics,"  a  name  that  has  become  universally  accepted. 

A  new  phase  in  the  history  of  heredity  research  was  introduced  by  Hugo 
DE  Vries.  Born  at  Haarlem  in  1848,  he  studied  at  Wiirzburg  under  Sachs, 
held  various  posts  in  Germany,  and  finally  became  professor  at  Amsterdam. 
He  applied  himself  first  to  the  study  of  plant  physiology  and  published  val- 
uable results  of  his  investigations  into  the  pressure  conditions  in  plant-cells. 
At  the  same  time  he  speculated  over  Darwinistic  problems.  He,  too,  pro- 
duced a  theory  of  life-entities,  which  he  called  "pangens,"  by  which  he 
meant  those  qualities  in  the  organism  which  are  capable  of  independent 
variation,  and  each  of  which  must,  in  his  view,  be  represented  by  one  ma- 
terial entity.  Like  so  many  other  biologists  of  the  younger  generation,  how- 
ever, he  entertained  doubts  as  to  the  ability  of  the  traditional  Darwinism 
to  solve  the  problem  of  evolution.  He  was  especially  preoccupied  with  the 
undeniable  fact  that  the  species  in  nature  remain  constant  and  that  the  slight 
transitions  whereby,  according  to  the  old  theory,  one  species  is  converted 
into  another  can  never  be  observed;  the  species  is  a  self-contained  entity, 
and  yet  the  conversion  of  species  must  have  taken  place  in  the  course  of 
the  ages.  Kolliker's  previously  mentioned  theory  of  sudden  changes  of  species 
seemed  to  him  to  offer  the  possibility  of  adjusting  this  inconsistency,  nor, 
indeed,  had  Darwin  himself  denied  the  existence  of  sudden  "single  varia- 
tions." It  was  only  a  question  of  obtaining  actual  proof  of  the  existence 
of  such  changes.  Eventually  de  Vries  believed  that  he  had  found  it  in  CEno- 
thera  lamarckiana  (evening  primrose),  a  plant  introduced  from  America,  which 
has  spread  over  various  European  countries.  This  plant  grew  in  masses  in 
a  meadow  in  the  neighbourhood  of  Amsterdam  and  exhibited,  besides  a 
number  of  typical  forms,  some  few  with  an  entirely  divergent  appearance. 
A  number  of  specimens  having  been  transferred  to  a  garden  and  there  al- 
low^ed  to  multiply  by  self-fertilization,  it  was  discovered  that  in  the  course 
of  a  few  years  there  developed  out  of  seed  of  the  old  species  not  only  forms 
similar  to  it,  but  also  isolated  specimens  With,  well-marked  new  species- 
characters,  which  were  retained  for  the  purpose  of  further  cultivation: 
among  them  a  dwarf  form,  a  markedly  latifoliate  form,  and  some  others. 
Here,  then,  we  get,  according  to  de  Vries,  a  species  that  suddenly  "ex- 
ploded," as  he  expresses  it,  and  gave  rise  to  a  number  of  new  species,  each 
with  definite  characteristic  features.  This  case  shows,  according  to  him,  how 
the  species  in  general  have  arisen;  the  species,  he  says,  are  no  arbitrary 
groups,  but  completely  independent  entities,  delimited  in  time  and  space, 
which  originate  through  old  species'  suddenly  disintegrating  into  a  number 
of  new  forms;  of  these  some  are  capable  of  life  and  survive  unchanged  until 
the  next  mutation,  while  others  cannot  sustain  the  struggle  for  existence 


588  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

and  succumb  to  natural  selection.  All  fresh  characters  have  thus  been  formed 
as  a  result  of  mutations;  between  the  mutations  a  species  survives  with  its 
characters  unchanged;  the  slight  variations  that  occur  daily  in  the  life  of 
the  species  have  no  effect  on  evolution,  because  they  are  not  hereditary,  and 
the  recombinations  of  characters  that  arise  through  the  crossing  of  different 
forms  have  no  new  significance.  "As  many  steps  as  an  organism  has  made 
from  the  beginning,  so  many  mutation  periods  must  have  occurred."  These 
mutation  periods,  de  Vries  believes,  must  have  arisen  at  a  far  more  rapid 
pace  during  previous  geological  periods  than  they  do  nowadays,  and  he  is 
thus  able  to  explain  on  the  basis  of  this  theory  the  origin  of  the  forms  of 
life  without  the  assumption  of  those  infinite  spaces  in  time  that  the  old 
Darwinism  required  at  its  disposal. 

When  it  first  appeared,  de  Vries's  theory  naturally  met  with  violent 
opposition  on  the  part  of  loyal  Darwinists.  It  was  certainly  admitted  that 
in  all  essentials  he  really  accepted  the  point  of  view  of  the  old  Darwinism, 
in  that  he  maintained  the  theory  of  natural  selection  as  the  principle  govern- 
ing life,  but  the  fact  that  he  denied  the  heredity  of  the  slight  variations 
and  their  importance  for  selection  and  maintained  the  immutability  of  species 
in  the  normal  existence  between  mutations  was  far  too  much  at  variance 
with  old  traditional  ideas  to  be  acceptable.  Every  possible  effort  was  made 
to  get  away  from  the  facts  that  he  had  adduced  and  the  conclusions  that 
he  drew  therefrom.  As  a  matter  of  fact,  these  certainly  have  been  open  to 
objection.  His  cultural  experiments  with  CEnothera  have  failed  to  withstand 
the  criticism  of  later  years.  Johannsen  has  objected  that  the  material  with 
which  the  experiment  was  carried  out  was  casually  selected  and  was  not 
kept  as  pure  as  it  should  have  been,  and  finally  a  Swedish  naturalist,  Heri- 
BERT-NiLssoN,  Carried  out  the  entire  experiment  over  again  and  came  to  the 
conclusion  that  the  new  generations  of  Oenothera  lamarckiana  only  show  fresh 
combinations  of  characters  that  already  existed  in  the  main  species.  De  Vries, 
who  was  one  of  those  who  rediscovered  Mendel's  law  of  cleavage,  has,  in 
fact,  denied  the  validity  of  that  law  as  regards  mutations,  such  as  those  of 
CEnothera,  but  this  has  been  found  to  be  a  mistake.  Consequently  his  theory 
of  the  formation  of  new  species  of  that  plant  collapsed.  His  service  to  sci- 
ence, on  the  other  hand,  lies  in  the  fact  that  he  revealed  the  phenomenon 
of  mutation,  for  that  this  phenomenon  exists  has  since  been  proved  over 
and  over  again.  Moreover,  on  the  basis  of  his  "pangen"  theory  he  insisted 
upon  the  necessity  of  analysing  with  regard  to  their  elementary  units  the 
hereditary  qualities  that  characterize  the  species.  "It  is  not  a  question,"  he 
says,  "of  the  origin  of  species,  but  of  the  development  of  the  species-char- 
acters." Through  these  assertions  he  became  a  pioneer  of  modern  heredity- 
research.  "His  mutation  theory,"  Johannsen  declares,  "has  represented  the 
principal  milestone  in  the  transition  from  the  old  ideas  to  the  modern 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  589 

conception  of   heredity  and  will   always,  therefore,   retain   its   historical 
significance." 

WiLHELM  LuDviG  JoHANNSEN  was  bom  in  1857  at  Copenhagen,  studied 
there  and  in  Germany,  and  eventually  became  a  professor,  first  at  the  In- 
stitute of  Agriculture  and  afterwards  at  the  University  in  his  native  country. 
Being  a  pupil  of  PfefFer,  he  first  of  all  went  in  for  experiments  in  plant  physi- 
ology, making  a  number  of  interesting  observations  in  this  sphere  in  connex- 
ion with  the  effect  of  ether  on  the  metabolism  and  growth  of  plants.  Soon, 
however,  he  devoted  himself  exclusively  to  experimental  heredity-research 
and  has  gradually  become  one  of  the  leading  authorities  in  that  field.  Origi- 
nally a  supporter  of  Galton's  statistical  method,  he  quickly  realized  its 
deficiencies:  that  by  working  with  mixed  m.aterial  it  reached  conclusions 
utterly  at  variance  with  the  true  facts.  Starting  from  de  Vries's  insistence 
upon  the  necessity  of  investigating  the  units  of  hereditary  characters,  he 
began  to  follow  with  minute  care  the  phenomena  of  heredity  in  generations 
of  plants.  He  purchased  a  quantity  of  beans,  weighed  them,  and  then  culti- 
vated the  seeds  of  every  bean  separately;  he  thereupon  found  that  within 
a  succession  of  individuals  thus  produced  —  a  "pure  line,"  as  he  called  it  — 
there  exists  a  certain  type  of  hereditary  units,  which  remains  unchanged 
throughout;  if  the  plants  are  starved,  both  they  and  their  seeds  become  small; 
if  they  are  manured,  they  grow  strong,  but  this  has  no  effect  upon  the  heredi- 
tary character;  whether  one  sows  small  or  large  seeds  of  the  same  pure  line, 
one  obtains  under  the  same  external  conditions  the  same  plant-type.  There 
is  thus  within  one  and  the  same  pure  line  a  certain  hereditary  type  —  a 
"genotype,"  as  it  is  called  —  that  is  unalterably  the  same,  whether  or  not 
the  vital  conditions  alter  the  external  form  of  the  actual  individual  —  that 
is,  the  phenomenon-type,  or  "phenotype,"  as  Johannsen  called  it.  Those 
characters  which  form  the  genotype  are  thus  the  only  ones  that  are  really 
hereditary,  whereas  the  phenomenon-type  produced  by  environment  has 
nothing  to  do  with  heredity;  stunted  growth  in  generations  of  plants  grow- 
ing on  poor  soil  is  an  external  character,  a  "false  heredity."  There  is  there- 
fore no  possibility  of  acquired  characters'  being  inherited,  nor  is  there  within 
the  pure  lines  any  chance  of  variation  of  the  kind  assumed  by  Darwinism. 
Those  characters  that  go  to  make  up  the  hereditary  disposition  Johannsen 
terms  hereditary  factors,  hereditary  units,  or  genetic  elements;  in  a  pure 
line,  then,  the  genetic  elements  are  the  same:  its  individuals  are  homozygotes 
("zygote"  denotes  the  fusion-product  of  the  male  and  female  sexual  cells), 
while  the  offspring  in  life-forms  that  multiply  by  the  pairing  of  different 
individuals  is  a  heterozygote,  as  it  represents  a  fusion  of  the  parents'  vari- 
ous inheritable  factors.  A  heterozygous  individual  therefore  always  has  a 
hybrid  nature,  and  special  methods  are  necessary  for  the  elucidation  of  its 
qualities.  But  at  this  point  we  come  to  the  subject  of  hybrid  research,  which 
possesses  a  history  of  its  own. 


59°  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

JoHANN  Mendel  was  born  in  i8iz  of  peasant  parents  at  Heinzendorf, 
a  German  colony  in  the  midst  of  the  Slav  population  of  Austrian  Silesia. 
Having  shown  remarkable  intelligence  at  an  early  age,  he  was  sent  to  a 
grammar-school,  and,  probably  with  a  view  to  obtaining  better  opportun- 
ities for  devoting  himself  to  study,  he  entered  an  Augustine  monastery  at 
Briinn  in  the  district  of  Moravia.  As  a  monk  he  adopted,  after  the  Catholic 
custom,  a  new  Christian  name,  Gregor,  by  which  he  became  known  to 
posterity.  He  was  sent  at  the  expense  of  the  monastery  to  Vienna,  where 
he  studied  for  three  years,  devoting  himself  especially  to  mathematics  and 
natural  science;  upon  returning  home  he  became  a  schoolmaster  and  in  his 
leisure  hours  cultivated  plants  in  the  cloister  garden  for  scientific  purposes. 
He  published  the  account  of  his  results  in  the  little-known  "treatises"  that 
were  brought  out  by  the  natural-science  society  at  Briinn.  In  1868  he  was 
appointed  head  of  the  monastery,  or  prelate,  as  it  was  called.  This  appoint- 
ment, however,  actually  proved  his  undoing.  Four  years  later  the  then  liberal 
parliament  in  Austria  sought  to  reduce  the  country's  financial  distress  by, 
inter  alia,  taxing  the  monasteries.  The  monks,  like  all  the  reactionary  parties 
in  general  in  the  country,  considered  that  the  tax  menaced  the  monasteries' 
ancient  privileges  and  set  themselves  up  in  opposition  to  it.  Eventually, 
however,  the  measure  was  carried  through  in  several  instances,  but  the  one 
who  refused  to  give  in  was  Mendel;  for  twelve  years  he  held  out,  defying 
penalties  and  warrants  of  distraint,  but  finally  he  broke  down  completely 
under  the  struggle,  contracting  a  sickness  that  resulted  in  his  death  in  1884. 
Thus  fell  one  of  the  pioneers  of  modern  biology  as  a  champion  of  Catholic 
clericalism  —  in  its  way  an  irony  of  fate. 

Alendel's  experiments  with  peas 
Mendel's  fame,  which  was  late  in  coming,  rests  simply  and  solely  upon 
two  short  essays  in  the  above-mentioned  journal.  They  are,  however,  the 
fruit  of  many  years'  work  and  testify  to  a  keen  observation  of  nature  and 
a  thorough  grounding  in  mathematical  thought,  which  do  not  often  go 
together;  Darwin,  for  instance,  had  a  genius  for  observation,  but  the  sum- 
mary accounts  of  his  observations  are  vague  and  obscure;  Gal  ton  was  a 
mathematician,  but  he  worked  mostly  upon  material  obtained  second-hand 
as  the  result  of  inquiry,  so  that  it  was  not  truly  accurate.  Mendel  applied 
himself  to  the  study  of  the  phenomena  of  heredity  in  garden  plants;  he  se- 
lected, to  start  with,  certain  easily  observable  characters  —  the  colour  of 
the  flowers,  the  shape  of  the  seeds,  the  structure  of  the  position  of  the  blooms 
—  and  he  studied  their  modifications  in  different  generations.  He  crossed  peas 
with  white  and  red  flowers;  the  hybrids  then  proved  to  be  red  throughout; 
when,  again,  these  hybrids  were  allowed  to  fertilize  themselves,  the  succeed- 
ing generations  turned  out  to  be  coloured  in  a  peculiar  way:  for  every  three 
red  individuals  there  was  one  white.  These  white,  if  self-fertilized,  invariably 
produced  white  offspring,  one-third  of  the  red  remained  similarly  con- 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  591 

stant,  while  the  remaining  red  flowers  repeated  the  above-mentioned  colour 
ratio. 

Dominant  and  recessive  characters 
The  explanation  that  Mendel  gave  of  this  strange  phenomenon  was  as  in- 
genious as  the  observation  itself;  the  fact  that  the  flowers  of  the  first  hybrid 
generation  are  red  and  acquire  no  intermediate  colour  between  red  and  white 
he  accounts  for  by  the  red  colour's  being  dominant  over  the  white,  which 
latter  character  he  calls  recessive.  In  the  succeeding  generation  both  domi- 
nant and  recessive  characters  again  appear;  transitional  characters  cannot  be 
observed.  From  this  he  concluded  that  in  the  sexual  cells,  or  gametes,  there 
exists  no  fusion  of  characters;  in  the  hybrid  red-white  exist  potentialities 
for  red  and  white  side  by  side  in  the  male  and  the  female  cells;  when  these 
are  united,  the  fusion  must  thus  take  place  in  accordance  with  one  out  of 
four  possibilities:  red-red,  red-white,  white-red,  white-white.  This  explains 
the  proportion  between  the  offspring's  qualities;  the  two  single-coloured 
combinations  no  longer  vary,  but  remain  constant,  while  those  with  the 
double  characters  are  capable  of  repeating  the  same  four  possibilities  so  long 
as  they  exist.  The  same  system  of  law-bound  heredity  was  shown  by  all 
the  characters  that  Mendel  investigated  in  various  plant  species.  He  after- 
wards took  up  experiments  with  the  crossing  of  bees,  which,  as  is  well 
known,  produce  many  different  racial  types,  but,  disappointed  over  the  lack 
of  encouragement  that  he  received  as  a  result  of  his  investigations  into  plants, 
he  did  not  publish  the  results  of  this  subsequent  research-work,  and  they 
have  now  been  lost  to  us.  During  his  own  lifetime  Mendel's  achievements 
attracted  no  attention  whatever;  Nageli,  as  we  have  seen,  found  them  ir- 
reconcilable with  his  own  theories,  and  the  other  botanists  displayed  utter 
indifference.  It  was  not  until  the  turn  of  the  century  that  Mendel's  remark- 
able results  were  rediscovered  in  connexion  with  the  hybrid  research-work 
that  was  then  being  carried  out.  Three  observers  —  de  Vries,  Correns,  and 
TscHERMAK  —  simultaneously  pointed  out  the  agreement  between  Mendel's 
observations  and  their  own  results.  Thenceforward  Mendel's  name  has  been 
one  of  the  best-known  in  biology;  even  among  the  general  public  his  fame 
has  in  more  recent  times  competed  with  that  of  Darwin  himself.  Much  sur- 
prise has  been  expressed  over  the  fact  that  Mendel's  brilliant  observations 
did  not  attract  greater  attention,  and  the  blame  has  been  laid  upon  the  un- 
known journal  in  which  they  were  published.  One  might  with  greater  justi- 
fication ask  oneself  whether  any  of  the  more  important  publications  of  the 
time  would  have  undertaken  to  print  results  of  research  so  utterly  at  vari- 
ance with  the  prevailing  conception  of  biology.  We  have  only  to  remember 
that  Mendel  denies  variability  in  those  characters  that  he  observed,  whereas 
all  the  biologists  were  just  at  the  time  seeking  after  variations  as  material  in 


5  92.  THEHISTORYOFBIOLOGY 

proof  of  natural  selection;  and  then  come  these  assertions  as  to  absolutely  con- 
stant or  constantly  divisible  characters  from  the  pen  of  a  monk  in  a  monastery! 
It  would  certainly  have  been  a  miracle  if  they  had  found  support  from  the 
generation  that  had  been  brought  up  on  Haeckel's  Natural  History  of  Creation. 

Universality  of  the  Mendelian  laws 
Nevertheless,  the  Mendelian  principle  of  cleavage  now  forms  the  basis  of 
all  hybrid  research.  All  characters  that  it  has  been  possible  to  observe  in 
living  beings  have  the  quality  of  "mendelizing";  de  Vries's  statement  that 
mutations  cannot  be  subject  to  this  law  has  proved  to  be  incorrect,  and  the 
exceptions  that  have  since  been  observed  have  actually  been  explained  in 
accordance  with  the  same  principle.  Mendelian  research  has  been  carried  on 
to  an  ever-increasing  extent  year  by  year,  both  by  theoretical  observers  and 
by  practical  breeders.  And  Mendelism  has  stood  the  test  in  regard  to  the 
improvement  of  seeds  and  domestic  animals  no  less  than  in  the  theoretical 
field;  it  is  only  by  its  aid  that  the  practical  improvement  of  breeds  has  been 
successfully  based  on  exact  principles  instead  of  on  mere  chance.  In  Scandi- 
navia Mendelism  has  won  many  adherents;  Johannsen  has  contributed 
greatly  to  its  advancement,  and  in  Sweden  H.  Nilsson-Ehle  especially  has 
applied  it  to  practical  purposes  with  universally  acknowledged  success;  his 
work  for  the  improvement  of  seed  cultures,  carried  on  at  Svallov,  has  been 
done  in  accordance  with  its  principles  and  has  received  widespread  recogni- 
tion. And  both  in  Europe  and  America  there  are  a  great  many  Mendelian 
students  —  to  name  only  a  few,  W.  Bateson  and  R.  C.  Punnett,  in  England, 
Erwin  Baur  and  Carl  Correns,  in  Germany,  the  previously  mentioned 
A.  Lang  in  Switzerland,  L.  Cuenot  in  France,  T.  H.  Morgan  in  America. 
As  a  result  of  the  investigations  of  these  and  many  others  more  and  more 
light  has  been  throwm  upon  the  whole  complex  and  manifold  profusion  of 
varied  hereditary  factors  and  their  mutual  relation.  In  this  field,  indeed, 
there  must  be  a  vast  amount  of  research  material;  it  only  remains  to  select 
certain  characters  of  importance  in  one  respect  or  another  and  follow  them 
up.  This  has  in  fact  been  done,  and  numerous  Mendelian  students  have  taken 
up  various  subjects  for  research  at  which  they  have  worked  with  an  ever- 
increasing  tendency  to  specialize.  Of  these  subjects  we  shall  examine  one 
somewhat  closely  —  namely,  that  which  has  been  made  possible  through 
the  application  of  the  methods  of  modern  cell-research  to  the  problem  of 
heredity. 

The  Nlorgan  school 
The  home  of  this  cytological  heredity-research  has  mainly  been  America. 
The  experimental  biologist  Edmund  Beecher  Wilson  (born  in  1856,  pro- 
fessor at  Columbia  University),  to  whom  we  have  previously  referred,  had 
already  made  valuable  studies  of  the  influence  of  the  reproductive  chromosomes 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  593 

Upon  heredity,  but  it  was  really  a  scientist  who  had  been  trained  in  the 
same  school  —  namely,  the  above-mentioned  Thomas  Hunt  Morgan 
(born  1866,  likewise  a  professor  at  Columbia  University)  —  who  discovered 
both  the  aim  of  this  research  work  and  the  means  for  carrying  it  out,  thereby 
providing  the  study  of  heredity  with  a  wealth  of  material  by  way  of  detailed 
discoveries  of  far-reaching  theoretical  application,  such  as  had  never  been 
found  elsewhere.  His  subject  for  investigation  has  been  a  small  parasite 
fruit-fly,  Drosoplnla  melanogaster,  of  which  it  has  been  said  that  it  has  appar- 
ently been  created  by  God  solely  as  an  object  of  heredity  research.  It  repro- 
duces itself  with  incredible  rapidity  and  profusion  —  in  heat  an  individual 
requires  only  twelve  days  to  develop  from  the  egg  to  sexual  maturity  —  it 
is  extraordinarily  hardy  and  can  stand  every  possible  kind  of  experimental 
treatment;  its  cells  contain  only  four  pairs  of  chromosomes,  all  of  a  differ- 
ent size  and  easily  recognizable;  and,  finally,  it  has  given  rise  under  labora- 
tory conditions  to  a  profusion  of  mutations,  the  factors  of  which  have  been 
found  to  be  constant  and  well  adapted  to  Mendelian  investigations.  Morgan 
and  his  numerous  pupils  have  examined  millions  of  these  creatures,  in  the 
course  of  which  he  has  built  up  a  methodology  of  his  own  and  a  terminology, 
which,  owing  to  its  refined  subtlety,  is  extremely  difficult  for  anyone  but  a 
specialist  to  comprehend.  Among  the  results  of  this  research  work  we  note, 
first  of  all,  a  number  of  fresh  principles,  as  hard  and  fast  as  Mendel's  origi- 
nal ones.  As  had  already  been  assumed,  the  hereditary  factors  are  localized 
in  the  chromosomes,  and  it  has  been  discovered  that  the  factors  in  the  same 
chromosome  are  not  free,  but  invariably  follow  one  another  upon  cleavage-, 
they  are  "linked,"  as  it  is  called.  Thus,  all  the  factors  in  this  animal  are 
grouped  into  four  linkage-systems,  one  for  each  pair  of  chromosomes.  Fur- 
ther, after  a  series  of  ingenious  experiments  it  has  been  possible  largely  to 
determine  the  position  of  the  factors  in  each  chromosome,  and,  finally,  in 
certain  cases  to  establish  the  absence  of  parts  of  chromosomes  or  entire 
chromosomes  as  being  the  cause  of  various  external  modifications  — ■  that 
is,  a  set-back  for  the  theory  of  the  absolute  constancy  of  the  chromosomes 
in  the  same  species.  Besides  this,  it  has  to  a  large  extent  been  made  possible 
to  ascertain  the  part  played  by  the  previously  mentioned  sex-chromosome 
in  the  determination  of  sex  and  in  heredity  —  a  problem  which,  as  a  matter 
of  fact,  observers  not  belonging  to  Morgan's  school  have  also  studied.  In 
this  province  likely  explanations  have  been  found  for  a  number  of  hitherto 
incomprehensible  phenomena  of  heredity;  among  those  that  are  generally 
known  may  be  mentioned  the  inheritability  of  certain  diseases,  such  as  hae- 
mophilia and  colour-blindness  in  man,  and,  further,  a  number  of  cases  of 
heredity  in  the  sphere  of  mental  diseases.  And,  finally,  mention  should  be 
made  of  the  valuable  studies  in  regard  to  the  relation  of  the  chromosomes  in 
species  hybrids;  in  this  sphere  may  be  mentioned,  of  Scandinavian  students. 


5  94  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

H.  O.  G.  Rosenberg,  of  Stockholm,  who  has  investigated  the  hybrids 
of  Drosera,  H.  Federley,  of  Helsingfors,  who  established  the  fact  that  in 
the  butterfly  hybrid  the  number  of  chromosomes  is  equal  to  the  total  of  the 
father's  and  mother's  combined,  and  O.  L.  Mohr,  of  Oslo,  who  has  carried 
out  independent  investigations  on  the  reproductive  chromosomes  and  has 
besides  done  valuable  work  in  subjects  dealt  with  by  the  Morgan  school. 

Heredity  has  been  the  most  popular  field  of  research  of  the  age;  it  has 
succeeded  Darwinism  in  the  way  it  has  taken  hold  of  the  public  mind  and 
has  nowadays  to  serve  as  an  explanation  for  anything  that  presents  any  diffi- 
culty in  the  various  spheres  of  life.  Just  as  formerly  it  was  natural  selection, 
so  now  it  is  the  mixing  of  breeds  that  has  to  bear  the  blame  for  every  kind 
of  circumstance  and  disparity  even  in  human  community  life,  in  which  po- 
litical and  social  prejudices  take  good  care  that  problems  are  at  least  not 
treated  impartially  in  the  scientific  sense.  As  a  result  of  exact  heredity- 
research  the  theory  of  evolution  has  itself  been  directed  along  other  lines; 
phylogenetical  speculations  have  for  the  most  part  been  abandoned  —  at 
least  for  the  time  being.  Natural  selection  is  certainly  retained  in  principle 
by  some  students  of  heredity  —  by  Baur,  for  instance  —  but  it  is  really  of 
no  practical  importance;  the  phenomenon  cannot  be  observed  and  it  is  there- 
fore not  possible  to  fit  it  into  a  subject  of  research  that  is  based  on  exact 
observations.  And  while  the  old  Darwinism  operated  with  outward  resem- 
blance as  a  positive  proof  of  common  origin,  heredity  research  has  established 
the  fact  that  resemblance  and  affinity  are  not  analogous  terms,  thus  under- 
mining the  very  foundations  of  phylogeny.  Generally  speaking,  heredity  re- 
search goes  to  work  in  a  more  limited  sphere;  for  the  very  reason  that  it 
has  become  an  exact  science  it  has  not  been  able  to  follow  the  old  Darwinism 
in  its  speculative  ranging,  but  whatever  may  have  been  lost  in  the  way  of 
the  general  conception  of  life  has  undoubtedly  been  won  in  the  way  of  con- 
centration on  facts  and  reliable  results. 

There  are  still  one  or  two  other  subjects  for  experimental  research  which 
must  be  briefly  dealt  with  in  this  chapter,  and  we  shall  now  pass  on  to 
these. 


3.   Biochemistry 

Application  of  modern  chemistry  to  biology 
The  science  of  chemistry  as  applied  to  biology  has  always  afforded  it  valu- 
able assistance  in  the  search  for  an  explanation  of  vital  phenomena.  In  mod- 
ern times,  as  is  well  known,  chemistry  has  made  splendid  progress,  and  every 
new  step  has  at  once  had  its  influence  on  our  knowledge  of  living  organisms. 
At  the  present  day  biochemistry  is  a  line  of  research  that,  in  point  of  the 


THOMAS     HENRY     HUXLEY 

From  a  portrait  by  the  Hon.  John  Collier,  reproduced  in  Some  Aposfhs  of 
Physiology  by  William  Stirling,  Waterlow  and  Sons,  Limited,  London 


OSCAR     HERTWIG 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  595 

value  of  its  results,  competes  well  with  experimental  morphology  and  hered- 
ity research.  Unfortunately,  these  results  are  far  less  accessible  for  the  pur- 
poses of  popular  presentation  than  any  other  of  the  advanced  spheres  of 
biology;  in  fact,  biochemistry  requires  a  very  special  technical  training  for 
both  its  students  and  its  critics.  Nevertheless,  space  may  be  found  here  for 
a  few  brief  indications  as  to  the  most  important  progress  that  has  been  made 
in  its  various  special  provinces  in  order  to  complete  the  picture  of  the  gen- 
eral progress  made  by  experimental  biology  in  modern  times. 

That  branch  of  chemical  research  which  has  had  the  greatest  success 
in  our  own  day  and  has  excited  the  keenest  interest  is  undoubtedly  physical 
chemistry;  each  stage  of  its  progress  has  at  once  been  applicable  to  the  liv- 
ing substance.  Biology  has  actually  led  the  way  in  certain  physico-chemical 
discoveries,  as  in  the  question  of  osmotic  pressure,  in  which  the  results  of 
Pfeffer's  and  de  Vries's  research-work  formed  the  foundations  on  which 
scientists  have  subsequently  built  further.  On  the  other  hand,  the  modern 
theory  of  solutions,  as  created,  among  others,  by  van  t'Hoff,  Arrhenius, 
and  Nernst,  has  contributed  towards  explaining  a  great  many  biological 
phenomena;  as  an  instance  may  be  mentioned  the  above-described  partheno- 
genetical  phenomena  in  eggs  that  have  been  subjected  to  hypertonic  saline 
solutions;  further  may  be  quoted  the  part  played  by  hydrogen  ions  in  the 
metabolism  of  the  fluids  of  the  body:  they  play  a  decisive  part  especially  in 
producing  respiratory  irritation,  while  other  ion-combinations  have  been 
found  to  be  necessary  for  growth  in  individuals  and  organs. 

Colloid  chemistry 
Of  special  significance  for  forming  a  conception  of  the  nature  of  protoplasm 
has  been  modern  colloid  chemistry;  it  has  founded  a  province  of  its  own, 
with  its  own  methods,  which  have  made  it  possible  to  study  far  more  closely 
than  before  the  most  minute  structural  details  in  the  category  of  elements 
in  which  living  substance  is  included.  Thanks  to  these  accurate  observations 
and  experiments,  the  granular  and  vacuolized  structure  of  plasm  has  been 
given  a  far  more  natural  explanation  than  that  once  given  by  Biitschli  in 
his  froth  theory.  It  has  in  many  instances  been  possible  to  compare  the  mu- 
tual interpenetration  of  the  various  structures  even  with  physico-chemical 
metabolistic  phenomena  occurring  in  inanimate  colloid  substance,  while, 
on  the  other  hand,  the  old  dispute  as  to  the  solid  or  fluid  nature  of  plasm 
has  lost  all  point;  the  intrinsic  character  of  and  changes  in  the  colloids  are 
investigated  on  entirely  different  principles  and  have  given  rise  to  problems 
utterly  different  from  this  old  question  of  the  state  of  aggregation.  Instead, 
extensive  investigations  have  been  made  into  the  question  of  the  penetra- 
bility of  cells  and  tissues  by  solutions  of  various  kinds;  in  this  sphere 
especially  Charles  Ernest  Overton  (born  in  England  in  1865,  and  after 
studying  in  Germany  appointed  professor  in  Sweden)  propounded  a  theory, 


5  96  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

which  has  been  both  contradicted  and  supported  by  others,  that  the  cellular 
membranes  consist  of  a  peculiar  category  of  elements  called  lipoi-ds^  elements 
dissolved  in  these  permeate  the  cell-v/alls,  and  vice  versa. 

Ferment  chefnistry 
With  colloid  chemistry  the  modern  chemistry  of  ferments  is  closely  allied. 
In  regard  to  ferments  it  has  been  known  for  a  hundred  years  that  through 
their  presence  in  extremely  small  quantities  they  are  capable  of  causing  vari- 
ous chemical  changes  in  large  masses  of  the  substances  on  which  they  are 
acting.  In  modern  times  this  influence  they  exert  has  been  compared  with 
the  catalytic  effect  of  certain  inorganic  substances  (first  pointed  out  by  Ber- 
zelius),  as,  for  instance,  the  part  played  by  acid  in  the  production  of  ether 
out  of  alcohol.  Of  fundamental  importance  is  the  discovery  that  not  only 
are  phenomena  of  disintegration  induced  by  ferments,  but  also  synthetic 
processes,  as,  for  example,  the  production  of  starch  in  the  leaves  of  plants 
through  the  chlorophyll  granules  under  the  influence  of  sunlight.  The  fer- 
ment syntheses  of  fats,  albuminous  substances,  and  other  products  of  vege- 
table and  animal  life,  which  have  been  the  objects  of  special  study,  are  in 
themselves  of  immense  interest,  but  they  cannot  be  discussed  in  detail  here; 
nor  can  we  describe  the  extremely  subtle  investigations  that  have  been  carried 
out  in  connexion  with  the  co-operation  of  various  ferments  within  the  same 
vital  unit. 

In  connexion  with  fermentation  research  mention  should  be  made  of 
the  process  of  internal  secretion,  our  knowledge  of  which  has  increased  more 
and  more  in  recent  times.  Bernard,  whom  we  mentioned  earlier,  may  claim 
to  have  been  its  discoverer.  As  we  have  seen,  it  was  he  who  established  the 
fact  that  the  liver  produces  substances  which  are  directly  carried  away  by 
the  blood.  Charles  Edouard  Brown-Sequard  (1817-94)  succeeded  to  Ber- 
nard's professorship  after  the  latter's  death.  The  son  of  an  American  father 
and  a  French  mother,  Brown-Sequard  studied  at  Paris  and  afterwards  worked 
in  England  and  America,  but  later  on  returned  to  France.  He  became  fa- 
mous for  his  valuable  investigations  in  the  sphere  of  neuro-physiology,  but 
more  especially  for  his  experiments,  which  he  published  in  his  old  age,  with 
the  injection  of  extract  of  genital  glands,  whereby  he  demonstrated  that 
these  glands  contain  a  special  secretion  inducing  sexual  desire.  The  experi- 
ments in  themselves  were  somewhat  clumsy  and  were  published  with  a  good 
deal  of  advertisement,  especially  as  regards  the  power  of  rejuvenating  the 
individual,  which  was  promised  as  a  result  of  them;  all  the  same,  it  cannot 
be  denied  that  through  them  attention  was  drawn  to  a  fact  that  has  since 
been  investigated  by  others  with  greater  thoroughness  than  before.  The  in- 
terstitial gland  of  the  genital  organs  has  been  anatomically  investigated  by 
the  two  collaborators  Ancel  and  Bouin,  of  Nancy;  its  physiological  func- 
tion and,  in  general,  the  influence  of  the  genital  organs  upon  the  vital 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  597 

manifestations  of  the  body  have  been  studied,  inter  alia,  by  J.  Meisenheimer, 
ofLeipzig,whoexperimentedonthelarvie  of  butterflies,  and  by  Eugen  Stein- 
ACH,  of  Vienna,  who  studied  vertebrates  from  the  same  point  of  view.  Stein- 
ach  has  succeeded  by  means  of  operations  in  influencing  the  sexual  character; 
the  genital  glands  of  male  and  female  animals  have  been  interchanged,  with 
the  result  that  both  the  outward  appearance  and  the  sexual  behaviour  of  the 
animals  have  been  correspondingly  altered.  Otherwise,  Steinach  is  best  known 
for  his  having  resumed  rejuvenation  experiments  similar  to  those  of  Brown- 
Sequard,  but  more  carefully  carried  out  both  in  theory  and  in  their  details. 
These  experiments  have  won  him  a  fame  that,  owing  to  the  nature  of  the 
problem,  has  become  associated  with  much  of  the  glamour  that  surrounded 
his  predecessor;  moreover,  they  appear  already  to  have  exhibited  defects  that 
have  rendered  them  impossible  of  realization  in  practice. 

Internal  secretion  and  rejuvenation  experiments 
In  the  mean  time  our  knowledge  of  internal  secretion  in  other  spheres  has 
increased  with  great  rapidity.  So-called  endocrine  glands  have  been  discov- 
ered in  large  numbers;  among  them  may  be  mentioned  the  suprarenal  cap- 
sules, hypophysis,  the  thymus  and  the  thyroid  gland;  and  our  knowledge 
of  their  functions  has  at  the  same  time  been  extended.  But  other  organs  have 
also  become  known  as  producers  of  internal  secretions,  or  hormones,  as  they 
are  also  called;  the  small  intestine  produces  such  a  secretion,  which  is  termed 
"secretin"  and  which,  when  conveyed  through  the  blood  to  the  pancreas, 
induces  secretion  in  that  gland;  another  similar  substance  is  produced  in  con- 
nexion with  the  pregnancy  of  female  animals  and  causes  the  segregation  of 
milk,  and  a  third  is  the  product  of  a  special  cell-category  in  the  pancreas 
and  has  a  definite  influence  upon  the  metabolism  of  the  body,  in  that  its 
absence  induces  diabetes.  On  the  whole,  many  of  these  internal  secretions 
have  become  known  only  by  indirect  means,  through  the  diseases  that  arise 
if  the  organs  which  produce  them  are  injured  or  removed. 

Serology 
In  modern  times  serology  forms  a  separate  field  of  research,  embracing  one 
of  the  most  important  chapters  in  practical  medicine.  Pasteur  should  be 
named  as  its  founder,  while  later  Behring,  Ehrlich,  and  their  pupils  have 
particularly  distinguished  themselves  in  that  subject.  It  has  been  established 
that  the  danger  of  the  disease-producing  bacteria  lies  in  the  fact  that  in  the 
course  of  their  multiplication  in  the  body  they  produce  special  isolatable 
chemical  compounds  having  a  specific  poisonous  effect,  which  have  been 
given  the  name  of  toxins;  the  body  reacts  against  these  by  forming  similarly 
specific  elements,  antitoxins,  which  counteract  them.  To  isolate  these  latter 
and  to  use  them  as  a  counter-poison  has  in  many  cases  proved  the  only  w'ay 
for  medical  science  to  cure  infectious  diseases.  By  injecting  the  bacterial  poi- 
son into  experimental  animals,  these  latter  have  been  allowed  to  produce 


598  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

the  antitoxin,  their  blood-serum  afterwards  being  used  as  a  counter-poison 
against  the  disease.  The  actual  elements  —  both  toxins  and  antitoxins  — 
that  operate  in  this  process  always  exist  in  very  small  quantities,  and  for 
that  reason  and  owing  to  their  complicated  composition  it  has  not  been 
possible  to  analyse  them;  their  quantitative  effect  upon  one  another  has 
nevertheless  been  investigated  by  Svante  Arrhenius  and  others. 

In  connexion  with  this  research  work  the  nature  of  the  blood  in  gen- 
eral has  been  the  object  of  very  detailed  investigations,  often  with  quite 
remarkable  success.  Among  the  best-known  of  these  is  the  precipitin  re- 
action, which  was  discovered  by  Paul  Uhlenhuth  (born  1870,  Behring's 
successor  at  Marburg).  If  we  take  serum  from  an  animal  —  for  instance,  a 
dog  —  and  inject  it  into  a  rabbit,  we  obtain  from  the  rabbit's  blood  within 
some  days  a  serum  that  produces  precipitation  in  the  serum  of  the  dog's 
blood.  This  reaction  is  specific  and  can  therefore  be  utilized  in  medico-legal 
investigations  in  order  to  distinguish,  for  instance,  human  blood  from  ani- 
mal blood.  In  this,  however,  similar  forms  act  in  an  identical  way;  for  ex- 
ample, human  blood  and  the  blood  of  anthropoid  apes  produce  the  same 
reaction.  When  this  chemical  resemblance  between  allied  organisms  was  dis- 
covered, it  excited  great  enthusiasm  as  a  phylogenetical  argument;  closer 
consideration,  however,  at  once  makes  it  clear  that  this  agreement  of  chemi- 
cal composition  demonstrates  just  as  much  or  just  as  little  as  the  morphologi- 
cal resemblance  that  can  be  demonstrated  by  the  old  comparative  method; 
the  fact  that  resemblance  in  bodily  structure,  food,  and  habit  is  accompanied 
by  corresponding  chemical  agreement  is  essentially  so  obvious  that  the  con- 
trary would  be  more  surprising. 

We  may  here  cite  one  more  example  of  discoveries  in  this  sphere.  We 
have  previously  mentioned  how  the  Russian  naturalist  Ilja  METscHNiKorF 
(1845-1916),  who  after  studying  at  German  universities  was  a  professor  at 
the  Pasteur  Institute  in  Paris,  produced  the  so-called  phagocyte  theory;  he 
found,  as  indeed  Haeckel  had  already  observed,  that  the  white  blood-cor- 
puscles absorb  foreign  substances  into  the  body;  in  particular,  he  discovered 
that  the  leucocytes  in  this  way  free  the  body  from  bacteria  that  enter  it,  pro- 
vided the  latter  are  not  too  strong  and  do  not  get  the  upper  hand.  In  more 
recent  times  it  has  been  found  that  special  substances  are  produced,  which 
have  been  called  "opsonins,"  which  possess  the  ability  to  increase  the 
leucocytes'  power  of  killing  the  bacteria.  These  substances,  however,  are 
at  present  little  known,  but  they  are,  of  course,  of  the  very  greatest  interest. 
They  have  been  mentioned  here  as  examples  of  the  wide  possibilities  with 
which  modern  biochemistry  has  to  reckon.  The  immense  practical  benefits 
that  this  research  work  has  brought  humanity  can  only  be  hinted  at  here; 
some  of  the  theoretical  speculations  to  which  it  has  given  rise  will  be  dealt 
with  in  the  following. 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  599 

V. 

4.   Animal  Psychology 

Animal  psychology  would  rightly  have  been  made  part  of  experimental 
biology  if  it  had  consistently  remained  on  the  basis  of  empirical  research. 
This,  however,  has  been  far  from  being  the  case;  on  the  contrary,  ideas 
about  the  psychic  life  of  the  animals  have  varied  infinitely  up  to  the  pres- 
ent day,  from  the  standpoint  of  primitive  man,  who  ascribes  to  the  animals 
an  intelligence  of  the  same  kind  as  his  own,  to  Descartes's  conception  of 
animals  as  completely  automatically  operating  mechanisms.  The  reason  for 
this  confusion  is,  of  course,  to  be  sought  in  the  vague  ideas  of  human  psy- 
chology, which  have  varied  according  to  the  general  point  of  view  taken 
by  the  different  schools  of  philosophy.  It  was  not  until  the  middle  of  last 
century  that  an  exact  psychological  research  began  to  appear,  thanks  to 
precursors  like  Theodor  Fechner,  Wilhelm  Wundt,  and  their  pupils.  This 
empirical  psychology  treats  of  psychical  phenomena  just  like  any  other  ma- 
terial for  observation;  it  is,  as  Hoffding  says,  "no  more  bound  to  begin  with 
an  explanation  of  what  the  soul  is  than  physics  is  bound  to  begin  with  an 
explanation  of  what  matter  is."  Unfortunately,  those  biologists  who  have 
dealt  with  the  phenomena  of  animal  psychology  have  by  no  means  always 
taken  this  warning  to  heart;  not  infrequently  they  have  followed  Haeckel's 
bad  habit  of  involving  themselves  in  speculations  upon  the  soul  as  such 
without  having  the  qualifications  to  give  critical  treatment  to  this  com- 
plicated problem. 

Self-observation  the  joiindation  of  psychology 
The  foundation  of  all  empirical  psychology  is  self-observation;  on  this  point 
an  animal  psychologist  of  the  old  school,  such  as  Romanes,  is  in  agreement 
with  a  modern  experimental  psychologist  of  the  type  of  Alfred  Lehmann 
(1858-19x1),  a  pupil  of  Wundt,  professor  at  Copenhagen.  Lehmann  main- 
tains that  it  is  only  in  one's  own  consciousness  that  one  can  observe  psychical 
states  and  functional  manifestations;  the  assumption  of  psychical  phenomena 
in  other  creatures  depends  on  whether  these  latter  are  seen  to  act  in  given 
circumstances  as  man  would  do  in  the  same  circumstances.  As  regards  one's 
fellow  human  beings,  this  conclusion  can  be  confirmed  by  means  of  language, 
but  such  a  mode  of  control  is  wanting  in  animals;  as  far  as  the  vertebrate 
animals  are  concerned  a  good  deal  can  be  concluded  from  their  bodily  struc- 
ture where  it  agrees  with  that  of  man,  but  even  this  check  is  lacking  in  the 
invertebrates.  As  a  general  principle  of  animal  psychology  there  remains, 
then,  according  to  Lehmann,  the  principle  of  ascertaining  by  experiment 
whether  the  animal  can  adapt  itself  to  new  and  unexpected  situations; 
whether  it  can  by  learning  from  experience  modify  its  actions  to  suit  the 
conditions.  If  this  is  done,  then  we  have  the  right  to  assume  the  existence 
of  an  individual  psychic  life  in  the  animal  —  to  assume  life-phenomena  of 


6oO  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

a  different  kind  from  the  instinctive  adaptation  to  normal  conditions  of  life 
which  characterizes  all  animal  life  and  which  is  based  upon  nervous  reflexes 
or  simply  upon  tropisms  induced  by  chemical  and  physical  reactions,  such 
as  are  observed  even  in  the  most  primitive  of  organisms.  Such  experiments 
with  individual  experiences  as  their  object  are  extremely  difficult  to  carry 
out,  however,  and  still  more  difficult  to  interpret  aright.  On  the  one  hand, 
animals  should  be  brought  into  situations  which  prove  that  they  can  learn 
something  new,  but,  on  the  other  hand,  they  should  not  be  faced  with  situa- 
tions which  involve  violence  to  their  true  nature.  The  road  to  a  true  insight 
into  the  subject  is  thus  both  long  and  difficult,  and  this  explains  to  some 
extent  why  so  many  contradictory  statements  and  theories  have  arisen  in 
this  sphere,  even  among  observers  who  have  been  comparatively  successful 
in  freeing  themselves  from  preconceived  opinions.  The  confusion  has,  of 
course,  been  increased  by  so  many  students  and  dilettanti,  for  "  Darwinistic  " 
purposes,  ivanting  necessarily  to  find  in  the  animals  as  great  and  as  human- 
like an  intelligence  as  possible.  On  the  other  hand,  there  have  not  been 
wanting  in  modern  times  zoologists  who  have  seen  in  animals  nothing  but 
reflex  mechanisms,  and  that,  too,  not  merely  as  a  result  of  their  holding  a 
conservative  view  of  life,  but  quite  as  often  owing  to  ultra-radical  views  — 
through  endeavouring  to  restrict  as  far  as  possible  the  part  played  by  the 
psychic  life  in  nature.  We  shall  here  cite  in  brief  a  few  examples  of  different 
views  on  these  problems. 

Insect  psychology 
One  subject  that  has  specially  interested  animal-psychologists  from  ancient 
times  has  been  the  psychology  of  the  insects,  particularly  of  the  community- 
forming  Hymenoptera.  Here  in  earlier  times  the  imagination  and  credulity 
have  combined  to  celebrate  veritable  orgies  of  the  fancy;  one  reads  with  un- 
feigned amazement  of  all  that  people  even  in  the  latter  half  of  last  century' 
imagined  they  could  observe  in  the  ant-communities.  A  much  more  sober 
atmosphere  has  latterly  prevailed,  and  it  has  now  begun  to  be  realized  that 
most  of  the  actions  of  the  ants  must  after  all  be  due  to  inherited  instinct. 
A  very  prominent  observer  in  this  sphere  is  the  Jesuit  father  Erich  Wasmann 
(born  1859),  who  has  especially  elucidated  a  number  of  facts  in  regard  to 
the  ants'  relations  to  many  different  kinds  of  parasites,  which  swarm  in 
the  ant-heaps  and  which  are  often  carefully  looked  after.  Wasmann  has 
otherwise  appeared  as  a  keen  opponent  of  Haeckelian  monism  and  has  elab- 
orated in  opposition  to  it  a  history  of  creation  approved  by  Roman  Catholic 
authorities,  in  which  Darwinism  in  most  of  its  aspects  has  been  ingeniously 

2  As  an  instance  may  be  cited  a  story  related  by  many  authors  —  Romanes,  for  example 
—  of  an  American  species  of  ant,  according  to  which  those  ants  whose  duty  it  is  to  guard  the 
communities  do  so  formed  up  in  a  regular  square;  within  the  square  the  workers  carry  out  a 
great  manv  equally  intelligent  and  well-ordered  movements. 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  6oi 

introduced,  though  at  the  same  time  the  old  doctrine  of  creation  has  been 
retained.  In  regard  to  the  psychic  life  of  the  animals,  its  intrinsic  resemblance 
to  human  life  is,  of  course,  denied,  and  accordingly  the  reflexive  and  in- 
stinctive functions  are  sharply  emphasized  and  the  idea  of  individual  con- 
sciousness rejected.  Nevertheless,  even  the  insects  are  allowed  a  certain  power 
of  methodical  action.  Albrecht  Bethe  comes  to  a  far  more  radical  conclu- 
sion, based  on  entirely  opposite  grounds;  by  means  of  extensive  and  in  part 
highly  ingenious  experiments  he  endeavours  to  prove,  and  in  many  cases 
actually  succeeds  in  doing  so,  that  the  actions  of  the  ants  are  pure  reflex- 
actions.  On  the  other  hand,  the  famous  student  of  psychiatry  and  psychology 
AuGusTE  FoREL,  of  Geneva,  holds  another  view;  after  a  series  of  careful  ex- 
periments he  believes  that  he  has  been  able  to  prove  that  insects  can  actually 
learn  by  experience  and  thus  possess  intelligence.  Another  distinguished  ob- 
server of  insect  life  who  arrived  at  partially  similar  results  was  the  well- 
known  English  naturalist,  banker,  and  philanthropist  John  Lubbock, 
Lord  Avebury  (1834-1913).  A  very  important  animal  psychologist  was 
George  John  Romanes  (1848-94},  professor  at  Oxford,  an  enthusiastic  sup- 
porter of  Darwin,  whose  theory  he  defended  in  a  number  of  writings,  in 
which  he  especially  attacked  Weismann  for  his  denial  of  the  heredity  of 
acquired  characters.  In  particular,  he  carried  out  experimental  investigations 
into  the  psychic  life  of  the  higher  animals,  which  he  believed  to  be  —  in 
kind,  if  not  also  in  degree  —  similar  to  that  of  human  beings.  Like  Darwin, 
however,  he  has  accepted  without  criticism  stories  and  anecdotes  derived 
from  foreign  sources,  but  his  own  observations  are  very  keen.  Animal  psy- 
chology has  been  dealt  with  experimentally  with  special  keenness  in  Amer- 
ica; among  its  pioneers  in  that  country  may  be  mentioned  R.  M.  Yerks, 
who  has  carried  out  a  long  series  of  experiments  in  order  to  try  to  discover 
the  power  of  animals  to  learn  by  experience;  he  is  especially  well  known  for 
his  "labyrinth,"  in  which  he  placed  animals,  who  then  had  to  find  their 
way  out  as  best  they  could. 

As  a  general  result  of  the  work  of  these  investigators  it  may  be  men- 
tioned that  the  vertebrate  animals,  at  least  the  higher,  can  certainly  acquire 
knowledge  from  experience;  whether  the  higher  invertebrates  can  also  do 
so  would  seem  to  be  more  doubtful.  But  even  experience  can  be  exhibited 
in  different  ways;  either  the  animal  finds  its  way  in  every  fresh  case  to  a  new 
experience,  independent  of  what  it  has  gone  through  before,  or  else  it  really 
possesses  the  power  to  retain  its  experiences  in  the  memory  and  to  profit 
by  them  in  new  situations.  The  former  power  is,  of  course,  the  more  primi- 
tive, as  it  is  also  the  more  usual  in  the  animal  kingdom;  the  latter,  the  ra- 
tional power  of  adaptation,  has  certainly  been  observed  to  exist  only  in  a 
few  of  the  very  highly  developed  animals.  Still  more  debatable  are  the  cases 
in  which  the  power  of  grasping  relations  of  number  and  other  abstract  ideas 


6oi  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

has  come  into  question.  Isolated  cases  have  been  known  of  old  of  alleged 
purely  human  intelligence  in  domestic  animals.  Shakspere  in  one  of  his  com- 
edies alludes  to  a  horse,  on  show  at  the  time,  that  was  able  to  count;  in 
our  own  day  one  or  two  similar  cases  have  certainly  given  rise  to  much  dis- 
cussion. Even  professional  biologists  have  believed,  after  investigation,  in 
the  famous  horses  of  Elberfeld,  which  performed  operations  of  counting  in 
higher  mathematics  and  other  equally  remarkable  feats.  On  the  other  hand, 
the  authenticity  of  these  cases  has  been  very  keenly  disputed  —  Alfred  Leh- 
mann  describes  them  unreservedly  as  self-deception  on  the  part  of  the  spec- 
tators or  conscious  duplicity  on  the  part  of  the  exhibitor.  At  best,  however, 
it  could  only  be  a  matter  of  abnormal  receptivity  to  training,  which  cannot 
be  considered  in  any  respect  to  characterize  normal  intelligence  in  the  ani- 
mals and  thus  cannot  offer  any  guidance  for  judging  the  development  of 
the  intelligence  in  the  animal  kingdom,  which,  however,  has  been  very 
generally  asserted  by  those  who  have  felt  convinced  of  the  reality  of  the 
feats  exhibited.  In  cases  like  these  keen  criticism  is  more  than  ever  essential; 
unfortunately  many  even  distinguished  biologists  have  shown  themselves, 
owing  to  their  preconceived  ideas,  far  stronger  in  their  beliefs  than  clear 
in  their  judgments,  and  this  has  been  not  least  apparent  in  that  much  dis- 
puted chapter,  the  psychic  life  of  the  animals. 


CHAPTER    XVIII 


MODERN     THEORETICAL     SPECULATIONS 


I.    Mechanism  and  Vitalism 

IT  WILL  HAVE  BEEN  SEEN  from  the  previous  chapter  that  biology  in  our 
own  day  has  distinguished  itself  far  more  through  practical  detailed  re- 
search than  through  theoretical  speculations.  Actually  no  further  gen- 
erally accepted  theory  of  life  such  as  that  offered  by  Darwinism  has  been 
discovered;  instead,  there  has  prevailed,  a  restless  search  for  fresh  grounds 
on  which  a  theory  of  life  might  be  built  up.  Many  have  been  the  roads  along 
which  the  search  for  the  theoretical  solution  of  the  problem  of  life  has  been 
made  since  the  turn  of  the  century,  and  they  have  run  in  widely  differing 
directions.  On  the  one  hand,  we  find  repetitions  in  a  newer  form  of  the  old 
materialistic  and  mechanistic  theories  of  life  from  the  days  of  Vogt  and 
Haeckel;  on  the  other  hand,  vitalistic  ideas  that  have  looked  for  support 
in  Bichat,  in  Stahl,  in  Aristotle.  The  old  antagonism,  Christian  conservatism 
versus  Darwinistic  radicalism,  which  half  a  century  ago  resulted  in  the  for- 
mation of  parties,  has  now  been  essentially  adjusted,  though  in  no  wise 
everywhere  eradicated;  in  this  respect  it  must  be  acknowledged  that  the 
struggle  in  modern  times  is  more  definitely  a  matter  of  facts  than  it  was 
previously,  at  least  among  students,  but  the  differences  of  opinion  have  in 
many  quarters  certainly  been  sharp  enough.  It  is  possible  to  give  here  only 
a  few  examples  of  views  taken  from  the  rival  camps,  this  as  a  final  summary 
of  the  position  of  biology  as  it  stands  in  the  present  generation;  unfortunately 
it  is  more  difficult  than  ever  to  draw  conclusions  from  them  as  to  the  direc- 
tion likely  to  be  taken  by  evolution  in  the  future. 

Max  Verworn  (1861-19x1)  was  born  in  Berlin,  studied  there  and  at 
Jena,  and  eventually  became  professor  of  physiology  at  Gottingen.  He  was 
a  pupil  of  Haeckel  and  throughout  his  life  retained  both  his  admiration  for 
his  master  and  his  association  with  Haeckel's  fundamental  ideas.  To  him 
the  biogenetical  principle  as  well  as  the  theory  of  selection  always  was  a 
proved  fact;  of  the  more  recent  contributions  to  the  hypothesis  of  evolution 
he  embraced  de  Vries's  mutation  theory,  but  he  showed  no  interest  in  Men- 
delism.  On  these  foundations,  however,  he  built  up  a  life  theory  of  his  own 

603 


6o4  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

that  has  found  lively  support  in  many  quarters.  He  calls  it  "cellular  physi- 
ology" and  bases  it,  as  its  name  implies,  on  the  doctrine  of  the  cell  as  the 
unit  of  life,  which  he  maintains  repeatedly,  and  with  greater  emphasis  than 
anyone  else  has  done,  against  all  theories  of  smaller,  independent  entities, 
such  as  Altmann's  granula.  To  him  the  body  is  exclusively  a  cell-state;  the 
formation  and  co-operation  of  the  organs  have  little  interest  for  him  and  are 
dealt  with  only  in  passing;  Roux's  name  is  mentioned  as  little  as  Mendel's 
even  in  the  most  recent  edition  of  his  Allgememe  Physiologie.  He  chiefly  oc- 
cupies himself  with  the  living  substance  and  its  nature.  And  though  he  has 
removed  from  this  field  of  research  those  hypothetical  life-units  of  a  mechan- 
ical kind  that  played  such  a  large  part  in  the  theories  of  his  predecessors 
and  contemporaries,  he  has  nevertheless  reverted  to  the  same  unworkable 
imaginative  system  of  thought,  although  on  different  grounds;  that  is  to 
say,  he  has  imagined  a  chemical  unit  of  life  of  an  albuminoid  character, 
which  he  terms  "biogen,"  whose  chief  characteristic  apparently  consists 
in  an  extreme  chemical  lability:  a  constant  and  simultaneous  alternation  of 
disintegration  and  reconstruction.  In  this  chemical  change  consists,  accord- 
ing to  Verworn,  the  true  essence  of  life;  there  is  no  difference  between  ani- 
mate and  inanimate  except  that  which  is  brought  about  by  the  extraordinary 
metabolistic  possibilities  of  the  biogen  molecule.  Verworn,  it  is  true,  admits 
that  the  biogen  is  really  as  hypothetical  as  plastidules  or  micellx  ever  were, 
but  he  has  the  same  weakness  as  other  speculative  biologists  for  allowing 
hypothesis,  when  it  is  once  completed,  to  stand  for  fact.  It  is  a  more  serious 
matter,  however,  that  the  biogen  cannot  be  reconciled  with  modern  biochem- 
istry; the  latter' s  representatives  have  fairly  unanimously  condemned  the 
whole  hypothesis,  maintaining  that  there  exists  no  other  albumen  molecule 
than  that  which  is  already  known  to  general  chemistry.  "There  is  no  such 
thing  as  dead  and  living  albumen  any  more  than  there  is  dead  and  living 
sugar  or  fat,  and  the  reactional  powers  of  the  protoplasm  depend  upon  the 
co-operation  of  its  various  component  parts  in  definite  proportions"  (Hober). 
Verworn,  however,  paid  no  heed  to  these  objections,  especially  as  modern 
biochemistry  did  not  interest  him  in  the  least;  he  makes  no  mention  of  the 
progress  of  colloid  chemistry,  but  instead  discusses  the  old  problem  as  to 
whether  plasm  is  solid  or  fluid. 

Verworn  s  conditionism 
On  the  whole,  then,  Verworn  went  his  own  way,  heedless  of  the  progress 
of  contemporary  science;  he  had  made  it  a  principle,  one  of  his  biographers 
relates,  not  to  read  too  much,  but  to  think  for  himself.  He  was,  moreover, 
of  an  ardent  disposition;  ethical  and  social  questions  interested  him  keenly, 
and  every  new-year's  eve  he  ceremoniously  inaugurated  the  coming  year's 
work  by  sitting  down  at  his  writing-desk  at  the  stroke  of  twelve.  Having 
such  a  temperament  he  was  naturally  inclined  to  indulge  in  philosophical 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  605 

Speculations  upon  the  main  problems  of  life;  he  elaborated  a  theory  of  his 
own  that  he  called  "conditionism,"  which  was  to  replace  the  old  ideas  of 
cause  and  effect  by  a  conception  of  all  phenomena's  being  due  to  a  multi- 
plicity of  simultaneous  conditions;  what  he  was  trying  to  get  at  was,  of 
course,  the  old  contrast  of  things  and  phenomena  and  thereby  ultimately 
the  contrast  between  the  physical  and  the  psychical,  which  he  would  replace 
by  an  all-comprehensive  "psycho-monism."  But  Verworn  was  no  clear- 
sighted thinker;  conditionism  is  reminiscent  of  Mach's  phenomenalism, 
which,  however,  is  far  better  thought  out,  and  psycho-monism  merely  leads 
to  a  great  many  far-fetched  and  unnatural  attempts  to  get  away  from  the 
actually  existing  and  observed  difference  between  animate  and  inanimate,  in 
which  the  hypothetical  "living"  albumen  must  play  the  part  of  a  universal 
remedy  for  all  difficulties.  Through  his  enthusiasm,  his  brilliant  style,  and 
his  undeniably  valuable  contributions  to  the  problem  of  the  cell  as  a  physi- 
ological unit  of  life,  Verworn  has  at  any  rate  been  an  important  personality 
among  the  biologists  of  his  age. 

Loeh  on  the  movements  of  animals 
A  MECHANISTIC  explanation  of  nature  on  entirely  different  grounds  has  been 
produced  by  the  experimentalist  Loeb,  who  has  been  mentioned  in  the  pre- 
vious chapter.  He  was,  as  already  pointed  out,  a  pupil  of  Sachs,  whose 
studies  of  the  tropisms  of  plants  became  the  basis  of  his  entire  conception 
of  life.  In  his  earlier  years  he  himself  carried  out  a  number  of  valuable  in- 
vestigations on  the  subject  of  tropisms  in  the  lower  animals;  since  then  he 
has  made  the  above-described  experiments  on  parthenogenesis  in  eggs  caused 
by  chemical  reagents.  The  general  theory  of  life  that  he  set  up  is  actually 
based  on  these  two  classes  of  experiments.  He  regards,  as  far  as  is  possible, 
the  movements  of  animals  as  tropisms  caused  by  external  influence;  when  an 
animal  moves  towards  the  light,  there  actually  takes  place  through  the  effect 
of  the  light  an  oxidization  of  certain  elements  in  the  animal,  and  this  causes 
the  movement;  other  movements,  again,  are  induced  by  chemical  associa- 
tions that  arise  directly  in  the  innermost  being  of  the  animal,  as,  for  instance, 
in  the  mating-flight  of  insects.  On  these  facts  he  bases  a  "mechanistic  con- 
ception of  life,"  which,  however,  he  hardly  succeeds  in  formulating  in  a 
very  convincing  way.  Indeed,  he  has  no  idea  of  a  scientific  student's  duty 
of  first  thinking  out  his  theories;  when  his  theory  suits  one  case,  it  is  at 
once  made  to  hold  good  for  all  cases  without  further  investigation,  and  if 
it  does  not  do  so,  then  the  inexpedient  cases  are  simply  passed  over.  He  gives 
an  account,  for  instance,  of  the  phototropism  of  the  Aphida:,  on  which  he 
carried  out  most  ingenious  experiments,  and  he  traces  the  phenomenon  to 
the  said  oxidizing  process  —  the  fact  that  this  phenomenon  upon  repeti- 
tion proceeds  with  greater  rapidity  "may  be  brought  about  by"  the  lactic 
acid  produced  by  the  muscles  upon  movement.  Thus  the  phenomenon  in 


6o6  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

question  is  ascribed  to  a  cause  that  is  stated  to  possess  a  general  significance 
for  all  vital  phenomena,  but  when  shortly  afterwards  it  is  declared  that  the 
worker-ants  do  not  exhibit  any  such  tropism,  no  attempt  is  made  to  explain 
this  notable  exception.  And  the  same  lack  of  consecutive  thought  is  dis- 
played everywhere.  The  development  of  the  egg  is  explained  as  being  due 
to  oxidization;  that  this  development  can  be  caused  by  such  diverse  external 
influences  as,  on  the  one  hand,  a  solution  of  acid  and,  on  the  other,  the 
prick  of  a  needle  certainly  evokes  some  surprise,  but  no  more  than  that  the 
whole  phenomenon  is  after  all  accounted  for  as  being  a  physico-chemical 
process,  it  not  being  considered  at  all  necessary  to  discuss  the  most  remark- 
able feature  of  all  —  namely,  the  nature  of  the  egg  itself.  Indeed,  in  the 
opinion  of  Loeb,  there  exist  no  structural  conditions  whatever;  there  is 
hardly  any  question  of  the  organism's  possessing  a  chemical  composition 
of  its  own;  all  that  takes  place  in  the  organism  is  the  result  of  outside  im- 
pulses, the  result  being  that  no  discrimination  whatever  is  made  between 
one  life-phenomenon  and  another,  whether  it  is  a  question  of  sea-urchins, 
insects,  or  frogs.  The  goal  to  be  attained  is,  as  we  have  said,  a  mechanical 
explanation  of  life,  but  just  because  of  this  exclusive  interest  for  external 
influences  the  explanation  proves  to  be  essentially  negative  —  a  denial  of 
the  existence  of  any  operating  forces  other  than  the  said  external  influences. 
When  he  comes  to  discuss  more  complicated  problems,  Loeb  shows  the  most 
amazing  lack  of  criticism;  he  gives  an  account  of  Mendelism  and  declares 
that  the  riddle  of  heredity  is  thereby  solved,  but  a  little  further  on  he  as- 
serts the  exact  opposite,  that  any  ossean  can  be  crossed  with  any  other  os- 
ean;^  he  himself  has  kept  such  hybrids  alive  for  a  month.  The  explanation 
of  what  has  taken  place  is  manifestly  a  parthenogenetical  development  of 
the  eggs  through  the  "activating"  influence  of  foreign  sperm;  but  Loeb 
literally  declares  that  it  is  possible  to  obtain  a  hybrid  between  a  salmon  and 
a  flounder.  With  such  facility  in  drawing  conclusions  and  such  irresponsi- 
bility as  to  their  consequences  there  need  be  no  limit  to  one's  flights  of 
imagination,  and,  moreover,  one  is  free  in  the  long  run  to  dispense  with 
all  exchanges  of  views  with  scientists  possessing  a  normal  sense  of  respon- 
sibility. Loeb  is  without  doubt  a  brilliant  experimentalist,  and  as  such  he 
deserves  mention  among  the  pioneers,  though  among  biological  thinkers  he 
can  claim  no  place. 

Vitalistic  explanations  of  life 
On  the  whole,  the  mechanistic  speculations  in  the  sphere  of  modern  biology 
give  a  somewhat  monotonous  impression  and  it  is  therefore  hardly  worth 
while  making  the  acquaintance  of  any  more  representatives  of  this  line  of 
thought.  Those  who  are  constantly  making  the  assertion  that  there  is  no 

1  See  The  Mechanistic  Conception  of  Life,  p.  2.4:  "It  is  possible  to  cross  practically  any  marine 
teleost  with  any  other." 


MODERN      BIOLOGY  607 

essential  difference  between  animate  and  inanimate  very  quickly  lose  ail  ap- 
preciation of  what  is  truly  characteristic  in  living  matter  and  its  metabolistic 
phenomena,  which  must  otherwise  be  the  chief  interest  even  of  those  bi- 
ologists who  maintain  the  old  assertion,  already  proclaimed  by  Kant,  that 
only  material  phenomena  can  be  subjects  for  natural-scientific  treatment.  It 
is  not,  then,  the  idea  —  in  itself  justifiable  —  of  limiting  discussion  to  the 
chemical  and  physical  manifestations  of  the  phenomena  of  life  that  consti- 
tutes the  weakness  of  these  mechanistic  theories  of  life,  but  the  stubborn 
insistence  upon  the  rough  comparisons  between  phenomena  in  animate  and 
inanimate  nature  —  comparisons,  in  fact,  the  weakness  of  which  would  un- 
doubtedly be  realized  by  their  proponents  if  the  latter  were  not  really  trying 
all  the  time  to  lay  the  foundations  of  some  kind  of  general  philosophical 
theory  extending  far  beyond  the  bounds  of  natural  science.  When  Verworn 
discusses  and  denies  the  possibility  of  the  immortality  of  the  soul,  he  is 
arguing,  from  the  natural-scientific  point  of  view,  about  nothing  at  all,  for 
though,  as  we  have  seen,  biology  studies  psychical  phenomena,  it  does  not 
imply  that  it  has  anything  to  do  with  the  impossible  problem  of  what  the 
soul  is  or  is  not.  And  if  we  ask,  quite  apart  from  such  metaphysical  quibbles, 
whether  all  observable  material  processes  in  the  living  organism  or  its  parts 
can  be  directly  derived  from  known  material  processes  in  inanimate  nature, 
the  answer  even  today  must  still  be  in  the  negative;  those  who  have  at- 
tempted to  do  so  have  either  reverted  to  gross  schematism  or  else  drawn  a 
bill  on  the  possible  progress  of  tomorrow  —  an  unworthy  manner  of  wrig- 
gling out  of  the  fact  of  the  problem's  insolubility.  It  may  at  once  be  assumed 
that  the  future  will  bring  us  nearer  the  heart  of  the  problem;  whether  it 
will  ever  be  entirely  solved  we  know  no  more  than  the  truth,  laid  down  by 
Herbert  Spencer  and  many  others,  that  the  capacity  for  knowledge  is  limited 
and  the  most  general  laws  in  existence  must  therefore  remain  unexplained. 
Strictly  speaking,  the  same  causes  have  brought  about  the  popularity 
of  the  mechanistic  theories  of  life  as  those  that  at  one  time  produced  so 
many  editions  of  Haeckel's  Natural  History  oj Creation.  It  is  obvious,  however, 
that  a  reaction  against  this  conception  of  life  was  bound  to  set  in,  owing  to 
the  disappointment  felt  over  its  splendid  but  unfulfilled  promises.  And  so  we 
find,  even  before  the  turn  of  the  century,  vitalistic  theories  of  life  of  various 
kinds  being  produced,  supported  by  representatives  of  no  small  importance, 
as  regards  both  their  numbers  and  their  attainments.  And  during  the  pres- 
ent century  their  number  has  still  further  increased;  true,  they  can  nowhere 
be  said  to  have  dominated  the  situation,  but  the  part  they  have  played  has 
been  quite  an  important  one,  many  of  them  having  had  a  perceptible  in- 
fluence even  in  circles  in  which  vitalistic  or  spiritualistic  ideas  have  other- 
wise never  been  very  highly  appreciated.  They  have  for  the  most  part  come 
from  the  physiologists,  while  the  morphologists,  v/ith  far  fewer  exceptions. 


6o8  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

have  adhered  to  the  standpoint  that  they  had  maintained  since  the  appear- 
ance of  the  descent  theory.  The  views  of  some  of  the  vitalists  have  arisen 
in  connexion  with  certain  religious  or  social  principles,  as  in  the  case  of 
the  above-mentioned  Jesuit  priest  Wasmann,  who,  owing  to  his  ecclesias- 
tical point  of  view,  was  bound  to  feel  attracted  to  a  theory  of  life  that  offers 
the  possibility  of  a  spiritualistic  explanation  of  existence.  So,  too,  the  Luth- 
eran conservative  botanist  and  politician  J.  Reinke,  mentioned  in  the  pre- 
ceding chapter  as  an  opponent  of  Haeckel  and  known  for  his  violent  polemics 
against  materialism.  Greater  impartiality  has  been  shown  by  the  physiolo- 
gists GusTAv  BuNGE  and  R.  Neumeister,  both  of  whom  have  interested 
themselves  in  the  question  of  whether  the  phenomena  of  life  can  originate 
merely  in  physico-chemical  causes.  Bunge  sustains  his  arguments  especially 
upon  the  complicated  structure  and  vital  manifestations  of  the  cell,  which 
cannot  be  explained  on  a  physical  or  chemical  basis;  moreover,  he  takes  as 
his  premisses  that  life  as  a  whole  cannot  be  studied  except  through  self- 
observation  and  is  therefore  a  psychical  process.  Neumeister,  on  the  other 
hand,  maintains  against  Haeckel  and  his  supporters  that  the  origin  of  life 
is  a  transcendent  problem  and  that  the  psychical  phenomena  cannot  be  de- 
rived from  the  material.  This  criticism  of  contemporary  materialism  is  in 
itself  certainly  justified,  but  it  actually  implies  a  negative  attitude;  to  try 
to  substitute  for  it  an  imaginary  life-force  is  only  to  create  a  fresh  compli- 
cation of  the  problem;  it  militates  against  our  striving  after  simplicity,  as 
Henle  once  said.  The  most  pronounced  vitalists  of  our  own  day  have  been 
fully  conscious  of  the  fact,  but  they  have  deliberately  exceeded  the  bounds 
of  exact  research  and  gone  over  into  the  sphere  of  abstract  speculation. 

The  ' '  autonomy  of  life-phenomena 
The  most  interesting  of  these  modern  philosopher-scientists  is  undoubtedly 
the  previously  mentioned  experimental  biologist  Hans  Driesch,  inasmuch 
as  his  history  shows  the  natural  development  of  the  consistent  vitalist  from 
biologist  to  metaphysician.  Born  in  1867,  the  son  of  a  wealthy  merchant, 
he  was  allowed  full  liberty,  regardless  of  prevalent  trends  of  thought,  to 
devote  himself  to  science.  His  start  as  an  experimental  biologist  has  already 
been  described  above,  as  also  how  he  interpreted  his  experiments  in  a  mark- 
edly epigenetical  way,  thereby  finding  himself  opposed  to  Roux  and  his  pre- 
formation theory.  Markedly  antagonistic  was  also  his  attitude  towards 
Darwinism,  which  when  still  a  youth  he  declared  to  be  a  thing  of  the  past. 
Owing  to  these  two  facts  —  the  results  of  his  experiments,  and  his  anti- 
Darwinism  —  he  adopted  from  the  outset  an  aggressive  attitude  towards 
the  older  biological  school,  which  accounts  for  his  keen  insight  into  its 
weaknesses.  Moreover,  his  is  a  pronounced  speculative  nature,  with  wide 
philosophical  interests  and  corresponding  erudition,  and  he  has  been  very 
deeply  attracted  by  the  Aristotelean  abstract  construction  of  life-phenomena. 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  609 

On  these  grounds  he  has  produced  his  arguments  in  proof  of  "the  autonomy 
of  life-phenomena";  he  asserts  that  a  living  being  forms  a  "harmoniously 
equipotential  system,"  by  which  he  means  that  a  hydra  or  other  primitive 
organism  can  be  regenerated  out  of  severed  parts;  this  proves,  to  his  mind, 
that  the  animal  is  not  a  machine,  for  a  machine  cannot  be  evolved  out  of 
its  parts.  This  antithesis  —  machine  and  living  being  —  he  is  constantly 
bringing  forward  as  a  proof  of  the  impossibility  of  deriving  the  animate 
from  the  inanimate,  and  by  drawing  a  comparison  between  them  he  comes 
to  the  same  negative  result  as  the  vitalists  referred  to  above,  though  on 
markedly  abstract  and  schematic  grounds. 

The  ' '  entelechy 
He  is  not  content  with  this,  however,  but  seeks  to  discover  what  life  really 
is.  The  answer  is  summed  up  in  an  expression  borrowed  from  Aristotle:  "an 
entelechy."  By  this  word  Aristotle  meant  the  potentiality  which  is  inherent 
in  matter  and  which  achieves  reality  to  the  extent  of  matter's  development 
into  an  ever  higher  and  higher  form  (see  Part  I,  p.  36).  Driesch  has  likewise 
a  marked  interest  for  form  in  living  nature,  which,  he  considers,  lends  itself 
far  more  readily  to  "philosophical  analysis"  than  metabolism  does.  By  en- 
telechy,  however,  Driesch  means  something  far  more  involved :  it  is  supposed 
to  mean  "something  that  carries  its  purpose  within  itself."  It  is  thus  the 
functional  adaptation  of  living  beings  that  is  here  indicated,  but  in  entering 
into  a  profound  and  far-reaching  analysis  of  the  idea  Driesch  becomes  in- 
volved in  a  maze  of  abstract  speculations,  which  become  still  more  difficult 
to  understand  owing  to  the  extremely  complicated  terminology  he  employs; 
really  we  have  to  go  back  to  the  heyday  of  Hegelian  philosophy  to  find  the 
counterpart,  in  point  of  difficulty  of  comprehension,  of  Driesch's  definitions 
and  characterization  of  the  phenomena  of  life.  This  much,  however,  can  be 
gathered  from  them,  that  as  the  ultimate  proof  of  his  vitalism  he  cites  his 
own  personal  consciousness;  it  is  thus,  apparently,  that  we  are  to  interpret 
his  expression  "  phenomenological  idealism,"  which,  according  to  his  con- 
ception, leads  directly  to  vitalism,  at  any  rate  as  far  as  his  own  body  is 
concerned.  He  then  draws  the  same  conclusion  in  other  living  bodies.  But 
this  is  certainly,  if  anything,  pure  metaphysics;  it  has  nothing  to  do  with 
biology;  to  give  a  detailed  account  of  how  the  idea  of  the  relation  of  en- 
telechy to  matter  is  further  developed  would  in  such  circumstances  be  super- 
fluous, all  the  more  so  as  here  the  incomprehensibility  of  his  language  ex- 
ceeds all  bounds;  sentences  such  as  the  chapter  heading:  " Entelecbie  bex,ieht 
sich  auj  den  Kaum  und  gehort  daher  %}ir  Natur,  aber  Entelecbie  ist  nicht  im  Kaum," 
which  is  afterwards  explained  as  follows:  "  Sie  wirkt  nicbt  hn  Kaum,  sie  wirkt 
in  den  Kaum  hinein,''  do  not  make  the  reader  much  the  wiser.  The  same  is 
true  of  such  a  statement  as  that  "  Mater ie  ist  nicbt  einmal  in  irgend  einem 
Sinne  die  Grundlage  des  Lebens."  The  new  formula  that  Driesch  gives  in  this 


6lO  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

connexion  to  the  law  of  the  conservation  of  energy  is  a  matter  for  the  physi- 
cists to  consider.  Driesch  having  thus  already  at  an  early  stage  taken  up  a 
position  essentially  on  the  other  side  of  the  boundary  line  between  meta- 
physics and  empirical  research,  he  has  ultimately  adopted  this  step  formally 
as  well;  he  is  now  professor  of  philosophy  at  Leipzig  and  in  that  capacity 
has  been  engaged  in  speculations  of  the  most  abstract  kind. 

Another  vitalist  of  whom  a  good  deal  has  been  heard  is  Emanuel  Radl. 
He  was  born  in  Bohemia  in  1873,  studied  at  Prague,  and  has  been  a  lecturer 
in  physiology  there.  His  research  work  has  concentrated  partly  on  physio- 
logical subjects  —  he  has  dealt  with  the  tropisms  in  the  lower  animals  — 
and  partly  on  the  morphology  of  the  brain.  He  is  best  known,  however, 
for  his  Geschichte  der  biologischen  Theorien  der  Neu^eif,  a  much  read  and  widely 
quoted  work,  the  first  part  of  which  has  come  out  in  two  editions,  which 
are  essentially  different  from  each  other.  To  examine  this  work  properly, 
however,  we  must  have  some  knowledge  of  its  author's  biological  stand- 
point, which  is  clearly  apparent  in  his  most  important  monograph,  Neue 
Lehre  vom  xentraUn  Nervensysfem.  In  its  introduction  the  author  shows  that 
he  holds  particularly  broad  views,  and,  on  the  other  hand,  that  he  is  fully 
convinced  of  the  soundness  and  future  value  of  his  own  ideas.  The  Darwin- 
istic  morphology  is  rejected  as  a  soulless  description  and  specification  of  dif- 
ferent developmental  forms  one  after  another;  he  gives  slightly  more  credit 
to  experimental  evolutional  physiology  on  the  lines  of  Roux,  but  the  science 
that  in  Radl's  view  has  the  greatest  future  is  that  of  ideal  morphology,  of 
which  he  himself  is  an  exponent.  As  a  pioneer  of  this  science  he  mentions 
Geoffroy  Saint-Hilaire,  and  also,  though  in  a  less  degree,  Cuvier;  its  aim 
is  stated  to  be  to  discover  the  ideas  according  to  which  the  forms  of  living 
organisms  are  constructed.  "Many  ideas  compete  at  the  root  of  organic  life 
for  precedence,  and  an  ideal  structure  forms  the  basis  of  every  organism." 
This  must  be  sought  for  by  means  of  comparisons  throughout  the  animal 
kingdom,  for  only  thus  can  we  gain  any  knowledge  of  the  fundamental  ideas 
of  existence.  This  is,  of  course,  simply  the  idealistic  morphology  of  the  begin- 
ning of  the  nineteenth  century  over  again.  When  it  comes  to  working  out  his 
idea  in  detail,  however,  we  find  only  a  collection  of  disjointed  sentences  taken 
from  other  authors,  in  conjunction  with  his  own,  not  always  very  convincing, 
observations  concerning  the  object  of  his  investigation,  the  central  nervous 
system.  Apathy's  fibrilla  theory  is  thus  maintained  as  against  the  doctrine 
of  neurones;  Radl  himself  describes  in  word  and  illustration  one  category 
of  fibrillar,  existing,  according  to  him,  throughout  the  animal  kingdom, 
which  are  convoluted  in  a  special  way  at  the  entrance  to  every  ganglion 
and  which  he  terms  "cascade  fibrillar."  They  do  not,  however,  give  the 
impression  of  being  very  natural  and  would  appear  rather  to  have  arisen 
through  being  cut  obliquely  or  through  the  ordinary  nerve-fibres'  being 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  6ll 

wrongly  fixed.  The  formal  points  of  agreement  in  the  nervous  system,  upon 
which  ideal  morphology  is  based,  must,  on  the  whole,  seem  rather  unin- 
teresting to  a  morphologist  of  the  old  school,  for  they  prove  nothing  new; 
but  Radl  imagines  that  his  method  has  achieved  extraordinary  results.  The 
theory  of  organic  structure  is  to  prove  capable  of  building  up  a  magnificent 
philosophy  of  its  own,  "such  as  speaks  to  us  out  of  the  Pythagoreans'  theory 
of  harmony,  out  of  Plato's  doctrine  of  ideas,  and  out  of  the  romantic  rev- 
eries of  the  obscure  German  natural  philosophy."  Radl's  conception  of  the 
world  as  a  "  Schopjung  des  sie  betrachtenden  Geistes"  is  undeniably  reminiscent 
of  the  latter;  in  fact,  his  expressed  intention,  underlying  the  entire  work, 
is  to  excite  surprise,  "for  it  is  through  being  surprised  that  man  has  now  and 
always  begun  to  philosophize."  And  the  work  certainly  does  evoke  surprise, 
though  not  perhaps  of  the  kind  the  author  intended.  It  has  manifestly  not 
exercised  any  influence  whatever  upon  the  development  of  neurology,  and 
would  not  have  been  worth  while  referring  to  had  not  the  author's  above- 
mentioned  historical  work  acquired  such  widespread  fame. 

KddTs  history  of  biological  theories 
This  fame  is  based  partly  on  Radl's  undeniable  merits  as  a  historian:  a  wide 
knowledge  of  literature,  a  lively  style,  and  shrewd,  often  striking  discern- 
ment (his  account  of  the  development  of  Darwinism  in  Germany  in  Part  II 
is  particularly  animated  and  instructive);  partly  on  his  opposition  to  the 
original  Darwinism,  an  opposition  which  came  into  force  at  a  date  when 
the  old  doctrine  was  certainly  undermined,  but  nevertheless  still  officially 
accepted;  and  partly  again  on  the  numerous  philosophical  digressions,  some- 
times witty,  but  more  often  merely  odd,  which  are  found  scattered  through- 
out his  history  and  which  proved  attractive  to  a  generation  that  had  wearied 
of  the  old  phylogenetical  speculations  without  having  on  that  account  ac- 
quired any  other  speculative  foundation  on  which  to  build.  Of  the  various 
parts  of  the  book,  the  first  edition  of  Part  I  is  the  one  that  contains  most 
of  the  old  biological  ideas;  in  the  foreword  of  Part  II  the  author  regrets 
the  far  too  confident  belief  that  he  had  earlier  entertained  in  an  objective 
science;  and  in  the  second  edition  of  Part  II,  which  was  published  last,  Radl 
declares  that  he  intends  to  promulgate  a  "realistic  cosmic  view,  such  as 
finds  its  deepest  expression  in  Dostoievsky's  novels."  The  work  expresses 
throughout,  each  part  more  extravagantly  than  the  last,  a  purely  panegyri- 
cal enthusiasm  for  Aristotle,  who  is  declared  to  be  the  unattainable  ideal 
as  a  natural  philosopher,  but  at  the  same  time  a  warm  admiration  for  his 
opponent  and  very  antithesis,  Paracelsus;  and,  further,  the  book  extols 
Stahl's  vitalism  and  romantic  and  idealistic  speculation  in  general,  while  it 
disparages  exact  research,  particularly  cytology  (whose  methods  the  author 
nevertheless  himself  employed,  though  not  very  skilfully),  Darwinism,  and 
exact  heredity-research,   all  of  which    is    described    as   materialism.    The 


6li  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

author's  subjectivism  culminates  in  the  above-quoted  saying  that  there  is  no 
such  thing  as  objective  science;  all  interest  is  centred  upon  the  personalities 
figuring  in  the  history  of  science.  This  may  to  a  certain  extent  be  justified, 
when  it  is  a  question  of  giving  expression  to  the  purely  ideal  strivings  of 
humanity,  but  when  it  is  a  question  of  nature,  our  knowledge  rests  undeni- 
ably upon  certain  facts  that  reveal  themselves  equally  to  all.  He  who  refuses 
to  admit  this  had  best  turn  his  back  upon  exact  natural  science  for  ever. 
Radl  has  in  fact  done  so;  he  is  now  professor  of  natural  philosophy  at  Prague. 

Uexkull  on  the  life-process 
On  the  whole,  little  is  to  be  gained  from  the  biological  point  of  view  by 
becoming  too  deeply  engrossed  in  the  works  of  the  modern  vitalists.  Some 
of  them  have  gone  in  for  speculations  about  the  theory  of  knowledge,  as, 
for  instance,  Jacob  von  Uexkull,  who  holds  that  only  a  part  of  the  life- 
process  is  mechanically  comprehensible,  while  that  part  of  it  which  gives 
to  the  mechanical  phenomena  their  "  Zielsfrebigkeit"  is  super-mechanical  and 
must  be  referred  to  impulses  produced  by  an  organized  natural  force;  me- 
chanical biology  is  concerned  with  the  fitting-in  of  every  being  into  certain 
given  conditions,  which  give  to  the  organism  its  limitations;  in  the  world 
of  dew-worms  tjiere  exist  only  dew-worm  conditions,  while  man  can  ob- 
serve only  human  things.  To  analyse  the  different  conditions  of  life  and  to 
work  out  the  laws  governing  this  reciprocal  action  between  individual  and 
environment  is,  to  his  way  of  thinking,  the  aim  of  biology.  Other  vitalists 
have  reverted  to  downright  mysticism,  and,  finally,  the  neo-Lamarckian 
school  previously  referred  to,  which  is  represented  by  Pauly  and  his  pupils, 
has  tried  to  see  in  the  phenomena  of  life,  especially  in  evolution,  expressions 
for  consciously  operating  psychical  forces  in  the  living  substance.  What  is 
common  to  all  these  different  aims  is  the  attempt  to  discover  the  difference 
between  animate  and  inanimate  matter  and  what  it  is  that  produces  the  pe- 
culiar character  of  the  phenomena  of  life.  For  this  purpose  the  methods  of 
physics  and  chemistry  have  proved  ineffective,  with  the  result  that  other 
means  have  been  sought  to  attain  the  end  in  view.  We  have  already  seen 
that  these  means  have  proved  fruitless.  In  such  circumstances  obviously  the 
wisest  course  would  be:  neither  mechanism  nor  vitalism,  but  resignation  in 
face  of  the  inexplicable.  But  science  has  not  yet  struck  into  that  path,  nor 
is  it  likely  to  do  so  in  the  future.  And  fortunately  too,  we  may  well  say,  for 
had  not  humanity  possessed  a  belief  in  the  possibility  of  solving  the  insoluble 
riddles  of  life,  there  would  never  have  been  any  science  at  all.  Every  delusion 
that  has  involved  an  honest  striving  after  truth  has  at  any  rate  contributed 
something  to  human  knowledge,  even  if  it  is  only  negative,  and  the  specu- 
lations that  have  just  been  described  are  in  this  respect  by  no  means  valueless. 


w 

u 

w 

< 

W 
u 

M 

(A 

w 

H 

2 


s^ssBi«e;-^ 


2 

CO 

o 

1—5 
O 


Q 
D 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  613 

X.  The  Idea  of  Species  and  Some  Problems  in  Connexion  Therewith 

In  a  popular  account  of  the  results  of  heredity  research  published  some  years 
ago  occurs  the  sentence:  "For  the  very  reason  of  the  great  number  of  fresh 
facts  that  modern  heredity-research  has  brought  to  light,  chaos  prevails  at 
present  in  regard  to  the  views  on  the  formation  of  species."  These  words 
characterize  both  the  situation  as  regards  the  problem  of  species  at  the  pres- 
ent day  and  the  causes  that  have  brought  it  about.  Modern  heredity-research 
has  completely  dislocated  the  circles  drawn  by  the  old  morphological  classi- 
fication. Linn^eus's  idea  of  species,  it  will  be  remembered,  was  essentially 
genetical-  he  counted  as  many  species  as  had  been  created  in  the  begnining, 
or    in  later  years,  at  any  rate  some  species  created  in  the  dawn  of  time  in 
respect  of  each  genus,  out  of  which  the  other  species  have  since  been  evolved. 
This  idea  of  species  could  very  easily  be  reconciled  with  the  idealistic  idea 
of  species  which  has  existed  since  the  days  of  Greek  philosophy  and  which 
the  biology  of  the  romantic  period  preferred;  in  those  days  greater  attention 
was  paid  to  the  idea  expressed  in  the  species  form  than  to  the  question  of 
origin   Darwinism  brought  the  genetical  idea  of  species  once  more  into  re- 
pute To  discover  the  origin  of  the  different  forms  of  life  by  a  close  compari- 
son of  their  external  and  internal  structure  was,  according  to  Gegenbaur, 
Haeckel,  and  their  disciples,  the  end  of  biology-  thus,  a  natural  classification 
system  was  to  be  created  with  species  based  upon  true  relationship  —  species 
which    it  is  true,  must  be  assumed  to  vary  and  overlap,  but  which  in  their 
typical  forms  could  be  determined  and  characterized.  Nevertheless,  this  ge- 
netical idea  of  species  rested  upon  an  indispensable  proviso  —  namely,  that 
from  resemblance  one  could  positively  conclude  affinity:  the  greater  and  the 
more  universal  the  resemblance,  the  closer  the  affinity.  Every  species,  and 
even  every  variety,  had  a  common  origin,  as  proved  by  the  mutual  resem- 
blance between  its  individuals.  It  is  this  foundation  for  the  idea  of  species 
that  modern  heredity-research  has  undermined;  it  has  clearly  demonstrated 
that  very  close  morphological  resemblance  can  in  certain  cases  be  due  to 
entirely  different  causes.  It  is  not  outward  resemblance,  but  the  concurrence 
of  hereditary  factors  that  proves  true  affinity;  that  is  to  say,  it  is  not  phe- 
notypical,  but  genotypical  resemblance  that  determines  the  affinity.  But 
nowadays  in  all  systematical  works  the  species  are  described  entirely  ac- 
cording to  phenotypes;  genotypical  agreement  can  be  ascertained  only  by 
experimental  means.  And  in  practice,  of  course,  this  can  take  place  only  on 
a  small  scale;  the  plant-geographer  who  makes  records  of  localities  and  dis- 
tribution charts  at  home  or  abroad  would  be  stranded  if,  every  time  he  sees 
a  form    he  were  compelled  to  carry  out  hybridizing  experiments  with  it  in 
order  to  establish  its  identity,  and  this  applies  also  to  the  morphologist  and 
the  systematist.  In  these  circumstances  it  seems  to  be  absolutely  necessary 


6l4  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

to  decide  exactly  what  the  categories  of  the  system  are  intended  to  denote. 
Unfortunately  it  has  not  been  possible  to  obtain  unanimity  on  this  point; 
opinions  have  clashed  and  their  advocates  have  been  very  little  disposed 
to  modify  their  views.  We  shall  here  cite  one  or  two  examples  of  these 
divergences  of  opinion. 

Lotsj  and  the  species  question 
The  Dutch  student  of  the  heredity  problem  J.  P.  Lotsy  has  taken  up  an 
uncompromisingly  genetical  attitude  towards  the  idea  of  species.  "What  is 
a  species?"  he  asks  in  one  of  his  treatises.  The  answer  is:  A  species  in  the 
Linnasan  sense  is  no  species,  for  it  comprises  a  large  number  of  different  life- 
forms  whose  outward  appearance  bears  a  certain  resemblance,  but  as  to 
whose  origin  we  can  determine  nothing.  The  Linnxan  species  are  therefore 
nothing  but  products  of  the  imagination,  as  also  the  Linn^an  genera  and 
other  higher  classified  groups;  consequently  they  should  no  longer  be  called 
species  but  linn^onts.  Nor  are  the  minor  species  into  which  some  Linnxan 
species  can  be  divided  and  which  remain  constant,  true  species;  these  forms, 
which  were  specially  studied  by  the  French  botanist  Jordan  in  the  beginning 
of  the  nineteenth  century,  should  be  named  after  him  jordanonts,  but  they 
are  not  species,  for  their  internal  resemblance  cannot  be  ascertained.  On  the 
other  hand,  a  species  is  a  summary  of  all  the  homozygous  individuals  having 
the  same  hereditary  character.  "Consequently,  not  even  all  the  pure-lines  in 
the  Johanssenian  sense  are  true  species;  they  are  so  only  if  they  are  at  the 
same  time  homozygotes.  And  in  regard  to  organisms  with  sexless  repro- 
duction, V,  e  can  never  know  whether  they  are  species,  for  that  can  be  dis- 
covered only  through  the  analysis  of  hybridizing  experiments."  In  these 
circumstances  it  becomes  a  matter  for  doubt  whether  any  species  exist  at 
all  in  nature. 

This  conclusion  of  Lotsy's  clearly  proves  that  an  insistence  upon  the 
genetical  idea  of  species  can  only  lead  to  sheer  paradox;  he  admits  himself 
that  only  linn^eonts  and  jordanonts  can  possess  any  practical  systematical 
significance.  The  whole  of  his  reasoning  is  really  a  striking  proof  of  the 
power  of  language  over  thought;  he  wants  what  is  called  species  to  be  a 
genetical  entity,  and  so  he  comes  to  a  point  where  he  does  not  know  whether 
species  in  his  sense  of  the  word  exist  at  all  in  nature.  Other  students  of 
heredity  have  also  taken  warning  from  this  result:  thus,  Heribert-Nilsson 
declares  that  the  term  "species"  might  well  be  used  in  the  form  in  which 
Linnxus  employed  it;  thereby,  it  is  true,  the  idea  of  species  becomes  purely 
morphological — "The  species  of  classification  is  a  phylogenetical  con- 
glomerate," he  says  —  but  for  the  genetical  entities  we  have  of  course 
the  new  nomenclature  "genotype"  and  "pure-line."  The  necessity  of 
thus  dispensing  with  the  genetical  idea  of  species  has,  indeed,  been 
realized  by  many   others;   Ernst   Lehmann,   for  instance,  maintained  in 


MODERN     BIOLOGY  615 

his  controversy  with  Lotsy  that  the  species  are  abstract  and  arbitrary 
ideas  and  he  has  quoted  the  statements  of  other  observers  in  support  of 
this  view. 

Mutations  and  hereditary  factors 
That  the  systematic  species  in  the  old  sense  of  the  term,  comprising  indi- 
viduals having  a  certain  mutual  resemblance,  must  possess  immense,  even 
inevitable,  significance  from  a  purely  practical  point  of  view,  will  at  once 
be  realized;  moreover,  it  has  both  morphological  and  physiological  impor- 
tance, in  that  resemblance  of  various  kinds,  both  outward  and  inward,  char- 
acterize the  same  type  of  organism,  from  the  simplest  characters  referred  to 
in  the  text-books  to  the  precipitin  reaction.  But  the  species-characters  — 
mutual  resemblance  —  say,  as  is  established,  nothing  about  mutual  affinity, 
and  heredity  research  is  the  one  branch  of  biology  that  cannot  utilize  the 
idea  of  species,  except  under  experimental  control.  The  old  speculations  upon 
species-phylogenesis,  however,  have  not  been  given  up  by  the  representa- 
tives of  modern  heredity-research;  on  the  contrary,  there  is  current  among 
them  a  veritable  maze  of  ideas  on  the  problem  of  origin.  The  problem  has 
been  further  complicated  by  a  divergence  of  views  regarding  the  relation 
between  mutations  and  Mendelian  cleavage;  while  Heribert-Nilsson,  for  in- 
stance, has  found  that  mutations,  where  they  exist,  only  cause  loss  of  heredi- 
tary factors,  and  on  that  account  holds  that  the  process  of  evolution  can  be 
conceived  merely  as  a  series  of  reductions  in  the  original  material  of  genes, 
the  specialists  in  Drosophila  have  proved  that  there  have  existed  mutations 
which  have  given  rise  to  positively  new  rudiments.  The  conception  of  the 
development  of  life  on  the  earth  must  of  course  be  influenced  by  this  prob- 
lem. Heribert-Nilsson  has  resolutely  followed  up  the  consequences  of  his 
theory  that  only  detrimental  mutations  exist  and  has  declared  that  a  theory 
of  evolution  is  on  the  whole  unthinkable,  while  other  geneticists  have 
deemed  it  unnecessary  to  take  refuge  in  this  desperate  expedient.  Baur  in 
particular  has  endeavoured  to  create  a  theory  of  evolution  by  combining 
the  results  of  research  work  on  mutations  and  hybridization  with  Darwin's 
theory  of  selection;  a  similar  view  has  been  held  by  Morgan  and  his  school. 
Other  students  of  heredity,  again,  have  sought  to  establish  a  mutational 
Lamarckism  by  assuming  mutations  induced  by  the  influence  of  external 
conditions  upon  the  germinal  plasm.  Earlier  attempts  to  prove  the  possi- 
bility of  transmitting  to  the  offspring  characters  that  have  been  experimen- 
tally imparted  to  the  parents  either  have,  as  has  been  mentioned  before, 
proved  unsuccessful,  or  else  could  be  given  a  different  interpretation,  as,  for 
instance,  Kammerer's  and  Tower's  results  referred  to  above.  Recently,  how- 
ever, some  new  observations  of  this  kind  have  been  carried  out,  certain  ex- 
perimentally acquired  characters  in  animals  under  investigation  having  been 
transmitted  to  the  offspring  along  Mendelian  lines,  to  this  class  belong,  for 


6l6  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

example,  the  attempts  of  Little  and  Bagg"  by  passing  Rontgen  rays  through 
female  rats  to  induce  defects  in  the  eyes  and  other  parts  of  the  body  of  their 
offspring,  and  the  experiments  of  Harrison^  with  melanism  in  butterflies 
induced  by  the  introduction  of  metallic  salts  in  the  food.  However,  there 
are  no  doubt  obstinate  anti-Lamarckists  who  have  explained  or  will  eventu- 
ally explain  even  these  results  in  a  different  way.  In  this  connexion  may 
also  be  mentioned  the  recently  published  attempt  of  Professor  Muller,  of 
Austin,  Texas,  to  produce  mutations  in  Drosophila  by  means  of  extreme 
temperatures  and  Rontgen  rays. 

The  whole  of  this  problem  of  evolution  is  of  course  highly  involved 
and  its  discussion  must,  as  far  as  our  own  times  are  concerned,  terminate 
in  a  number  of  unanswered  questions.  First  of  all,  selection;  that  it  does 
not  operate  in  the  form  imagined  by  Darwin  must  certainly  be  taken  as 
proved,  but  does  it  exist  at  all?  It  is  obvious  that  by  the  influence  of  external 
conditions,  especially  such  as  interfere  with  sudden  violence,  a  thinning-out 
of  the  species  is  possible.  If,  for  instance,  a  quantity  of  seed  from  a  southern 
climate  is  sown  in  a  northern  country,  the  delicate  plants  will  die,  whereas 
the  hardy  ones  will  live,  but  this  selection  is  only  a  matter  of  relation  to 
cold  and  proves  nothing  as  to  the  quality  of  the  individuals  in  other  respects. 
But  the  competition  between  the  individuals,  in  which  Haeckel  thought  he 
saw  true  selection  —  does  it  exist  at  all,  or  is  it  only  imaginary,  as  O.  Hert- 
wig  affirmed?  And  outside  influence  —  has  it  no  effect  whatsoever  upon  the 
germinal  plasm  and  offspring  of  the  individuals,  or  is  there  really  any  such 
influence  in  the  form  of  some  kind  of  mutational  Lamarckism? 

These  and  many  other  questions  it  is  for  the  future  to  answer.  We  have 
now  followed  the  history  of  biology  up  to  our  own  times;  our  task  is 
fulfilled. 

"^  Little  and  Bagg,  Anat.  Record,  Vol.  XXIV,  1913. 

3  Proceedings  of  the  Royal  Society  of  London,  ser.  B,  Vol.  XCIX,  1516. 


SOURCES   AND   LITERATURE 


SOURCES 
PART  I 


Chapters  I-X 

^lianus,  Works,  translated  by  Jakobs.  Stuttgart,  1839. 

Aristotle,  Historia  animalium,  ed.  Aubert  et  Wimmer.  Leipzig,  1868. 

— ,  De  partibus  animalium,  ed.  Frantzius.  Leipzig,  1853. 

— ,  De  generatione  animalium,  ed.  Aubert  et  Wimmer.  Leipzig,  i860. 

— ,  Physica,  ed.  Prantl.  Leipzig,  1854. 

Diel,  Die  Fragmente  der  Vorsokratiker.  Berlin,  1903. 

Galeni  opera,  ed.  Kiihn.  Leipzig,  i8ii. 

— ,  CEuvres  choisis,  translated  by  Daremberg.  Paris,  1854. 

Lucretii  de  rerum  natura,  ed.  Munro.  Cambridge,  1893. 

Plato,  Timaus,  selected  dialogues,  translated  by  Dalsjo.  Stockholm,  1870. 

(Swedish) 
Plinii  naturalis  historia,  libri  VIII-XI,  ed.  Junius.  Leipzig,  1856. 

Chapters  XI-XIV 

Aldrovandi,  Ulysses,  Ortiithologia,  hoc  est  de  avibus  historia,  libri  XII.  Bologna, 
1599. 

Bacon,  Francis,  Works.  London,  1847. 

Belon,  Pierre,  La  Nature  et  diversite  des  Poissons.  Paris,  1555. 

— ,  VHistoire  des  oyseaux.  Paris,  1555. 

Bruno,  Giordano,  Von  der  Ursache,  dem  Prin^ip  und  dem  Einen,  translated  by 
Lasson.  Berlin,  1873. 

C^esalpini,  Andr^ee,  Quastionum  peripateticarum,  libri  V,  ed.  Vignon,  1588. 

Columbi,  Realdi,  De  re  anatomica,  libri  XV.  Venice,  1559. 

Fabricii  ab  Aquapendente,  Opera  omnia  anatomica  et  physiologica.  Leipzig,  1867. 

Falloppii,  Gabrielis,  Observationes  anatomica.  Cologne,  1561. 

Galilei,  Galileo,  Opere,  ed.  nazjonale.  Florence,  1890  ff. 

Gesner,  Conrad,  Historia  animalium.  Zurich,  1551  fF. 

Harvei,  Guilielmi,  Exercitatio  de  motu  cordis  et  sanguinis  in  animalibus .  Frank- 
furt, 15x8. 

— ,  Exercitationes  de  generatione  animalium.  London,  1551. 

617 


6l8  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

Rondeletii,  Guilielmi,  De  fiscibus  marinis,  libri  XC.  Lyons,  1554  fF, 
Servetus,  Michael,  Christianismi  restitutio.  1553  (ed.  1790). 
Severinus,  Marcus  Aurelius,  Zootomia  Democritea.  Nuremberg,  1645. 
Vesalii,  Andrea;,  De  humani  corporis  jabrica,  libri  VII.  Basel,  1543. 
— ,  Ibid.,  Epitome.  Basel,  1543. 

PART  II 

Chapters   I-III 

Descartes,  Rene,  CEuires  pbilosophiques,  ed.  Aime  Martin.  Paris,  i88i. 
Helmont,  J.  B.  van,  Ortus  medicina.  Amsterdam,  1648. 
Paracelsus,  Theophrastus,  Bucber  und  Schriften,  ed.  Huserus.  Basel,  1589  fF. 
Spinoza,  Baruch,  Sdmtliche  IVerke,  translated  by  Auerbach.  Stuttgart,  1841. 

Chapter  IV 

Aselli,  Gaspare,  De  lactibus  sive  lacteis  venis.  Basel,  i6i8. 

Bartholin,  Thomas,  De  lacteis  thoracicis.  Copenhagen,  1652.. 

— ,  Opuscula  nova  de  lacteis.  Copenhagen,  1670. 

Borelli,  Alfonso,  De  jnotu  animalimn,  ed.  2..  Leyden,  1685. 

Glisson,  Francis,  Anatomia  hepatis.  Amsterdam,  1659. 

Graaf,  Reinier  de.  Opera  omnia,  ed.  x.  Amsterdam,  1705. 

Grew,  Nehemiah,  The  Anatomy  oj  Vegetables.  London,  1672.. 

Leeuwenhoek,  Antony,  Opera  ofnnia.  Leyden,  17x1. 

Malpighi,  Marcello,  Opera  omnia.  Leyden,  1687. 

— ,  Opera  posthuma.  Amsterdam,  1698. 

Pecquet,  Jean,  Experimenta  nova  anatomica.  Amsterdam,  1661. 

Perrault,  Claude,  Essais  de  physique.  Paris,  1680. 

Rudbeck,  Olof,  De  circulatione  sanguinis.  Upsala,  1652.. 

— ,  Nova  exercitatio  anatotnica.  Upsala,  1653. 

Ruysch,  Frederik,  Opera  omnia.  Amsterdam,  1711. 

Steno,  Nicolaus,  De  musculis  et  glandulis.  Copenhagen,  1664. 

— ,  Elementorum  myologia  specimen.  Florence,  1667. 

— ,  De  solido  intra  solidum  naturaliter  contento  dissertationis  prodromus.  Florence, 

1669. 
Swammerdam,  Jan,  Bibel  der  Natur.  Leipzig,  1751. 
Vieussens,  Raymond,  Neurographia  universalis.  Lyons,  1685. 
Wharton,  Thomas,  Adenographia.  London,  1656. 
Willis,  Thomas,  Cerebri  anatome.  London,  1664. 
— ,  De  anima  brutorum.  London,  1671. 

Chapter  V 

Boerhaave,  Hermann,  Institutiones  medica,  ed.  3.  Leyden,  1710. 
Hoffman,  Friedrich,  Fundamenta  medicina.  Halle,  1703. 


SOURCES  619 

Hoffman,  Friedrich,  Medicina  rationalis.  Halle,  1739. 
Stahl,  G.  E.,  Theoria  medica  vera.  Halle,  1737. 
Swedenborg,  E.,  CEconomia  regni  animalis.  London,  1740. 
Sydenham,  Thomas,  Works,  ed.  Grcenhill.  London,  1849. 
— ,  Regnum  animale.  London,  1745. 

Chapters  VI,  VII 

Artedi,  Peter,  Icbthyologia.  Leyden,  1738. 

Bauhin,  Caspar,  Prodromus  theatri  botanici.  Frankfurt,  1610. 

— ,  V max  theatri  hot anici.  Frankfurt,  1613. 

Brunfels,  Otto,  Herbarum  viva  eicones.  Strassburg,  1530  ff. 

Camerarius,  R.J. ,  Das  Geschlecht  der  Pflanzen,  translated  by  Mobius.  Ostwald's 

Klassiker  der  exakten  Wissenschaften.  Leipzig,  1899. 
Cesalpino,  Andrea,  De  Flantis.  Rome,  1603. 
Fabricius,  J.  Ch.,  Species  insectorum.  Hamburg,  1781. 
Fuchs,  Leonhard,  Historia  stirpium.  Basel,  1542.. 
Jung,  Joach.,  Isagoge  phytoscopica.  Hamburg,  1678. 
Linnasus,  Carl  von,  Amcenitates  academica.  Vol.  I-X.  Leyden,  1749  ^- 
— ,  Classes  plantarum.  Leyden,  1738. 
— ,  Fauna  suecica,  ed.  2..  Stockholm,  1671. 
— ,  Fundament  a  botanica.  Leyden,  1736. 
— ,  Genera  plantarum,  ed.  i.  Leyden,  1742. 
— ,  Methodus  plantarum.  Leyden,  1737. 

— ,  Papers  published  by  the  Swedish  Academy  of  Science.  Upsala,  1907. 
— ,  Sy sterna  nature,  ed.  i,  2,  6,  10,  ii.  Leyden,  1735;  Stockholm,  1740,  1748, 

1758,  1766. 
— ,  Juvenile  Works,  published  by  Ahrling.  Stockholm,  1888. 
Ray,  John,  Methodus  plantarum,  ed.  i,  x.  London,  i68x,  1733. 
— ,  Historia  plantarum.  London,  1686  ff. 
— ,  Synopsis  animalium  quadrupedum.  London,  1693. 
Tournefort,  J.  P.  de,  Institutiones  rei  herbaria,  ed.  i.  Paris,  1700. 

Chapters  VIII-XI 

Albinus,  Icones  ossium  foetus  humani.  Leyden,  1737. 

— ,  Tabula  sceleti  et  musculorum  corporis  humani.  Leyden,  1747. 

Bonnet,  Charles,  Contemplation  de  la  nature.  Amsterdam,  1769. 

— ,  Insectologie,  ed.  x.  Amsterdam,  1780. 

— ,  La  Palingenesie  philosophique.  Lyons,  1770. 

Buffon,  G.  L.  L.  de,  Histoire  naturelle.  Paris,  1749  ^- 

— ,  CEuvres  completes.  Paris,  1778  ff. 

Camper,  Petrus.  Kleinere  Schriften,  Leipzig,  1788. 

De  Geer,  Charles,  Memoires  pourservirh  l' histoire  des  insectes.  Stockholm,  1751  ff. 


6xo  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

Hales,  Stephen,  Statical  Essays.  London,  1738. 

Haller,  Albrecht  von,  Anfangsgrunde  der  Physiologic  des  Menschen,  translated 

by  J.  S.  Haller.  Berlin,  1759  fF. 
— ,  Bibliotheca  anatomica.  Berne,  1774. 
— ,  M.emo!res  sur  la  nature.  Lausanne,  1746  fF. 
— ,  On  Sensible  and  Irritable  Parts  of  the  Body.  Swedish  Academy  of  Science, 

Transactions,  Vol.  XLV.  Stockholm,  1753. 
— ,  Prima  linea  physiologia.  Gottingen,  1747. 
Hunter,  John,  Works.  London,  1835. 
Koelreuter,  J.  G.,  Vorlaufige  Nacbricht  von  einigen  das  Geschlecht  der  Pfanzfn 

betreffenden  Versuchen.  Ostwald's  Klassiker,  1893. 
La  Mettrie,  J.  O.  de,  CEuvres  philosophiques.  Berlin,  1774. 
Lieberkiihn,  J.  N.,  Dissertatio  .  .  .  de  fabrica  .  .  .  villorum  intestini.  Leyden, 

1745- 
Lyonet,  Pierre,  Traite  anatomique  de  la  chenille,  etc.  The  Hague,  1746. 

Pallas,  P.  S.,  Elenchus  xpophytorum.  The  Hague,  1766. 

— ,  M-iscellanea  %pologica.  The  Hague,  1766. 

— ,  l>iova  species  quadrupedum,  etc.  Erlangen,  1778. 

Reaumur,  A.  F.  de,  Memoires  pour  servir  a  V histoire  des  insectes.  Paris,  1734  fF. 

Rosel  von  Rosenhof,  Monatliche  Insektenbelustigungen.  Nuremberg,  1753  fF. 

Spallanzani,  L.,  Experiences  pour  servir  h  V histoire  de  la  generation.  Geneva,  1785. 

— ,  Programme  .  .  .  d'une  ouvrage  sur  les  reproductions  animales.  Geneva,  1768. 

Sprengel,  Conrad,   Das  entdeckte  Geheimnis  der  Natur.   Ostwald's  Klassiker. 

Leipzig,  1894. 

Trembley,  A.,  Memoires  pour  servir  h  V histoire  d'une  polype  d'eau  douce.  Leyden, 

1744- 
WolfF,  C.  F.,  Theoria  generationis,  ed.  z.  Halle,  1774. 

Chapters  XII-XIV 

Agardh,  C.  A.,  Text-book  on  Botany.  Malmo,  18x9  fF.  (Swedish) 

Carus,  C.  G.,  Grmid^uge  der  vergleichenden  Anatomic.  Dresden,  i8i8. 

— ,  Natur  und  Idee.  Vienna,  1861. 

Darwin,  Erasmus,  Zoonomie,  translated  by  Brandis.  Hanover,  1795. 

Goethe,  J.  W.,  Sdmtliche  Werke.  Cotta,  Stuttgart,  1851  fF. 

Herder,  J.  G.,  Sdmtliche  Werke.  Berlin,  1887  fF. 

Hwasser,  L,  Essays.  Upsala,  1839.  (Swedish) 

— ,  Selected  Essays.  Stockholm,  1868  fF.  (Swedish) 

Ingenhousz,  J.,  Experiments  upon  Vegetables.  London,  1779. 

Kant,  J.,  Gesamyneltc  Schriften,  Berlin,  1901. 

Lavoisier,  A.  L.,  CEuvres.  Paris,  1863  fF. 

Nees  von  Esenbeck,  C.  G.,  Handbuch  der  Botanik.  Nuremberg,  i8io. 

Oken,  Lorenz,  Naturgeschichte  fur  alle  Stdnde.  Stuttgart,  1841  fF. 


SOURCES  62.1 

Oken,  Lorenz,  Naturphilosophie.  Jena,  1809. 

Priestley,  J.,  Experiments  and  Observations  on  Different  Kinds  of  Air.  London, 

^775- 
Saussure,  N.  Th.  de,  Kecherches  chimiques  sur  la  vegetation.  Paris,  1804. 

Schelling,  F.  W.  J.,  Samtliche  Werke.  Stuttgart,  1856  fF. 

PART   III 

Chapters  I-III 

Barthez,  P.  J.,  Nouveaux  Elements  de  la  science  de  Vhomme.  Montpellier,  1778. 

Bichat,  F.  M.  X.,  Anatomie  generale,  ed.  i.  Paris,  1818. 

— ,  Traite  d' anatomie  descriptive.  Paris,  1801. 

— ,  Traite  des  membranes^  ed.  2..  Paris,  i8oi. 

Blumenbach,  J.  F.,  Collectionis  suce  craniorum,  etc. ,  decades  VI.  Gottingen,  1790. 

— ,  Handbuch  der  Naturgeschichte.  Gottingen,  1803. 

— ,  ijber  die  natiirlichen  V erschiedenheiten  itn  Menschengeschlechte ,  translated  by 

Gruber.  Leipzig,  1798. 
— ,  tjber  den  Bildungstrieb.  Gottingen,  1791. 
Bordeu,  H.  de,  Kecherches  anatomiques  sur  la  position  des  glandes,  ed.  1.  Paris, 

1799. 
Cuvier,  G.,  Le  Kegne  animal.  Paris,  1817  fF. 
— ,  Eecons  d' anatomie  cotnparee.  Paris,  1799  ff. 

— ,  Kecherches  sur  les  as  semens  fossiles  de  quadrupedes.  Paris,  18 12.  fF. 
Gall,  F.  J.,  Lehre  uber  die  Verrichtungen  des  Gehirns.  Dresden,  1805. 
— ,  et  Spurzheim,  Kecherches  sur  le  systeme  nerveux,  etc.  Paris,  1809. 
— ,  Sur  I'origine  des  qualites  morales.  Paris,  182.2.  fF. 
Humboldt,  A.  von,  Ansichten  der  Natur.  Stuttgart,  1849. 
— ,  Kosmos.  Stuttgart,  1845  fF. 

— ,  Versuche  uber  die  gereixte  Muskel-  und  Nervenfaser.  Berlin,  1797. 
Lamarck,  J.  B.  de,  Histoire  naturelle  des  animaux  sans  vertebres.  Paris,  1815  fF. 
— ,  Memoires  de  physique  et  d' histoire  naturelle.  Paris,  1797. 
— ,  Philosophie  zpologique,  ed.  z.  Paris,  1873. 
— ,  Kecherches  sur  V organisation  des  corps  vivants.  Paris,  i8oi. 
Reil,  J.  C,  Archiv  fur  Physiologie,  1796,  Bd.  I. 
Sommerring,  S.  T.,  De  corporis  humani  fabrica.  Frankfurt,  1794  fF. 
— ,  Uber  das  Organ  der  Seek.  Konigsberg,  1796. 
Vicq  d'Azyr,  Felix,  CEuvres.  Paris,  1805  fF. 
— ,  Traite  d' anatomie  et  de  physiologie.  Paris,  1786. 

Chapters  IV-VI 

Baer,  K.  E.  von,  Uber  Entwicklungsgeschichte  der  Tiere,  Konigsberg,  182.8  fF. 
— ,  De  ovi  mammalium  et  hominis  genesi.  Leipzig,  1817. 


62.x  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

Bell,  Ch.,  Die  menschlkhe  Hand,  trans,  by  HaufF.  Stuttgart,  1836. 

— ,  Idea  of  a  New  Anatomy  of  the  Brain,  ed.  Ebstein.  Klassiker  de  Medizin,  pub- 
lished by  SudhofF.  Leipzig,  191 1. 

Bernard,  Claude,  La  Science  experimental.  Paris,  1878. 

— ,  Legons  de  physiologie  experimental .  Paris,  1855. 

— ,  Lecons  sur  les  phenomenes  de  la  vie.  Paris,  1878. 

Berzelius,  J.  J.,  Lectures  on  Animal  Chemistry.  Stockholm,  1806  ff.  (Swedish, 
trans,  into  German  by  Wohler) 

Blainville,  H.  M.  D.  de,  Traite  des  animaux.  Paris,  1812.  fF. 

Fourcroy,  A.  F.,  Philosophia  chemica,  trans,  by  Sparrmann.  Stockholm,  1795. 
(Swedish) 

Magendie,  F.,  Legons  sur  les  phenomenes  physiques  de  la  vie.  Paris,  1836. 

— ,  Precis  elementaire  de  physiologie,  ed.  5.  Brussels,  1838. 

Meckel,  J.  F.,  System  der  vergleichenden  Anatomie.  Halle,  i8zi  fF. 

Miiller,  Johannes,  Bildungsgeschichte  der  Genitalien.  Diisseldorf,  1830. 

— ,  Handbuch  der  Physiologie  des  Menschen.  Coblenz,  1837-40. 

— ,  ijber  den  Bau,  etc.,  des  Amphioxus.  Berlin,  1844. 

— ,  Vergleichende  Anatomie  der  Myxinoiden.  Brllin,  1835-40. 

— ,  Zur  vergleichenden  Physiologie  des  Gesichtssinnes.  Leipzig,  i8i6. 

Pander,  H.  C,  Beitrdge  zur  Entwicklungs geschichte  des  Hiihnchens  im  Eye.  Wiirz- 
burg,  1817. 

Purkinje,  J.  E.,  Beohachtungen  und  Versuche  z^^  Physiologie  der  Sinne.  Berlin, 
18x5. 

— ,  De  phanomeno,  etc.,  motus  vibratorii  continui.  Breslau,  1835. 

— ,  Symbols  ad  ovi  avium  historiam.  Breslau,  1815. 

Rathke,  H.,  Beitrdge  z^r  vergleichenden  Anatomie  und  Physiologie.  Danzig,  1842.. 

— ,  Bemerkungen  uber  den  Bau  des  Amphioxus,  etc.  Konigsberg,  1841. 

— ,  Untersuchungen  iiber  den  Kiemenapparat.  Riga,  1831. 

Rudolphi,  C.  A.,  Entozoorum  synopsis.  Berlin,  1819. 

— ,  Grundriss  der  Physiologie.  Berlin,  i8xi  fF. 

Scheele,  C.  W.,  Letters  and  Annotations,  published  by  A.  E.  Nordenskiold. 
Stockholm,  1891.  (Partly  in  Swedish) 

Chapter  VII 

Henle,  J.,  All gemeine  Anatomie.  Leipzig,  1841. 
— 5  Symbols  ad  anatomiam  villorum  intestinalium.  Berlin,  1837. 
— ,  Essays  in  Archiv  fur  Anatomie  und  Physiologie. 
Kolliker,  A.,  Entivicklungs geschichte  der  Cephalopoden.  Zurich,  1844. 
— ,  Entwicklungs  geschichte  des  Menschen  und  der  hoheren  Tiere.  Leipzig,  i86i'. 
— ,  Handbuch  der  Geivebelehre  des  Menschen.  Leipzig,  i85X. 
— ,  Essays  in  Zeitschrift  fur  wissenschaftliche  Zoologie  and  in  Archiv  fur  Anato- 
mie und  Physiologie. 


SOURCES  613 

Leydig,  F.,  Lehrbuch  der  Histologie  des  Menschen  und  der  Tiere.  Frankfurt,  1857. 
— ,  Essays  in  Archiv  fur  Anatomie  und  Physiologic  and  in  Zeitschrift  fur  ivissen- 

schaftliche  Zoologie. 
Mohl,  H.,  Grundxiige  der  Anatomie  und  Physiologic  der  vegetabilischen   Zcllc. 

Braunschweig,  185 1. 
• — ,  Vermischte  Schriften.  Tubingen,  1845. 
— ,  Essays  in  Botanische  Zeitung. 

Nageli,  K.,  Zur  Entivicklungsgeschichte  dcs  Pollens.  Zurich,  i84z. 
Reichert,  K.  B.,  Be  if  rage  %ur  heutigen  Entivicklungsgeschichte.  Berlin,  1843, 
— ,  Betnerhingen  %ur  vergleichcnden  Naturforschtmg,  etc.  Dorpat,  1845. 
— ,  Das  Entivicklungsleben  im  Wirbeltierreich.  Berlin,  1840. 
— ,  Essays  in  Archiv  fur  Anatotnie  und  Physiologic. 
Remak,  R.,  Essays  in  Archiv  fur  Anatomic,  etc.;  in  Cotnptcs  rendus  de  l' Academic 

des  Sciences;  et  al. 
Schleiden,  M.,  Grund^Jige  der  wissenschaftlichcn  Botanik.  Leipzig,  1842.. 
— ,  Essays  in  Archiv  fur  Anatomic  und  Physiologic. 
Schwann,  Th.,  Mikroskopischc  Untcrsuchungen  uber  die  XJhereinstimmung  in  der 

Struktur  und  dem  Wachstum  der  Tiere  und  Pflanxen.  Berlin,  1839. 
Virchow,  R.,  Die  Cellularpathologie.  Berlin,  1858. 
— ,  Gcsammelte  Abhandlungen.  Frankfurt,  1856. 
— ,  Essays  in  Archiv  fur  pathologische  Anatomic. 

Chapter  VIII 

Brown,  R.,  Botanische  Schriften,  ed.  Nees  von  Esenbeck.  Leipzig,  182.5  ^• 
Candolle,  A.  de.  Physiologic  vegetalc.  Paris,  i83x. 
— ,  Theorie  elementaire  de  la  botanique,  ed.  t.  Paris,  1918. 
Du  Bois-Reymond,  E.,  Reden.  Leipzig,  1886. 
— ,  Untcrsuchungen  uber  tierische  Elektri^itdt.  Berlin,  1848  ff. 
Dujardin,  F.,  Histoire  naturelle  des  infusoires.  Paris,  1841. 
Ehrenberg,  C.  G.,  Die  Infusionstiere  als  vollkommene  Organisfnen.  Leipzig,  1838. 
Endlicher,  S.,  Enchiridion  botanicum.  Leipzig,  1841. 
— ,  Genera  plantarum.  Leipzig,  1836  ff. 
Fries,  E.,  Lichenographia  europaa  reformata.  Lund,  183 1. 
— ,  Sy sterna  mycologicum.  Lund  and  Greifswald,  i8io  ff. 

Hedwig,  J.,  Theoria  gencrationis,  etc.,  plantarum  crypto gamicarum,  ed.  i.  Leip- 
zig, 1798. 
Helmholtz,  H.,  Vortrdge  und  Reden,  ed.  3.  Braunschweig,  1903. 
■ — ,  Wisscnschaftliche  Abhandlungen.  Leipzig,  i88z. 
Jussieu,  A.  L.  de,  Genera  plantarum.  Paris,  1789. 

Leuckart,  R.,  Uber  die  Morphologic  der  Wirbellosen  Tiere.  Braunschweig,  1848. 
— ,  Uber  den  Polymorphismus  der  Individuen.  Giessen,  185 1. 
— ,  Die  menschlichen  Parasitcn.  Leipzig,  1863. 


6z4  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

Leuckart,  R.,  Essays  in  Miiller's  Archiv. 

Ludwig,  K.  F.  W.,  Lehrbuch  der  Pbysiologie  des  Menschen.  Heildelberg,  1851. 

Mayer,  R.,  Die  Mechanik  der  Wdrme  in  Gesammelte  Abha^tdlungen,  published  by 

Weyrauch.  Stuttgart,  1893. 
Miiller,  O.  F.,  Vermium  terrestrium  et  piviatilium  historia.  Copenhagen,  1773. 
— ,  Animalcula  infusoria.  Copenhagen,  1786. 
Nordmann,  A.,  Micrographische  Beitrage.  Berlin,  1831. 
Owen,  R.,  On  the  Archetype  and  Homologies  of  the  Vertebrate  Skeleton.  London, 

1848. 
— ,  Lectures  on  the  Comparative  Anatomy.  London,  1843  fF. 
— ■,  On  the  Anatomy  of  Vertebrates.  London,  1866. 
— ■,  On  the  Nature  of  Limbs.  London,  1849. 
Pasteur,  L.,  Etudes  sur  le  vin.  Paris,  1868. 
— ,  Etudes  sur  le  vinaigre.  Paris,  1866. 
— ,  Essays  in  Annales  de  chim.  et  de  phys.  and  Comptes  rendus  de  V Academic  des 

Sciences. 
Siebold,  Th.  and  Stannius,  H.,  Lehrbuch  der  vergleichenden  Anatomic.  Berlin, 

1848. 
Siebold,  tjber  die  Band-  und  Blasemvurmer.  Leipzig,  1854. 
— ,  Wahre  Parthenogenesis.  Leipzig,  1856. 

— ,  Essays  in  Miiller's  Archiv  and  Zeitschrift  fur  tvissenschaftliche  Zoologie. 
Stannius,  Das  perpherische  Nervensystem  der  Fische.  Rostock,  1849. 

Chapter  IX 

Biichner,  L.,  Kraft  und  Stoff,  ed.  7.  Leipzig,  i86i. 

Comte,  A.,  Cours  de  philosophic  positive,  ed.  3.  Paris,  1869. 

Liebig,  J.,  Chcfnische  Brief e.  Heidelberg,  1844. 

— ,  Die  organische  Chtmie  in  ihrer  Anwendung  auf  Agrikultur  und  Physiologic. 

Braunschweig,  1840. 
— ,  Die  organische  Chemie  in  ihrer  Anwendung  auf  Physiologic  und  Pathologic. 

Braunschweig,  i84x. 
Mill,  J.  S.,  System  of  Logic,  ed.  5.  London,  1852.. 
Moleschott,  J.,  Kreislauf  des  Lebens.  Mainz,  1851. 
Vogt,  K.,  Kohlerglaube  und  Wissenschaft,  ed.  4.  Giessen,  1855. 
Wagner,  R.,  Menschliches  Gehirn  als  Seelcnorgan.  Gottingen,  1862.. 
— ,  Vortrag  mit  Diskussion  im  Bericht  iiber  die  51.  Versammlung  deutschcr  Natur- 

forscher  und  Arzte.  Gottingen,  1854. 

Chapters  X-XII 
Agassiz,  L.,  An  Essay  on  Classification.  London,  1859. 
— ,  Kecherches  sur  les  poissons  fossiles.  Neuchatel,  1833  fF. 
— ,  Essays  in  American  Journal  of  Science  and  Arts. 


SOURCES  615 

Darwin,  Ch.,  The  Structure  of  Coral  Reefs.  London,  1842.. 
— ,  Geological  Observations  on  Volcanic  Islands.  London,  1844. 
— ,  A  Monograph  on  Cirripedia.  London,  1851  fF. 
— ,  The  Origin  of  Species,  ed.  i,  z,  5.  London,  1859,  i860,  1871. 
— ,  Variations  of  Animals  and  Plants  under  Domestication.  London,  1868. 
— ,  The  Descent  of  Man.  London,  1871. 
— ,  Expression  of  Emotions.  London,  iSyz. 
— ,  Movements  and  Habits  of  Climbing  Plants.  London,  1875. 
— ,  Insectivorous  Plants.  London,  1875. 
— ,  The  Effects  of  Cross-  and  Self-fertilization.  London,  1876. 
— ,  On  Earth-u'orms.  London,  1881. 
— ,  Life  and  Letters,  ed.  Fr.  Darwin.  London,  1887  fF. 
Gray,  A.,  Danviniana.  New  York,  1887  fF. 
Hooker,  J.  D.,  Flora  Tasmania.  London,  i860. 
Huxley,  T.  H.,  Evidence  as  to  Man  s  Place  in  Nature.  London,  1863. 
— ,  Lectures  on  the  Elements  of  Comparative  Anatomy.  London,  1864. 
— ,  Lay  Sermons,  addresses  and  reviews.  London,  1871. 
— ,  Life  and  Letters,  ed.  L.  Huxley.  London,  1900. 
— ,  Essays  in  Transactions  of  Royal  Society. 
Lyell,  Ch.,  Elements  of  Geology.  London,  1831  ff. 
— ,  The  Geological  Evidences  of  the  Antiquity  of  Man.  London,  1863. 
Malthus,  T.,  Essay  on  Population,  ed.  5.  London,  1817. 
Quatrefages,  A.  de,  Charles  Darivin  et  ses  precurseurs  frangais.  Paris,  1870. 
Spencer,  H.,  Essays.  London,  1868. 
— ,  A  System  of  Synthetic  Philosophy.  London,  1870  fF. 

Wallace,  A.  R.,  Contributions  to  the  Theory  of  Natural  Selection.  London,  1870. 
— ,  Island  Life.  London,  1880. 
— ,  Darwinism.  London,  1889. 
Wigand,  A.,  Der  Dartvinismus.  Braunschweig,  1874  fF. 

Chapters  XIII,  XIV 

Fiirbringer,    M.,    Untersuchungen    zur  Morphologie   und  Systematik  der   V'ogel. 

Amsterdam,  1888. 
Gegenbaur,  C,  Grundzuge  der  vergleichenden  Anatomie,  ed.  i,  2..  Leipzig,  1859, 

1870. 
— ,  Untersuchungen  xur  vergleichenden  Anatomie  der  Wirheltiere.  Leipzig,  1864  fF. 
— ,  Grundriss  der  vergleichenden  Anatomie.  Leipzig,  1874. 
— ,  Vergleichende  Anatomie  der  Wirbeltiere.  Leipzig,  1898. 
— ,  Gesammelte  Abhandlungen.  Leipzig,  1911. 
Haeckel,  E.,  Die  Radiolarien.  Berlin,  1861,  1888. 
— ,  Die  Kalkschu'dmme.  Berlin,  1871. 
— ,  Das  System  der  Medusen.  Jena,  1879. 


62.6  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

Haeckel,  E.,  Generelle  Morphologic.  Berlin,  1866. 

— ,  Nattirliche  Scbopjungsgeschichte.  Berlin,  1868. 

— ,  Anthropogetiie.  Leipzig,  1874. 

— ,  Gesammelte  Vortrdge.  Bonn,  1878. 

— ,  Weltrdtsel.  Bonn,  1903. 

— ,  Funjz.ig  J^hre  Stammesgeschkhte.  Jena,  191 6. 

— ,  Entwkklungsgeschkbte  emer  Jugend.  Published  by  Schmidt,  Leipzig,  192.1. 

— ,  Italknjahrt.  Published  by  Schmidt,  Leipzig,  1911. 

Hubrecht,  A.,  Dk  Sdugetkrontogemse.  Jena,  1909. 

Mach,  E.,  Analyse  der  Empfi7idungen.  Jena,  1906. 

— ,  Erkenntnis  und  Irrtum.  Leipzig,  1906. 

Miiller,  F.,  Fur  Darwin.  Leipzig,  1864. 

Chapter  XV 

Altmann,  R.,  Die  Element ar or ganismen.  Leipzig,  1890. 

Balfour,  F.,  Works.  London,  1884  fF. 

Beneden,  E.  van,  Kechercbes  sur  la  maturation  de  I'ceuf.  Paris,  1883. 

Boveri,  Th.,  Zellenstudien.  Jena,  1887  fF. 

Braun,  A.,  Betracbtungen  tiher  die  Verjungung  in  der  Natiir.  Leipzig,  1851. 

Buchner,  E.,  Essays  in  Bericbten  der  Deutscben  cbemiscben  Gesellscbaft. 

Biitschli,  O.,  Studien  uber  die  ersten  Entivicklungsvorgdnge  der  Ei^elle.  Frank- 
furt a.  M.,  1876. 

— ,  ProtoXpa.  Bronn's  Klassen  und  Ordnungen.  Leipzig,  1889. 

Cajal,  S.  Ramon,  Histologic  du  systhne  nerveux.  Paris,  1909  fr. 

Engelmann,  Th.,  Essays  in  Pfliiger's  Archiv  fur  Pbysiologie. 

Engler,  A.,  Entu'ickhmgsgescbichte  der  Pflan'^enivelt.  Leipzig,  1879. 

Flemming,  W.,  Zellsubstan^,  Kern  und  Zellteilung.  Leipzig,  1881. 

Fol,  H.,  Lehrbucb  der  vergleicbenden  mikroskopiscben  Anatomie.  Leipzig,  1896. 

— ,  Essays  in  IS/ihnoires  de  la  societe  de  pbysique  et  d'bistoire  naturelle.  Geneva. 

Goette,  A.,  Entioicklungsgescbicbte  der  Unke.  Leipzig,  1874. 

Hansen,  E.  C,  Essays  in  Mitteilungen  des  Carlsberg-Laboratoriums.  Copenhagen. 

Heidenhain,  M.,  Plasma  und  Zelle.  Jena,  1907  ff. 

Heidenhain,  R.,  Essays  in  Studien  des  Pbysiologiscben  Instituts  xu  Breslau. 

Hensen,  V.,  Die  Planktonexpedition.  Kiel,  1890  ff. 

Hertwig,  O.,  Allgemeine  Biologic,  ed.  4,  Jena,  i9iz. 

— ,  Das  Werden  der  Organismen.  Jena,  191 6. 

— ,  Zur  Abivebr  des  ethiscben,  etc.,  Darivinismus.  ]ena.,  191 8. 

— ,  Essays  in  Morpbologiscbe  Jahrbiicber,  Jenaiscbe  Zeitschrift,  and  Zeitscbrift 
fur  wissenscbaftlicbe  Mikroskopie. 

Hertwig,  R,,  Lebrbucb  der  Zoologie.  Jena,  1890. 

— ,  Essays  on  the  Protozoa  in  scientific  journals. 

Hertwig,  O.  and  R.,  Untersucbungen  %ur  Morpbologie  der  Zelle,  I-VL  Jena,  1884  ff. 


SOURCES  62.7 

His,  W.,  Unsere  Korperform.  Leipzig,  1874. 

Hofmeister,  W.,  Vergleichende  Untersuchungen  der  Keimung  hoherer  Kryptogamen 
Leipzig,  185 1. 

Holmgren,  E.,  Text-book  on  Histology.  Stockholm,  ic)io.  (Swedish) 

Kleinenberg,  N.,  Hydra.  Leipzig,  1871. 

— ,  Essays  in  the  Zeitschrift  fur  wissenschaftliche  Zoologie,  1886. 

Koch,  R.,  Gesammelte  Werke.  Leipzig,  i9ix  fF. 

Korschelt,  E.,   and  Heider,  K.,  Lebrbuch    der   vergleicbenden    Entivkklungsge- 
schichte  der  wirbellosen  Tiere.  Jena,  i^oi. 

Kowalewsky,  A.,  Essays  in  the  Acta  of  the  Imperial  Academy,  St.  Peters- 
burg. 

Lang,  A.,  Lehrbuch  der  vergleichenden  Anatomie.  Jena,  1850  fF. 

Lankester,  E.  R.,  Treatise  on  Zoology.  London,  1900. 

Laveran,  A.,  Nature  par asit aire  des  accidents  de  V impaludisme.  Paris,  1881. 

Mobius,  K.,  Fauna  der  Kieler  Bucbt.  Leipzig,  1865. 

Nageli,  C,  Entstebung  des  Begriffes  der  naturbistoriscben  Art.  Munich,  1865. 

— ,  Mecbaniscb-pbysiologiscbe  Tbeorie  der  Abstammungslebre .  Munich,  1884. 

— ,  Essays  in  Zeitscbrift  fur  tvissenscbaftlicbe  Botanik. 

Ranvier,  L.,  Legons  d' anatomie  generale.  Paris,  1881. 

Rollett,  A.,  Untersucbungen  uber  die  q^uergestreiften  Muskelfasern.  Vienna,  1885. 

Ross,  R.,  Researcbes  on  Malaria.  Stockholm,  1904. 

Schaudinn,  P.,  Essays  in  Arbeiten  aus  dem  Kaiserlicben  Gesundheitsamte  and  in 
Sitxungsbericbte  der  Konigl.  Akademie  der  Wissenschaften.  Berlin. 

Schimper,  A.  F.  W.,  Pflanzengeograpbie  auf  pbysiologiscber  Grundlage.  Jena,  1898. 

Schwendener,  S.,  Untersucbungen  tiber  den  Flecbtentballus.  Leipzig,  i860. 

— ,  Das  mecbaniscbe  Prinzip  im  anatomiscben  Bau  der  Nlonocotyle.  Leipzig,  1874. 

— ,  Mecbaniscbe  Tbeorie  der  Blattstellungen.  Leipzig,  1878. 

Strasburger,  E.,  Zellbildung  und  Zellteilung,  ed.  1-3.  Jena,  1875-80. 

Wiedersheim,  R.,  Vergleicbende  Anatomie  der  Wirbeltiere,  ed.  6.  Jena,  1906. 

Chapters  XVI-XVIII 

Bataillon,  A.,  Essays  in  Arcbives  de  Zoologie  experimentale  et  generale. 

Bateson,  W.,  Mendel's  Principles  of  Heredity.  Cambridge,  1909. 

Baur,  E.,  Einfubrung  in  die  experimentelle  Vererbimgslehre,  ed.  4.  Berlin,  1919. 

Bayliss,  W.,  Principles  of  General  Pbysiology,  ed.  -l.  London,  1918. 

Bethe,  A.,  Essays  in  Arcbiv  fiir  die  gesamte  Pbysiologie,  Vol.  LXX. 

Bunge,  G.,  Lebrbucb  der  pbysiologiscben  und  patbologiscben  Cbemie,  ed.  z.  Leip- 
zig, 1889. 

Driesch,  H.,  Analytiscbe  Tbeorie  der  organiscben  Entwicklung.  Leipzig,  1904. 

— ,  Pbilosophie  des  Organiscben.  Leipzig,  1909. 

— ,  Essays  in  Morpbologiscbe  Jabrbucber  and  Zeitscbrift  fiir  tvissenscbaftlicbe 
Zoologie. 


62.8  THE     HISTORY     OF     BIOLOGY 

Eimer,  Th.,  Die  Entstehung  der  Arten.  Jena,  1888  ff. 
_  Galton,  F.,  Natural  Inheritance.  London,  1889. 
— ,  Essays  in  the  Journal  of  the  Anthropological  Institute.  London,  1875. 
Giard,  A.,  Contro verses  transformistes.  Paris,  1904. 
Goebel,  K.,  Organographie  der  Pflanxen.  Jena,  1898. 

— ,  Einleitung  in  die  experimentelle  Morphologie  der  Pflanzen.  Leipzig,  1908. 
Herbst,  C,  Essays  in  Arcbiv  ftir  Entwicklungsmecbanik. 
Heribert-Nilsson,  N.,  Experimentelle  Studien  uber  Variabilitdt,  etc.  in  der  Gat- 

tung  Salix.     Lund,  191 8. 
Hertwig,  O.,  Z.eit-  und  Streitfragen  der  Biologie,  I,  IL    Jena,  1894  ff. 
— ,  Der  Kampf  um  die  Kernfragen  der  Entwicklungs-  und  Vererbungslehre.    Jena, 

1909. 
Hober,  R.,  Physikalische  Chemie  der  Zelle  und  der  Geivebe,  ed.  4.  Leipzig,  1914. 
Johannsen,  W.  L.,  Elemente  der  exakten  Erblichkeitslehre,  ed.  x.  Jena,  1913. 
— ,  Erblichkeit.  Cojsenhagen,  1917.  (Danish) 
— ,  False  Analogies,  Swedish  by  Larsson.  Stockholm,  1917. 
— ,  Biology  in  the  Nineteenth  Century.  Copenhagen,  1919.  (Danish) 
Lehmann,  A.,  Grund%iige  der  Psychophysiologie.  Leipzig,  i9ix. 
Loeb,  J.,  tJber  den  chemischen  Charakter  des  Befruchtungsvorganges.  Leipzig,  1908. 
— ,  The  Mechanistic  Conception  of  Life.  Chicago,  191 2.. 
Lotsy,  J.,  Qjc  est-ce  quune  espece.  Amsterdam,  1916. 

Lubbock,  J.,  On  the  Senses,  Instincts  and  Intelligence  of  Animals.  London,  1888. 
Mendel,  G.,  Versuche  uber  Pflan^enhybriden.  Ostwald's  Klassiker  der  Natur- 

ivissenschaft.  Leipzig,  1913. 
Morgan,  T.,  The  Mechanism  of  Mendelian  Heredity.  New  York,  191 5. 
Neumeister,  R. ,  Betrachtungen  uber  das  Wesen  der  Lebenserscheinungen.  Jena,  1903 . 
Nilsson-Ehle,  H.,  Essays  in  the  Journal  of  the  Swedish  Society  of  Seed-Culture 

and  in  the  journal  Hereditas.  Lund. 
Overton,  E.,  "Uber  den  Mechanismus  der  Resorption  und  Sekretion."  Nagel's 

Handbuch  der  Physiologic.  Braunschweig,  1907. 
Pauly,  Darwinismus  und  Lamarckismus.  Munich,  1905. 
Pfeffer,  W.,  Pflanxenphysiologie,  ed.  t.  Leipzig,  1897  fF. 
Plate,  L.,  Selektionsprin^ip  und  Probleme  der  Artbildung,  ed.  4.  Leipzig,  1913. 
Punnett,  R.  C,  Mendelism.  London,  191 1. 

Radl,  E.,  Geschichte  der  biologischen  Theorien  der  Neux.eit-  Leipzig,  1905-13. 
— ,  Neue  Lehre  vom  xentralen  Nervensystem.  Leipzig,  \^ix. 
Rauber,  A.,  Essays  in  Morphologisches  Jahrbuch,  1883. 
Romanes,  G.,  Animal  Intelligence,  ed.  3.  London,  1888. 
Roux,  \V.,  Collected  Essays.  Leipzig,  1895. 
— ,  Essays  in  Archiv  fur  Entwicklungsmechanik. 
Sachs,  J.,  Geschichte  der  Botanik.  Munich,  1875. 
— ,  Vorlesungen  uber  PJlanxenphysiologie.  Leipzig,  iSSi. 


LITERATURE  6x9 

Semon,  R.,  Das  Problem  der  Vererbimg  erworbener  Eigenschaften.  Leipzig,  igii. 

Spemann,  H.,  Essays  in  Archiv  fur  Etitivicklungsmechanik. 

Uhlenhuth,  P.,  Essays  in  Deutsche  medizinische  W ochenschrijt . 

Verworn,  M.,  Allgetneine  Pbysiologie,  ed.  5.  Jena,  1909. 

Vries,  H.  de.  Die  Mutationstheorie.  Leipzig,  1901  ff. 

— -,  Essays  in  Berichten  der  deutschen  botanischen  Gesellschaft. 

Wasmann,  E.,  Die  moderne  Biologie,  ed.  3.  Freiburg,  1906. 

Weisraann,  A.,  Aufsdtxe  uber  Vererbung.  Jena,  1852.. 

— ,  Das  Keimplasma.  Jena,  1891. 

— ,  Uber  Gertninalselektion.  Jena,  1896. 

— ,  Die  Selektionstbeorie.  Jena,  1909. 

Wundt,  W.,  Vorlesungen  uber  die  Menschen-  und  Tierseele,  ed.  2..  Hamburg,  1892 , 

LITERATURE 

Boucke,  Goethes  Weltanschauung.  Stuttgart,  1907. 

Burckhardt,  Geschichte  der  Zoologie,  ed.  i,  2..  Leipzig,  1907,  1911. 

Carus,  Geschichte  der  Zoologie.  Munich,  187^. 

Eckermann,  J.  P.,  Gesprdche  mit  Goethe.  Leipzig,  1836. 

Fries,  Th.,  Lifine.  Stockholm,  1903.  (Swedish) 

Gomperz,  Griechische  Denker.  Leipzig,  1896. 

Haeser,  Geschichte  der  M.edixin.  Jena,  1875. 

HofFding,  Geschichte  der  neueren  Philosophie.  Leipzig,  1895. 

— ,  Modern  Philosophers.  Copenhagen,  1904.  (Danish) 

Hulth,  J.  M.,  Bibliographia  linneana,  I.  Upsala. 

Kohlbrugge,  J.  H.  T.,  Historisch  kritische  Studien  uber  Goethe  als  Naturforscher. 

Zoologische  Annalen,  Vols.  V,  VL  Wiirzburg,  1913-14. 
Kopp,  H.,  Geschichte  der  CheTnie.  Braunschweig,  1843. 
Lamm,  M.,  Sivedenborg.  Stockholm,  191 5.  (Swedish) 
Lange,  Geschichte  des  Materialismus,  ed.  i,  9.  Leipzig,  1914. 
May,  W.,  Haeckel.  Leipzig,  1909. 
Paulsen,  Fr.,  Kant.  Stuttgart,  1899. 

Radl,  Geschichte  der  biologischen  Theorien,  ed.  i,  ±.  Leipzig,  1907,  1909,  1913. 
Roth,  M.,  Andreas  Vesalius.  Berlin,  1891. 
Sachs,  J.,  Geschichte  der  Botanik,  Munich,  1875. 
Zeller,  Die  Philosophie  der  Griechen.  Tiibingen,  1879. 


INDEX 


Abbe,  German  physicist,  548 

Abelard,  medieval  theologian  and  scholar,  76 

Abdallatif,  Arabian  zoologist,  73 

Abu  Sina,  Persian  physician  and  philosopher, 

71 
Academies,  early  scientific  societies,  142. 
Acharius,  Erik,  Swedish  botanist,  440 
Adtnographia,  work  on  glands,  by  Wharton,  148 
Advancement  of  Learning,  The,  by  Francis  Bacon, 

87 
itlianus,  Claudius,  Roman  orator  and  natural 

historian,  65,  78 
Agardh,  Carl  Adolf,  Swedish  scientist,  191, 

2-92-.  439 

Agardh,  Jacob  Georg,  439 

Agassiz,  Jean  Louis  Rodolphe,  American 
scientist,  479,  480,  491 

Airs,  Waters,  and  Places,  medical  treatise  by 
Hippocrates,  2.6 

Albertus,  Magnus,  mediaeval  scientist,  79 

Albinus,  Bernhard  Siegfried,  German  anato- 
mist, 158,  159,  2.66 

Albnius,  309 

Aldrovandi,  Ulisse,  zoologist  of  the  Renais- 
sance, 56,  94,  95 

Allgemeine  Anatomie,  by  Henle,  397 

AUgemeine  Naturgeschichte  jiir  alle  Stdnde, 
natural  history  by  Oken,  i88 

Allgemeine  Naturgeschichte  und  Theorie  des  Him- 
mels,  by  Kant,  170 

Allgemeine  Physiologie,  by  Verworn,  604 

Altmann,  Richard,  German  scientist,  536, 
53S,  539,  604 

Amici,  Italian  microscopist,  389 

Analogy,  term  first  used  in  comparative 
anatomy  by  Owen,  415 

Anatomy,  first  knowledge  of,  3;  earliest  work 
on,  13;  Greek  development  of,  2.8;  Aris- 
totle's contribution  to,  40;  Herophilus,  con- 
tribution to,  51;  Galen's  contribution  to, 
62.-64;  comparative,  by  Belon,  98;  progress 
in  the  Renaissance,  98-107;  stimulus  to,  in 
17th  century,  141;  progress  in  England,  147- 
150;  Malpighi's  contribution  to,  161; 
vegetable,  founded,  161-164;  influence  of 
microscope  on,  158-164;  Daubenton's  com- 
parative,  X2.J;    Cuvier's   pioneer   work   in, 


333;  development  in  the  i8th  century,  2.58, 
351;  d'Azyr's  contribution  to,  305;  com- 
parative, in  France,  359;  influence  of 
Darwinism  on,  518 

Anaxagoras,  Greek  philosopher,  13 

Anaximander,  early  Greek  philosopher,  11, 
i-L,  19,  2.0,  2.2.,  30,  31 

Anaximandros,  Greek  philosopher,  453 

Anaximcnes,  early  Greek  philosopher,  12. 

Ancel,  French  biologist,  596 

Animal  Life,  by  Brehm,  52.1 

Animal  Life,  by  Muhammed  el  Damiri,  73 

Animalculists,  school  of  i8th  century  bi- 
ologists, 173,  130 

Animals,  relation  to  primitive  man,  4 

Animals  and  Plants  under  Domestication,  by 
Darwin,  471 

Annalen  der  Chemie,  published  by  Liebig,  408 

Anselm  of  Canterbury,  medixval  theologian, 
76 

Anthropogenie  oder  Entwicklungsgeschichte  des 
Menschen,  series  of  lectures  by  Haeckel,  515 

Anthropology,  development  of,  by  Buffon, 
12.6;  pioneer  work  by  Blumenbach,  307; 
development  of,  by  Retzius,  415 

Antitoxins,  discovery  of,  597 

Apathy,  Stefan,  Hungarian  scientist,  540,  610 

Appert,  French  chef,  430 

Aquinas,  Thomas,  mediaeval  theologian,  77 

Arabs,  their  contribution  to  advancement  of 
science,  69-73 

Archimedes,  Greek  philosopher  and  physicist, 
19,69 

Archiv  fur  pathologische  Anatomie  und  Physiologie, 
founded  by  Virchow,  401 

Archiv  fiir  Physiologie,  scientific  journal  founded 
by  Reil,  313 

Archives  de  hiologie,  journal  published  by 
van  Beneden,  534 

Argyle,  Duke  of,  in  dispute  with  Huxley,  491 

Aristotle,  his  theory  of  fossilization,  15;  in- 
fluenced by  Heracleitus,  19;  influenced  by 
Democritus,  10;  his  debt  to  Plato,  36;  his 
life,  33-35;  his  cosmogony,  36,  37;  con- 
tribution to  biology,  38;  references  to,  zi, 
11,  45,  46,  48,  50,  53,  55-58,  61,  63,  III,  114, 
i^")>  i35>  i38>  141.  147.  161,  166,  190-193, 


ii  IN 

198,  199,  lOI,  12.1,  145,  151,  177,  181,  303, 
310,  331,  334,  341,  361,  365,  430,  443,  470, 
603,  609,  611 

Arrehenius,  Svante,  Swedish  scientist,  595,  598 
Artedi,  Peter,  Swedish  scientist,  109,  no 
Asclepiads,  early  Greek  physicians,  15 
Aselli,   Gasparo,   Italian   physician,    141-144, 

147 

Astronomy,  development  of,  by  the  Arabs,  69; 
contribution  of  Cartesianism,  115 

Athens,  first  mention  of  in  Greek  scientific 
history,  13 

Atomic  theory,  origin  of,  10;  Lucretius'  con- 
ception of,  47;  development  by  Dalton,  49; 
development  by  Berzelius,  49 

Avenarius,  Richard,  Swiss  philosopher,  517 

Averroes,  Arabian  philosopher,  71,  71 

Avicenna,  see  Abu  Sina 

Babylon,  earliest  home  of  civilization,  5 
Bacon,  Francis,  87-89,  111,  176,  111,  175,  443, 

481 
Bacon,  Roger,  mediaeval  scientist,  80,  8i,  84 
Bacteriology,  recent  developments  in,  546-550 
Baer,  Karl  Ernst  von,  German  scientist,  363- 

366,  368,  373,  376,  381,  384,  483,  494,  517, 

532- 
Bagg,  biologist,  616 
Balfour,  Francis  Maitland,  English  scientist, 

530.  531 
Barthez,  Paul  Joseph,  French  scientist,   345, 

346 
Bartholin,  Caspar,  professor  of  medicine,   144 
Bartholin,  Thomas,  professor  of  medicine,  143- 

147,  156 
Bary,  Heinrich,  Anton  de,  German  biologist, 

558 
Bataillon,  A.,  French  scientist,  583 
Bates,  Henry  Walter,  English  scientist,  485,  487 
Bateson,  W.,  English  biologist,  591 
Bauhin,  Caspar,  professor  of  medicine,   194, 

196 
Baur,  Erwin,  German  biologist,  591,  594,  615 
Beagle,  cruise  of  the,  461 

Behring,  Emil,  German  scientist,  548,  597,  598 
Beitrdge    zjir   Methodik   der   Naturforschung,    by 

Wigand,  483 
Beitrdge  xur  Optik,  work  by  Goethe,  181 
Beitrdge  zur  Phytogenesis,  essay  by  Schleiden,  391 
Bell,    Charles,    Scotch    anatomist,    374-375, 

377.  414 
Belon,  Pierre,  scientist  of  the  Renaissance,  97 
Benecke,  405 
Bentham,  Jeremy,  English  political  economist, 

446,  459 
Bergman,  180 


D  E  X 

Berlin     zoological     museum,     founded     by 

Rudolphi,  353 
Bernard,   Claude,    French   physiologist,   377- 

380,  434,  4S4,  596 
Berzelius,  Jons  Jakob,  Swedish  chemist,  193, 

354.  371-374.  383.  406.  4M.  431.  596 
Bethe,  Albrecht,  German  psychologist,   540, 

601 
Bible,  the,  quoted  by  Linna:us,  107 
Bichat,  Marie  Francois  Xavier,  French  scien- 
tist, 181,  118,  191,  314,  330,  345-351,  353, 
354.  359.  361.  37^.  373.  376,  379.  384.  390. 
397.  398.  41^.  444.  446.  603 
Bijbel  der  Natuure,  collected  works  of  Swam- 

merdam,  168 
Binary  nomenclature,  worked  out  by  Linnasus, 

^13 

Biochemistry,  modern  developments  in,  594- 
598 

Biology,  development  of,  3-7;  Greek  specula- 
lations  in,  10-30;  influence  of  Plato  on,  33; 
contributions  of  Aristotle  to,  37-39,  43,  44; 
contribution  of  Galen  to,  64;  service  of 
Albertus  Magnus  to,  80;  progress  in  the 
Renaissance,  81-107;  niodern  development 
initiated  by  Harvey,  118;  contribution  of 
Descartes  to,  115;  contribution  of  Paracelsus 
to,  137;  its  debt  to  Malpighi  and  Grew, 
164;  contribution  of  Leeuwenhoek  to,  166; 
progress  in  17th  century,  111-173;  contribu- 
tion of  Linnaeus  to,  111;  ecological,  origi- 
nated by  Linna:us,  115;  influence  of  Buffon 
on.  111,  118;  progress  in  i8th  century, 
174-163;  aid  given  by  Kant  to,  17^1;  ad- 
vances in  beginning  of  19th  century,  301- 
351;  pioneer  work  by  Lamarck,  316-330;  im- 
portance of  Cuvier  to,  333-341;  discoveries 
of  Purkinje,  381;  importance  of  Darwin  to, 
477;  service  of  cytology  to,  541;  geograph- 
ical, 558-561;  modern  experimental  methods, 
574;   present  position  of,  603 

"Biology,"  term  created  by  Lamarck,  310 

Bismarck,  510,  513 

Blainville,  Henri  Marie  Ducrotay  de,  359-361, 
390,  441,  444,  445 

Blumenbach,  Johann  Friedrich,  German  anato- 
mist, 306-309,  333,  334,  354,  417,  415,  450, 

555 
Boerhaave,    Hermann,    Dutch   scientist,    153, 

168,  183-186,  104,  106,  134,  138,  140,  345, 

347.  444 
Bollstadt,  Albert  von,  see  Albertus  Magnus 

Bonnet,  Charles,  Swiss  scientist,  143-147, 148, 

■2-95.  ^97.  308,  317.  32-8,  334.  340.  415 
Bordeu,  Theophile  de,  French  scientist,  345, 
346,  348 


I  N 

Borelli,  Giovanni  Alfonso,  Italian  scientist, 
151-160,  174,  177,  185,  186,  130,  140,  305, 

Bostrom,  Kristofcr  Jakob,  Swedish  biologist, 

2-78 
Botany,  contribution  of  Theophrastus  to,  45; 
development  by  Arabs,  69;  systematized 
by  Linnxus,  2.09,  2.11;  during  the  i8th 
century,  152.;  development  after  Linnxus, 
435-440;     development    in    19th    century, 

551-558 
Bouin,  French  biologist,  596 
Bourignon,  Antoinette,  religious  mystic,  16S 
Boveri,  Theodor,  German  scientist,  535,  536, 

581 
Bowman,  William,  English  scientist,  540 

Boyle,  Robert,  chemist,   119,   175,   176,   179, 

^54.  ^75 

Brandis,  383 

Braun,  Alexander,  German  botanist,  551 

Breau,  Jean  Louis  Armand  de  Quatrefages  de, 
French  scientist,  484 

Brehm,  A.,  German  naturalist,  511 

Brewster,  2.85 

Broca,  307,  415 

Brogniart,  336 

Brown,  Robert,  Scottish  botanist,  391,  391, 
436, 561 

Brown-Sequard,  Charles  Edward,  French 
biologist,  568,  596 

Brunfels,  Otto,  botanist,  191,  192. 

Bruno,  Giordano,  pioneer  of  natural  science 
in  the  Renaissance,  49,  86,  87,  12.1,  132. 

Brunner,  353 

Buch,  Christian  Leopold  von,  German  ge- 
ologist, 455 

Buchner,  Eduard,  German  chemist,  549 

Biichner,  Friedrich  Karl  Christian  Ludwig, 
German  thinker,  451,  511 

Buckle,  Henry  Thomas,  English  historian,  459 

Buffon,  Georges  Louis  Leclerc  de,  French 
scientist,  his  life,  2.19,  no;  his  philosophy, 
2.11-12.3,  ^^8;  history  of  the  earth,  113,  114; 
biological  theory,  114-117;  influence  of, 
118,  119;  references  to,  130,  131,  141,  145, 
146,  170,  181,  194,  196,  197,  301,  304,  307, 
316,  317,  314,  318,  331,  334,  336,  337,  416, 

430.  453.  454>  484 
Bunge,  Gustav,  physiologist,  608 

Biitschli,  Otto,  German  scientist,  534-537, 
54^.  543.  545>  595 

Cabanis,  317,  351 

Cajal,  Santiago  Ram6n  y,  Spanish  scientist, 

539.  540 
Calvin,  persecutes  Servet,  no 


D  E  X  111 

Camerarius,  Rudolph  Jacob,  professor  ot 
medicine,  197,  198,  loc,  108,  155 

Campanella,  philosopher  of  the  Renaissance, 
106 

Camper,  Petrus,  Dutch  scientist,  159,  160, 
180,  181,  301,  305,  307,  309,  314,  333,  334 

Candolle,  Augustin  Pyramc  de,  Swiss  botan- 
ist, 436-438,  440,  466 

Canon  of  Medicine,  by  Abu  Sina,  71 

Carlyle,  Thomas,  561 

Carolinian  Institute,  founded  by  Berzelius,  371 

Carus,  Gustav  Carl,  German  philosopher,  190, 

543 
Cavendish,  165 

Cell,  smallest  form  of  living  substance,  539 

Cellular  physiology,  Verworn's  theory  of,  604 

Cellular  theory,  advanced  by  Wolff,  150,  151 

Celsius,  dean  of  Upsala,  patron  of  Linnxus, 
104 

Celsus,  99 

Cesalpino,  Andrea,  professor  of  medicine  in 
the  Renaissance,  106,  113,  117,  161,  191- 
196,  199,  107 

Challenger  expedition,  559 

Chamisso,  A.  von,  poet  and  circumnavigator. 
419 

Charles  Darwin  et  scs  prtcurseurs  frangais,  by  de 
Breau,  484 

Chemise  he  Briefe,  by  Liebig,  450 

Chemistry,  first  practised  as  a  science  by  the 
Arabs,  69;  contribution  of  Albertus  Magnus 
to,  80;  influence  of  Boyle  on,  119;  advance 
brought  about  by  Stahl  in,  180;  quantitative, 
founded  by  Lavoisier,  165;  contribution  of 
Berzelius  to,  371;  colloid,  595;  ferment,  596 

Chevalier,  French  microscopist,  389 

Chevreul,  434 

China,  medical  science  of,  7 

Christianismi  restitutio,  theological  work  by 
Servet,  no 

Chromosomes,  named  by  Waldeyer,  536 

Chwolson,  Russian  physicist,  514 

Circulation  of  the  blood,  ancient  ideas  of,  18, 
41,  64,  65,  108,  109;  ideas  of  the  Renais- 
sance, 111-114;  invention  of  the  term,  114; 
discovery  of,  115;    theory  of,  115,  116. 

Classes  flantarum,  botanical  work  by  Linna:us, 
110,  114 

Classification,  early  developemcnt  of,  190- 
101;  contribution  of  Linnaeus  to,  109, 111 

Climatology,  established  by  von  Humboldt, 

315 
Coelum  theory,  developed  by  the  Hertwigs, 

5^9.  530 
Colloid  chemistry,   modern   development   of, 

595 


IV  IN 

Columbus,  Realdo,  anatomist  of  the  Renais- 
sance, 104,  112.,  116 

Columella,  Lucius  Junius  Moderatus,  Roman 
naturalist,  53 

Comparative  histology,  contribution  of  Ru- 
dolphi  to,  353 

Comparative  morphology,  advances  in,  369 

Comte,  Isidore  Auguste  Marie  Francois  Xavier, 
French  philosopher,  441-447,  450,  452.,  459, 

493 
Condillac,  French  philosopher,  304,  32.7,  340, 

Conservation  of  energy  theory,  discovery  of, 
407-410 

Controverses  transformistes,  by  Giard,  567 

Cope,  D.  E.,  American  scientist,  568 

Copernicus,  Nicolaus,  astronomer  of  the  Ren- 
aissance, 14,  85,  86 

Correns,  Carl,  German  biologist,  591 

Corti,  Italian  cytologist;  396 

Cosmology,  Ionian  conceptions,  10-13; 
Pythagorean  conception,  14 

Cossus  ligtiiperda,  monograph  by  Lyonet,  133 

Cours  de  philosophic  positive,  by  Comte,  443 

Cours  de  physiologic,  by  Plainville,  360 

Cuenot,  L.,  French  biologist,  592. 

Cusanus,  Nicolaus,  churchman  and  scholar  of 
the  Renaissance,  84,  85,  1x2.,  131 

Cuvier,  Georges  Leopold  Chretien  Frederic 
Dagobert,  French  biologist,  98,  169,  iz8, 
2.46,  147,  X97,  198,  307,  311,  32.4,  32.8-344, 

35^.  354.  355'  357-360,  361,  365.  387,  415. 
416,  4^1,  415,  437,  444,  451,  454,  465,  469, 
483,  567,  610 
Cytology,  development  of,  390-405;    progress 
of,  in  19th  century,  533-544 

Darstellung  meines  Systems,  paper  by  Schelling, 

2-75 
Darwin,  Charles  Robert,  English  biologist, 
life  of,  461-464;  geological  works,  465,  466; 
theory  of  variations,  467,  468;  evolution 
theory,  468-471;  geography  of,  469;  theory 
of  heredity,  471;  pangenesis  theory,  472.; 
on  the  descent  of  man,  473;  sexual  selection 
theory,  474;  general  philosophy,  475; 
judgments  on,  476;  references  to,  131,  157, 
191,  196,  301,  304,  316,  318,  357,  416,  447, 

452->  453.  457-460,  477-497,  501,  506,  507, 
511,  514-516,  519,  515,  555,  562.,  563,  566, 

569.  571,  572-,  584,  587,  59O'  591.  601,  615 
Darwin,  Erasmus,  English  scientist,  194-196, 

313 
Daru'iniana,  by  Gray,  491 

Darwinism,    development    in    England    and 

Germany,  491 


D  E  X 

Daubenton,  Louis,  French  anatomist,  110, 117, 
118,  i8i,  196,  197,  301,  303,  305,  307,  308, 

333>  334 
Davaine,  Casimir  Joseph,   French  physician, 

547 
Da  Vinci,  Leonardo,  as  pioneer  in  anatomy, 

98.  99.  453 
D'Azyr,  Felix  Vicq,  French  scientist,  304-306, 

308,  318,  333-336,  371,  416 
Dc  cerebro  anatomical  work  by  Swedenborg,  187 
De  dijferentiis  animalium,  by  Edward  Wotton, 

93 
De  Graaf,  Reinier,  Dutch  physician  and  scien- 
tist, 171,  171,  180,  186,  130,  363 
T)c  humani  corporis  jabrica,  anatomical  work  by 

Vesalius,  101 
De  r organisation  dcs  animaux,  by  Blainville,  360 
Dc  motu  animalium,  biological  work  by  Borelli, 

151-153 
De  naturis  rerum,  mediicval  treatise  on  natural 

history  and  science,  80 
De  ovi  ynammalium  genesi,  by  von  Baer,  363 
De  piscibus  marinis,  by  Rondelet,  96 
De    Plantis,    botanical    work    by    Pesalpino, 

191 
De  re  anatomica,  by  Columbus,  104 
De    trinitatis    erroribus,    religious    treatise    by 

Server,  no 
De  valvula  coli,   medical   treatise,   by  Lieber- 

kiihn,  159 
De  Vries,  Hugo,  Dutch  biologist,  557,  587- 

589.  591.  59^.  595.  603 
Delage,  Yves,  French  scientist,  583 
Democritus,  Greek  natural  philosopher,  10-11, 

2-9-32-,  37,  4o>  43.  45-47,  107,  III,  571 
Desault,  patron  of  Bichat,  346 
Descartes,  Rene,  French  philosopher,  113-118, 

141,  148,  149,  153,  174,  187,  101,  116,  140, 

310,  316,  443,  445,  599 
Descent  oj  Man,  and  Selection  in  Relation  to  Sex, 

by  Darwin,  473 
Des  epoques  de  la  nature,  essay  by  Buffon,  113, 

114 
Dichogamy,  discovered  by  Sprengel,  157 
Die  Lebenskraft  oder  der  rhodische  Genius,  philo- 
sophical work  by  von  Humboldt,  315 
Die  Lebenswutider,  by  Haeckel,  515 
Die  Kadiolarien,  by  Haeckel,  505 
Die  Wahlverwandtschaften,  romance  by  Goethe, 

510 
Die  Weltrdtsel,  by  Haeckel,  514 
Diogenes  of  Apollonia,  philosopher  of  Ionian 

school,  13 
Dioscorides,  Greek  philosopher,  191 
Dohrn,  Anton,  559 
Dolland,  English  mechanician,  389 


I  N 

Dollinger,      Ignaz,     German      professor      of 

anatomy,  363 
Dominant  and  recessive  characters,  discovered 

by  Mendel,  591 
Driesch,  Hans,  580,  581,  608-610 
Du   Bois-Reymond,   Emil,    German  scientist, 

388,  411-413.  52-1 
Diihring,  E.,  German  lecturer  in  philosophy, 

410 
Dujardin,    Felix,   French  scientist,   42.8,    419, 

508 
Dumerie,  pupil  of  Cuvier,  333 
Dutrochet,  377 
Dzierzon,  Johann,  apiculturist,  410 

Ecological   biology,   originated   by  Linna:us, 

2-15 
Egypt,  development  of  medical  knowledge  in, 

6;  development  of  biological  knowledge  in, 

Ehrenberg,  Christian  Gottfried,  German 
scientist,  413,  42-7-42-9.  43 1 

Ehrlich,  Paul,  German  scientist,  540,  597 

Eimer,  Theodor,  German  biologist,  570,  573 

Eleatic  school  of  philosophy,  15 

Embryology,  advanced  by  Fabrizio,  105; 
pioneer  work  by  Wolff  in,  2.48;  progress  in 
19th  century,  361-369;  influence  of  Dar- 
winism on,  519-531;  experimental,  created 
by  Roux,  579 

Empedocles,  early  Greek  philosopher,  16,  17, 
30,  40,  44,  47,  141,  453;  cosmogony  of,  17- 
18;   scientific  influence  of,  18 

Enchiridion,  by  Endlicher,  439 

Endlicher,  Stephen  Ladislaus,  Austrian  botan- 
ist, 438,  439 

Endocrine  glands,  discovery  of,  597 

Engelmann,  Theodor  Wilhelm,  German  scien- 
tist, 541 

Engler,  Adolf,  German  scientist,  561 

Entdeckte  Geheimnis  der  Natur  im  Bau  mid  in  der 
Befruchtung  der  Bliimen,  Das,  botanical  work 
by  Sprengel,  156 

Entelechy  theory  of  life  expounded  by 
Driesch,  609 

Entomostraca  Dania,  by  O.  F.  Miiller,  417 

Entoxporum  historia  naturalis,  work  on  parasites 
by  Rudolphi,  353 

Entwickelungsgeschichte  der  Unke,  by  Goethe,  531 

Entivicklungsgeschichte  der  Cepfjalopoden,  mono- 
graph by  KoHiker,  401 

Entwicklungsgeschichte  des  Menschen  und  der  ho- 
heren  Tiere,  text-book  by  Kolliker,  400 

Epicurus,  Greek  philosopher,  46,  47,  61,  116 

Epigenesis  theory,  introduced  by  Harvey,  118, 
2.30;   developed  by  Wolff,  151,  361 


D  E  X  V 

Epitome,  compendium  of  Vesalius's  anatomical 
works,  ID! 

Erasistratus  of  Cheos,  founder  of  medical 
school,  51 

Erster  Entwurf  einer  allgemeinen  Einleitung  in  die 
vergleichende  Anatomie,  by  Goethe,  181 

Esenbeck,  Christian  Gottfried  Daniel  Nees 
von,  German  botanist,  189,  190,  191,  383, 
436 

Essais  de  la  physique,  biological  essays  by 
Perrault,  154 

Eugenics,  created  by  Galton,  587 

Eustacchi,  Bartolommeo,  professor  of  medi- 
cine, 106,  158 

Evolution,  Anaximander's  theory  of,  11; 
Aristotle's  view  of,  37,  43;  as  maintained  by 
Darwin,  468-476;  expounded  by  Spencer, 
494-497;  championed  by  Haeckel,  506;  as 
defined  by  Giard,  567 

Exercitationes  de  generationt  animalium,  by 
Harvey,  117 

Experimental   heredity-research,   583-594 

Experimental  morphology,  574-583 

Experimental  plant-biology  created  by  Sachs, 

575 
Experimental  research,  development  of,  370- 

388,  406 
Expression  of  the  Emotions  in  Man  and  Animals, 

by  Darwin,  475 

Fabricius,  John  Christian,  pupil  of  Linna;us, 

117,  362. 
Fabrizio,    Girolamo,    professor   of  medicine, 

105,  106,  116,  117,  161 
Fallopio,  Gabriele,  professor  of  medicine,  104, 

105,  171 
Farbenlehre,  by  Goethe,  181 
Fauna  der  Kie/er  Bucht,  Die,  by  Mobius,  559 
Fechner,  Theodor,  599 
Federley,  H.,  Danish  biologist,  594 
Ferment  chemistry,  modern  development  of, 

596 
Fertilization,  elucidation  of,  541 
Feuerbach,  Ludwig,  German  philosopher,  447 
Fichte,  Johann  Gottlieb,  German  philosopher, 

2-73.  2.74.  2-77 
Filament  theory  of  protoplasm,  advanced  by 

Flemming,  536,  537 
Fischer,  Kuno,  German  philosopher,  500 
Flemming,  Walter,  Austrian  cytologist,  534- 

537,  539,  541,  543 

Flourens,  Marie  Jean  Pierre,  French  physiolo- 
gist, 377 

Fluxions,  by  Newton,  119 

Fol,  Hermann,  Swiss  scientist,  534,  535,  541, 
543 


vi  IN 

Forel,  Auguste,  Swiss  psychologist,  6oi 
Forskal,  Peter,  Swedish  scientist,  ±i6 
Fourcroy,  Antonie  Francois  de,  French  chem- 
ist, 370-371 
Fracastoro,  Girolamo,  Italian  physician,  546 
Franke,  founder  of  Halle  University,  178 
Frederick  II,  emperor  and  scholar,  79 
Frederick  II,  of  Prussia,  139 
Freie  Wissenschaft  mid  freit  Lehre,  pamphlet  by 

Haeckel  on  education,  52.2. 
Fresnel,  2.85 

Fries,  Elias,  Swedish  botanist,  439,  440 
Fries,  Jacob  Friedrich,  German  philosopher, 

393 

Froth    theory    of    protoplasm    advanced    by 

Biitschli,  536,  537 
Fuchs,  Leonard,  professor  of  medicine,   191, 

194 
Fundamenta  hotanka,  botanical  work  by  Lin- 

na:us,  iio,  xii 
Fiinjzjg  Jahre  Sta7fim€sgeschkhte,   by   Haeckel, 

Fur  Darwin,  paper  by  F.  Miiller,  517 
Fiirbringer,  Max,  disciple  of  Gegenbaur,  503, 

515 

Galapagos  Islands,  visited  by  Darwin,  463 
Galen,  Greek  physician  and  biologist,  60-65, 
69,  71,  76,  83,  91,  98-104,  108-111,  113,  137, 

138.  375 
Galilei,  Galileo,  scientist  of  the  Renaissance, 

43,  89-91,  113,  116-118,  12-1,  115,  116,  119, 

130,  141,  151,  151,  154,  181,  113,  175,  373, 

376,  378,  385,443,444,  515 
Gall,   Franz  Joseph,   German   physician   and 

scientist,  310-311,  355,  445,  446 
Galton,   Francis,   English  scientist,   585-587, 

589,  590 
Galvani,  344 
Gartner,  Karl  Friedrich,  German  scientist,  468, 

584 
Gas,  invention  of  name,  139 
Gassendi,    Pierre,    philosopher,    opponent   of 

Descartes,  116,  154 
Gay-Lussac,  449 
Geber,  Arabian  alchemist,  70 
Geer,  Charles  de,  Swedish  naturalist,  131 
Gegenbaur,  Carl,  German  biologist,  359,  469, 

499-505.  511-51^.  5^^'  532-,  541.  613 
Genera  flantarum,  by  Endlicher,  439 
Genera  flantartwi,  by  Jussieu,  435 
Gcnerelk  Morphologic  der  Organismen,  by  Haeckel , 

417,  444,  511 
Geography,    established    as    science    by    von 

Humboldt,  315;    vegetable,  created  by  von 

Humboldt,  315 


D  E  X 

Geology,  development  of,  453-457 

Geological  Evidence  on  the  Antiquity  of  Man,  by 

Lyell,  485 
Geschichte  der  biologischen  Theorien  der  Neuzeit, 

by  Radl,  498,  610 
Geschichte  der  Botanik,  by  Sachs,  551,  575 
Geschichte  des  Materialistnus,  by  Lange,  450 
Gesner,  zoologist  of  the  Renaissance,  56,  93, 

94>  19^ 
Giard,  Alfred,  French  biologist,  567 
Gladstone,  in  controversy  with  Huxley,  490 
Glisson,  Francis,  professor  of  medicine,  147, 

148,  149,  156 
Goebel,  Karl  Eberhard,  German  scientist,  577 
Goethe,  Johann  Wolfgang  von,  117,  193,  115, 
138,  147,  173,  174,  176,  179-185,  187-193, 
196,  198,  310,  330,  341,  356,  359,  367,  368, 
38c^3S4,  387,  393,  441,  494,  501,  511,  511, 
514,  515,  510,  516,  551,  551,  578 
Goette,   Alexander    Wilhelm,   German   scien- 
tist, 531 
Golgi,  Camillo,  Italian  scientist,  539 
Granule  theory  of  protoplasm,  advanced  by 

Altmann,  536,  538 
Grassi,   Giovanni  Baptista,  Italian  scientist, 

549 
Gravitation,  discovered,  119 

Gray,  Asa,  American  botanist,  491,  491 

Greece,  first  to  develop  natural  science,  5,  8; 
national  character  of,  8;  religion  of,  8,  9; 
educational  system  of,  9;  early  scientists  of, 
10-19;  natural  philosophy  of,  11,  13; 
medical  science  of,  15,  16 

Grew,  Nehemiah,  English  physician  and 
scientist,  161-164,  ^97>  ^°°'  ^^4'  39° 

Grisebach,  August  Heinrich,  German  scien- 
tist, 561 

Grundriss  der  Physiologic,  text-book  by 
Rudolphi,  354 

Grinid'zuge  der  wissenschajtlichen  Botanik,  text- 
book by  Schleiden,  393 

Haeckel,  Ernst  Heinrich,  German  biologist, 
life  of,  505-508;  works  of,  508-510,  511, 
515,519;  philosophy  of,  511;  morphology 
of,  5 11;  mechanical  interpretation  of  nature, 
513;  biogcnetical  principle  of,  516-519; 
references  to,  117,  131,  185,  318,  319,  330, 

358.  359.  393.  399.  403.  413.  417.  444-447, 
469,  473,  491,  499,  500,  511  513-52.6,   519, 

531-534.  542-,   544,   551-554.  562.,  564.  566, 

568,  570,  571,  573,  578,  579,  598,  599,  603, 

608,  613,  616 
Hcemastaticks,  scientific  treatise  by  Hales,  154 
Hales,  Stephen,   English   botanist,  119,  151- 

2-54.  2-65,  370 


I  ND 

Haller,  Albrecht  von,  Swiss  scientist,  134-138, 
144,  149,  195,  303,  349,  364,  370,  374,  379 

Hamm,  Dutch  biological  student,  166 

Haiidbuch  der  Gewebelehre  des  Menschen,  by  K61- 
liker,  400 

Handbuch  der  Physiologic  des  Menschen,  by  Miil- 
ler,  384 

Hansen,  Emil  Kristian,  Danish  biologist,  548 

Hansen,  F.  C.  C,  Danish  scientist,  541 

Harrison,  English  biologist,  616 

Harting,  405 

Hartmann,  Eduard  von,  German  philosopher, 

Hartmann,  M.,  pupil  of  Schaudinn,  550 
Harvey,  William,  English  scientist,  61,  in, 

114,  118,  111,  114,  115,  141,  141,  144-147, 

149,  151,  158,  161,  169,  170,  139,  151,  158, 

361,  379,  430,  541,  541 
Hasselqvist,  F.,  pupil  of  Linnxus,  116 
Hedwig,  Johann,  Hungarian  botanist,  439 
Heer,  Oswald,  Swiss  scientist,  561 
Hegel,    Georg    Wilhelm    Friedrich,    German 

philosopher,  178, 198,  393,  450,  516,  551,  556 
Heidenhain,   Martin,   German  scientist,    535, 

538 
Heidenhain,   Rudolf,    German   scientist,   535, 

539 
Hellwald,     F.     von,     German     geographical 

writer,  511 
Helmholtz,     Hermann     Ludwig      Ferdinand, 

German  scientist,  388,  408-410,  411,  413, 

5^6,  541 
Helminthology,  advanced  by  Siebold,  410 
Henle,  Jacob,  German  scientist,  388,  397-398, 

400,  401,  546,  608 
Hensen,  Victor,  German  scientist,  559 
Heracleitus  of  Ephesus,  early  Greek  philoso- 
pher, 19,  II,  18,  44 
Herbarum  viva  eicones,  botanical  work  by  Brun- 

fels,  191 
Herbst,  Curt,  German  scientist,  581 
Herder,  Johann  Gottfried,  German  poet  and 

student,  171,  173,  179-181,  331 
Heredity,  modern  experiments  in,  583-594 
Heribert-Nilsson,  Swedish  naturalist,  588,  614, 

615 

Herophilus,  teacher  in  the  Museum  at  Alexan- 
dria, 51 

Hertwig,  Oscar,  German  anatomist,  470,  503, 
518,  519,  533-535,  541,  543,  567-570,  574, 
579,  580,  616 

Hertwig,    Richard,    German    zoologist,    390, 

52-9.  533.  534.  545.  546,  582- 
Heyse,  Paul,  507 
Hildegard    of   Bingen,    nun    and    author    of 

Physica,  78 


EX  Vll 

Hindu  science,  7 

Hippo,  early  Greek  naturalist  and  philosopher, 

13 
Hippocrates,  Greek  pioneer  of  medical  science, 

16-18,  175, 177,  361 
His,  Wilhelm,  Swiss  scientist,  405,  518,  530, 

531,  540,  578 
Histoire  des  oyseaux,  by  Belon,  98 
Histoire  des  sciences  de  I'organisme,  by  Blainville, 

360 
Histoire  nature  lie,  by  Buff  on,  110 
Histoire     naturelle     de     I'dme,    work     by     La 

Mettrie,  139 
Histoire  naturelle  des  animaux,  by  Buffon,  114 
Histoire  naturelle  des  animaux  sans  verterbres,  by 

Lamarck,  310 
Histoire    naturelle    des    crustacees,     by    Milne- 
Edwards,  415 
Histoire  naturelle  des  estranges  poissons  marins, 

monograph  by  Belon,  97 
Histologie  du  systeme  nerveux,  by  Ramon  y  Cajal, 

540 
Historia    animalium,     biological    treatise    by 

Gesner,  93,  94 
Historia  plantarum  generalis,  botanical  work  by 

Ray,  199 
Historia  Stirpium,  botanical  work  by  Fuchs, 

191 
History  of  Philosophy  of  Later  Times,  by  Hoff- 

ding,  441 
Hobbes,  Thomas,  116 
Hoffding,  516,  599 
Hoffmann,  Friedrich,   professor  of  medicine, 

176-178,  185-188,  106,  140 
Hofmeister,   Wilhelm,  German  botanist,   558 
Hohenheim,  Theophrastus,  see  Paracelsus 
Holbach,  168 

Holmgren,  Emil,  Swedish  scientist,  541 
Homme  machine,  L' ,  polemic  by  La  Mettrie,  139, 

140 
Hofno    duplex,    anatomical    treatise    by    Dau- 

benton,  118 
Homology,  term  created  by  Owen,  415 
Hooker,    Joseph    Dalton,    English    botanist, 

463,  491-495,  561 
Horses  of  Elberfeld,  601 
Hubrecht,  A.  A.  W.,  Dutch  scientist,  504 
Humboldt,  Alexander  von,  German  scientist, 

314-316,  334,  344,  351,  397,  417,  436,  441, 

447.453.558.560 
Hume,  David,  Scotch  philosopher,  195,  491 
Hunter,  John,  Scotch  anatomist,  160-161,  309 
Hutton,  James,  Scotch  geologist,  454,  456 
Huxley,   Thomas   Henry,   English   biologist, 

417,  446,  473,  481,  485,  488-495,  501,  517, 

544 


VIU  INDEX 

Huygens,  155 

Hwasser,    Israel,    Scandinavian    philosopher, 

191,  193,  3ii,  373 
Hjdrachna,  by  O.  F.  Miiller,  42.7 

Ibn-Rushd,  see  Averroes 

Idea  of  a  New  Anatomy  of  the  Brain,  by   Bell, 

375 

Ideen  7ji  einer  Philosophie  der  Natur,  philo- 
sophical work  by  Schelling,  ^74 

Ideen  'Zjif  Philosophie  der  Geschichte  der  lAensch- 
heit,  philosophical  work  by  Herder,  2.73 

Idioplasma  theory,  developed  by  Nageli,  556 

Ilmoni,  Immanuel,  Finnish  philosopher,  193 

Infusionstierchen  a  Is  vollkommene  Organismen,  by 
Ehrenberg,  417 

Ingemarsson,  Nils,  father  of  Linnaeus,  103 

Ingenhousz,  Jan,  Dutch  scientist,  2.66, 2.67,  370 

Institutiones  medica,  by  Boerhaave,  185 

Internal  secretion,  process  of,  discovered  by 
Bernard,  596 

Ionic  philosophers,  earliest  of  Grecian  scien- 
tists, 10 

Isagoge  phytoscopica,  handbook  of  botanical 
study  by  Jung, 195 

Isis,  German  journal  of  science,  2.87 

Israelites,  their  conception  of  nature,  6 

Jacobsen,  founder  of  the  Karlsberg  laboratory, 
Jacobson,  Ludwig,  Swedish  biologist,  405,  4x4 

548 
Jager,  C,  German  naturalist,  511 
Janssen,  inventor  of  microscope,  158 
Johanssen,  Wilhelm  Ludwig,  Danish  biologist, 

89,  461,  565,  568,  57i,  588,  589,  591 
Jordan,  French  botanist,  614 
Joule,  J.  P.,  English  physicist,  408-410 
Jung,  Joachim,  botanist,  194,  195,  199,  109 
Jussieu,  Antoine  Laurent  de,  French  botanist, 

435.  436 
Jussieu,  Bernard  de,  French  botanist,  435,  436 

Kalkschwdmme,  Die,  by  Haeckel,  509 
Kalm,  Per,  Finnish  biologist,  2.16 
Kammerer,  569,  615 
Kampf  der  Teile  im  Organismus,  Der,  by  Roux, 

566 
Kant,  Emmanuel,  German  philosopher,  2.69- 

^75.  334.  340.  393.  447.  491.  5^6,  607 
Karlsberg  laboratory,  548 
Kepler,  52.5 

Keplerbund,  formation  of,  5x5 
Kielmayer,  Karl  Friedrich,  German  biologist, 

331 
Kleinenberg,  Nicolaus,  German  biologist,  532., 

578 


Klingenstierna,  Samue  ,  Swedish  physicist, 
389 

Koch,  Heinrich  Hermann  Robert,  German 
scientist,  540,  547-548.  55° 

Koelreuter,  Joseph  Gottlieb,  German  plant- 
physiologist,  154,  155,  156,  468,  584 

Kohlbrugge,  German  biologist,  453 

Kolliker,  Rudolf  Albert,  Swiss  biologist,  388, 
400,  401,  418,  481,  49i,  499,  505,  540,  551, 

570,  587 
Kosmos,  cosmology  by  von  Humboldt,  316 
Kowalewsky,   Alexander,   Russian   biologist, 

5^9 
Kraft  und  Staff,   popular   scientific    work    by 

Biichner,  451 
Kreislauf  des  Lebens,  by  Moleschott,  450 
Kristall-Seelen,  by  Haeckel,  515 
Kritik  der  reinen  Vernunft,  philosophical  work 

by  Kant,  170 

Lacaze-Duthiers,  Felix  Joseph  Henri,  French 

scientist,  415 
Lamarck,  Chevalier  de,  French  scientist,  12.8, 

Z46,  147,  196,  316-336,  339,  340,  343,  351, 

357-361.  416,  430,  437.  438.  446.  456-458. 
464,  467,  484,  489,  511,  555,  564 
La  Mettrie,  Julien  Offroy  de,  French  scientist, 
138-2.43,  145,  i6o,  z68,  177,  2.80,  2.95,  314, 

373 
Lang,  Arnold,  Swiss  anatomist,  5x9,  592. 

Lange,  Albert,  413,  450 

Lankester,  Edwin  Ray,  English  scientist,  530 

Latour,  Charles  Cagniard  de,  French  scientist, 

431 
Laveran,  Alphonse,  French  physician,  549 
Lavoisier,  Antoine  Laurent,  French  scientist, 

180,  2.65-2.67,  Z75,  313,  319,  334,  335,  370, 

407.  431 
Leche,  W.,  333 

Legofis  sur  l' anatomie  comparie,  by  Cuvier,  334 
Lectures  on  Animal  Chemistry,  by  Berzelius,  372. 
Leeuwenhoek,  Antony  van,  Dutch  scientist, 

158,  164-166,  170,  171,  180,  186,  2.30,  350, 

389,  42.6 
Lehmann,  Alfred,  pyschologist,  599,  601 
Lehmann,  Ernst,  614 

Lehrbuch  der  Botonik,  by  von  Esenbeck,  189 
Lehrbiich  der  Histologic,  by  Leydig,  401 
Lehrbuch  der  Naturphilosophie,  by  Oken,  2.88 
Lehrbuch  der  Physiologic,  by  Ludwig,  413 
Lehrbuch  der  vergleichenden  Anatomic,  by  Siebold 

and  Hannius,  417,  418 
Leibniz,  Gottfried  Wilhelm,  philosopher,  12.7, 

12.8,  130,  I4Z,  174,  177,  183,  ii5,  i2.i,  1x3, 

1x5,  i44,  Z45,  148 
Leucippus,  early  Greek  philosopher,  2.0 


INDEX 


IX 


Leuckart,  Karl  Georg  Friedrich  Rudolf,  Ger- 
man zoologist,  411,  42.2.,  450,  563 
Leydig,  Franz,  German  cytologist,  401,  499 
Liberalism,  in  the  19th  century,  458 
Lieberkiihn,     Johann     Nathanael,      German 

scientist,  158,  159,  389 
Liebig,  Justus,  German  chemist,  431,  448,  449, 

450 
Linnaeus,  Carl,  Swedish  scientist,  life  of,  2.03- 

io6,  L09;   fame  of,  2.06;   philosophy  of,  zo6, 

107,  115,  L16;   as  a  systematician,  2.07,  2.10- 

115;   pupils  of,  XI6-2.I7;   references  to,  184, 

191,    193,    195,    198,    2.01,   12.0-2.2.2.,    2.16,   2.^7, 

130,  2.32.,  135,  155,  2.78,  z8l,  192.,  303,  308, 
315,  3^6,  32.7,  339,  340,  346,  417,  435-440, 
445,446,  514,  546,  560,  575,613 

Linne,  Carl  von,  son  of  Linnasus,  2.05,  2.06 

Linnean  Society,  founded,  lo6 

Lister,  547 

Little,  biologist,  616 

Locke,  English  philosopher,  175,  317 

Loeb,  Jacques,  member  of  Rockefeller  Insti- 
tute, 581,  583,  605,  606 

Loffler,  F.  J.  S.,  German  scientist,  548 

Lofling,  P.,  pupil  of  Linnasus,  ii6 

Lotsy,  J.  P.,  Dutch  biologist,  614 

Lotze,  German  philosopher,  450 

Lovcn,  Sven  Ludwig,  Swedish  biologist,  419, 
413,  414,  543 

Lubbock,  John,  Lord  Avebury,  601 

Lucretius,  Roman  philosopher,  47-49,  87, 
12.6,  154 

Ludwig,  Karl  Friedrich  Wilhelm,  German 
physiologist,  413,  414,  535 

Lyell,  Charles,  Scotch  geologist,  453,  455-457, 
464,  470,  485 

Lymphatic  system,  discovery  of,  144,  145 

Lyonet,  Pierre,  French  biologist,  133 

Lyser,  Michael,  professor  of  medicine,  144 

Mach,    Ernst,    Austrian   scientist,   52.6,    52.7, 

605 
Magendie,     Frangois,     French     professor     of 

medicine,  375-389,  384,  386,  406,  444 
Maillet,  de,  484 
Maistre,  Joseph  de,  French  author  and  posi- 

tivist,  441 
Malpighi,    Marcello,    professor   of  medicine, 

M9i  159-164,  166,  185,  188,  196,  ioo,  2.14, 

2.30,  2.51,  350,  361,  368,  373,  389,  390 
Malthus,  Thomas  Robert,  English  economist, 

453,  460,  464,  470,  486 
Manuel  d' actinologie  et  de  :(oophytologie,  by  Blain- 

ville,  360 
Marx,  Karl,  German  socialist,  447 
Materialism,  in  the  i8th  century,  2.68,  2.69 


Mayer,  Julius  Robert,  407-410,  448 
Mechanical    explanation    of   life-phenomena, 

151-158 
Mkhanique  des  animaux,  by  Perrault,  154 
Mechanische    Prinzip  im   anatomischen  Bau   der 

Monokotylen,  Das,  by  Schwcndener,  557 
Mechanisch-physiologische    Theorie    der    Abstam- 

mungslehre,  by  Nageli,  555 
Mechanism,  modern  theory  of,  603 
Meckel,  Johann  Friedrich,  German  scientist, 

355-359.  365,  367,  393.  516,  549 

Medicine,  beginning  of  science  of,  4,  5;  de- 
velopment in  Egypt,  6,  50;  development  in 
China,  7;  development  in  Greece,  2.5-2.6; 
contributions  of  Herophilus,  51,  51;  de- 
velopment by  Arabs,  69;  state  of,  in  By- 
zantine Empire,  74;  progress  in  the  Renais- 
sance, 99-107;  influence  of  Paracelsus  on, 
137;    development  in  17th  century,  141-150 

Meisenheimer,  J.,  German  biologist,  597 

Memoires  de  physique  et  d'histoire  naturelle,  by 
Lamarck,  318,  319,  310 

M-cmoires  pour  servir  i  I'  histoire  des  insectes,  by 
Reaumur,  2.31 

Mendel,  Gregor,  Austrian  biologist,  i55,  156, 
469,  471,  490,  557,  588,  590^592.,  604 

Mendel,  Johann,  see  Gregor  Mendel 

Mendelism,  spread  of,  592. 

Menscbenschopfung  und  Seelensubstanz.,  lecture  by 
Wagner,  450 

Mesmer,  344 

Methodus  plantarum,  botantical  work  by  Lin- 
naeus, 109 

Methodus  platitarum,  botanical  work  by  Ray, 

199 
Metschnikoff,  Ilja,  Russian  biologist,  508,  598 
Micella  theory  of  cells,  developed  by  Nageli, 

554 
Michaelis,  Caroline,  wife  of  Schelling,  2.74 
Microbiology,  developed  in  19th  century,  42.6- 

435,  544-550 
Micrographie,  by  Mohl,  391 

Micropyle,  discovered  by  Leuckart,  442. 

Microscope,  invention  of,  158;  improved  by 

Leeuwenhoek,    165;     development   in    19th 

century,  389 
Microscopical  anatomy  founded  by  Malpighi, 

159 
Microscopy,  science  of,   founded  by  Bichat, 

347;    advances  made  in  19th  century,  389, 

405 
Microtome,  introduced  by  His,  405 
Mikrographische  Beitrdge,  by  Nordmann,  412. 
Mikroscopische  Untersuchutigen  iiber  die  Uberein- 

stitnmung  in  der  Struktur  und  dem  Wachstum 

der  Tiere  und  Pflanzen,  by  Schwann,  394 


X  I  ND 

Mill,  James,  English  philosopher,  446 

Mill,  John  Stuart,  English  philosopher,  447, 

459 
Milne-Edwards,  Henri,  Belgian  scientist,  415, 

434 
Mirandola,  Pico  de,  Italian  mystic,  131 

Mirbel,  Charles  Frangois,  French  botanist,  390 

Mobius,  Karl  August,  German  scientist,  559 

Mohl,  Hugo,  German  scientist,  391,  396,  449 

Mohr,  O.  L.,  Norwegian  biologist,  594 

Moleschott,  Jacob,  Dutch  physiologist,  449, 

45^ 
Monad  theory,  ix8 

Monatliche  Insectenhelustigungen,  natural-history 

work  by  von  Rosenhof,  2.33 
Monet,  Jean  Baptiste  Pierre  Antoine  de,  set 

Lamarck 
Monism,  philosophical  theory,  516 
Monist  League,  formation  of,  52.5 
Morseus,  father-in-law  of  Linnaeus,  104 
Morgan,  Thomas  Hunt,  American  biologist, 

581,  591,  593,  615 
Morphology,  development  in  the  19th  century, 

414;  influence  of  Darwinism  on,  518-558 
Muhammed  el  Damiri,  Arabian  zoologist,  73 
Muller,  American  biologist,  616 
Miiller,  Fritz,  German  biologist,  469,  516-518 
Muller,  Heinrich,  405 
Muller,  Johannes  Peter,  German  scientist,  lyz, 

2-85,  375.  382.-388,  394-396,  398,  400,  402., 

403,  406,  409,  411-414,  417,  4ii,  42.4,  449, 

499.  505.  508,  516,  572. 
Muller,  Otto  Frcderik,  Danish  scientist,  4x6, 

4^7 
Museum  fiir  Volkerkunde,   founded   by  Vir- 

chow,  402. 
Mutation  theory,  advanced  by  de  Vries,  588 
Mystical  speculation  in  science,  1 31-140 

Nageli,  Karl  Wilhelm,  Swiss  botanist,  396, 
42-9>  535.  547,  551-557,  563,  565,  568,  570, 

575,  591 
Napoleon,  32.6,  331,  333 

Nathorst,  Alfred,  Swedish  scientist,  561 

Natur  und  Idee,  by  Carus,  2.90 

Natural  History,  by  Pliny,  53,  54 

Natural  History  of  Creation,  by  Haeckel,  591, 
607 

Natural  Inheritance,  by  Galton,  585 

Natural  philosophy,  character  of,  in  i8th  cen- 
tury, 186-198,  301 

Natural  selection,  as  adduced  by  Darwin,  464, 
470,  471;  upheld  by  Weismann,  566;  at- 
tacked by  Hertwig,  568;  defended  by  Plate, 
571;  as  applied  by  Roux,  579;  present-day 
view  of,  616 


E  X 

Nature  et  diversites  des  poissons.  La,  monograph 

by  Belon,  97 
Natiirliche  Schopfungsgeschichte,  series  of  lectures 

by  Haeckel,  515 
Needham,  English  microscopist,  430 
Neo-Darwinism,  561-573 
Neo-Lamarckism,  561-573 
Nernst,  595 
Nettesheim,   Heinrich  von,  German  mystic, 

132- 

Neut  Lehre  vom  Zftitrakn  Nervensystem,  by  Radl, 
610 

Neumeister,  R.,  physiologist,  608 

Neurologis  universalis,  work  on  the  nervous 
system  by  Vieussens,  150 

New  M.a?nf?ial  Species  from  the  Kodentia,  biologi- 
cal work  by  Pallas,  163 

Newton,  Isaac,  English  scientist,  43,  91,  119- 
131,  155,  177,  181,  113,  153,  170,  175,  176, 
181,  1S3,  376,  389,  476 

Nietzsche,  561 

Nilsson-Ehle,  H.,  Swedish  biologist,  591 

Nissl,  Friedrich,  German  physician,  540 

Nordmann,  Alexander  von,  German  biologist, 

42-^-,  4^3 
Novum  Organum,  by  Francis  Bacon,  87 

Observationes  anatomicce,   anatomical   work   by 

Fallopio,  104 
CEconomia  natura,  treatise  by  Linnaeus,  115 
Oken,  Lorenz,  German  philosopher,  184,  187- 

189,  191,  354,  366,  383,  387,  400,  415,  416, 

489,  501,  511,  515,  551 
Old  Testament,  record  of  Israelitic  conception 

of  nature,  6 
On  Air  and  Fire,  chemical  treatise  by  Sheele, 

164 
On  Coral  Reefs,  by  Darwin,  465 
On  Diet,  early  Greek  medical  treatise,  19 
On    Nature,    philosophical    poem    by    Anaxi- 

mander,  11 
On  the  glands,  by  Bordeu,  345 
On  the  Habits  of  Animals,  by  Claudius  /Elianus, 

On  the  History  of  Animals,  biological  work  by 

Aristotle,  37 
On  the  Nature  of  Things,  philosophical  poem  by 

Lucretius,  47 
On  the  Origin  of  Species  by  Means  of  Natural 

Selection,  by  Darwin,  465,  471,  473 
On  the  Parts  of  Animals,  biological  work  by 

Aristotle,  37 
On  the  Relations  of  Numbers  in  connexion  with  the 

Movements  of  Animals,  treatise  by  Muller,  383 
On  the  Reproduction  of  Animals,  biological  work 

by  Aristotle,  37 


I  ND 

On  the  Soul,  biological  work  by  Aristotle,  37 
On    Volcanic    Islands,    geological    treatise    by 

Darwin,  465 
Ophthalmascope,  invented  by  Hclmholtz,  409 
"Opsonins,"  discovery  of,  598 
Opuscula  anatomka,  treatise  by  Eustacchi,  106 
Ordo  plantarum,  botanical  work   by   Rivinus, 

195 
Organic  chemistry,  370,  371;   development  of, 

406 
Organische    Bewegung    in    ihrtm    Zusammenhange 

mit   dem   Stojfwechsel,    essay    on    energy    by 

Mayer,  408 
Organographie,  by  de  Candolle,  438 
Origin  of  species,  Darwin's  theory  of,  465 
Orsted,  2.77 

Osteographie,  by  Blainville,  360 
Osteology,  Greek  study  of,  z8 
Overton,    Charles    Ernest,    English    scientist, 

595 
Ovists,    school    of    18th-century    biologists, 

17}.  2.30 
Owen,  Richard,  English  anatomist,  414-417, 
4x8,  441,  478,  479,  489,  502. 

Palaeontology,  contribution  of  Steno  to,  157; 

pioneer  work  of  Cuvier,  337 
Pallas,   Peter  Simon,   German  scientist,  1.60, 

^62.,  353 
Pander,  Heinrich  Christian,  German  scientist, 

363,  368-369,  517 
Pangenesis  theory  of  Darwin,  471 
Paracelsus,  133-139,  177,  180,  2.69,  2.79,  611 
Paramirum,  work  on  science  by  Paracelsus,  135, 

136 
Parasitic  research,  pioneer  work  by  Rudolphi 

in.  353 
Parmenides,    Greek    philosopher    of    Eleatic 

school,  15-18,  zo 

Parthenogenesis,  discovered  by  Bonnet,  144 

Pasteur  Institutes,  establishment  of,  432. 

Pasteur,  Louis,  French  scientist,  432.-435,  449, 

5V.  546,  548.  549.  554>  571.  597 
Paulus   of  /Egina,    Byzantine   physician    and 

author,  74,  75 
Pauly,  August,  German  biologist,  571,  6iz 
Pecquet,  Jean,  medical  student,  143,  144 
Perigenesis  der  Plastiduh,  Die,  by  Haeckel,  519 
Peripatetic  Problems,  by  Cesalpino,  113,  114 
Perrault,  Claude,  French  physician  and  archi- 
tect, i53-i55>  158,  174.  177.  MO.  305.  310 
Petersen,  C.  G.  J.,  Danish  scientist,  559 
Pfeffer,  Wilhelm,  German  botanist,  576,  578, 

589.  595 
Pflaniengeographie  auf  physiologischer  Grundlage, 

by  Schimpfcr,  561 


EX  XI 

Phagocyte  theory,  produced  by  MctschnikofF, 

598 
Pharmacology,  beginnings  of,  5;  development 

by  Arabs,  69 
Phonological  biology,  originated  by  Linnaeus, 

ZI5 
Philosophica  botanica,  by  Linnaeus,  Z14,  2.82.,  437 
Philosophie  chimique,  by  de  Fourcroy,  371 
Philosophic  zpologique,   by   Lamarck,  yio,  32.3, 

314,  3i6,  330 
Philosophy,  origin  of  term,  11 
Phlogiston,  chemical  theory  invented  by  Stahl, 

179,  180,  x64,  z65 
Physica,  mediaeval  treatise  on  natural  history, 

78 

Physiologic  vigetale,  by  de  Candolle,  438 

Physiologus,  medixval  treatise  on  natural  his- 
tory, 78 

Physiology,  early  ideas  of,  3,  4,  5;  Greek  de- 
velopment of,  x-j,  18;  Aristotle's  conception 
of,  41;  aid  of  Paracelsus  to,  137;  contribu- 
tion of  Haller  to,  Z35, 136;  evolutional,  578 

Pinax  theatri  botanici,  botanical  work  by 
Bauhin,  194 

Plate,  Ludwig,  German  biologist,  572.,  573 

Plato,  Greek  philosopher,  19,  31-33,  41,  48, 
59,  61,  65,  76,  IZ3,  190,  z69,  611 

Pliny,  Roman  natural  philosopher,  53-57,  65, 
73,  80,  94,  191,  XXi 

Plotinus,  founder  of  neo-Platonism,  66 

Politia  natura,  treatise  by  Linnaeus,  2.15 

Polo,  Marco,  81 

Positive  philosophy,  system  developed  by 
Comtc,  443 

Positivism,  as  a  conception  of  nature,  441 

Pouchet,  Felix  Archimede,   French  scientist, 

433.  434.  479.  571 
Precipitin  reaction,  discovered  by  Uhlenhuth, 

598 
Preformation  theory,  developed  by  Swammer- 

dam,    170,    12.5,  x3o;  Bonnet's  conception, 

Z45,  2.48,  149-151,  3 6z 
Prenant,  Auguste,  French  scientist,  541 
Priestlev,  John,  English  chemist,  i8o,  164, 165 
Principle  of  Population,  The,  by  Malthus,  460 
Principles  of  Geology,  by  Lyell,  456 
Pringsheim,  Nathaniel,  German  botanist,  558 
Printing,  its  service  to  the  spread  of  scientific 

knowledge,  91,  94,  99 
Prodromus,  botanical  work  by  Bauhin,  194 
Prodrotnus  systematis  naturalis  regni  vegetahilis, 

by  de  Candolle,  437 
Prometheus,  poetical  work  by  Goethe,  z8o 
Protagoras,  founder  of  Sophist  philosophy,  14 
Protozoa,  investigations  of,  545 
Prowazek,  S.,  pupil  of  Schaudinn,  550 


xii  I N 

Psychiatry,  reformed  by  Reil,  311 
Psychology,  animal,  599,  601,  601;   insect,  600 
Psycho-physics,  discovered  by  La  Mettrie,  2.41 
Punnett,  R.  C,  English  biologist,  591 
Purkinjc,  Johannes  Evangelista,  Czech  scien- 
tist, 2.85,  36},  380-383,  417,  414,  575 
Pyrrho  of  Elis,  Greek  philosopher,  50 
Pythagoras,  early  Greek  scientist,  13,  14,  16, 

17,  32->  12.3 
Pythagorean  philosophy,  13,  14 

Quastiones   naturales,    philosophical    work    by 
Seneca,  107 

Rabl,  Karl,  German  scientist,  544 

Radl,  Emmanuel,   Hungarian   biologist,   470, 

477.  498.  610-611 
Ranvier,  Louis  Antoine,  French  scientist,  540, 

541 
Rathke,  Martin  Heinrich,  German  scientist, 

363,  364,  366-368,  382.,  384,  386,  489 
Rauber,  August,  German  anatomist,  578 
Ray,  John,  scientist,   198,   199-2.01,  108-111, 

2-2-3.  435.  436 
Reaumur,  Rene  Antoine  Ferchault  de,  French 

scientist,  131,  131,  143,  490 
Kecherches  sur  les  ossemens  fossihs,   by  Cuvier, 

337,  338 
Recherches    sur  I' organisation   des   corps   vivants, 

biological  work  by  Lamarck,  310,  311,  313, 

3M 
Redi,  Francesco,  Florentine  physician,  430 
Kegne  animal,  anatomical  work  by  Cuvier,  333, 

339 
Reichert,  Karl  Bogislaus,  German  cytologist, 

398-400 

Keign   of  Law,  The,    by  the  Duke  of  Argyle, 

491 
Reil,  Johann  Christian,  German  scientist,  311- 

314.  354.  355,  37^ 
Reincke,  J.,  German  botanist,  515,  608 

Rejuvenation  experiments,  597 

Remak,  Robert,  German  scientist,  388,  399- 

400,  517 
Retzius,  Anders  Adolf,  Swedish  biologist,  193, 

307,  414,  415 
Retzius,  Gustaf,  son  of  Anders  Retzius,  540, 

541,  543 
Rivinus,     Augustus    Quirinus,     professor    of 

medicine,  195,  196, 100, 108 
Rollett,  Alexander,  German  scientist,  541 
Romanes,  George  John,  English  psychologist, 

599.  601 
Romanticism,  as  a  conception  of  nature,  441 
Rondelet,  Guillaume,  biologist  of  the  Renais- 
sance, 96,  97 


D  E  X 

Rosenberg,  H.  O.,  Swedish  biologist,  594 
Rosenhof,  August  Roesel  von,  German  natural- 
ist, 133 
Ross,  Ronald,  English  scientist,  549 
Rothman,  teacher  of  Linnaeus,  103 
Rousseau,  J.  J.,  459 
Roux,  Wilhelm,  German  biologist,  531,  566, 

578-580,  604,  608,  610 
Royal  Society,  founding  of,  147 
Royal  Society  of  Medicine  in  France,  founding 

of,  301 
Rudbeck,  Olof,  145-147,  187,  159 
Rudbeckius,  Johannes,  bishop,  145 
Rudolphi,  Carl  Asmund,  German  anatomist, 

352--355.  358.  375,  38^,  384-386,  417,  418, 
411,  413,  431 
Ruysch,  Frederic,  Dutch  physician  and  scien- 
tist, 170,  171,  185 

Sachs,  Julius,  German  botanist,  551,  575-578, 
580,  587,  605 

Saint-Hilaire,  Etienne  GeofFroy,  French  bi- 
ologist, 196-198,  305,  317,  331,  333,  336, 

341.  343,  355.  356,  358,  416,  437,  441,  483, 

511,  610 
Saint-Hilaire,  Isidore,  French  biologist,  198 
Sakarja  ben  Muhammed,  "el  Kasvini,"  natural 

historian  of  Arabia,  73 
Sars,  Michael,  Norwegian  zoologist,  367,  419, 

4^3  _  ^ 

Saussure,  Nicholas  Theodore  de,  Swiss  scien- 
tist, 166,  167,  575 

Schaudinn,  Fritz,  German  scientist,  550 

Scheele,  Carl  Wilhelm,  German  scientist,  180, 
164,  370 

Schelling,  Friedrich  Wilhelm  Joseph,  German 
philosopher,  173,  174-177,  178,  181,  183, 
186,  188,  189,  191-193,  197,  313,  330.  342-, 
354.  356.  393.  511.  513.  52-6,  553 

Schiller,  381 

Schimper,  Andreas  Franz  Wilhelm,  Swiss 
scientist,  561 

Schimper,  Karl  Friedrich,  German  botanist, 

551 
Schleiden,  Matthias  Jacob,  German  scientist, 

39^-394.  395.  396,449.  505,  552- 
Schmidt,  J.,  German  scientist,  559 
Schultze,    Max  Johann    Sigismund,    German 

biologist,  403-405,  500,  508,  533 
Schwann,     Theodor,     German    professor    of 

anatomy,     388,     394^395.    398,    399,    431, 

433 
Schwendener,  Simon,  Swiss  biologist,  557 
Science  de  I'hotnme,  by  Barthez,  345 
Scotus,  Michael,  translator  of  Aristotle,  79 
Sedgwick,  Adam,  English  geologist,  461 


IN 

Selektioiuprinz.ip    und   Probhnie   der   Artbildung, 

by  Plate,  572. 
Semon,  Richard,  German  biologist,  570 
Semper,  Karl,  German  biologist  and  explorer, 

560 
Seneca,  Roman  philosopher,  107 
Serology,  modern  development  of,  597 
Server  y  Reves,  Miguel,  109-112. 
Servetus,  Michael,  see  Server  y  Reves 
Severino,   Marc'   Aurelio,   Italian   anatomist, 

106,  107 
Sexual  selection  theory  of  Darwin's,  474 
Sexuality  of  plants,  197,  198 
Shaksjxre,  602. 
Siebold,    Karl   Theodor   Ernst    von,    German 

biologist,  417-42.1,  42-1,  419 
Smith,  William,  English  palaeontologist,  454, 

455 
Socrates,  Athenian  philosopher,  31,  169 

Solander,  Daniel,  pupil  of  Linnarus,  117 

Sommerring.SamuelThomas,  German  scientist, 

309,  310,  353 
Sophist  school  of  philosophy,  2.3,  30 
Spallanzani,  Lazzaro,  Italian  biologist,  2.47- 

X48,  370,  376,  42.Z,  4i6,  430 
Species,  present  ideas  of,  613-616 
Speculum  natura,  mediaeval  nature  treatise,  80 
Spcmann,  Hans,  German  scientist,  581 
Spencer,   Herbert,   English  philosopher,   459, 

49^-497,  511.  566,  607 
Spener,  founder  of  Halle  University,  178 
Spicilegia  xoologka,  monographs  by  Pallas,  i£x 
Spinoza,  Baruch,  Dutch  philosopher,  12.6,  117, 

142.,  156,  174,  184,  2.73-2.75>  2.79.  5M,  52-6 
Spiritualism,  in  the  i8th  century,  2.68,  169 
Spontaneous  generation  theory,  430-435 
Sporozoa,  discovery  of,  549 
Sprengel,  Christian  Conrad,  German  botanist, 

2.56,  157,  2.69,  475 
Spurzheim,  311 
Stahl,   Georg  Ernst,   German  scientist,    178- 

183,  185,  186,  io6,  107,  147,  2.50,  z6z,  2.69, 

304,  308,  313,  317,  344,  345,  347,  349,  354, 

385,  41L,  444,  603,  611 
Stannius,    Friedrich    Hermann,    German    bi- 
ologist, 417,  418 
Steensen,  Nils,  see  Steno,  Nicolaus 
Steenstrup,  Johannes  Japetus  Smith,   Danish 

biologist,  418,  419,  42.0,  413 
StefFens,  Henrik,  Norwegian  philosopher,  2.91 
Stein,  Friedrich,  Austrian  scientist,  42.9 
Steinach,  Eugen,  Austrian  biologist,  597 
Stelluti,  Francisco,  Italian  biologist,  159 
Steno,    Nicolaus,    Danish    philosopher,    144, 

155-158,  167,  168,  2.2.3,  302-,  453 
Stobxus,  professor  of  medicine,  103 


D  E  X  xiu 

Strasburger,  Eduard,  German  cytologist,  534, 

535.  543 

Strato,  Athenian  philosopher,  45 

Strauss,  D.  F.,  German  scholar,  447 

Strindberg,  475 

Studien  xur  Bldttertheorie,  by  the  brothers  Hert- 
wig,  519 

Studnicka,  541 

Surgery,  origin  of,  4;  contributions  of  Byzan- 
tine Empire  to,  75;  advancement  by  Fa- 
brizio,  105 

Sutton,  W.  S.,  American  scientist,  544 

Swammerdam,  Jan,  Dutch  scientist,  149,  167- 
171,  2.30,  131,  2.33,  151,  309,  430 

Swedberg,  Jesper,  bishop,  186 

Swedenborg,  Emmanuel,  religious  founder  and 
scientist,  ii,  iii,  149,  150,  161,  186-189, 
2.13,  2.37,  169,  X70,  2.79,  ^89,  310,  311,  373, 
410,451 

Sydenham,  Thomas,  English  physician,  175, 
176,  184,  191 

Sylvius,  Jacob,  medical  student  of  the  Renais- 
sance, 99 

System  der  Medusen,  Das,  by  Haeckel,  510 

System  der  vergleichenden  Anatomie,  by  Meckel, 

356 
System  of  Logic,  by  J.  S.  Mill,  447 
System  of  Synthetic  Philosophy,  by  Spencer,  493 
Systema  natura,  biological  work  by  Linnaeus, 

104,  2.06,  107,  zio,  Z13,  331 
Systhne  de  la  Nature,  by  Hoi  bach,  2.68 
Sy Sterne  d' Epicure,  by  La  Mettrie,  140 

Tabula    sceleti  et  musculorum    corporis    humani, 

anatomical  work  by  Albinus,  2.58 
Thales    of    Miletus,     early     Greek     natural 

philosopher,  10,  11 
Theophrastus,     Athenian     philosopher     and 

disciple  of  Aristotle,  45,  191,  196 
Theoria  generationis,  treatise  by  Wolff,  2.49 
Theoria  medica  vera,  biological  work  by  Stahl, 

180 
Theorie  de  la  terre,  essay  by  Buffon,  113 
Theorie  elementaire  de  la  botanique,  by  de  Can- 

dolle,  437 
Theory  of  the  Earth,  by  Hutton,  454 
Thevenot,  friend  of  Swammerdam,  167,  168 
Thomas    Cantimpratensis,   mediaeval    scholar 

and  naturalist,  80 
Thunberg,  Karl  Peter,  pupil  of  Linnxus,  Z17 
Timaus,  dialogue  by  Plato,  31,  33 
Totemism,  4 
Tournefort,  Joseph  Pitton  de,  botanist,  195- 

197,  108,  iio,  113,  ill,  435,  436 
Tower,  569,  615 
Toxins,  discovery  of,  597 


xiv  I N 

Traite  de  cytologic,  by  Prenant,  541 
Trdmne  eines  Geistersehers,  by  Kant,  2.70 
Treatise  of  Comparative  Embryology,  by  Balfour, 

531 
Trembley,    Abraham,    Swiss   naturalist,    131, 

^33.  M4 

Treviranus,  Ludolf  Christian,  German  botan- 
ist. 390.  396 

Trithemius,  alchemist  and  mystic,  131,  133 

Tschermak,  591 

ijber    das    Organ    der    Seek,    by    Sommerring, 

..310 
tjber  den  Bildungstrieb,  physiological  work  by 

Blumenbach,  308 

Uber  die  Aufgabe  der  Naturgeschichte,  by  Nageli, 

..553 
ijberdie  Erhaltung  der  Kraft,  by  Helmholtz,  409 

Uber  die  Grenzen  des  Naturerkennens,  lecture  by 

Du  Bois-Reymond,  41^ 
Uber  die  Morphologic  der  wirbellosen   Tiere,   zo- 
ological work  by  Leuckart,  411 
Uber  die  ruckschreitende  Metamorphose  der  Tiere, 

anatomical  treatise  by  Rathke,  367 
Uber  die  Spiraltendenz.  der  Vegetation,  by  Goethe, 

184 
Uber  die   Verjiingung   in   der  Natur,    work   on 

morphology  by  Braun,   551 
iJber  Entwicklungsgeschichte  der  Tiere,    by   von 
__Baer,  363,  364 

Uber  Germinalselektion,  by  Weismann,  567 
Uber  Muskelkorperchen  und  was  man  eine  Zelle  ZM 

nennen  hahe,  essay  by  Schultze,  404 
Uexkiill,  Jacob  von,  612. 
Uhlenhuth,  Paul,  German  biologist,  598 
Universities,  founding  of,  76,  77;    status  in 

17th  and  i8th  centuries,  142. 
Untersuchungen  Uber  tierische  Electrizitdt,  by  Du 

Bois-Reymond,  411 
Untersuchungen  zttf  Morphologic  und  Systematik 

der  Vogel,  by  Fiirbringer,  503 
Untersuchungen  zur    vergleichenden  Anatomic  der 

Wirbeltiere,  by  Gegenbaur,  500 
Utilitarianism,  philosophical  system,  446 

Valdivia  expedition,  559 

Van  Beneden,  Edouard,  Belgian  biologist,  534- 

536,  543 
Van  Helmont,  Jean  Baptiste,  Belgian  scientist, 

138-140,  141,  180,  188,  2.07,  2.54,  z69,  Z79, 

430 
Van  t'HofF,  595 
Vandelaar,  artist,  158 
Variation,  467 

Varolio,  Costanzo,  anatomist,  106 
Vascular  system,  discovered,  143 


DE  X 

Vegetable  Staticks,  botanical  work  by  Hale,  2.19, 

^-53 
Vererbungslehre,  monograph  by  Plate,  573 
Vergleichende  Osteologie,  by  Pander,  368 
Versuch,  die  Metamorphose  der  Pflanzen  xu  erklaren, 

by  Goethe,  i8i 
Verworn,   Max,  German  biologist,   603-605, 

607 
Vesalius,  Andreas,  professor  of  medicine,  loi- 

104,  137,  142.,  145,  172.,  138,  158,  2.80 
Vesling,  Johann,  anatomist,  143 
Vieussens,  Raymond,  French  physician,  150 
Vilmorin,  Louis  Leveque  de,  French  scientist, 

584 
Vincentius  Bellovacensis,  Vincent  of  Beauvais, 

medieval  scholar,  80 
Virchow,  Rudolf  Ludwig  Carl,  307,  388,  402.- 

404,  415,  499,  505,  508,  52.1,  52.Z 

Vitalism,  modern  theory  of,  603 

Vogt,  Karl,  German  scientist,  451,  452.,  506, 

511,  603 
Voltaire,  Frangois  Marie  Arouet  de,  130,  131, 

2-15.  3^9 
Von  der  Erhalticng  der  Kraft,   essay  on   energy 

by  Helmholtz,  408 

Wagner,  Rudolf,  German   physiologist,  411, 

450.  451 
Waldeyer,  405,  536 
Wallace,    Alfred    Russell,  English   biologist, 

485-488,  588 
Warming,  Eugen,  Danish  scientist,  561 
Wasmann,  Erich,  psychologist,  600,  608 
Wedel,  G.  W.,  instructor  at  Jena,  176 
Weismann,   August,   German   biologist,   563- 

568,  573.  575.  579.  580.  585>  601 
Werden  der  Organismen,  Das,  by  Hertwig,  470, 

568 
Werner,  Abraham  Gottlob,  German  geologist, 

453.455 
Wharton,  Thomas,  English  physician,  148,  156 

Wiedersheim,  Robert,  German  anatomist,  519 

Wiesner,  Julius,  Austrian  botanist,  577 

Wigand,  Albert,  German  botanist,  483 

Wilberforce,   S.,    Bishop   of  Oxford,    attacks 

Darwinism,  481 
Willis,  Thomas,  professor  of  medicine,  148- 

150,  161 
Willughby,  Francis,  pupil  and  benefactor  of 

Ray,  199,  loi,  102. 
Wilson,  Edmund  Beecher,  American  biologist, 

581.  59^ 
Winkler,  Hans  Karl  Albert,  German  botanist, 

577 
Winslow,  Jacob  Benignus,  Danish  anatomist, 

302. 


I  N 

Wohler,  Friedrich,  German  chemist,  406,  431, 

448,  450 
WoKF,  Caspar   Friedrich,  German   naturalist, 

183,  148-2.51,  169,  195,  308,  356,  361,  362., 

365,  368,  385,  390,  431,  494,  531 
Wolff,  Christian,  pupil  of  Leibniz,  2.48,  2.52. 
Wollaston,  185 
Wonders  of  Nature,  The,    by  Sakarja  ben  Mu- 

hammed,  73 
Wotton,  Edward,  mediasval  scientist,  92.-93 
Wundt,  Wilhelm,  599 

Xenophanes,  Greek  philosopher,  founder  of 
Eleatic  School,  15,  zz,  99 

Yerks,  R.  M.,  American  psychologist,  601 

Zeitschrift  fur  wissenschaftliche  Zoologie,  founded 
by  Siebold  and  Kolliker,  418 


D  E  X  XV 

Zellbildung  und  Zellteilung,  cytological  work  by 
Strasburger,  535 

Zeno,  philosopher  of  Eleatic  School,  16 

Zoography  development  during  the  Renais- 
sance, 92.-98;  contribution  of  BufFon  to,  117 

Zoology,  status  of  science  in  early  Chi- 
nese civilization,  7;  in  Greek  civiliza- 
tion, 19;  Pliny's  contribution  to,  57; 
Gesner's  contribution  to,  93,  94;  reforms 
by  Linnxus,  2.13,  Z15;  contribution  of 
Cuvicr  to,  333,  334,  337;  development  of 
experimental  method  in,  578 

Zoonotnia,  by  Erasmus  Darwin,  Z94 

Zooto)nia  Democritea,  anatomical  work  by 
Severino,  107 

Zur  Abwehr  des  ethischen,  des  sozialen,  des  poli- 
tischen  Darwinismus,  polemical  treatise  by 
O.  Hertwig,  569 

Zygote,  definition  of,  589 


A    NOTE    ON    THE    TYPE 
IN    WHICH    THIS    BOOK    IS    SET 

This  book  is  set  on  the  Monotype  in  Garamont,  a  modem 
rendering  of  the  type  first  cut  in  the  sixteeyith  century  by 
Claude  GarafnondC^i; io-is6i).  He  was  a  pupil  of  Geofroy 
Tory  and  is  believed  to  have  based  his  letters  on  Venetian 
models,  although  he  introduced  a  number  of  important  dif- 
ferences. It  is  to  him  xve  owe  the  letter  ivhich  we  know  as 
Old  Style.  He  gave  to  his  letters  a  certain  elegance  and  a 
feeling  of  movement  which  won  for  their  creator  an  imme- 
diate reputation  and  the  patronage  of  the 
French  King,  Francis  I. 


MANUFACTURED    BY    MONTAUK    BOOKBINDING    CORP.